________________
Alex Wayman
Nirgrantha
a concordant example is used for teaching purposes. So, even though the author had labelled as 'useless' (vyartha) an external example, he himself found it useful to mention the 'concordant example' (sādharmya-drstānta) (in N. A.18) and the discordant example' (vaidharmya-drstānta) (in N. A. 19). Before comparing Ratnākaraśānti's position on Antarvyāpti with that of the N. A. it is well to refer to his approximate dating. Because he is well-established in the field of Buddhist Tantra, I included him in my Sarnath, Varanasi, seminar contribution on “An Historical Review of Buddhist Tantras 14." Here I explained why his dating is tied in with that of the great Tibetan translator Rin-chen Bzang-po, born A. D. 958 and that he would be a junior by about 20 years, hence born about A. D. 978. Hence he lived several decades after the author of N. A. It follows that śānti-pā (as the Tibetans call him), in defending the theory of Antarvyāpti, does not directly depend on the Jaina work N. A., even though this latter work may contain the first use of the term antarvyāpti. Sānti-pā's treatise is subtle and difficult. When I translated it, using the text edited by Haraprasad Shāstri5 compared with the Tibetan translation, I found editing mistakes both in the Sanskrit edition as well as in the Tibetan rendition. I believe that Shăstri's introductory comments are quite appropriate and insightful. To put it in my own words, the usual examples given for the theory of pervasion (vyāpti), or invariable concomitance, are illustrated by the 'syllogism' of claiming that there is fire on that mountain, giving as reason that we notice smoke there, as in the case of the kitchen. Hence, the generality of inferences is based on prior experiences, and there is a constant appeal to previous experiences in a given culture, which justifies the example that has been popularly experienced. Hence, one could not argue against the claim that the pervasion in such cases requires inclusion of the example. But then śānti-pā claims that in some cases of a thesis and reason, which he terms sattvahetu (reason for a real or existent thing), it is not possible for an example to be part of the pervasion. In illustration, if the Buddhist argues, "What exists is momentary," and the various sects of India have their own theses (on Ātman, Brahman, etc.) of similar declaration-it does not help to say "like a pot", since being momentary does not add a quality to the sattva as does the color 'red' to a pot, nor is a pot a paragon for what exists. Therefore, Buddhism has doctrinal reasons for the assertion "What exists is momentary," which presumably appeal to the followers of the lineage which so asserts. The various philosophical and religious schools of India all have their own declarations, giving reasons that appeal to the followers of such schools, and usually not providing any example that is popular and accepted by people at large. Now, presuming that various of those "reasons for an existent thing" are reasonable and acceptable, it must be that the pervasion was just between the thesis and the reason and does not extend to an example. Hence, even if an example is provided
Jain Education Intemational
For Private & Personal Use Only
www.jainelibrary.org