Book Title: Studies in Jaina Philosophy
Author(s): Nathmal Tatia
Publisher: Jain Cultural Research Society
Catalog link: https://jainqq.org/explore/001616/1

JAIN EDUCATION INTERNATIONAL FOR PRIVATE AND PERSONAL USE ONLY
Page #1 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Page #2 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Sanmati Publication No. 6 STUDIES IN JAINA PHILOSOPHY Page #3 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Page #4 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ STUDIES IN JAINA PHILOSOPHY BY NATHMAL TATIA M.A., D.Litt. (Cal.) WITH A FOREWORD BY MAHAMAHOPADHYAYA GOPINATH KAVIRAJ M.A., D.Litt., Late Principal, Government Sanskrit College, Banaras NEUER STIETO SON salIgammi le gampisArA JAIN CULTURAL RESEARCH SOCIETY BANARAS 5 (INDIA) Page #5 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ A thesis approved for the degree of Doctor of Literature by the University of Calcutta 1951 Printed in India The Modern Art Press, Calcutta 12 Page #6 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ TO MY GURUS PANDIT SUKHLALJI SANGHAVI AND PROFESSOR SATKARI MOOKERJEE THIS HUMBLE WORK IS RESPECTFULLY DEDICATED Page #7 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ yadatra sauSThavaM kiJcittadgurvoreva me na hi / yadatrAsauSThavaM kiJcittanmamaiva tayorna hi // Whatever merit the book may possess belongs exclusively to my gurus and not to myself. Whatever defects there may be in it belong entirely to myself and not to them at all. Page #8 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PUBLISHER'S NOTE Sheth Bholabhai J. Dalal and Sheth Premchand K. Kotawala, the Trustees of the P. K. Kotawala Trust, Bombay, offered to the Society a monthly grant of Rs. 200/- for six years from June, 1945. The Executive Committee of the Society gladly accepted the liberal offer and decided to found the Kotawala Research Fellowship. In the beginning, as no qualified scholar was available, the amount was spent for the students of Jaina philosophy at the Banaras Hindu University. But in the last quarter of 1946, Sri Nathmal Tatia, M.A., was appointed Kotawala Research Fellow for research in Jaina philosophy. He prepared his thesis Some Fundamental Problems of Jaina Philosophy (now entitled Studies in Jaina Philosophy) and submitted it to the University of Calcutta for the degree of Doctor of Literature. It is a matter of gratification and pride for us that he has been admitted to the D.Litt. degree by the University of Calcutta. We feel proud to observe that the Society fulfils one of its objectives by publishing the work of Dr Tatia, which sets up a landmark in the field of Jainalogical research. The scope of the literature produced by the Jaina masters is unlimited. They left no subject worth the name untouched. From the time of the Agamas up to the time of Yasovijaya, it had been the universal custom with the Jaina authors that they should make their own contribution to every possible branch of knowledge. The huge literature known as Jaina Literature is so called only because its authors happened to be Jainas. And the Jaina community regard it to be their own only on account of its having been composed by their ancestors. In fact, however, it is nothing but a continuation and expansion of Indian literature as such and intended to promote the well-being of entire mankind. Without this literature, the treasure of India's literary heritage is bound to remain incomplete and truncated. It has been unanimously admitted by the students of Jainalogy that numerous problems of India's history and culture would remain unsolved in the absence of the study of this so-called "Jaina Literature.' And in their opinion the confusion prevailing over a number of historical and cultural issues can be cleared up with the help of the light afforded by this branch. It has, however, to be admitted with regret that the output of systematic research work on Jaina religion, philosophy and culture has been very meagre. The scientific exploitation of this vast literature is even now only in its initial stage. It is a work to be done by not one or two isolated scholars but a task to be performed by a continuous stream of scholars who will dedicate their whole time and energy for the purpose. The result will be the production of a larger number of works of which the present work is a sample and specimen. This work has been adjudged by the highest authorities as a meritorious contribution and I am sure that the field of research on Jainalogy is so wide that it can give scope for such first-rate researches which can become legitimately the subject of at least a score of D.Litt. theses. The present work, however, sets an Page #9 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ viii PUBLISHER'S NOTE example of assiduous study and analysis of the basic problems, the treatment of which was attempted before only in a scrappy and haphazard fashion. It is hoped that the future research workers will follow the standard set up by the author and apply themselves to the intensive study of individual authors and also of individual problems and thus bring up the results of Jainalogical researches to the same level as has been attained in the field of Vedanta or Nyaya for instance. It will be dereliction of duty on my part if I do not give an account of the background against which the author had to carry on his researches. There was no such systematic exposition of the metaphysical and epistemological problems of Jaina philosophy, either in English or in Hindi. Of course, the learned and luminous Introductions of Pandit Sukhlalji Sanghavi contain, among many things, the expositions of many a problem of Jaina thought. But nobody else has utilized these accounts in a systematic way and put them in their historical setting. Dr Tatia has not only made full use of these materials but has succeeded in supplying the connecting links from a study of other systems of Indian philosophy, and this makes his work fully representative of the evolution of thought that took place in the adolescent and fruitful period of Indian speculation. This has been made possible by profound penetration into the inner meaning of the philosophical solutions of problems. His work is the outcome of extraordinary industry and broad philosophical outlook, intense reflection and critical appreciation of the fine shades of difference in the approaches of the various schools to the fundamental problems of philosophy. His treatment of avidya is by itself an independent contribution. It shows his wide study and deep penetration. It can be claimed that he has not allowed himself to be influenced by sectarian or communal considerations in his appraisal of the logical values of the arguments employed by different schools. His criticism of the Vedantic and the Buddhist conceptions of avidya, for instance, is not stereotyped in character, but distinctly original. The student of Indian philosophy, who will compare the author's exposition with that found in the original texts, will be surprised to find that such abundant light has been shed upon the cryptic texts. His exposition is not philological but philosophical and it will evoke the spontaneous admiration of unbiased votaries of truth that the Jaina philosophers have succeeded in defending themselves against the overwhelming onslaughts of the idealists. It is not only an exposition of the old stand but a new vindication which will strike a student of comparative philosophy with a thrill of surprise for the originality of approach and unperturbed equanimity of philosophical temper. Fortunately the author has not succumbed to the temptation of repeating the vitriolic attacks and vituperations of the mediaeval age. His arguments in defence and criticism of the rival positions are characterized by soberness of temper and expression and detached evaluation which are the outcome of modern culture at its best. It is an ardent desire of the Society that not one or two scholars like Dr Tatia but a number of scholars should co-operate with it and prove that this field of research is not unworthy and barren. This Page #10 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PUBLISHER'S NOTE ix . can be possible only if the wealthy people also co-operate with us. We cherish the hope that the present publication will draw the attention of the rich. We have ventured to undertake the publication of such a big work, even though the funds of the Society are so scanty, with the hope that public attention would be drawn to the quality of work that is being done by the Society. We consider it a duty to acknowledge our thankfulness to Sheth Bholabhai J. Dalal and Sheth Premchand K. Kotawala, the Trustecs of the Kotawala Trust for their liberal encouragement in this respect. As regards the author he regards the Society as his own and has written the work as a part of his duty. We wish that the work receives appreciation of scholars and proves an incentive to the author for the writing of similar valuable works in future. In conclusion, I place on record, on behalf of the Society, our thankfulness to Mahamahopadhyaya Dr Gopinath Kaviraj for the illuminating Foreword he has written for this book in spite of the multifarious calls on his valuable time. to Word he aluable BANARAS 5 25 October 1951 DALSUKH MALVANIYA, Secretary, Jain Cullural Research Society. JP-B Page #11 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CONTENTS (The numbers indicate pages) FOREWORD by Mahamahopadhyaya Dr Gopinath Kaviraj INTRODUCTION PRONUNCIATION ABBREVIATIONS CHAPTER I THE NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS Nature of ancient Indian literature, Study of the philosophical attitudes Bhahmanical, Buddhist and Jaina-proposed (1). xvii XXV xxxii xxxiii THE BRAHMANA ATTITUDE-Philosophical speculations of the Rgveda, Nasadiya hymn analysed, Reality is inexpressible (1-2); Speculations become more concrete in the Upanisads (2-4); Gradual development of the philosophical attitude described (4); Doctrine of rebirth and karman, Ethical attitude (4-6); Summary (7). I-26 THE BUDDHIST ATTITUDE-The rationalistic attitude of the Buddha (7-8); The avyakata problems, the four kinds of questions (8); Origin of metaphysics (8-9); Sasvatavada and ucchedavada (9-10); Finiteness and infiniteness of the world (10): Body and soul (10-1): Doctrine of sunna (12); Nirvana (13-4); Buddha's avoidance of metaphysics and his rationalistic attitude (14-5); Ethical attitude of the Buddha (15-7). THE JAINA ATTITUDE-Mahavira's attitude towards life, Stress on the principle of ahimsa and adherence to common experience (17-8); Jaina outlook reviewed on the basis of the Acaranga (18-21); Jaina attitude based on rational consciousness (21); Non-absolutistic attitude and its origin (21-2); Mahavira's solution of the avyakata problems (22-3); Being and becoming not naturally incompatible (24); Doctrines recorded in the Sutrakrtanga (24-5); Attitudes of Mahavira and the Buddha compared and contrasted (25-6). CHAPTER II THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS 27-80 INTRODUCTORY-Necessity of the study (27) Antiquity of Jaina epistemology (27) Criterion of right knowledge (27-8); Imperfection due to karmic veil, Function of the sense-organs, Five classes of knowledge classified into pratyaksa and paroksa (28); Samvyavaharapratyaksa (28); Comparative and critical attitude of the Jainas (28-9). MATI-JNANA-Its nature as paroksa and samuyavahara pratyaksa (30); Manas recognized as only a quasi-sense by the Jainas while the other systems accorded it the status of a sense-organ (31-2); Synonyms Page #12 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CONTENTS of mati-jnana, its definition and varieties and the different opinions (32-4); The four subdivisions of mati-jnana: (a) Avagraha-Its nature, synonyms, definition and varieties, and the different opinions (34-40); (b) Iha-Its nature, synonyms and definition, and the different opinions (40-1); (c) Apaya-Its nature, synonyms and definition, and the different opinions (41-2); (d) Dharana-Its nature, synonyms and definition, and the different opinions (42-4). THE FOUR BUDDHIS-Problem of srutanisrita and asrutanisrita and their differentiation (44-6); Two categories of asrutanisrita, mental and sensuous, and the four buddhis as the constituents of the former (46) Meanings and illustrations of the fourfold buddhis (46-8). SRUTA-JNANA-Original meaning (48) ; Fourteen characteristics of sruta-jnana and their nature elaborately considered with special consideration of the nature of samjna and its varieties and of the Jaina view that a soul can never be bereft of mati and sruta (48-53); Gradual development of the meaning of sruta summarized (53). NATURE OF SAMJNA-Conception of samjna elaborated (53-5). MATI AND SRUTA--Problem of the relation of mati and sruta and the different opinions (55-6); Upayoga and labdhi demarcated (55-6). DIFFERENTIATION OF MATI AND SRUTA--Jinabhadra's view stated (56-9). NON-DIFFERENCE OF MATI AND SRUTA-Siddhasena Divakara's view stated (59-61). AVADHI-Knowledge an essential characteristic of the soul, imperfection of knowledge is due to the karmic veil (61); Vital source of Jaina epistemology (62); Nature of avadhi-jnana and its varieties (62-3); Jaina conception of time, space, substance and modes (63-4). MANAHPARYAYA-JNANA-Nature of the mind-stuff (65) Nature of manahparyaya and the different opinions (65-8). AVADHI AND MANAHPARYAYA-No essential difference between them according to Siddhasena Divakara (69). KEVALA-JNANA-Its origination and nature (69-70). JNANA AND DARSANA-Twofold nature of consciousness, determinate and indeterminate (70-1); Antiquity of the conception (71); Problem of upayoga and pasyatta as found in the Prajnapana Sutra and explained by the commentator Malayagiri (71-2); Kundakunda's peculiar conception of jnana and darsana as well as the views of Virasena and Brahmadeva (72-4); Problem of the temporal relation between jnana and darsana of the omniscient (74-5); Consideration of the view of Siddhasena Divakara who refused to admit separate identity of jnana and darsana (75-8); Jinabhadra's position (78); Position of Akalanka and Vidyanandi (78); Three different views referred to by Haribhadra (78-9); Comprehensive reconciliation of the conflicting views by Yasovijaya (79-80); Transition to the next chapter (80). CHAPTER III THE PROBLEM OF AVIDYA I. INTRODUCTORY-Spiritual outlook of Indian thought, Necessity of logical discipline and philosophical speculation recognized 81-219 Page #13 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CONTENTS (81-2); Principle of nescience admitted by all the systems of Indian thought, Comparative study of the nature and function of the principle proposed (83) II. AVIDYA IN THE YOGA SCHOOL-Nature of purusa and prakyti and their relation (83-4); Nature and function of avidya (84-5); Nature of subject, object and their relation (85-7); Sankhya-Yoga epistemology of perception, the views of Vacaspati and Vijnanabhiksu differentiated (87-9); Fundamental characteristic of nescience and its relation to the other klesas (89-90). III. AVIDYA IN THE SAMKHYA SCHOOL-Metaphysical position of Sankhya identical with that of the Yoga, Points of agreement and difference between the Sankhya and the Yoga stated on the basis of the Mahabharata (90-3); Reason why Sankhya conception of avidya is separately stated, terminological difference (93); Sankhya scheme of Psychical factors and the psychical complexes (93-5); Vijnanabhiksu's differentiation between the Yoga and the Sankhya conceptions of avidya (95-6); Vijnanabhiksu's position criticized (96-100): Destruction of avidya followed by emancipation (100-1). IV. AVIDYA IN THE NYAYA SCHOOL-Specific qualities of the soul, Dharma and adharma, Threefold defects, Fivefold links of the chain of worldly existence the fundamental condition being delusion or perverted belief (101-2); The process how the soul is made to repeat its worldly career (102-3); Nature and function of delusion or nescience (103); Primal nescience compared to Original Sin, Process how the soul develops belief in the intrinsic value of the brute material facts described (104-5); In what sense is knowledge of reality possible? View of Vatsyayana and Uddyotakara stated (105-6); Importance of meditation and ecstasy in the Nyaya system (106-7); Process of the cessation of worldly life (107). V. AVIDYA IN THE VAISESIKA SCHOOL-Place of dharma and adysta in the subject-matter of the Vaisesikasutra (108-9); Two kinds of cognition viz. vidya and avidya described (110-1); Adrsta held as the fundamental condition of worldly existence in the Vaisesikasutra (111); Prasastapada quoted in order to show his conception of ultimate nescience (111-2). VI. AVIDYA IN THE VEDANTA SCHOOL-Limitation of the subject-matter of the section to the consideration of the positions of Upanisads, Gaula pada and Sankara (113); Avidyu and maya in the Upanisads (113-5); Gaudapada on maya and avidya (115-21); Sankara's examination of the nature of experience (121); Nature and function of adhyasa or avidya (121-3); Adhyasa is the very texture of our experience (123-4); Sankara's conception of maya (124-6). VII. AVIDYA IN THE BUDDHIST SCHOOL-Chain of dependent origination headed by avidya, Maitreyanatha's description of the links of the chain, Function and nature of avid ya (126-8); Sarinvytisatya and paramarthasatya (128) : Threefold characteristics of a thing illustrated (128-9); Vijnanavadin's conception of vasana responsible for subjectobject determination of consciousness (129-30); Nature of abhutaparikalpa as found in Lankavatara (131); Maitreyanatha, Vasubandhu and Sthiramati on the nature of abhuta parikalpa and its function and necessity for the explanation of bondage and emancipation (131-3); Page #14 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CONTENTS kh'iii Lankavatara on the unreality of bondage and emancipation (133); Conceptions of jneyavarana and klesa varana (134); Conception of avidya in the tathata-philosophy of Asvaghosa (134-7). VIII. AVIDYA IN THE SAIVA SCHOOL-Dualistic Saivism: Categories and nature of soul (137) ; Malapasa and its functions (138) ; Other forms of pasa described (138-40); Different states of the soul such as sakala, pralayakala and the like (140); Condition and function of the descent of Divine Grace (140) : Function and varieties of diksa (140-1). Monistic Saivism : Nature of Paramasiva or the Absolute and the process and the results of its self-concealment and self-limitation (141-2); Subjectivity, Objectivity and their intermixture (142) ; Genesis of three fold mala viz. anava, mayaya and karma (142-3); Genesis of kala etc. (143); Anava-mala further elucidated (143) ; Spiritual and intellectual ignorance (143-4). IX. AVIDYA. IN THE JAINA SCHOOL--Jaina conception of mithyatuu equated to that of avidya of the other systems (144) : Various expressions of mithyatva, Various classifications of mithyatva and their uniform purpose (144-5); Mithyatva or mith yadarsana as the root of all evils, Problem of beginninglessness of mithyatva and the origination of samyaktva (145-6); Five conditions of bondage reduced to three viz. mithyadarsana, mithy:ijnana and mithyacaritra (147); Mutual relation among samyag-darsana, samyag-jnana and samyak-Caritra (147-51); Jainas do not believe in perverted knowledge alone as the cause of worldly bondage, Necessity of the postulation of threefold cause of bondage (151); Vidyanandi's objections against the view that perverted knowledge alone is the cause of bondage (151-5). X. CRITICISM OF THE SAMKHYA-YOGA CONCEPTION OF AVIDYA-Relation between the world process and purusa criticized (155-7); Multiplicity of prakytis criticized (157-8); Logical difficulties and implications of the Samkhya-Yoga system according to Hemacandra, Haribhadra and Viciyanandi (158-61). XI. CRITICISM OF THE NYAYA-VAISESIKA CONCEPTION OF AVIDYA-Relation between knowledge and soul and the conception of inherence criticized (162-4); Jaina view of the relation between quality and substance, Consciousness is the very essence of self, Meaning of bondage and the problem of change (165-6); Omniscience necessary for emancipation, Logical difficulties of the Nyaya-Vaisesika view of ignorance according to Samantabhadra (167-8); The Nyaya position regarding the means of emancipation compared and contrasted with the Jaina view, Omniscience admitted in the later writings of the NyayaVaisesika school (168-9). XII. CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA CONCEPTION OF AVIDYAVedantin's position restated (169-71); Jaina philosopher's criticism of the Vedantist's contention that plurality is unreal (171-2); Vedantist's interpretation of the content of error as neither real nor unreal and the Jaina reply (172-3); The Vedantist agrees with Nagarjuna in declaring causality as an irrational principle and thinking that there is antagonism between plurality and unity, but he admits experience as the proof of the reality of consciousness and existence and the Jaina asks him to admit the reality of plurality as well on the verdict of the same experience (174-5); The Vedantist rejects the world of experience as unreal because it involves both identity and difference, Page #15 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ xiv CONTENTS but the Jaina thinks that the world of experience transcends both identity and difference and synthesizes them in a separate category which is different from both of them (175-6); Criticism of the Vedantist's denial of causality (176); Criticism of the Vedantist's appeal to dream-experience in support of the position that the Absolute appears as the plurality of phenomena Pure identity or pure difference is never experienced and so cannot be real (176-8); Some absurd consequences of monism and Vedantist's reply (178-9); Vedantist's deduction of the unreality of an independent objective world from ani analysis of an ordinary empirical judgment (179-84); Criticism of the Vedantist's position (184-5); The Jaina regards the relation between cognition and cognitum as a case of identity-in-difference (185-7) ; Monism cannot be established by revelation as well (187); Argument of Suresvara and its criticism (187-8); Negation of dualism presupposes the reality of dualism (188): The Vedantist's reply (188-9); Nature and relation of nescience as expounded by Suresvara, Pure consciousness as the locus and abode of nescience (189-91); Distinction between knowledge and pure consciousness, Error is opposed to knowledge but not to pure consciousness, Vedantist's refutation of a priori opposition between consciousness and nescience, Nescience is not an eternal verity because it is destroyed by knowledge, No iogical repugnance in the unreal association of unreal nescience with omniscience (191-3); Vedantist's assertion that his theory is the simplest of all (193-4); Jaina reply (194-8); Vedantist's position that constancy, continuity and uniformity are the characteristics of reality and the Jaina criticism, Ultimate nature of reality can be known by experience alone, Vedantist accepts existence on the testimony of experience and the Jaina asks him not to read contradiction in the combination of unity and multiplicity or identity and difference on the verdict of the same experience (198-200); Jaina's reply to the objections of Suresvara (200-1). XIII. CRITICISM OF THE BUDDHIST CONCEPTION OF AVIDYA-Buddhist conception recapitulated (201-2); Justification for treating only a few conceptions, General defects of absolutistic conceptions (202-3); Universal belief in the necessity of nescience, Jaina view (203-4); Logic must co-operate with experience in its quest for the Holy Grail (204); Position of Nagarjuna inconsistent with the Moral Law, Sautrantika fluxist is also guilty of self-contradiction, Causation is impossible in the absence of a real link between the past and the present, Other difficulties in the doctrine of flux (204-8); Subjectivist idealist criticized (208-11); Nagarjuna's criticism of causal relation (212-3); The Jaina philosopher thinks that the difficulties shown by Nagarjuna are the creation of a priori logical thought. There is no such thing as absolute identity or absolute difference. Relation between cause and effect is a sui generis relation which can be expressed as identity--in-difference (213-4); Problem of the relation of the characteristics with the things considered, The Jaina solution by admitting the relation of identity-in-difference (214-5); The Jaina asserts that logic is blind without experience and experience is a cripple without logic (215) XIV. CRITICISM OF THE SAIVA CONCEPTION OF AVIDYAPossibility of release from imperfection admitted by all systems of thought (215-6); The Saiva position regarding nature of self, cause Page #16 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CONTENTS of bondage and clawn of omniscience and omnipotence compared and contrasted with the Jaina view (216-7); The Saiva conceptions of Paramasiva, free will, the relation between Paramasiva and the world order and between karman and the individual self, and the idea of Divine Grace criticized (217-8). XV. CONCLUSION-Avid ya qua the basic defect is the perverted attitude, Avidya qua the conditions of worldly existence consists in the threefold elements of perverted attitude, perverted cognition and perverted conduct (218-9). CHAPTER IV THE JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN 220-260 INTRODUCTORY-Outlook of the Vedic people, Jaina and Buddhist attitudes, Demarcation between the Sramanic and the Brahmanic, Growth of asceticism, Rebirth and karman, Nescience, Necessity of karman, Subject-matter of the chapter (220-1); Nyaya-Vaisesika admits God as the necessary condition for the fruition of karman, Other systeins admit adrsta as competent to produce its fruit in time, Nature of the passions determines the nature of karman or adysta (221-2); Different views regarding the relation between spirit and nonspirit responsible for worldly existence, Sankhya-Yoga and Jaina conceptions differentiated, Common ground among the different systems (222-3). I THE MATERIAL NATURE OF KARMAN-Worldly status is an evil ; Position of the Carvaka criticized (223-4); Sankhya-Yoga position criticized (224) : Criticism of the Vedantic and the Nyaya-Vaisesika positions, Creation is a veritable intermixture of the spiritual and the material (224-6); Criticism of the Buddhist position (226); The Jaina avoids the absolutist conception of karman, Jaina position contrasted (226-8); Tentative reconstruction of the structure of the ancient thought, Value of the historical speculation (228-31). II. RELATION BETWEEN SOUL AND KARMAN--Importance of the problem, Relation between a substance and its modes determined by experience, Concrete identity between the soul and the karmic matter in the state of bondage (231-2). III. CLASSIFICATION OF KARMAN-Eight main types of karman deduced (232-3); The sub-types (233-5); Function of passions in the bondage (235-8); Function of vibration (238-9); Division of the eight types of karman into obscuring and non-obscuring and its justification (239-43) ; Another way of classification of the karmans into virtuous and sinful or auspicious and inauspicious (243); Some similar speculations recorded (243-6); Buddhist conception of karman and its classification (246-51); Buddhist jneyavarana and klesavarana compared respectively with Jaina jnanavarana and caritramohaniya (251-2). IV. THE STATES AND PROCESSES OF KARMAN-Imperfect expression of the energy, that is, yoga is responsible for the various states and processes of karman (252); Nature of coloration and its association with energy (253); The problem further elaborated (254); Various processes and states of the karmic matter described (254-9); Comparative remarks (259-60). Page #17 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Xvi CONTENTS CHAPTER V JAINA YOGA 261-304 INTRODUCTORY-Short retrospect (261); Paths of spiritual realization, Meaning of yoga (261-2); General scheme of the Jaina doctrine of conduct and the subject-matter of the chapter (263-8). I. THE DOCTRINE OF GUNASTHANA-Jaina conception of Godhead (268-9); Processes leading to the first dawn of spiritual vision (269-73); Nature of the spiritual vision (273); Condition of the soul after the enlightenment (273-4); Processes required for the perpetuation of the spiritual vision (274-5); Nature of the twofold ladders of spiritual ascent (275-6); Stages of spiritual development (276-9); Process of samudghata (280). II. THE DOCTRINE OF DHYANA-Fundamental motive inspiring the Jaina outlook towards dhyana (281); Bahiratman, antaratman and paramatman (281-2); Definition and the basis of classification of dhyana (282-3). (a) Dharma-dhyana: Fourfold aspects described in the Sthanangasutra (283); Position of Jinabhadra (284); Umasvati's definition and opinions of Akalanka, Pujyapada and Siddhasenagamin (284-5); Subhacandra's views as contained in his nanarnava elaborately stated (285-9); Yogasastra of Hemacandra analysed (289-91). (b) Sukla-dhyana: Conditions and nature of sukladh yana (291); Four types of sukla-dhyana described (291-3). III. HARIBHADRA'S COMPARATIVE STUDIES IN YOGAHaribhadra's works on yoga (293); Meaning of yoga and its constituent activities and their nature and relation with the gunusthanas as found in the Yogavirsika (293-6); Sodasakas analysed, Primary defects of the mind, A yogin's mind, Nature of self-realization in the non- Jaina systems compared to that of the Jaina school, Haribhadra stresses unanimity of the various conceptions of final realization, Virtues necessary for the pursuit of truth (296-7); Yogabindu analysed, Haribhadra stresses unanimity about the principle of consciousness and the ground of worldly existence in the various systems, Origin of the different systems of thought, Complete course of yoga. Two periods of worldly existence viz. dark and white, Condition of disentanglement from worldly existence, Characteristics of a bodhisattva, Tirthankara is a bodhisattva destined to redeem the world from sin, Three categories of soul destined to be emancipated, Five steps of the complete course of yoga (297-300); Yogadystisamuccaya analysed, Eight dystis enumerated, Three broad divisions of the stages of yoga, Oghadysti and yogadysti differentiated, Nature and illustrations of the dystis and the corresponding conceptions, Dystis elaborately described, Four types of yogins (300-304). INDEX I: AUTHORS MENTIONED 305 INDEX II: WORKS QUOTED INDEX III: GENERAL SUBJECTS 309 INDEX IV: SANSKRIT, PRAKRIT AND PALI WORDS 314 306 Page #18 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ FOREWORD by Mahamahopadhyaya Dr Gopinath Kaviraj The following pages embody the results of a wide and systematic study in the field of Jaina philosophy, and deal with certain basic problems of the system. These problems which relate to Jnana, Ajnana, Karman, and Yoga have a universal bearing and though an attempt has been made to examine each of them and to determine its value from a particular point of view it is bound to be of special interest to every earnest student of Indian philosophy. As the writer has undertaken to interpret the Jaina viewpoint, it is but natural that he should have approached his subject from this standpoint. The work begins with a brief enunciation of the general philosophical attitude of Brahmanism, as revealed in the earlier Upanisads, described as chiefly monistic, and is followed by a comparison with the Buddhist approach which is rationalistic and the Jaina attitude which is non-absolutistic. With this preliminary statement as a preamble the work proceeds to discuss at length each of the four problems mentioned above on the basis of ancient Jaina traditions recorded in works considered as possessed of undisputed authority. There is ample evidence to show not merely that the author's studies have been wide and varied, but also--and this is very important that his interpretation is faithful and illuminating. To this rare combination he has added another commendable quality, viz. lucidity of presentation. His criticisms of some of the doctrines of the rival schools may not be acceptable to the exponents of those schools. But they have a distinct value of their own. It is an established convention that the exponent of a particular line of thought considers it a part of his duty not only to interpret it in its own light and judge it on its own merits but also to bring it into comparison or contrast with other lines of similar thought. In such cases the defence of one line leads usually to the condemnation of the rest. But such condemnation is not necessarily a condemnation if the ultimate postulates of those lines are taken into consideration. The Jaina theory of knowledge has been dealt with in the chapter on Jaina epistemology. It is based on the Agamas and had, like the doctrine of Karman, probably its origin in the wisdom of the ancient seers. The fivefold division of knowledge is very old. Knowledge is an essential attribute of the soul, but its rightness or wrongness JP-C Page #19 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ xviii FOREWORD depends on the attitude. What is usually known as avidya implies in fact only a perversion (mithyatva) of the attitude on account of which the purity of knowledge is vitiated. Upayoga or Consciousness is called jnana when it is determinate (sakara) and darsana when it is indeterminate (nirakara). These two qualities, like virya and ananda, are unlimited and unobscured in the emancipated soul and are clouded by the karmic matter when the soul is in bondage. To a person in ordinary life no two acts of knowledge, in fact no two states of consciousness, are concurrent. Simultaneity, wherever it seems to appear, is erroneous, the error being due to various causes, incompetence of the apprehending faculty to cognize two successive acts together being responsible for the erroneous notion. But when the obscuring karmans veiling the omniscience of the soul are removed omniscience is bound to be manifest. It is true. But the question is: Do jnana and darsana occur in succession or simultaneously? The Agamas are emphatic on the point that simultaneity of jnana and darsana is not possible before the ghatikarmans are destroyed. On this there is unanimity between the Digambara and the Svetambara schools. But for a kevalin there is no succession of jnana and darsana according to the Digambaras and also to a section of the Svetambaras. The question of the possibility of krama in omniscience is as old as it is universal and is also relevant in the context of epistemological problems. So far as normal knowledge is concerned krama is inevitable, as in each case a distinct contact between the self and the mind and between the mind and the sense-organ would be necessary according to Nyaya-Vaisesika or as every act of knowledge represents a distinct modification (parinama) in the mind stuff which is subject to constant flux according to Sankhya-Yoga. But omniscience is a supernormal experience. Patanjali refers to vivekaja-jnana which arises from a meditation on ksana and its sequence. It is described as saving knowledge (taraka-jnana) and is integral and all comprehending having for its object All in all its aspects. This knowledge is free from krama and corresponds in a sense to the kevala-jnana of Jainism. It grasps in one sweep everything-past, present and future as well as near and remote. This is pratibha-jnana or pratibha. The implication of akrama is that it is not an act in Time (kala) but in the Moment which is beyond time. It is said that the Buddha attained to Universal Vision in which he saw all things simultaneously as if reflected in a mirror.3 The Tripurarahasya" refers to Pratibha, 1 Cf. pratibhad va sarvam-YD, III. 33. 2 Cf. eka-ksanoparudham sarvam sarvatha grhnati-Bhasya, YD, III. 54. 3 dadarsa nikhilam lokam adarsa iva nirmale--Buddhacarita, XIV. 8e-d. 4 Tnanakhanda, XX. 36. (Saraswati Bhavana Texts No. 15, 1933). Page #20 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ FOREWORD xix which being devoid of all limitations is called Supreme (Para), as the of the Deity. Utpalacarya, in his isvarapratyabhijna-karika, states plainly that Pratibha or Divinity is above all krama and yet holds within itself the entire krama of the universe associated with the action of the forces of space and time (desa-kala-sakti) projected by Divine Freedom. In other words, there is krama in outer appearances while there is no krama in the Inner Mirror of the Ineffable Light which reveals those appearances. This is exactly what the Vaiyakaranas say in regard to the Pasyanti Vak which is conceived as free from krama within, as One, and yet as holding within itself the forces of krama as well. It is equated to Parabrahman, Aksara, Sabdarupa, Para Vak and Atman." There is no use multiplying instances to show that the Supreme Omniscience is akrama and yet possesses within itself every form of krama. The chapter on avidya, consisting of fifteen sections, is devoted to a careful examination of the problem in all its implications and bearings. The views of other schools viz. Nyaya-Vaisesika, SankhyaYoga, Vedanta, Buddhism and saivism have been stated and refuted and the Jaina theory upholding avidya as identical with triple perversity (mithyatva) has been finally confirmed. The Jaina view of avidya implies erroneousness not in knowledge only, as usually conceived, but in attitude and conduct as well. Closely connected with the problem of avidya is the question of karman which in Jaina literature, as elsewhere in Indian thought, occupies a position of great importance. A separate chapter in four sections is assigned to an elaborate discussion of this topic. The conception of karman as dravya, in addition to its character as bhava, is unique in Jainism and has received a special treatment in its literature. It has parallels elsewhere indeed, but its importance in Jaina thought cannot be overrated. The conception of anava-mala* in dualistic Saivism as a covering substance, which obscures the inner divinity of the self and converts it as it were into a mundane soul subject to the exigencies of various limitations, bears a close resemblance to the Jaina view. It may be of interest to note that the other two malas of the Tantric dualists would also in some way be partially covered by the Jaina concept of karman. It may be remembered that, 1 ya sai 'sa pratibha tattatpadartha krama-rusita akramananta-cidrapah pramata sa mahesvarah. --Isvarapratyabhijna-vimarsini, with Bhaskari, p. 348. (Saraswati Bhavana Texts No. 70). 2 Cf. pratisamhstakramapy antah saty apy abhede samavista kramasaktih pasyanti---Sivadysti, p. 39. (Kashmir Series of Texts and Studies No. LIV, 1934). 3 Vide ibid., p. 39. 4 Vide infra, p. 138. Page #21 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ XX FOREWORD like the kancukas of Maya concealing the omniscience, omnipotence, ubiquity, eternity and blissfulness of the soul, the karmans in Jainism. obscure the purity of the soul. The author has dwelt on the relatior. of karman with the soul, its classification, and its states and processes There is another point which deserves consideration, The Vedantic avidya has the dual power of obscuration (avarana) and projectior (viksepa). The dawn of self-knowledge removes the former and in special cases when some more qualifications are added-leads to jivanmukti. The existence of the latter, which is described as avidya lesa, does not stand in the way of jivanmukti. It is experience (bhoga alone which is held to be capable of exhausting the strength of th latter. This is of course the usual course. The Jaina conception o the basic difference in karman as ghatin and aghatin brings out th above truth clearly. The ghati-karman corresponds to the avaran aspect and the aghatin to the viksepa aspect of the Vedantic avidyi It is well known that the presence of aghati-karmans is not inconsister with the rise and function of kevala-jnana, though it is true that i the final state of Beatitude or Siddhi even the aghati-karmans whic are pure in nature disappear, causing the disintegration of the physica organism itself. First the kasayas disappear and then in due cours the yoga (activity), which is followed by Siddhi. The treatment of the problem of karman, like that of avidya, very elaborate, but it is not, I am afraid, thorough, if looked at fro the standpoint of the subject. All the issues relevant to a prop appreciation of the subject have not been, and could not have beei touched. It is true that in a work on Jainism the writer was not in position to discuss freely points raised in works on Buddhism, Tantra Yoga Sastra, and Puranas. But it is also true that these aspects of t1 problem might have been viewed and discussed in the interest thoroughness from the standpoint of Jaina thought itself. The autho for instance, says nothing of vicarious karman, of transfer of karme and its laws, and of what has been somewhere described as equilibr tion of karman (karma-samya). The nature of vipaka, its time ai its character as niyata or aniyata together with the laws of karm fructification required clarification. A clearer statement of the rel tion between the ghatin and aghatin karmans would have been ve useful to a proper philosophical appreciation of the theory. We now come to the last chapter which contains some ve interesting data on the basic principles of spiritual evolution. T Jaina view of paramatman in the role of World Teacher (tirthai kara) akin in some respects to the Sankhya and Tantric conceptions of isva and deserves to be studied in the same context. In each case it the human soul which on complete purification from matter attains Page #22 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ FOREWORD xxi the level of divine perfection. The pertinent question which occurs in this connection is: Why of all the souls which are similarly gifted a particular soul, and not every one, attains to this phase of perfection. Kaivalya is open to all, whether one is isvara and possessed of vivekaja-jnana or otherwise. So is Siddhi open to all, though the status of isvara or tirthankara is reserved for a chosen few only. What the special qualifications of these few are and how they were originally acquired we do not know. The Jaina view seems to point to radical differences inherent in the souls in spite of their essential sameness of qualitative perfection. Apart from the basic difference due to bhavyata in a soul there are other differences as well, which in fact tend to make each soul unique. The Christian and Madhva views, together with similar ideas in other schools including Buddhism, point to a similar outlook. In Sankhya an attempt has been made to show that the path of aisvarya at the beginning of a new cycle is consequent on apara-vairagya minus vivekaja-jnana in the earlier cycle, followed by a suspension of cosmic order in pralaya. This status of isvara is that of karyesvara, there being no provision in Kapila's system for a Supreme Being endowed with Divinity from eternity. In the Tantras also aisvarya ensues to a soul, which has purged itself from the shackles of karman and maya but has not attained to sufficient maturity in mala-paka so as to bring down Divine Grace upon it and transform it into an isvara, in the ensuing cosmic cycle, which is possible only on the attainment of the requisite maturity. The author says rightly that the inward tendency exists in every soul, but it is not awakened in each or not awakened at the same time in all. It may be that in some it is not awakened at all. This explains the difference in the starting point of spiritual evolution which commences with the awakening of this tendency and terminates with the attainment of Siddhi. Thus while the Siddhi is open to all awakened souls the status of tirthankara or World Teacher is reserved for a select few only. There are certain souls in which the spiritual evolution never takes place-not in the present cycle, nor even in the future. The yathapravrttakarana, as explained, is a very interesting factor, which is conceived as an act of unconscious resolution (adhyavasaya) working within from the beginningless past or as a momentary act of selfpurification manifested as vairagya. The life history of a soul consists mainly of four stages: (1) the embryonic stage in the nigoda, (2) the awakening of the inward tendency synchronizing with granthibheda, (3) the beginning of spiritual evolution marked by numerous gunasthanas, and (4) the perfection or Siddhi. Some souls do not come out into the evolutionary line at all, but those which come out are sure 1 etasyam avasthayam kaivalyam bhavati "svarasya 'nisvarasya va vivekajajnana-bhagina itarasya va--Bhasya, YD, III. 55. Page #23 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ xxii FOREWORD sooner or later to arrive at perfection. They have, as the earlier Buddhists would say, entered into the stream (srotas) and are destined for final realization. The section on gunasthana is admirably written and contains a mass of valuable information from the source books on the way in which the process of spiritual regeneration sets in and continues. Interesting details are given which remind one of the mysteries involved (i) in the awakening of kundalini or in the act of conversion which transforms a mundane into a supra-mundane citta moving inwards to Nirvana or (ii) in the anugraha-sakti which not only purges but also divinizes the soul. The process is analogous, from one point of view, to the process of the first reclaiming of a prthagjana into an arya, and then of leading an arya already in the stream, through gradual eradication of all the fetters that bind him down to the wheel of life, to a state of moral and spiritual freedom. From another point of view it is comparable to the process which generates a bodhicitta and leads it up from stage to stage till it realizes itself as a full grown Buddha. The process begins with right vision (samyag-darsana) in the soul as soon as the coating of relevant karmic matter is removed, at least for a short while, by means of the various karanas'. Right vision follows on the removal of this veil. Once it is acquired it never leaves until perfection is completed. There may be lapses, but these are at most temporary and bound to disappear. This shows that the elimination of karman or avidya is followed by the rise of jnana. Coats of matter must be removed if right vision is to emerge. Patanjali's conception of the relation between kriyayoga and samadhiyoga is relevant here. Kriyayoga helps to attenuate the karma-seeds but not to destroy them. They are destroyed only by prasamkhyana which follows from samadhi, thus showing that jnana alone either rising from samadhi or inspired from above effects the destruction of avidya and the granthibheda. The belief expressed in the couplet: bhidyate hrdayagranthis chidyante sarvasarsayah ksiyante ca'sya karmani tasmin dyste paravarea is on the contrary to the effect that the vision comes first, either as a result of an act of Grace from above or of an act of intense self-effort from within and is followed by granthibheda, samsayaccheda and karmaksaya, and not vice versa. In the Tantras however we have a synthesis of the two apparently conflicting positions. The counterpart of karmic matter obscuring t soul is, as has been already observed, anava-mala or atomic coating 1 Vide infra, p. 271. 2 MuUp, II. 2. 8. Page #24 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ FOREWORD and the Mayakancukas which obscure the divinity of the soul and limit omniscience, omnipotence etc. The basic coating has to be removed first before the true vision can arise. When the obscuring matter is mature Grace descends on the soul and by the application of kriyasakti in diksa the matter is removed. Thus spiritual ignorance disappears and spiritual knowledge follows. The rise of intellectual knowledge through practice of sadhanas and the removal of intellectual ignorance fall within these two limits.1 xxiii The Foreword has become inordinately long and I do not wish to make further observations on other points or issues raised in the work. The author, as an exponent of Jaina philosophy, has done full justice to the subject and has given unmistakable evidence of a wide acquaintance with and of great labours in the field of early Jaina philosophical speculations. It is desired however that, in the interest of a more comprehensive treatment of the problems concerned from the general viewpoint, the author should compile another work where India's outlook on these problems may be clearly represented. We have had enough of analytical work attempting to describe the different systems in isolation, taking each as a distinct prasthana and proceeding along its own line. But time, I believe, has come when scholars should come out from their narrow grooves, take up a synthetic view of things, and try to discover the underlying unity and interpret India's outlook as a whole. I invite the author, whom I consider to be competent enough, to undertake the work, to come forward as a pioneer in the field, and take upon himself the sacred task of interpreting the message of undivided ancient India to the outside world. 1 Vide infra, pp. 143-4. Page #25 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Page #26 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION Jainalogy is a vast subject or rather consists of a number of subjects each of which is immense in its extent and content. It is a matter of gratification that the canonical literature attracted the attention of scholars for the first time and authorized translations of some of the Agamas in the Sacred Books of the East Series and outside have gone a long way in acquainting the academic world with the basic doctrines and principles of Jaina religion and ethics. The contributions of the later masters in the field of logic, epistemology and metaphysics are literally stupendous. In the field of logic and epistemology the English translation of Hemacandra's Pramanamimamsa, a standard authoritative work on the subject, by my revered teacher Professor Dr Satkari Mookerjee, M.A., Ph.D., Asutosh Professor and Head of the Department of Sanskrit, Calcutta University, and my humble self is expected to enable a modern student of philosophy to have a dependable and fairly comprehensive knowledge of the contribution of the Jaina thinkers. As regards the philosophy of Anekantavada, it has received a thorough treatment and exposition in the work The Jaina Philosophy of Non-absolutism of my revered teacher. The paper on Anekantavada by Professor K. C. Bhattacharya is an outstanding and illuminating exposition of the fundamental logical attitude of the Jaina philosophers. It was felt by me that a study of Jaina philosophical thought could not be perfect without a knowledge of its evolution from its ancient moorings in the Agamas, a large number of which is happily still extant. In the present work I have addressed myself to this difficult task. I thought it imperative that a modern scholar should have a fair acquaintance with the spiritual and religious milieu in which Jainism is found to take its rise. It must be admitted that Jainism was not an exotic overgrowth on the soil. It arose in the midst of currents and cross-currents of spiritual and philosophical upheaval which characterized the times when Mahavira and Gautama Buddha strenuously engaged themselves in their missionary work. I did not dare to go further back beyond the Agamas for want of documentary evidence, although it is claimed by the orthodox adherents of the Jaina faith that Mahavira only promulagated an ancient doctrine which had been preached by an unbroken succession of tirthankaras whose activities were spread over thousands and thousands of years before the last tirthankara made his advent. In the first chapter I have tried to give an estimate of the distinctive trends of thought and attitude of the Vedic seers, the Buddha JP-D Page #27 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ xxvi INTRODUCTION and Mahavira. I have indicated that the later growth of Jaina philosophical thought in the fields of logic, epistemology, ethics and religion has been dominated and influenced by the peculiar philosophical outlook and attitude of Mahavira. Later writers, in their elaboration of the fundamental problems, have given evidence of their original thinking no doubt. But they have not made a departure from the fundamental tenets which gave Jaina thought their stamp of individuality. I have shown how Mahavira's attitude towards experience, sensuous and supersensuous, which provides a sharp contrast with that of the Buddha, has been the prime source of Jaina epistemology which has been dealt with in the second chapter of this work. I have tried to be scrupulously faithful to the celebrated exponents of Jaina thought, and though my treatment is mainly historical in character I have not hesitated to give a critical evaluation on points whereupon the tional doctors delivered conflicting and divergent views. A study of this chapter will, I hope, throw welcome light on the peculiar epistemology of perception of the Jaina school and will provide a student of the standard works of Jaina logic and epistemology with the necessary background to understand the tangled problem in a clear perspective. In the third chapter I have dealt with the supreme problem of avidya in the different schools of Indian thought and have shown how the Jaina conception of avidya radically differs from that of other schools. I do not know of any systematic and comparative study of this fundamental problem by a predecessor. I have endeavoured my best to be thorough in my treatment and have shown with reference to the original data how the approach to the problem has deeply influenced the philosophical outlook and conclusions of the different schools. I may not be accused of vanity if I modestly claim originality for my treatment of avidya in Yoga, Sankhya, Nyaya, Vaisesika and Saiva schools. As regards the Buddhistic and the Vedantic conceptions of avidya I have given a dispassionate and faithful exposition of the treatment accorded to it by the original exponents without the slightest leaning to weaken their position. I have given as faithful and powerful an exposition of the views of the philosophers as could be expected from an orthodox adherent of these systems, I have shown how the Jaina philosophers have squarely and boldly faced the sledge-hammer blows of the idealistic philosophers and have given their own realistic interpretation of the data from which the idealistic conclusion was deduced. The Vedantic conception of avidya has been expounded by modern exponents more or less elaborately. But the Jaina criticism Page #28 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION of it with all its logical strength has not been dealt with by any previous writer so far as my knowledge goes. I have drawn upon original writings of the exponents of both the schools, particularly Suresvara and Vidyanandi. I have not gone to the later writers such as Madhusudana Sarasvati as I did not think that it would serve an additional purpose. I have shown the fundamental and irreconcilable difference of the philosophical approach and outlook of the Jaina realist from that of the Vedantic and Buddhist idealists. The difference is ultimate and each has shown himself at his best and strongest. There can be no capitulation on the fundamentals and ultimate issues. The onslaughts are as powerful and telling as the defence is effective. It can be claimed without betrayal of partisan spirit and zeal of orthodoxy that the Jaina has laid his hands upon the most vulnerable point in the Vedantist's armoury of defence. The Jaina philosopher has laid enormous stress upon the Vedantist's reliance upon experience in his difference from the Buddhist nihilist Nagarjuna so far as he is expounded by Candrakirti and his critics. The Vedantist has criticized the absolute negativism as sponsored by a school of Buddhist sceptics on the ground of self-contradiction of experience. The Jaina has shown that the charge of selfcontradiction is not based upon and cannot be substantiated by pure logic. The contradiction is empirical in character. The Jaina therefore submits that the Vedantist should not give half-hearted allegiance to experience together with its contents. The Vedantist's appeal to the ultimate experience in final realization as an unpolarized simple affirmation does not find favour with the Jaina realist who scents mysticism in this defence. As regards appeal to the Upanisadic revelation the Jaina does not repudiate the validity of the Upanisadic text, but he has his own interpretation of the same which is radically different from that of the Vedantic monist. As a matter of fact, if we are to believe in the Jaina tradition as recorded in the authoritative works', Mahavira himself accepts the Upanisad as an authoritative declaration of ultimate truth. This tradition has paramount significance both to the orthodox adherents of the Jaina faith and to those of the Vedic school. We have not found a single text in the religious and philosophical literature of the Buddhists which accepts the validity of the Vedic revelation in any form or shape. Of course, Mahavira and his followers have condemned the sacrificial religion of the Vedas which accepts and approves animal slaughter as a religious act. But not only the Buddhists and the Jainas are sceptical of the purity of animal sacrifice but also the Sankhya-Yoga school explicitly denounces animal sacrifice as an act of demerit. In the Upanisads also we find denunciation of sacrificial religion as a vehicle of salvation. Of course the orthodox exponents 1 Cf. ViBh, 1596-1603. xxvii Page #29 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ xxvii INTRODUCTION of Vedanta do not regard animal sacrifice as enjoined in the Vedic rites as positively sinful. But they frankly and unreservedly assert that there can be no hope of salvation through performance of sacrifices alone. The renunciation of the world and of the sacrificial religion in the life of a recluse is emphasized as the sole means of cultivating the spiritual perfection which will put an end to worldly life by ushering in final realization of the ultimate truth. We need not be surprised at the denunciation of Vedic ritualism by Mahavira or the Buddha if we can put up with the unequivocal condemnation of Vedic ritualism in the Bhagavadgita. The highest spiritual life is abhorrent of inflicting slightest injury on life and this is happily the unanimous decision of the Upanisads and of Mahavira and of the Buddha. I have been drawn, in the fourth chapter, to a discussion of the Jaina theory of karman which is a highly complicated doctrine with its peculiar conception and interminable shades of difference in the working out of its details. The belief in the inevitability of the Law of Karman is rather common to all schools of Indian philosophy. It rests upon the fundamental ethical belief of moral responsibility of a living being. It is the prerogative of human life that it has the opportunity to get rid of the burden of the heritage of karman which it has acquired from beginningless past. Though the Jaina conception of karman as a physical substance and the theory of the influx and eflux of karmic matter is entirely different from that of the other schools, its difference with regard to the results as psychical and ethical forces is not essential from that of the other schools. It must be admitted that the Jaina theory is highly elaborate and logically consistent. Although several writers such as Dr Glasenapp and before him Mr V. R. Gandhi have written on the Jaina theory of karman, a philosophical presentation of this important doctrine was a desideratum. Apart from the importance and interest of the Jaina theory of karman by itself for a student of Jaina thought I was impelled to embark upon the subject in order to make the Jaina theory of avidya intelligible and complete. It was found in the discourse on Jaina conception of avidya that it was bound up with the doctrine of karman. Jaina avidya is the outcome of karmic veil. And so I had to deal with this important ethico-philosophical doctrine as a matter of internal necessity. Once drawn into the subject I could not avoid going into the essential and salient features of the doctrine though the treatment of the details might have an extra-logical look in it. But as the doctrine is very little known to students of other branches of philosophy and the presentment of it in Mr Gandhi's work is rather popular, and scrappy in Dr Glasenapp's thesis, and in view of the possibility of this respectable theory being misunderstood as a crudity or oddity, my treatment ought to be regarded as a contribution of some philosophical value. Page #30 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION xxix I had to cut through the maze of the tangled literature on karman and had to size it up and present it in a logical shape. A curious student who may feel impelled to pursue the study of this doctrine in Jaina literature will, I hope, now start with a clear perspective which will lighten his labour and save him from confusion of issues of which there is every risk in the unaided study of the original literature. My last chapter is on yoga. Yoga affirms its faith in the direct realization of the ultimate secrets of existence and the possibility of its achievement for a human being. It may savour of mysticism. But it is mysticism in the noble sense of the term and not in the sense of an illogical or anti-intellectual dogmatic assertion of a fact. Philosophy must culminate in the conviction of truth. But the intellectual resources that are given to a human being, though a valuable possession and asset in the progress of higher life, are found to be inadequate at the end of the journey. Philosophy may give us at best an intellectual conviction which is not and cannot be a substitute for direct intuition. The great teachers of India have unwaveringly affirmed their faith in direct intuition. This direct intuition is transcendental because it emerges only after the senses have exhausted their functions. The Jaina believes that our senses are rather hindrances to the realization of full truth. The knowledge that is achieved by means of the senses is mediate and indirect. The senses are more or less barriers standing between the knower and the truth to be known. Our empirical knowledge including that afforded by reason is bound to be hazy, indistinct and remote, beause the self does not envisage the reality as it is face to face. Besides, our senses do not give us a complete picture of the truth but rather, like a prism, they give us a distorted and blurred view. According to the Jaina philosopher consciousness is not a factitious product. It is innate in us and the fact that consciousness comes in contact with reality through a medium and in a graduated scale is rather an accident and a limitation. The power is there, and once the barrier between the conscious knower and the object is removed the full and complete knowledge of reality is bound to materialize. The Jaina has shown and other philosophers may agree that our imperfection of knowledge is the direct consequence of our ethical imperfection imposed by the accumulated burden of karman inherited by the self. The self only inherits what it has acquired in the past. This inheritance, call it karman or avidya or the Original Sin, has got to be done away with. The best and surest means is ethical perfection and perfect knowledge which can be acquired by a course of spiritual discipline as prescribed by the yogic process. It will be unscientific attitude to condemn it a priori. It stands as a challenge and as an exhortation to make the experiment and to test Page #31 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ XXX INTRODUCTION its validity or otherwise. One thing should be a warning against cheap complaisance of attitude and frivolous dismissal of this time-honoured discipline. It is this that the greatest teachers of mankind have pursued it and extolled it and it will be boldness in excelsis to look upon these persons as cranks and faddists. Whatever might be the opinion of a modern scholar he ought to have the charity to accept my treatment as a methodological necessity in order to complete my study of the Jaina philosophy. I do not pretend to be the original promulgator of this doctrine but rather an exponent of it. One thing I may claim to have done. It is this that I have shown how the Jaina conception of yoga is in perfect agreement and harmony with the system which was elaborated by Patanjali. This should be regarded as a welcome addition to our knowledge. Patanjali's philosophy is more or less widely known. The Jaina system of yoga is little known to the modern student and it was an agreeable surprise to me when I found in the course of my study the points of agreement which it presented to the yogic discipline as expounded by Patanjali and the Buddhists. I thought it would be an unpardonable act of dereliction on my part if I withheld the results of my study of this interesting side of Jaina philosophy from the modern student out of fear for being misunderstood. I now present the results of my prolonged study to the scholars who are interested in philosophical speculations for what they are worth. I felt the need of interpreting the ancient philosophy of the Jainas to the modern mind in a modern language and a modern way. I however assure the reader who will honour my humble contribution with a perusal that I have been scrupulously faithful to the masters whose thoughts I present in this book. In this connection I feel called upon to make a full acknowledginent of my deep gratitude and obligation to my gurus Pandit Sukhlalji Sanghavi and Professor Dr Satkari Mookerjee, to whom this work is dedicated, for the unfailing light and guidance received from them during my studies of the original texts and in the composition of the work. I must also place on record my obligation to my friend Pandit Dalsukh Malvaniya of the Banaras Hindu University who has helped me with suggestions and discussion of texts and problems. I am also indebted to Professor Rev. Bhikkhu J. Kashyap, M.A., with whom I read the Pali Tripitaka and the Abhidhamma system of philosophy, for the illuminating guidance I received from him at Banaras. I take this opportunity of making an acknowledgment of my debt to the departed savant the late Mahamahopadhyaya Phanibhusana Tarkavagisa who inspired me for the study of Indian philosophy and put me on the right track by placing me at the feet of Pandit Sukhlalji Page #32 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION Sanghavi. It is my misfortune that I cannot make a present of my book to him in this world. It was he who advised me to take to the study of Indian philosophy and predicted my success in this field. I was further fortunate to receive unbounded favour from the great savant Mahamahopadhyaya Dr Gopinath Kaviraj, M.A., D.Litt., the late Principal, Government Sanskrit College, Banaras, who read my work in manuscript and whose suggestions have led to the considerable improvement of my work. I refrain from the futile attempt to praise him as no praise can be adequate and on the contrary it is bound to result in belittling his unimaginable intellectual and spiritual majesty which strikes awe in a scholar who has received instruction from him. My debt of gratitude has incalculably increased on account of his favouring this humble work with his learned Foreword. To Professor Dr P. L. Vaidya, M.A., D.Litt. (Paris), Mayurbhanj Professor and Head of the Department of Sanskrit, Banaras Hindu University, I owe a tremendous obligation for the encouragement I received from him. I have always found in him the good Samaritan whose robust goodness had instilled courage into me when my spirits were drooping. He is to me the pattern of a combination of benevolence and scholarship, which is unfortunately becoming rare in these days. To Sir Sarvapalli Radhakrishnan to whom students of philosophy look forward as the beacon light and perennial source of inspiration, the author feels himself bound by an indissoluble tie of gratitude for an act of supreme justice which was conferred by him upon the author in the usual course of his duties as the judge of the merit of all philosophical works. I shall be failing in my duty and guilty of unpardonable ingratitude if I let slip this occasion of placing on record my debt of gratitude to the late Babu Bahadursingh Singhi, the great patron of scholars, who gave me all encouragement for the prosecution of my studies of Jaina philosophy at Banaras under the fostering care and guidance of Pandit Sukhlalji Sanghavi. The author cannot find suitable language to express his gratefulness to the two large-hearted benefactors of Jaina culture Sri Rajendrasingh Singhi, B.Com., and Sri Narendrasingh Singhi, M.SC., LL.B., M.L.A., the Singhi brothers, who are worthy sons of the worthy father, for the immense goodwill and patronage which the author has been receiving at their hands without ceasing. A formal expression of gratitude will be too cold an affair in the context of cordial relationship and intimacy which subsist between them and the author. xxxi I must here express my gratefulness to Dr Syamaprasad Mookerjee who bestowed the P. C. Nahar Research Fellowship upon me when he was the President, Post-Graduate Councils in Arts and Science, Calcutta University. I should also offer my thanks to the authorities Page #33 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ xxxii of the Jain Cultural Research Society, Banaras, for the award of the Punamchand K. Kotawala Research Fellowship which enabled me to complete my work, and also for the provision they made. for its publication. I am also much indebted to my esteemed friend Pandit Narendrachandra Vedantatirtha, M.A., Lecturer in Sanskrit, Calcutta University, for his kindly revising the proofs of this work. Singhi Park CALCUTTA 19 31 October 1951 INTRODUCTION PRONUNCIATION The vowels in Sanskrit are the same as in Italian, except that the sound of a approaches that of a in rural, and a that of a in father. A vowel with a bar (-) above it is long; r. are respectively pronounced as ri, li. The consonants are almost as in English, except that g is always hard and the sound of c approaches that of ch in church; t, d etc. (indicated by a dot below) are cerebrals and are the same as t in turn, d in drum, and so on; t, d, n are pure dentals; the aspirated letters kh, gh, ch etc. have the sound of the first letter plus an aspiration; n is like n in sing; n is like n in tinge; is like s in sure; h is a pure aspirate; m is the symbol of a nasal. For the convenience of the general reader the Sanskrit alphabet along with their transliterations are given below. aa, Aa, ii, la!, ee, kak, ca C, zt, t, paP, y y, v v, kha kh, ch, th thath, ph, r r, zU 5, Vowels I, uu, ai ai, o 0, Consonants Ig, ja j, 3d, ad, a b, l 1, S s, m or m, gh, jh, dh, dhU dh, bh, bhU La 1, s s, h. U, au au. n, n, n, nU n, m, NATHMAL TATIA lh, Eh, I, Page #34 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ ABBREVIATIONS ADv Anuyogadvara Sutra (Vijayakamala Surisvara Jaina Series No. 1). AMi Apta-mimamsa (of Samantabhadra with Astasati and Astasahasri, NSP, 1915). ANi Anguttara-Nikaya (PTS). ANir Avasyaka-Niryukti (Vijayadana Surisvara Jaina Granthamala No. 16). AS Agamasastra (of Gaudapada, ed. MM. V. Bhattacharya, Calcutta University, 1943). Astasahasri Vide AMi. Astasati Vide AMi. ASu Acaranga Sutra. AYV Anya-yoga-vyavacchedika (of Acarya Hemacandra). BAP Bodhicaryava tara-Panjika ed. Poussin, Bibliotheca Indica. BhGi Bhagavadgita. BhSu Bhagavati Sutra. BIUp Behadaranyaka Upanisad. BS Brahmasutra. BSSBh Brahmasutra-Sankara-Bhasya (with Bhamati, Kalpataru and Parimala, NSP, 1938). Buddhist Philosophy of Universal Flux By Prof. Dr Satkari Mookerjee, M.A., Ph.D. (Calcutta University, 1935). ChUp Chandogya Upanisad. Dhyanasa taka By Jinabhadra with Haribhadra's commentary. (Sri Vinaya bhaktisundaracarana Granthamala No. 3, Jamnagar). DN. Digha-Nikaya (PTS). DOK The Doctrine of Karman in Jaina Philosophy by Dr H. Von Glasenapp. (Published by the Trustees, Bai Vijibai J. P. Charity Fund, Bombay, 1942). Dravyasangraha By Nemicandra Siddhanta-cakravartin with the Vrtti of Brahmadeva. (The Sacred Books of the Jainas. Vol. I, Arrah). DV Nir Dasavaikalika-Niryukti. HIP A History of Inclian Philosophy (Vol. I) by Dr S. N. Dasgupta. First Edition: IP Indian Philosophy, Vol. I (1929), Vol. II (1931), by S. Radhakrishnan. TUp Isa-Upanisad. Jaina Philosophy of Non-absolutism By Prof. Satkari Mookerjee, M.A., Ph.D. JBP Jnana-bindu-prakarana (of Upadhyaya Yasovijaya, Singhi Jain Series No. 16). Jnanabindu Jnanabinduprakarana. Vide JBP above. Jnanarnava By Subhacandra. (Sri Rayacandra Jaina Sastramala No. 5. 7, 9 bound together, 1927). JTBh Jaina-tarka-bhasa (of Upadhyaya Yasovijaya, Singhi Jain Series No. 8). Ka Karika. KaUp Katha Upanisad. kg! Karmagranthas I to IV of Devendrasuri with his own commentary on I, II and IV, the commentary on III being by somebody else. Atma nanda Jaina Granthamala No. 85. Kg2 Karmagranthas V and VI. The former is the work of Devendrasuri with his own commentary while the latter is a work of Ciratnaparamarsi with the Vivarana of Malayagiri. Atmananda Jaina Granthamala No. 86. JP_E Page #35 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ xxxiv ABBREVIATIONS Kp Karmaprakrti with Curni and the commentaries of Malayagiri and Upadhyaya Yasovijaya (1937). [Upa - Upasamanakarana]. KSS Kashi Sanskrit Series. KSTS Kashmir Series of Texts and Studies. KUp Kena Upanisad. On p.114 (footnote) KUp refers to Katha Upanisad. Katha-vatthu. KV LA Lankavatara Sutra (ed. Bunyiu Nanjio, Kyto, 1923). Labdhisara By Nemicandra Siddhantacakravartin. mala No. 8, NSP, 1916. LT Laghiyastraya (Singhi Jain Series No. 12). Mahayana-vimsika By Nagarjuna ed. V. Bhattacharya. Rayacandra Jaina Sastra MK Madhyamaka-karika (ed. Poussin). MKV Madhyamaka-karika-Vrtti of Candrakirti ed. Poussin, Bib. Budh. MNi Majjhima-Nikaya (PTS). MuUp Mundaka Upanisad. MVS Madhyanta-vibhaga-sutra (of Maitreyanatha, vide MVSBhT). MVSBh Madhyanta-vibhaga-sutra-Bhasya (of Vasubandhu, vide MVSBhT). MVSBhT Madhyanta-vibhaga-sutra-Bhasya-Tika (of Sthiramati, ed. V. Bhattacharya and G. Tucci, 1932). Nandivrtti By Malayagiri (Srimati Agamodaya Samiti, Bombay, 1924). NBh Nyayasutra-Bhasya of Vatsyayana. NBhV Nyayasutra-Bhasya-Varttika of Uddyotakara. Niyamasara By Kundakundacarya. (The Sacred Books of the Jainas, Vol. IX, Lucknow, 1931). NKC Nyaya-kumuda-candra of Prabhacandra, Manik Chandra Digambar Jain Granthamala No. 38-39. NM Nyayamanjari of Jayanta (KSS No. 106, 1936). NS Nyaya-Sutra. NSP Nirnaya Sagar Press, Bombay. NSU Nandi-Sutra (ed. Hastimalla Muni, Candana Jainagama Granthamala No. 2). NSUVr Nandi-Sutra-Vrtti of Haribhadra (Ratlam, 1928). Pancastikayasara By Kundakundacarya (Sacred Books of the Jainas, Vol. III, Arrah, 1920). Paramatma-prakasa and Yogasara of Yogindudeva (Sri Rayacandra Jaina Sastramala No. 10, 1937 ed. A. N. Upadhye). PB Prasastapada-Bhasya (with Vyomavati and other commentaries, Chowkhamba Sanskrit Series, 1930). PBK Prasasta pada-Bhasya with Kandali (of Sridhara Bhatta ed. Pt. Vindhyesvariprasada, Kashi, V.S., 1951). PKM Prameya-kamala-martanda of Prabhacandra (NSP., 1941). PMi Pramana-mimamsa of Acarya Hemacandra (Singhi Jain Series). PNT Pramana-naya-tattvalokalankara of Vadi-Devasuri. Pratyabhijnahrdaya By Ksemaraja (KSTS, Vol. III). PrSu Prajnapana-Sutra. PS Pancasangraha (Upa Upasamanakarana). PTS Pali Text Society. PV Pramana-Varttika of Dharmakirti (ed. Rahula Sankrtyayana). RaP Raya-Pasenaiya-Sutta. SaBh Sabara-Bhasya. Samadhitantra By Pujyapada (ed. Jugalkishore Mukhtar, Sarsawa 1939).. Santiparva Mahabharata, Poona, 1932. Page #36 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ ABBREVIATIONS XXXV Sataratnasamgraha with Sataratnollekhani (Tantrik Texts Vol. XXII, Calcutta, 1944). Satkhandagama with Dhavala commentary, Amraoti, 1939. SBE Sacred Books of the East Series. SBh Sankara-Bhasya. SKa Sankhya-karika of Isvarakrspa. SNi Samyutta-Nikaya (PTS). SP Sodasaka-Prakarana of Haribhadra with Yasobhadra's tika, Jamnagar (V.S. 1992). SPB Sankhya pravacana-bhasya of Vijnanabhiksu. SS Siksasamuccaya ed. C. Bendall. Ssa Samksepa-Sariraka (of Sarvajnatmamuni, KSS No. 18, V.S., 1981). SSi Sarvarthasiddhi of Pujyapada Devanandi, a commentary on TSu. SthSu Sthananga-Sutra (Ahmedabad, 1937). STP Sanmati-tarka-prakarana of Siddhasena Divakara (vide STPT). STPT Sanmati-tarka-prakarana with (Abhayadevasuri's vyakhya called Tattva bodhavidhayini (Gujrat Puratattvamandira, Ahmedabad). Sukl Sutrakstanga. SUP, SyUp Svetasvatara-Upanisad. SVR Syadvadaratnakara of Vadi-Devasuri, a commentary on his own PNT. SVS Sastra-varta-samuccaya (of Haribhadra). Tantraloka By Abhinavagupta with commentary of Rajanaka Jayaratha, (KSTS, No. XXIII). Tk Trimsika of Vasubandhu (ed. Sylvain Levi in the Vijnaptimatratasiddhi, Paris, 1925). TKau Tattva-kaumudi of Vacaspati on SKa. TP Tattvaprakasa of Sri Bhojadeva with commentary of Srikumara (TSS, Vol. LXVIII). TRa Tattvartha-raja varttika (of Bhatta Akalanka, Kashi, 1915). TSIV Tattvartha-sloka-varttika of Vidyanandisvamin, NSP, 1918. TSN Tri-svabhava-nirdesa of Vasubandhu (ed. Sujit Kumar Mukhopadhyaya, Visvabharati, 1939). TSS Trivandrum Sanskrit Series. TSu Tattvarthadhigama-sutra of Umasvati (vide TSuBh). TSuBh Tattvarthasutra-Bhasya with Siddhasenaganin's Tika, 2 vols. (Seth Devchand Lalbhai Jain Pustakoddhara Fund Series No. 67 and 76). TUp Taittiriya-Upanisad.. UtSu Uttaradhyayana-Sutra. ViBh Visesavasyaka-Bhasya (with Sisyahita commentary. Yasovijaya Jaina Granthamala No. 35). Visuddhimagga By Buddhaghosacariya (ed. Dharmananda Kosambi, Part I, Bharatiya Vidya Bhavana, Bombay, 1940). VS Vaisesika-Sutra (of Kanada). V.S. Vikrama Samvat. YBI Yogabindu of Haribhadra (Jaina Grantha Prakasaka Sabha Series No. 25 Ahmedabad, 1940). YD Yogadarsana of Patanjali (KSS No. 110), containing Bhasya, Tattva vaisaradi, etc. YDS Yoga-drsti-samuccaya (ed. Prof. L. Suali, Ahmedabad, 1912). Yuktidipika A commentary on the Sarkhyakarika (Calcutta, 1938). YV Yogavinsika of Haribhadra with Yasovijaya's vyakhya, Agra, 1922. Page #37 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Page #38 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CHAPTER I THE NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS Culture presupposes history. Thought presupposes culture. Literature presupposes thought. Language helps thought and thought converts language into literature. Literature is the record of history, culture and thought. Ancient Indian literature, however, is more a record of culture and thought than a record of history. This is why we are comparatively in historical darkness about India. But as regards records of culture and thought, our heritage is second to none. Our Vedic literature can be considered as one of the richest that the ancients of the world could produce. It is a record of the Brahmanical culture and thought of India. Then there are the Buddhist Pitakas in Pali and Jaina Agamas in Prakrit, which are the records of quite a distinct current of culture which may be called Sramanic. These form the basis for the subsequent Brahmanical, Buddhist and Jaina literature that developed in many forms and constitutes today our rich literary heritage. We shall limit our attention only to the study of the philosophical attitude of the ancient thinkers whose experiences have been recorded in the Vedic literature, the Buddhist Pitakas and the Jaina Agamas. THE BRAHMANA ATTITUDE Speculation on the nature of the ultimate source of the universe is a common characteristic of human intellect. Kuta ajata kuta iyar visystih?!_From whence did it spring forth, from whence was born this creation? This is the question that stirs the mind of the sage (rsi) of the Nasadiya hymn. He starts with the assertion 'There was then neither what is not, nor what is',2 and then speculates whether there was deep abysmal water (ambhah kim asid gahanan gabhiram)? Philosophical misgivings overburden his heart and he says: 'There was no death, hence there was nothing immortal.'But he immediately reasserts 'That One breathed by Itself without breath, other than It there was nothing. There was absolute darkness and a sea without light. That One' was born by the power of austerity (tapas). "The sages (rsis), searching in their heart, discovered in non-existence 1 Rgveda, X. 129. 6. 2 na 'sad asin no sad asit tadanim-Ibid., X. 129. I. 3 Ibid., X. 129. 2. 4anid avatam svadhaya tad ekam tasmad dha 'nyan na parah kincana "sa.-Ibid. Page #39 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS (CH. the connecting bond of existence.' But again his mind is overwhelmed by doubts and he exclaims 'Who then knows, who has declared it here, from whence was born this creation? The gods came later than this creation, who then knows whence it arose? He from whom this creation arose, whether he made it or did not make it, the highest seer in the highest heaven, he forsooth knows, or does even he not know?'2 Doubt is the starting point of philosophy. Out of the fulness of the heart comes the assertion 'That One breathed by itself without breath' (anid avatar svadhaya tad ekam). But the human intellect is too weak to grasp the truth. It falls into the clutches of doubt in moments of weakness. The sage rejects the existent (sat) or the non-existent (asat) as the ultimate source of the universe and his heart finds solace in asserting 'That One' which 'breathed though breathless' (anid avatam). His deep spiritual experience manifests itself in self-contradictory expressions and points to the fact that the ultimate reality is inexpressible (anirvacaniya). In this famous hymn we can thus discern three distinct ways of speculation about creation viz. (1) that which bases it on existence (sat), (2) that which bases it on non-existence (asat), and (3) that which regards the ultimate source as inexpressible (anirvacaniya). Of these, the first two are rejected as untenable. The universe did not come out of what we call existent (sat) or what we call non-existent (asat), but out of 'The One' which cannot be expressed in words. How can something come out of the Nought? How can we believe that 'In the earliest age of the gods, the existent sprang from the non-existent'? Is it not, again, unmeaning to say that the existent came out of the existent? What then is the solution of the mystery of existence? This is the question that demanded solution from the seer. The answer comes forth from the depth of his heart though his mind still remains embarrassed. The selfsame question arises in the mind of yet another sage who asks 'Who has seen the first-born, when he that had no bones bore him that has bones? Where is the life, the blood, the self of the universe? Who went to ask of any who knew?' He finds his questions answered in the realization 'The real is One, the learned call it by various names, Agni, Yama and Matarisvan.'s In the Upanisads we find these speculations in more concrete forms. Sometimes we find that Non-being (asat) was the source of 1 sato bandhum asati niravindan htdi pratisya kavayo manisa.-Rgveda, X. 129. 4. 2 Ibid., X. 129. 6-7 as translated by Max Muller. 3 devanam purvye yuge 'satah sad ajayata.--Ibid., X. 72. 2. * Ibid., I. 164. 4. 5 ekam sad vipra bahudha vadanti agnim yamam matarisvanam ahuh-Rgueda, I. 164. 46. Page #40 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE BRAHMANA ATTITUDE Being. In the beginning this was non-existent. From it was born what exists.' In the Brhadaranyaka also we find 'In the beginning there was nothing here whatsoever. By death indeed all this was concealed.'2 Again, in the same Upanisads, we find that Being (sat) is the ultimate source of existence. How can existence come out of the Nought? 'In the beginning, my dear, there was that only which is, one only, without a second. Others say, in the beginning there was that only which is not, one only, without a second ; and from that which is not, that which is was born. ' But how could it be thus, my dear?' the father continued. 'How could that which is be born of that which is not? No, my dear, only that which is was in the beginning, one only, without a second.'3 Without going into further details which can be found lucidly delineated elsewhere we can sum up our enquiry thus: There was controversy regarding the exact nature of the ultimate source of creation, and that some thought it to have come out of Non-being or Nothing while others conceived it to have originated out of Being. There is of course controversy regarding the interpretation of Non-being' (asat). According to Sankara, it means, 'what is opposite of one defined by particular name and form'," in one word, what is undefined. "Non-being', according to him, refers to Brahman in its primary unrevealed state. But if this interpretation is correct, what is the necessity of the refutation of the theory 'In the beginning there was that only which is not,'s which we have quoted above? It is more on the side of fact to admit that there were originally two separate and mutually contradictory ways of thought which were reconciled or rather reinterpreted into a third which regarded reality as inexpressible (anirvacaniya). This third speculation is found in such passages as 'He who knows the bliss of that Brahman, from whence all speech, with the mind, turns away unable to reach it, he never fears.'s 'The eye does not go thither, nor the organ of speech, nor mind. We do not know, we do not understand, how anyone can teach it. It is different from the known, it is also above the unknown, thus we have heard from those of old, who taught us this. That which is not expessed by speech and by which l asad va idam agra asit. tato vai sad ajayata.-TUP. II. 7; also see CHUP. III. 19. I. 2 I. 2. I. CUP, VI. 2. 1-2. SBE translation. . Cf. asad iti vyakrta-nama-rupa-visesa-viparitarupam avikstam brahmo 'cyate-SBh on TUP. II. 7; also, asad avyakrta-namarupam-SBh on ChUp, III. 19. I. s asad eve 'dam agra asit. 6 yato vaco pivartante aprapya manasa saha anandam brahmano vidvan na bibheti kadacana.---TUP. II. 4. Page #41 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS [CH. speech is expressed, that alone know as Brahman, not that which people here think." We have found the seed of such speculation in the Nasadiya hymn of the Rgveda. The thinkers of the Upanisads have given it a concrete shape. Later on this became a theory and as such had a deep influence on the development of the philosophical thought of India, Brahmanical, Buddhist as well as Jaina. This will be apparent in the course of our study. There is a gradual development in the philosophical attitude of the sages of the hymns and the thinkers of the Upanisads. The various Vedic gods coalesce into One Sat (Absolute)." Gradually this Sat replaces the conception of fire (tejas), water, ether (akasa) etc. as the ultimate elements of creation. It is now regarded as the material as well as the efficient cause of the universe. This Sat is infinite, eternal and immutable. It is conscious according to the interpretation of Sankara. It is ubiquitous, immortal and unchanging. The universe which has sprung forth from It is finite, transitory and mutable. The finite self is mortal and changing. The doctrine of transmigration or rebirth also can be traced in the Vedic hymns. The Vedic people had a belief in the existence of the soul (atman) as distinct from the body, which after death goes to the other world to reap the fruits of its action. In the Upanisads, however, we find a clear development of the doctrine, although even there it is not as developed as with the Buddhists and the Jainas. There are scholars who think that the Vedic Aryans had no special doctrines about life after death and that the suggestions of the conceptions of karman and rebirth belonged to the aboriginal Indian thinkers who had their own distinct culture and philosophy, the remnants of which can still be traced in the non-Brahmanical systems of Jainism and Buddhism. But were original promulgators and systematizers of Buddhist and Jaina doctrines non-Aryans? From tradition we have it that the original Tirthankaras and the Buddhas were Ksatriya princes who were as influential a part of the Aryan community as the Brahmins were. The complex doctrine of karman, which is the exponent of ethical freedom of the will and is derived from the theory of law of causation as applied in the moral field, is the outcome of vigorous philosophical thought. We do not find in the autochthonous aboriginal 4 1 KUp, I. 3. 2 Cf. ekam sad vipra bahudha vadanti.-Rgveda, I. 164. 46. 3 BrUp, VI. 2. 16. 4 Cf. 'The references to transmigration which have been seen in the Rgveda are all of the most improbable character: it is to ignore the nature of poetry to press the wish that there may be long life for man among the gods into the view that it contemplates rebirth...... .-A. B. Keith: The Religion and Philosophy of the Veda and Upanishads (Harvard Oriental Series, Vol. 32), P. 570. Page #42 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE BRAHMANA ATTITUDE races of India, who are still alive, any developed philosophical doctrine about moral responsibility which is the foundation of the doctrine of karman. It is entirely speculative to seek to affiliate this important doctrine, which has been the universal principle of all systems of thought, to non-Aryan sources. The development of the doctrine is the work of the Aryan mind and there is no evidence to show that it was borrowed from others. In the philosophical hymns of the Vedas we find highly developed metaphysical conceptions, which have been gathered up into the later speculations. These have been the starting point and fountain of philosophical thought in India. Until indubitable crucial evidence be forthcoming it is safe to hold that the Aryan mind developed these philosophical theories under the stress of circumstances and the urge of the human intellect to find an explanation of the mysteries of the universe. It is safer still to suspend one's judgment about the original source. To assert even tentatively that the theory of rebirth and the law of karman were the invention of the non-Aryans smacks of dogmatism. A developed theory of rebirth presupposes a developed theory of karman which again presupposes a developed ethical attitude. The conception of Rta in the Rgveda anticipates the Law of Karman and gives an idea of the ethical attitude of the Vedic people. It furnishes us with a standard of morality. Ordered conduct is called a true vow (vrata).' Punishment is invoked against a liar, an abuser, a thief, and an adulterer.2 Virtues and vices are distinguished. Of course, all this is only treated as a side issue. But it is not very difficult to find that the attitude of the Vedic people was as much ethical and religious as it was secular. They believed as much in the ethical values as in the secular attainments. There were sages among them who devoted their life exclusively to the attainment of spiritual enlightenment. It is, however, only in the Upanisads that a radical change takes place on a mass scale. The conception of the fivefold duties of man towards gods, seers (rsis), manes (pitys), men and lower creation was developed in the Brahmanas. It was, of course, in the Upanisads that the Aryan attitude becomes supremely ethical. It is here that the philosophical insight is wedded to ethical wisdom which gradually developed, as we TIP, Vol. I, pp. 109-110. 2 Cf. yo na pakena manasa sarantam abhicaste anstebhir vacobhih ye va bhadram dusayanti svadhabhih yo asvanam yo gavam yas tanunam ripuh stenah steyakId dabhram etu ni sa hiyatam tanva tana ca. --Rgveda, VII. 104. 8 et seq. Page #43 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 6 NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS (CH. have said, under the stress of circumstances and the urge of human intellect to find an explanation of the mysteries of the universe. It is here that the search for the covetable (preyas) completely surrenders to the search for the good (sreyas).' Philosophy illumines the goal while ethics shows the pathway leading to it. Philosophy leads to the identification of self with the Absolute (Brahman) which is Truth, Consciousness and Infinite.2 The ethical sense finds expression in such passages as 'He who forms desires (kama) in his mind, is born again through his desires here and there. But to him whose desires are fulfilled (paryaptakama) and who is conscious of the true Self (within himself) all desires vanish, even here on earth. The Self cannot be gained by Scripture (pravacana), nor by understanding (medha), nor by much learning (sruta). He whom the Self chooses, by him the Self can be gained. The Self chooses him (his body) as His own. Nor is that Self to be gained by one who is destitute of strength (balahinena), or without earnestness (pramadat), or without proper meditation (tapaso va 'py alingat). But if a wise man strives after it by those means (by strength, earnestness, and proper meditation), then his self enters the home of Brahman. When they have reached Him (the Self), the sages become satisfied with knowledge (nanatrptah), they have realized their Self (krtatmanah), their passions have passed away (vitaragah), and the are tranquil (prasantah). The wise, having reached Him who is omnipresent everywhere, devoted to the Self, enter into Him wholly.'s Desire (kama) has been laid down as the cause of rebirth. Scriptural knowledge, logical understanding and academic learning are rejected as the pathway to spiritual realization. Spiritual strength and vigour, constant vigilance and readiness, and renunciation and asceticism are given as the means to freedom. When freed, the self attains consummation of knowledge, realizes itself and becomes passionless and tranquil. "When thou hast surrendered all this, then thou mayest enjoy. Do not covet the wealth of any man'' _such is the ethical principle of the Upanisads. Knowing Him, the Self (Atman), the Brahmins relinquish the desire for posterity, the desire for possessions, the desire for worldly prosperity and go forth as mendicants.'s Spiritual emancipation (moksa) means identification of the self with the Brahman. In the famous passage of the Byhadaranyaka Upanisad, Yajnavalkya describes to his wife Maitreyi the nature of the released soul as one with the highest reality and being not definable in terms of anything else." Emancipation (moksa) is as indefinable and ineffable as the Brahman, inasmuch as the former is nothing but the realization of the latter. 1 Cf. KaUp, II. 2. ? Cf. satyam jnanam anantam brahma-TUP, II. 1. 9 MuUp, III. 2. 2-5. SBE translation (slightly modified). * IUP, I. 5 ByUp, III. 5. I. IV. 5. 15. 7 Sir S. Radhakrishnan: Gautama the Buddha, p. 57. Page #44 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ TAE BUDDHIST ATTITUDE To sum up: The Vedic thinkers speculated in more than one way on the ultimate source of the universe-some regarded Sat as the ultimate source, some derived existence from Non-existence, and yet a third group regarded ultimate reality as indefinable. Gradually polytheism gives place to monotheism and monotheism is replaced by monism. Speculation and realization move hand in hand. When logic contradicts itself, spiritual realization comes to its help. Ultimate reality is conceived as Truth, Consciousness and Infinite. Conceptions of karman and rebirth were systematized in the Upanisads. Originally the Aryan attitude was more metaphysical than ethical. It becomes supremely ethical only in the Upanisads. Asceticism asserts itself at this stage. The conception of spiritual emancipation (moksa) finds importance in the Upanisads. The state of release is as indefinable as the ultimate reality. The world that we see is the world of change. It is finite existence, Pure Consciousness alone is real. It is eternal and infinite. It is unchanging. Our empirical self is finite and changing. The real self which is Brahman is infinite and unchanging. It is consciousness. It is bliss. It is to be noticed in this connection that these speculations did not take the shape of rigid theories. They were only free and supple soarings of the philosophical minds. It is only in the hands of later thinkers that they crystallized into rigid doctrines which were in vogue at the time of the Buddha and Mahavira. We shall now see how these problems were tackled by these two great personalities. THE BUDDHIST ATTITUDE The attitude of the Buddha was out and out rationalistic. He is reported once to have said to the Kalamas: "This I have said to you, O Kalamas, but you may accept it not because it is a report, not because it is a tradition, not because it is so said in the past, not because it is given from (our) basket (or scripture, bitaka). not for the sake of discussion, nor for the sake of a particular method, nor for the sake of careful consideration, nor for the sake of the forbearance with wrong views, nor because it appears to be suitable, nor because your preceptor is a recluse, but if you yourselves understand that this is so meritorious and blameless, and when accepted, is for benefit and happiness, then you may accept it.' He used also to say to his disciples that in ascertaining truth A Bodhisattva rests on reasons (yukti-sarana) and not 1 ANi, Part I, III. 65. 14. PTS. Also Cf. ta pac chedac ca nikasat suvaranam iva panditaih pariksya bhiksavo grahyam madvaco na tu gauravat. -nanasara-samuccaya. 31. Page #45 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 8 NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS (CH. on a person (pudgalasarana) though things might be explained by an Elder (sthavira), or an experienced man, or Tathagata or the Order (sangha). Thus resting on reason and not on a person he does not move away from the truth, nor does he follow the faith of others.'1 We have referred to the theories that were prevalent and much discussed among thinkers before the advent of the Buddha. The Buddha considered the following problems as unexplainable (avyakata) and refused to answer them either in the affirmative or in the negative: whether the world is eternal or the world is not-eternal ; whether the world is finite or the world is infinite ; whether the soul and the body are identical or they are different ; whether the Tathagata (soul) exists after death, or he does not exist after death, or whether the Tathagata both exists and does not exist after death, or whether the Tathagata neither exists nor does not exist after death. All these questions are not answerable. There are four kinds of questions: (1) which are ekamsa-vyakaraniya, i.e., answerable with certainty or categorically, e.g., "Will every one who is born die?' 'Yes' is the reply ; (2) vibhajya-vyakaraniya, that which is to be explained by making a division, e.g., 'Is every one reborn after death?' The reply is: 'One free from passions (klesas) is not reborn, but one who is not so is reborn ;' (3) prati-pyccha-vyakaraniya, that which is to be explained by putting another question, e.g., 'Is man superior or inferior?' It is necessary here to ask: 'In relation to what?' 'If in relation to animals, he is superior. But if in relation to gods, he is inferior ;' (4) sthapaniya, that which is to be set aside, e.g., 'Are the skandhas (aggregates the same as the living being (sattva)?' This question is not to be answered. For, according to the Buddhists there is nothing known as a living being. And so the question is like the question : 'Is the son of a barren woman black or white?'3 If the question is based on the presumption of what is a fiction, it cannot be answered. It is a defect of metaphysics that, in most cases, it proceeds with absurd hypotheses. Take, for instance, the question of existence. The metaphysical attitude usually tries to imagine the origin of existence in non-existence on the analogy of the commonplace experience of creation. We usually experience that a thing which was non-existent comes into existence, or is brought into existence by some agent. This commonplace experience is responsible for our intellectual unrest which we seek to end by finding out in non-existence the seed of existence. This unrest leads us to metaphysics. Our logical sense finds self-contra i Bodhisattvabhumi, I. XVII ; The Basic Conception of Buddhism, pp. II-12. 2 See MNi, Culamalunkya Sutta 63; The Basic Conception of Buddhism, pp. 12-13 3 See The Basic Conception of Buddhism, pp. 18-19, as well as footnote to p. 19 for reference. Cf. YD, Bhasya IV. 33. Milindaprasna, IV. 2. 5. Page #46 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE BUDDHIST ATTITUDE diction in our imagining in non-existence the seed of existence, and consequently we reject the conclusion, and try to form another which is intended to be logically consistent. We now derive existence from existence. But at this stage we become conscious of the futility of our speculation, because we have reached just the point from which we started. The Buddha was conscious of the absurdity of a priori metaphysical speculations moving in a vacuum, and so rejected the metaphysical vagaries as unanswerable. We shall consider here some such problems and the Buddha's attitude towards them. Let us begin with Eternalism (Sassatavada). The Brahmajala Sutta assigns the origin of such doctrine to the development of the power of remembering the former births due to some spiritual advancement. Some again arrive at this theory by means of logic and reasoning. It is stated in the Majjhima Nikayae that the self (atta), according to the Eternalists (Sassatavadins), is the speaker, feeler, and enjoyer of the fruits of good and evil actions (kamma), is permanent (nicca), fixed (dhruva), eternal (sassata), unchangeable (aparinamadhamma), and is steadfast like the so-called eternal objects viz. the Sun, Moon, ocean, earth and mountain.3 Memory of the past is responsible for the idea of persistence or permanence. Abstract logic also sometimes leads to the same conclusion. According to the Ucchedavada (nihilism), on the other hand, the soul is believed to become extinct after death. The Buddha's attitude to these problems is clearly expressed in the following dialogue : Is sorrow, Gotama, due to oneself (sayamkatam?' Not so, O Kassapa.'-_Thus said the Lord. Is sorrow then, Gotama, due to another (parakatam)?' Not so, O Kassapa.'-Thus said the Lord. Is then this sorrow, Gotama, due to oneself as well as due to another?' Not so, O Kassapa.'-Thus said the Lord. Is then this sorrow, Gotama, neither due to oneself, nor due to another?' 'Not so, O Kassapa.'-_Thus said the Lord. "See Dr. N. Dutt's Early Monastic Buddhism, Vol. I, p. 49. 21, p. 8. 3 Dr. N. Dutt: Op. cit., p. 50. + Cf. 'Endow this mind with memory, and specially with the desire to dwell on the past ; give it the faculty of dissociating and of distinguishing : it will no longer only note the present state of the passing reality ; it will represent the passing as a change, and therefore as a constant between what has been and what is.'-Bergson: Creative Evolution, (1928 edition), p. 310. JP-2 Page #47 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 10 NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS (CH. Then the Buddha expounded the position in the following way: If he who suffers is the same as he who does, then, O Kassapa, it is admitted that the sorrow is due to one who was existent, and consequently the agent is admitted as eternal (sassata). If again someone does, and someone else suffers, then, O Kassapa, it is admitted that one suffers for what is done by another, and consequently the agent is admitted as extinct . (ucchedam etam). The Tathagata, O Kassapa, avoids both these ends and preaches the Law (dhammam) by adopting the middle course (majjhena). Avijja (ignorance) causes sankhara (tendencies), sankhara causes vinnanal (resultant consciousness) and so on. Thus originates this khandha (aggregate) of absolute sorrow. By the total cessation of ignorance tendencies (sankharas) cease. By the cessation of tendencies, vinnana (consciousness) ceases, and so on. Thus the khandha (aggregate) of absolute sorrow ceases (nirodho hoti).'2 The Buddha, consistently with his doctrine of the Middle Path, could not give his reply either in the affirmative or in the negative. For, if it were in the former it would be eternalism (sasvatavada), while in the latter it would be nihilism (ucchedavada). But he accepted neither of them, as his doctrine is free from both of them.3 The problem of finiteness and infiniteness of the world is also treated in the same way. It is also regarded as an unanswerable question. The problem arises in the mind due to the absurd presuppositions and imaginary constructions. The imagination gives various dimensions, finite and infinite, limited and unlimited, to the world and consequently our intellect forms various conceptions which do not deserve affirmation or negation. They are only fictions of the mind. The Buddha's attitude towards the problem of the relation of body (sarira) and soul (jiva) is revealed from the following di What, O Lord, is jaramarana (decay-and-death)? Whom again does this decay-and-death belong to?' It is not a proper question'--said the Lord. If one, O Bhikkhu, would ask "What is decay-and-death, and whom does this decay-and-death belong to?', and if one, O Bhikkhu, would ask 'Is decay-and-death different, and is one 1 patisandhivasena ekunavisatividham pavattivasena dvatimsavidham vipakacittam vinnanam nama--Abhidhammatthavibhavini-tika, Sinhalese edition, 1933, p. 134. 2 SNi, XII. 17. 7-15. Also see Madhyamakakarika, XII, I. 3 The Basic Conception of Buddhism, p. 15 and the footnotes. Page #48 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE BUDDHIST ATTITUDE it whom this decay-and-death belongs to also different?', both would mean the same thing, differing only in modes of . expression. If one, O Bhikkhu, were to maintain that the self is identical with the body, then there would be no use of endeavouring for release (brahmacariyavaso na hoti); and if one were to maintain that the self is different, and the body is different, then also, O Bhikkhu, there would be no use of endeavouring for release. Having avoided, O Bhikkhu, both these two extremes, the Tathagata preaches the Law by adopting the middle course--depending upon birth (jati paccaya) there is decay-and-death.'1 The self (or soul) is neither different from nor identical with the body. If it were accepted that the self is identical with the body, then it would mean that the self perishes along with the body. The consequence is unrelieved materialism (or nihilism) which implies all stop to all progress towards release. Again, if the soul were different from the body, decay-and-death would have no effect on the soul. The soul would always remain as it is. This will lead to eternalism which too puts stop to all endeavours for final release. This is the difficulty that led the Buddha to avoid both these extremes. The so-called self or the soul is, according to him, nothing but an aggregate of rupa {material form), Uedana (feeling), saja (perception), sanskara (coefficients of consciousness), and vijnana (consciousness) all of which are impermanent (aniccam), full of sorrow (dukkham) and not-self (anatta). This is beautifully expressed in the following dialogue : .... Now what do you think, O Susima, is the material form (rupam) permanent or impermanent?' Impermanent, O Lord.' But is that which is impermanent, sorrow or joy?' Sorrow, O Lord.' Now that which is impermanent, full of sorrow, and subject to change, is it proper to say of it, 'This is mine, this am I, this is my self?' Certainly not, O Lord.' In the same way the Buddha dealt also with the remaining four viz. vedana (feeling), sanna (perception), sankhara (coefficients of consciousness) and vinnana (consciousness). Then he said: Therefore, O Susima, all material forms, that had been in the past, that are to be in the future as well as that are at present, whether they be internal (ajjhattan) or external, gross or subtle, good or bad, near or distant-are not mine, are not myself, and are not my self. All this should be properly realized as such with true wisdom.' I SNI, XII. 35. 5. Page #49 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 12 NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS [CH. The Buddha then spoke the same thing of vedana (feeling), sanna (perception), sankhara (coefficients of consciousness), and vinnana (consciousness).' The so-called self here is demonstrated to be devoid of any essence. It is shown to dissolve into nothing. It is at best an aggregate of rupa (material form), vedana (feeling) etc. which never coalesce into one indivisible entity. The synthetic reference of our perceptions is responsible for the idea of an unchanging substance called soul. But, as has been shown above, there is nothing like soul or what belongs to soul. This leads to the finding that substance is an unreal fiction, in other words, the doctrine of sunna (voidity or substancelessness). This will be clear from the following dialogue : O Lord,' asked Ananda, 'It is said-void is the world, void is the world (sunno loka) --Why is it so said, O Lord, that the world is void.' * As, O Ananda, (all) this is devoid (sunnam) of self (attena) or what belongs to self (attaniyena va), so it is said that the world is void. What, Ananda, is devoid of self or what belongs to self? The cakkhu (eye), O Ananda, is devoid of self or what belongs to self. The rupas (objects of eye) are also devoid of self or what belongs to self. The cakkhu-vinnana (eyeconsciousness) is devoid of self or what belongs to self. The cakkhu-samphassa (eye-contact) is devoid of self or what belongs to self. . . Whatever feeling, pleasant or painful or neutral, that arises depending upon mano-samphassa (mindcontact), that is also devoid of self or what belongs to self. As, O Ananda, (all) this is devoid of self or what belongs to self, so is it said that the world is void.'? When there is no soul, how can there be what belongs to it? And therefore, the sense, the object, the sense-object contact and the resultant consciousness all these are devoid of essence and as such are void. They are only passing states. But it is absurd to ask 'Whose states?'-a question which it is very difficult to eradicate from the mind once for all. This tendency of the human mind lies at the back of the metaphysics of eternalism which the Buddha was determined to abolish. The word atta (Sanskrit atma), with the Buddha, means something absolutely permanent, immutable and eternal. It is this conception of atta that he rejected as absurd. 1 SNi, XII, 70. 32-42. 2 SNi, XXXV. 85 (2). Atta here may also be taken in the sense of svabhava 'nature'. Page #50 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE BUDDHIST ATTITUDE Now let us see what the Buddha spoke of nirvana (emancipation) from the following dialogue! : ... Does, O Lord, Tathagata exist after death?-asked King Pasenadi.. The question whether a Tathagata exists after death has been left avyakata (unexplained) by me, O Maharaja.' 'Does not then, O Lord, Tathagata exist after death?' 'This too viz. whether Tathagata does not exist after death has been left avyakata (unexplained) by me, O Maharaja.' 'Does then, O Lord, Tathagata both exist as well as not exist after death?' * This too ... has been left unexplained by me, O Maharaja.' Then said the King: What is, O Lord, the reason, what the cause of that being left avyakata (unexplained)?' I put, O Maharaja, this question to you yourself, you may answer as you think proper. What do you think, O Maharaja, have you got any such calculator (ganaka), cashier (muddika) or statistician (sankhayaka) as can count the grains of sand of the Ganges and say 'These grains are so many' ... or 'These grains are so many hundred thousands'?' 'Not certainly, O Lord.' 'Have you, again, got any such calculator, cashier or statistician as can measure the water of the great ocean, and can say 'This is equal to so many alhakas? of water'... or "This is equal to so many hundred thousand ashakas of water'?' Not certainly, O Lord. * What is the reason here?' Great indeed, O Lord, is the ocean, deep, immeasurable, unfathomable.' Exactly so, O Maharaja, that form (rupa) of Tathagata is totally annihilated, uprooted, made like a tala (palmyra) tree whose head is cut off (talavatthukatan), has gradually reached extinction (anabhavagatam), made incapable of growing again in future. Being free from the knowledge of rupa (form), O Maharaja, the Tathagata is deep, immeasurable and unfathomable like the great ocean. Thus it is not proper 1 SNi, XLIV. 1. 22-34. 2 One ashaka is equal to two maunds (Vide Monier-Williams' SanskritEnglish Dictionary). Page #51 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 14 NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS (CH. to say that the Tathagata exists after death ... nor is it proper to say that he does neither exist nor does not exist after death.' The Buddha spoke the same thing about the annihilation etc. of vedana (feeling), sanna (perception), sankhara (coefficients of consciousness) and vinnana (consciousness) of a Tathagata who, when freed from all these, becomes deep, immeasurable, unfathomable. This critical and rationalistic attitude of the Buddha towards metaphysical problems is responsible for the development in later times of a number of mutually conflicting metaphysical doctrines within the fold of Buddhism. The Buddha's attitude, however, was one of strict avoidance of all metaphysics which he considered as futile, because he held that one might die before one gets elucidation of these problems. Nor was there anything esoteric in his preaching. The Buddha, on his deathbed, is reported to have said to Ananda: I have preached the truth without making any distinction between exoteric and esoteric doctrine (anantaran abahiram katva) for, in respect of truth, Ananda, the Tathagata has no such thing as the closed fist of a teacher' who keeps some thing back."? The Buddha avoided the extremes because the admission of any one of the extremes would involve either nihilism or eternalism-either of which doctrines implies futility of endeavour for final release. The hypothesis of eternalism is as much inconsistent with the idea of final release as the hypothesis of nihilism. Eternalism implies inherent perfection while nihilism implies its impossibility. It is in order to avoid these two undesired consequences that the Buddha adopted the middle course and left these problems auyakata (unexplained). These were time-honoured problems and as such the dogmatic minds could not get rid of them. The absolutely rationalistic mind of the Buddha, however, found absurdities in them and completely got rid of them. The truth is too deep to get expression in words. Then there was every possibility of it being misunderstood. It is due to these reasons that the Buddha did not explain it. Whenever he was asked to explain the truth, he asked the enquirer to endeavour to see it for himself instead of knowing it from him. The truth cannot be expressed in language. It is to be realized. His refusal to explain does not mean that he upheld agnosticism, because he believed in realization and asked the enquirer to realize for himself. He characterized i See the Buddha's dialogue with Malunkaputta, MNi, 63. 2 DNI, II, p. 100 (PTS edition). DNi, II. p. 217 (PTS). See The Basic Conception of Buddhism, Pp. 23-24. 3 Ibid. Page #52 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE BUDDHIST ATTITUDE nirvana (emancipation) as deep, immeasurable and unfathomable and as such cannot be a nihilist. His attitude is one of a thorough rationalist who would refuse to enter into enquiries which were selfcontradictory on the face of it. To know from others what can only be realized by oneself is absurd. And to express in words what can only be felt is still more absurd. Thought and language have their own shortcomings. If we can think only in terms of subject-object or substance-quality relation, our language also, being only an expression of thought, cannot be free from these. It is the characteristic of our thought and language that they make immobile of what is mobile, static of what is dynamic, eternal of what is evanescent and fleeting. 1 This leads to eternalism. The other extreme is materialism which believes in death as total extinction of personality. It denounces all efforts for final release as absurd and irrational. Self-interest is the only thing worth pursuit. Absence of self-interest means absence of everything else. Annihilation of individuality means annihilation of all. If I cannot remember the past, the past is non-existent. If I cannot keep my individuality of this life intact after death, there cannot be anything beyond death. This is materialism. It can also be called nihilism. Extreme interest in individuality and gross selfishness is the spring of this attitude of mind. It is born of the total disregard of everything unselfish in our attitude. The Buddha avoided both these by keeping aloof from all dialectics. His dialogues are full of philosophical wisdom and quite immune from sophistry and cheap metaphysical quibbles. The Buddha's dharma (Law) is well said (svakkhato), the result of it can be realized in this world (sanditthiko), it is immediate (akaliko), it says 'come-and-see' (ehipassiko), it brings about nivvana or emancipation (opanayiko), it is to be realized by the wise in their own hearts (paccattam veditabbo vinnuhi). The Buddha's attitude was more ethical than metaphysical. Karman and rebirth were acknowledged as facts. They were axioms with the Buddha. His interest was riveted on finding out the pathway to freedom from this cycle of existence. Metaphysics is allowed as subservient to this end. Psychological analysis is more helpful for the purpose than metaphysical speculation. Suffering and sorrow are universal facts and every individual seeks redemption from them. The Buddha starts from these facts. Perpetual change is also given to our 1 Cf. 'Such is the first proceeding of our thought: it dissociates each change into two elements--the one stable, definable for each particular case, to wit, the Form ; the other indefinable and always the same, Change in general. And such, also, is the essential operation of language. Forms are all that it is capable of expressing. It is reduced to taking as understood or is limited to suggesting a mobility which, just because it is always unexpressed, is thought to remain in all cases the same.'-Creative Evolution pressed in touch to main in a Pp. 344-5. Page #53 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ [CH. NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS experience. Substance is merely a creation of the staticizing tendency of the human mind which itself, on analysis, is found to be nothing but an ever renewing aggregate of consciousness, feeling, perception (sanjna) and coefficients of consciousness (samskara). The evil passions of lobha (greed), dosa (aversion) and moha (delusion), which a human being shares in common with animals, constitute bondage of existence. Rational life is actuated by a-lobha (absence of greed), a-dosa (absence of aversion) and a-moha (absence of delusion). Emancipation means freedom from evil passions. Life, as it is, is an evil, and to get rid of evil is to get rid of life. In this context emancipation means freedom from all life. Faith in the continuation of pure. untainted consciousness after emancipation is as much a heresy as the faith in a permanent substance called soul (atma). With the cessation of the trsna (craving) ceases the vijnana (consciousness) even as the flame of a lamp is extinguished (by the exhaustion of oil, wick etc.).1 16 The Buddha expounded the four noble truths (cattari ariyasaccani) of sorrow (dukkha), causal chain of sorrow (dukkhasamudaya), cessation of sorrow (dukkha-nirodha) and the path leading to the cessation of sorrow (dukkha-nirodha-gamini patipada)." Birth, decay, disease, death, bewailings etc. are all nothing but sorrow. Non-fulfilment of desires also is sorrow. In brief, the aggregate of rupa (form), vedana (feeling) etc., that springs from strong attachment is sorrow. This is the first noble truth of sorrow. The causal chain of avidya (ignorance), samskara (tendencies), vijnana (consciousness) etc. explains the origin of the aggregate of sorrow. This is the second truth which finds out the original cause of this sorrowful existence. By the cessation of the cause, the effect naturally ceases. The second truth thus leads to the discovery of the third which is called dukkhanirodha (cessation of sorrow). When the cause is known, the effect can be eliminated by eliminating the cause. What originates must cease. If suffering is a fact and if it is determined by welldefined conditions, it goes without saying that there must be cessation of suffering. The third truth can thus be considered as only a corollary of the first two. The fourth truth lays down the path to freedom or emancipation. It is called the eightfold path (atthangiko maggo). It consists of right view (samma-ditthi), right resolution (samma-samkappo), proper words (samma-vaca), proper action (sammakammanta), proper means of livelihood (samma-ajiva), proper exertion (samma-vayama), mindfulness in the right way (samma-sati) and proper meditation (samma-samadhi). Of these the first two relate to 1 Cf. vinnanassa nirodhena tanhakkhayavimuttino pajjotasseva nibbanam vimokkho hoti cetaso ti. -ANI, III. 89. 2 (Pt. I, p. 236, PTS). 2 Ibid., III. 61. 6; et seq. Page #54 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE JAINA ATTITUDE 17 panna (wisdom), the next three to sila (good conduct) and the last three to samadhi (meditation). The Buddha gave equal importance to each of them. Abstinence from all evils, acquisition of the good, and purification of one's own mind this is the teaching of the Buddha.'1 Attachment and aversion obscure the good tendencies. It is because of this that the teaching (sasana)--though effectively expounded_has little influence on the mass mind. Self-interest has a blinding effect. It keeps us tied to the past and the static. The common mass rolls downwards. It is necessary to turn the face upward and go against the common flow. It is due to this difficulty that the Buddha hesitated to preach his dhamma (Law). The Buddha, after he had realized enlightenment (bodhi), is reported to have said to himself Now it is useless to proclaim what I have attained by strenuous effort, for this dhamma (Law) is not easily understandable by those who are sunk in attachment and aversion. This goes against the current, is subtle, deep, very difficult to realize and atomic. Those coloured with attachment and covered by mass of darkness will not see it.' But this hesitation did not last long. Immense love for the suffering humanity asserted itself and the Buddha heard the voice of Brahma (a god) 'Rise up, O valiant warrior, thou hast won the war and art free from debt. Travel now in the world. Let the Blessed One teach the dhamma (Law). There will be persons who will understand it.'3 Love (maitri), compassion (karuna), sympathetic joy (mudita) and indifference (upeksa) were predominant in his character THE JAINA ATTITUDE Before studying the attitude of Mahavira to the metaphysical problems, it will be helpful to begin with his attitude towards life. A major part of Mahavira's teaching was concerned with the appeal not to interfere with the lives of others. Sorrow and suffering were as much the facts with Mahavira as with the Buddha. To get rid of the cycle of worldly existence was the common end of both of them as of the Upanisa dic thinkers. The Buddha found everything impermanent and hence sorrowful and substanceless. But Mahavira's attitude was 1 sabbapapassa akaranam kusalassa upasampada sacitta pariyoda panam etam buddhana sasanam. -Dhammapada, 183 (XIV. 5). 2 kicchena me adhigatam halam dani pakasitum ragadosa paretehi nayan dhammo susambudho patisotagami nipunam gambhiram duddasam anum ragaratta na dakkhanti tamokhandhena avuta. -Mahavagga, I. 5. 3. 3 Utthehi vira vijitasargama satthavaha apana vicara loke desetu bhagava dhammam annataro bhavissanti. -Mahavagga, I. 5. 7. JP-3. Page #55 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 18 NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS (CH. not so radical. If the Upanisadic thinkers found the immutable reality behind the world of phenomena and plurality, and the Buddha denounced everything as fleeting and sorrowful and pointed to the futility of all speculation, Mahavira adhered to the common experience, found no contradiction between permanence and change and was free from all absolutism. Existence is not an evil by itself and so freedom does not mean total cessation of it. With the Upanisadic thinkers what is impermanent is sorrowful and only empirical. The reality therefore is what is permanent and blissful. With the Buddha also everything is impermanent and hence sorrowful and substanceless. Freedom, therefore, means total cessation. But Mahavira did not believe in absolute permanence or total cessation. If life were accepted as an illusory phenomenon, or if it were accepted as nothing but evil and suffering, absolute permanence or total cessation would be the truth or the desired goal. But with Mahavira change was as much real as. permanence, and so his position was quite distinct from those of the absolutists. Freedom means freedom from passions only. It is a qualitative change rather than total cessation. The preaching of ahimsa (non-injury) is the most important task of Mahavira's life. Feeling of immense respect and responsibility for life inspires his activities. Suffering is an evil, and to impose suffering is to impose evil. Unless and until we are conscious of the vicissitudes of the soul, its transmigrations, we are not on the proper path. One who is conscious of these facts is aya-vai (believer in soul), loga-vai (believer in the world), kamma-vai (believer in karman), and kiriyavai (believer in action). Repeated births are due to the ignorance of the nature of kamma (actions). Suffering is a fact which is too obvious to overlook. "The world is afflicted, decrepit, difficult to instruct, and ignorant. In this agonized world, see how the afflicted ones are causing pains, here and there, by various means.'3 Injurious activities inspired by self-interest lead to evil and darkness. This is what is called bondage (gantha), delusion (moha), death (mara), and hell (naraa).4 To do harm to others is to do harm to oneself. "Thou art he whom thou intendest to kill! Thou art he whom thou intendest to tyrannize over!'s We corrupt ourselves as soon as we intend to corrupt others. We kill ourselves as soon as we intend to kill others. Pramada (unmindfulness) and attachment to guna (sensuous objects) 1 ASu, I. I. I as explained by commentators. 2 Ibid. 3 Ibid., I. I. 2. 4 Ibid. 5 tumam si nama tam ceva jam 'hantavvam ti mannasi tumam si nama tam ceva jar 'ajjaveyavvam' ti mannasi. -Ibid., I. 5. 5. Cf. Your own self is your own Cain that murders your own Abel. For every action and motion of self has the spirit of Anti-Christ and murders the divine life within you. William Law. Page #56 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE JAINA ATTITUDE are the spring of violence. To remain attached to sensuous objects is to remain in the whirl.2 Sensuous objects are the root of worldly existence (samsara). The wise should not remain unmindful even for a single moment. The stupid (manda) and the deluded (mohena pauda) turn away from the right path, and do not cross on to either side. But those who cross conquer greed by contentment and are not influenced by objects of desire." Penance (tavo), restraint of mind (damo) and restrainment or moral observances (niyamo) are not possible for one having attachment to life and property. By nature are we fond of life and have repulsion for suffering. It is not possible to cross the ocean of worldly existence (sarsara) unless the animal instincts are subdued and destroyed. Perpetrators of cruel acts come to grief. They cannot cross the stream of evils (anohantara) and so cannot cross the samsara (world), and go to the other shore (atiramgama). The sense of 'mine' is an evil. One who relinquishes the sense of 'mine' relinquishes also the thing about which one feels that it is 'mine'. And one who does not possess anything regarded as 'mine' is a sage who has seen the (right) path.'? Property is an evil inasmuch as it cannot be had without causing suffering to others. The common man is asleep while the ascetic is always awake, sutta amuni munino sayayam jagaranti. He who knows the nature of the sensuous objects is possessed of self (aya=atman), knowledge (nana=jnana), Scripture (veda), Law (dhamma) and Truth (bambha = brahma). The man indeed has many thoughts.9 Anger, pride and greed are his enemies. 'The brave should destroy anger and pride. He should look upon greed as a great hell. The hero, therefore, should desist from killing, should give up the agreeable and should move being lightened (of the burden).'10 The responsibility of fall or rise rests on the man himself. "Man! Thou art thy own friend ; y wishest thou for a friend beyond thyself? Man! Restrain thyself, and thou shalt be free from sorrow.'11 The freed has destroyed all anger, pride, deceit and greed. This is the doctrine of the Seer. 1 Cf. je pamatte gunatthie se hu dande pavuccai.--Ibid., I. 1. 4. 2 je gune se avatte.--Ibid., I. I. 5. 3 je gume se mulatthane.--Ibid., I. 2. I. 4 dhire muhuttam avi no pamayae.--Ibid. 5 Ibid., I. 2. 2. 6 Cf. savve pana piyauya, suha-saya, dukkha-padikula. - Ibid., I. 2. 3. ? je mamaiya-maim jahai, se jahai mamaiyam se hu ditthapahe muni, jassa natthi mamaiyam. -Ibid., I. 2. 6. 8 Ibid., I. 3. I. 9 anega-citte khalu ayam purise-Ibid., 1. 3. 2. 10 kohaimanam haniya ya vire, lobhassa pase nirayam mahantam tamha hi vire virao vahao chindejja sayam lahubhuya-gami.-Ibid. 11 Ibid., I. 3. 3. Page #57 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS [CH. One who knows one thing knows all things, and one who knows all things knows one thing. The unmindful apprehends danger from all sides. The mindful has no danger from any quarter. He does not hanker after life.1 The wise, always mindful and cautious, exerts himself day and night." 20 What acts as cause of bondage (asava) in the case of one can act as the cause of release (parissava) for another and vice versa.3 It is our attitude that counts. The path of the brave is thorny (duranucaro). It involves mortification of the flesh. Desires prove heavy on the soul. They lead one to death. To go near death means to recede back from freedom. To the wise life is like a water-drop on the tip of a tossing leaf. It is the stupid who do cruel acts and keep tied to the cycle of births and deaths.5 One should not let one's strength remain concealed (no ninhavejja viriyam). Easy life is no life for a spiritual aspirant. For him dhamma (Law) means equanimity. 'What thou knowest to be equanimity (sammam), know that to be sagedom monam). What thou knowest to be sagedom, know that to be equanimity. It is inaccessible to the weak, sinning, sensual, illconducted and house-inhabiting men." The mind of a sage is like a calm and quiet lake full to the brim and lying on an even plane and free from all dust. Meditation is impossible for a wavering mind." Knowledge of the self and the world is necessary for release. The knower is the self. The self is that by which we know. The world is a whirlpool. 'The current (of sin) is said to come from above, from below, and from the sides; these have been declared to be the currents through which, look, there is sinfulness.'9 Liberation means freedom from the influence of these currents. It cannot be described by words. 'All sounds recoil thence. Where speculation has no room, the mind cannot penetrate there.'1o The liberated soul has no shape, no colour, no smell, no taste, no weight, no touch, no rebirth, no attachment. It is neither male, nor female, nor otherwise. There is no analogy. It is formless existence, aruvi satta.11 The Jainas, like other exponents of asceticism, endorse suicide in case the body fails to fulfil the demands of the spirit. Of course, 'suicide' is a misnomer for this kind of death. It is only an abandonment of the body unable to help the spirit in its progress. It is not under the pressure of passions that the death is to be courted. Freedom from passions is the prerequisite of this kind of voluntary death. Complete absence of ill will towards every living creature, and good will for all inspire the life and activities of a true ascetic. He 1 Ibid., I. 3. 4. 4 Ibid., I. 4. 4. 7 Ibid., I. 5. 5. 10 Ibid. 2 Ibid., I. 4. I. 5 Ibid., I. 5. I. 8 Ibid., I. 5. 5. 11 Ibid. 3 Ibid., I. 4. 2. 6 Ibid., I. 5. 3. 9 Ibid., I. 5. 6. Page #58 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE JAINA ATTITUDE 21 does neither covet life, nor does he desire death.Attachment to life is as much an evil as attachment to death. If life helps progress of the spirit, it is to be preserved. If by courting death spiritual fall can be checked, it is welcome. We have reviewed the Jaina position on the basis of the oldest extant record. The main emphasis of Jainism is on ahimsa, noninjury. This attitude of Jainism is more due to its rational consciousness than emotional compassion. It is not based on social fellow-feeling, but on individual responsibility. Jainism presumes infinite capacity for spiritual progress in every individual. Infinite knowledge and joy is the innate character of every soul. What is needed is complete non-interference from outside. Given freedom of development, every individual is bound to progress. Interference means spiritual iragging. A truth is not to be forced, but is only to be preached. Individual freedom is more helpful than social pressure. Spiritualism gives more importance to individual perfection than to social progress. Life is not for enjoyment but for exertion. Deep spiritualism was the characteristic of the age of Mahavira. It is not for an improved life that exertion is recommended. But it is for a transformed existence that penances are prescribed. Heaven is 'not the ideal. Freedom from worldly pleasures and sufferings is the end. The Jaina attitude is not in the least pessimistic. It is realistic and optimistic. Suffering is as much an evil as worldly pleasures. But voluntary suffering for the sake of radical transformation is preferable to worldly pleasures. Deep faith in spiritual freedom inspires selfimposed suffering. There is no description of the nature of freed existence. The end is not envisaged. The means stands justified by itself. This is the background whereupon the philosophical superstructure of Jainism was raised. In consistency with this background, a Jaina sadhu (monk) is required to be very cautious about his speech.2 He is prohibited against making unwarranted categorical assertions or negations.3 'A wise man should not joke, nor should he explain without resort to conditional expressions.' 'He should explain with the help of vibhajjavaya, conditional expressions.'s We have already referred to the vibhajya-vyakaraniyas problems of the Buddhists. This vibhajyavada was developed into a full-fledged philosophical doctrine by Mahavira. The non-violent and tolerant attitude of the Jainas was 1 jiviyam nabhikankhejja maranam no vi patthae.--Ibid., I. 8. 8. 2 See ASU, II. 4. 3 Ibid., II. 4. I with commentary thereon. 4 na ya 'vi panne paribasa kujja na ya 'siyavaya viyagarejja.-Sukl, I. 19. The commentary however gives a different explanation. s vibhajja-vayam ca viyagarejja--Ibid., I. 14. 22. 6 Supra, p. 8. DNi, Sangitipariyaya Sutta (No. 33), fourfold Prasnavyakarana. 14. Page #59 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 22 NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS [CH. responsible for their uttermost carefulness regarding speech which was required to be unassaulting as well as true. Only the merits of a fact should be stressed and not the demerits. One should not hurt the feelings of others. If there are different doctrines, there must be reasons for their origin. It is the duty of a patient thinker to find out the sources of these doctrines. Non-violent search for truth should inspire the enquiries of a thinker. He should not be prejudiced by preconceptions. It is this attitude of tolerance and justice that was responsible for the origin of the doctrine of Non-absolutism (Anekanta). Out of universal tolerance and peace-loving nature was born cautiousness of speech. Out of cautiousness of speech was born the habit of explaining problems with the help of siyavaya (=syadvada) or vibhajjavaya.' This habit, again, developed into a non-absolutistic attitude towards reality. Our thought is relative. Our expressions are relative. The whole reality in its completeness cannot be grasped by this partial thought or expression. Nor can it be comprehended by combining these thoughts or expressions. What is required is the radical change in our absolutistic attitude. The error lies with the attitude and not with the thought or expression. Attachment and repulsion are the two great enemies of philosophical thinking. A thinker should not be guided by abstractionist tendencies which are responsible for mutually contradictory systems of thought. These tendencies are born of predilections, more or less inherent. It is as much difficult to get rid of these predilections as to get rid of the other evils of life. Truth reveals itself to an impartial thinker. This origin of the doctrine of Anekanta can be clearly seen from a study of the solutions by Lord Mahavira of the problems which were left unexplained by the Buddha as stated above. Let us begin with the problem of eternalism. The Buddha avoided both eternalism (sasvata-vada) and nihilism (uccheda-vada). But Mahavira explained both these attitudes as real with reference to different aspects of the same reality. This will be clear from the following dialogue between Mahavira and his disciple Gautama : Are the souls, O Lord, eternal or non-eternal?' The souls, O Gautama, are eternal in some respect and noneternal in some respect.' With what end in view, O Lord, is it so said that the souls are eternal in some respect and non-eternal in some respect?' They are eternal, Gautama, from the view point of substance, and non-eternal from the view-point of modes. And with this end in view it is said, O Gautama, that the souls are eternal in some respect and non-eternal in some respect.'3 1 Cf. Haribhadra's Dharmasangrahani, gatha 921 (Bombay 1918 ed.). 2 Cf. Ibid., 925. 3 Bhsa, VII. 2. 273. Page #60 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE JAINA ATTITUDE 23 It is our common experience that things persist as well as cease to persist. But if we stick to one side of the experience and reject the other as an illusion, we are led to formulate absolutist doctrines of universal eternalism, and universal nihilism. The Buddha rejected both these ends and left the problem unexplained. Mahavira accepted both the ends and explained the puzzle as originating from different mental attitudes, fostered by interests in the different aspects of the selfsame reality. The problem of finiteness and infiniteness of the world (loka)' is explained with reference to substance, space, time and modes. The world is finite as regards its substance and space. Its spatial dimensions are finite. Its substance is finite in space. The world is infinite with reference to its temporal dimension and modal expressions. Thus it can be considered as both finite and infinite. The process of the world has neither beginning nor end, though it is limited in space which, in itself, however, is infinite. The problem of the relation of body and soul is answered by Mahavira in the following way: Is the body, O Lord, (identical with the soul or is the body different from it?' The body, O Gautama, is (identical with the soul as well as it is different from it.'3 The relation of body and soul is given as one of identity-cumdifference. The soul suffers from the injuries of the body inasmuch as it is identical with the body. It does not become extinct with the extinction of the body inasmuch as it is different from it as well. The soul is not absolutely unchanging, and so it is liable to progress or regress. Moral endeavour is not inconsistent with this conception of soul. It is inconsistent with the doctrines of absolute staticity or absolute extinction. But this non-absolutist conception is free from this inconsistency. (The Buddha avoided both these absolutist extremes, as we have seen above, in order to justify moral endeavours.) Eternalism is as much inconsistent with moral endeavour as nihilism. But the Jaina theory does not endorse either eternalism or nihilism. The Buddha perhaps found self-contradiction in asserting both staticity and change in the selfsame entity with reference to identical space and time. But if experience gives this as a fact, we need not be afraid of accepting this as a truth. It is this finding of Mahavira that inspired the whole philosophical development of the Jaina mind. If staticity means incapability of change, then certainly 1 Loka means the contents of that portion of the space (akasa) where the existence and movements of spirit and matter are possible. 2 BhSu, II. I. 90. 3 BhSu, XIII, 7. 495. Page #61 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 24 NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS [CH. it is self-contradictory to say "The static entity changes. But the Jaina conception of staticity is not like this. It is better to use the term 'persistent' instead of 'static'. The Jaina conception of staticity is 'persistent flow'. The substance persists through modes. It is as well as becomes. Being and becoming are not mutually incompatible. One implies the other. Dead staticity is incompatible with change. Absolute being is inconsistent with becoming. If becoming were conceived as a super-addition to being, there would be self-contradiction. Becoming is not related to being in the same way as a pen is related to a table. But becoming means the state of being at a certain instant. Becoming involves and presupposes persistence. Becoming is not a derivative of being but its necessary concomitant. The question Why should a thing become and change?' is as absurd as the question 'Why should a thing exist?' Being and becoming are ontologically inseparable though they can be distinguished by logical thought. The kers who presume being as absolutely static and conceive becoming as a derivative of being are landed in self-contradiction. They eventually reject either being or becoming or both as illusory. The Sutrakrtanga records a number of old doctrines regarding soul, creation and morality. There were some who regarded soul as an evolute of the five material elements viz. earth, water, fire, air and ether, and regarded it as destroyed along with the dissolution of the elements. Some again held that the intelligent principle (vinnu) appeared in various shapes in the universe. There were again some who regarded soul as the sixth element and contended that both the world and the soul were eternal ; furthermore they believed in determinism. Another group believed in five momentary aggregates (skandhas) which were regarded neither as different, nor as identical, nor as caused, nor as uncaused. Suffering, according to some, was neither due to oneself nor due to another; it was due to mere blind chance or fate. There were again some who were suspicious about what was beyond suspicion and unsuspicious about what was actually liable to suspicion. There were sceptics (annaniya, literally agnostics) who did not know anything for certain.? As regards creation, again, there were some who regarded the world as created by gods, some who regarded it as created by Brahman ; others again regarded it as created by Isvara ; some again conceived it as derived from pradhana,& The Samosaranajjhayana mentions the doctrines of four types of heretics. These are (1) kiriyam (actionism), akiriyam (non-actionism), 1 Suky, I. I. I. 8. 2 Ibid., I. 1. I. 9. 3 Ibid., I. 1. I. 15-16. 4 Ibid., I. I. I. 17. 5 Ibid., I. 1. 2. 2-3 Sasankiyaim sankanti sankiyaim asankino.-Ibid., I 1. 2. 10. 7 nicchayattham na jananti.-Ibid., I. I. 2. 16. 8 Ibid., I. I. 3. 5-6. Page #62 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE JAINA ATTITUDE 25 vinayam (non-discrimination), annanam (agnosticism). The annaniya (agnostics or sceptics), though they are able arguers, do not get beyond confusion and doubt (no vitigicchatinna). The venaiya (upholders of vinaya) believe truth to be untruth and exemplify what is good as evil.2 The akiriyavai (non-believer in action does not admit good or evil acts as influencing the future. He believes in the world as futile and fixed (vanjho niyao kasine hu loe). The kriyavadins believe in actions, believe in suffering as due to oneself and not due to another, and also admit right knowledge and conduct as leading to liberation." It is in the context of these doctrines that the attitude of Mahavira is to be understood. The Jainas believed in soul as separate from the body and as persisting through different births. They believed in good and bad actions, and also in right faith, right knowledge, and right conduct as leading to final liberation. We have already reviewed the Jaina position. Mahavira's beliefs were opposed to the heretical beliefs enumerated above. (Mahavira was not a sceptic, nor an agnostic. Nor so was the Buddha. Nor were they materialists. Both of them believed in such transcendental things as morality and final emancipation, howsoever much might they differ about their nature...) The Buddha certainly did not believe in a spiritual substance persisting through various births, and surviving in its purest form in liberation. But he believed in the world as suffering, and regarded liberation from this suffering as the only end worth pursuit. Nama (consciousness) is different from rupa (material form), and so dissolution of the body does not mean dissolution of the mind. The nama (consciousness) originates from its own cause, and so its cessation depends upon the cessation of its ultimate cause which is avidya, ignorance. Belief in final emancipation and means thereto is the peculiarity of all those systems which are opposed to materialism. The sceptic lies in between the believers of such transcendental things as morality and final emancipation and the materialists. And the same is the position of the agnostics. We have seen the nature of the agnostics as described in the Sutrakrtanga. There we found that those thinkers who doubted everything and believed in nothing were called agnostics or sceptics. We also learn from the Buddhist sources about one Sanjaya Velatthiputta who, when asked about ultimate problems, refused to give definite answer. He 1 Ibid., I. 12. 2. 2 saccam asaccam iti cintayanta asahu sahu tti udaharanta. --Ibid., I. 12. 3. 3 lbid., I. 12. 4 4 Ibid., I. 12. 7. 5 lbid., I. 12. II. 6 Cf. dukkham eva hi na koci dukkhito karako na kiriya ca vijjati atthi nibbuti na niblyuto puma maggam atthi gamako na vijjati. -Visuddhimagga, XVI. 90. : DNi, Samanna phalasutta (No. 2). JP-4 Page #63 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 26 NON-ABSOLUTISTIC ATTITUDE OF THE JAINAS [CH. was an agnostic or a sceptic. His failure to answer was due to his indecision and all-round scepticism. (There are scholars who believe that the avyakata attitude of the Buddha and the non-absolutistic attitude of Mahavira towards the same problems were either influenced by or developed in opposition to this sceptical attitude of Sanjaya Velatthiputta. But it is beyond doubt that the respective attitudes of the Buddha and Mahavira were characteristic of their natures. The Buddha was a thoroughgoing rationalist and as such did not enter into problems which were beyond the reach of reason. His enquiries were mainly concerned with finding out the cause of suffering and the means to final emancipation, and he rejected as absurd the unnecessary metaphysical speculations. On the other hand, Mahavira inherited a number of doctrines from his predecessors and had to reinterpret and revise them in the context of the speculations of his age. In consonance with his immense faith in toleration, and peaceloving nature, he developed a non-absolutistic attitude which enabled him to solve the problems and create conviction among his followers. The whole subsequent Jaina thought is inspired by this attitude, and we shall have many occasions in the course of this work to see the results of this attitude. 1 Vide SBE, Vol. XLV, Introduction, p. xxvii et seq. Page #64 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CHAPTER II THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS INTRODUCTORY In the preceding chapter we have shown the difference of attitude of Mahavira with that of the Buddha and the Upanisads and have stressed his credence in the testimony of experience. He did not fall in the trap of abstract logic because he did not deprecate commonsense interpretation of experience. The logical attitude of Mahavira was intimately bound up with his empiricism. It is essential for the understanding of Jaina thought that the epistemology of experience as built up by the Jaina thinkers in consonance with the position of the first systematizer of Jaina thought and religion should be thoroughly understood. Realizing this necessity we now address ourselves to undertake an evaluation and exposition of Jaina theory of knowledge with special reference to experience. It is by no means a simple structure and the complexity of the theory shows that the evolution of the study was spread over a long period. The theory of knowledge of the Agamas is very old and perhaps originated in the pre-Mahavira period. It is said that Jnana-pravada forined a part of the Puruasrutal which was regarded as very old and had been lost long ago. Karma-pravada also formed a part of the same Purvasruta. The jnana-theory is closely related to the karma-theory which forms the very basis of Jaina ethics. The karma-theory is as old as Jainism itself, and so we can regard the Jaina theory of knowledge as of great antiquity. There seems to have been no controversy between the followers of Parsva and Mahavira regarding this theory of knowledge, though they differed, and later on compromised, on certain other topics. In the Rayapasenaiya Sutta, Kesi-Kumara, a follower of Parsva, is described as giving the same five divisions of knowledge as are found elsewhere in the Agamas. This theory, in its basic form, is presupposed by the Jaina doctrine of karman which, in its fundamentals, is beyond doubt pre-Mahavira. The Agamas are unanimous as regards the fivefold division of knowledge, and there is no controversy between the Svetambaras and the Digambaras regarding it. For a long time this theory passed more as an article of faith than as a logical doctrine. Samyag-jnana or the knowledge of a person of right attitude was considered as valid knowledge (pramana). If the 1 Jinabhadra, in his Vibh, quotes a Purva-gatha on jnana. (Vibh, 128). 2 Vide Bhsi, 1. 9. 76; Utsu, XXIII. 3 RAP, 165 Page #65 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ [CH. 1 attitude is right knowledge is right. If the attitude is wrong knowledge is wrong. A person of perverted attitude (mithyadrsti) cannot possess right knowledge. His knowledge is wrong knowledge (ajnana). Non-discrimination between the truth and the non-truth, perverted understanding leading to rebirths, and the absence of self-control which is the consummation of knowledge account for the wrongness of knowledge. Knowledge is inherent in the soul. It does not shine because there is karmic matter to veil it. The knowledge is perfect when this veil is totally removed. It is imperfect when there is only partial removal and subsidence of karmic matter. Absence of knowledge is unnatural to soul even as darkness is foreign to the sun. It is the clouds of the karmic matter that obfuscate the innate knowledge of the soul. Knowledge can be born, or rather emerge, with or without the help of the sense-organs. Of the five classes of knowledge, the mati (sensuous) and the sruta (scriptural) are born with the help of the sense-organs. The avadhi (visual intuition), the manahparyaya (intuition of mental modes) and the kevala (pure and perfect knowledge) are independent of them. The sense-organs, however, are only external instruments, the different states of the soul being the internal, or rather spiritual, counterparts of them. This conception of knowledge inspired the later epistemological enquiries of the Jaina logicians. When the problem of pramana (valid knowledge) presented itself before the Jaina thinkers, the term 'jnana' (knowledge) was replaced by the word 'pramana' (valid knowledge). The fundamental basis of the epistemological position of the Jaina logicians can be adequately expressed by the equation pramana samyag-jnana (right knowledge). Mati (sensuous) and sruta (scriptural) knowledge were put under paroksa (indirect or mediate cognition), and the other three-avadhi (visual intuition), manahparyaya (intuition of mental modes) and kevala (perfect knowledge) were classified under pratyaksa (direct or immediate intuition)." This was but natural. The knowledge is pratyaksa (direct) or paroksa (indirect) according as it is born without or with the help of an external instrument different from the self. But in order to bring their theory of knowledge in line with the theories of other systems of thought, the later Jaina thinkers accorded the status of pratyaksa (direct knowledge) to the knowledge produced by the sense-organs also. Jinabhadra designates as samvyavahara-pratyaksa (empirically direct and immediate) the knowledge produced by the sense-organs and the mind. This gradual reorientation was due to 1 Cf. ViBh, 115: 28 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS sadasad-avisesanao bhavaheu-jadicchiovalambhao nanaphalabhavao micchadditthissa annanam. Also TSu, I. 33. 2 Cf. SthSu, II. 1. 71; TSu, I. 9-12. 3 See ADv, PP. 194-5; NSu, 4. 4 imdiyamanobhavan jam tam samvavahara-paccakkham-ViBh, 95. Page #66 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II] INTRODUCTORY 29 the non-absolutistic attitude and its two corollaries viz. the doctrines of different attitudes' (nayas) and 'sevenfold predication' (saptabhangi) which formed the nucleus of the development of Jaina thought. The Agamic thought reveals the working of these principles in full measure. We have attempted to give a short account of it in the first chapter. But the account given is by no means full. Complete account of it requires a separate treatise, and so we have refrained from it. It can be said in general that the Jaina mind was always open to receive the alien thoughts without any distortion and assimilate them with their own. This fact was due to more than one reason. Firstly, the Jaina logical thought had a comparatively late origin, and so the non-Jaina thinkers had already asserted their position even before the Jaina thinkers came to the arena. The Jainas had a lot to learn and assimilate. Secondly, they had to argue their own case before the hostile thinkers with a measure of efficiency and critical outlook before they could hope to get a patient hearing from their opponents who would naturally refuse to listen to their arguments unless they embodied correct appreciation and fair criticism. Thirdly, many of the first-rate Jaina thinkers such as Siddhasena, Samantabhadra, Akalanka, Haribhadra and others were converts from learned Brahmins and had first-hand knowledge of the non-Jaina systems of thought. This helped correct estimate and comparative understanding. Lastly-and this is the most important reason, the Jaina attitude was non-absolutistic, and its scope was wide enough to assimilate such theories as were based upon reason and truth. Along with this comparative understanding, the Jaina thinkers had a critical disposition towards their own theories. The Agamic position regarding mati (sensuous) and sruta (scriptural) knowledge, avadhi (visual intuition) and manahparyaya (intuition of mental modes), and kevala-jnana (perfect knowledge) and kevala-darsana (perfect intuition) was reoriented by Siddhasena Divakara. Jinabhadra took great pains to reinstate the Agamic position. Bhatta Akalanka and Vidyanandi also were original thinkers and made valuable contribution to the theory. The task of reconciling Siddhasena Divakara and Jinabhadra was left to Upadhyaya Yasovijaya whose thought also was not without its marks of originality. We shall substantiate these remarks in the course of our study. Besides this theory of knowledge, the Jaina Agamas contain also the materials for the logical theory of valid knowledge (pramana). The Anuyogadvara Sutradivides valid knowledge (pramana) into hliad peopledge (pramana), BhSu, V. 3. 192; SthSu, 338. The former mentions four kinds of pramanas viz. pratyaksa, anumana, aupamya and agama. The Sthananga mentions the same four categories under the name hetu. 2 ADU, PP. 194-202. Page #67 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 30 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. four categories viz. pratyaksa (perceptual), anumana (inferential), aupamya (analogical) and agama (scriptural) cognition and further gives their subdivisions in detail. It also gives illustrations of the subdivisions of the latter three. The Dasavaikalikaniryuktil of Bhadrabahu deals also with the problem of the number of members of a syllogism. Let us now deal with the nature of the fivefold knowledge (jnanas) and their subdivisions. MATI-JNANA (SENSUOUS COGNITION) Mati-jnana is usually known as abhinibodhika-jnana (perceptual cognition) in the Agamas.2 It belongs to the category of paroksa (indirect cognition) inasmuch as it is born with the help of the senseorgans and the mind. Of course, the Anuyogadvara Sutra and the Nandi Sutra, as noted above, recognize the knowledge born of the five senses as indriya-pratyaksa (sensuous direct cognition) and Jinabhadra designates the knowledge born of the senses and the mind as samvyavahara-pratyaksa (empirical perception). But that is only by way of concession to popular usage as is clear from the use of the word 'samvyavahara' (empirical) by Jinabhadra. Vacaka Umasvati, however, is definitely opposed to this concession. The recognition of indriya-pratyaksa (sensuous direct cognition) is only a later addition, and this extraneous character of it is proved by the fact that the knowledge born of the senses and the mind is also recognized as matijnana (sensuous cognition) which is always counted under the category of paroksa (indirect knowledge). The Jaina thinkers are unanimous in ascribing the status of paroksa (indirect knowledge) to the mati (sensuous cognition) and the sruta-jnana (scriptural knowledge). When pratyaksa (direct knowledge) is subdivided into the categories of indriya-pratyaksa (sensuous direct cognition) and no-indriya-pratyaksa (non-sensuous direct knowledge), avadhi (visual intuition), (manahparyaya (intuition of the mental modes) and kevala (perfect knowledge) are put under the latter while the knowledge born of any of the five senses is counted under the former category. One interesting fact should be noticed in this connection. The old Jaina thinkers unanimously and from the very beginning counted knowledge born with the help of any of the five senses as well as manas (mind) as types of mati-jnana (sensuous cognition). But under indriya-pratyaksa DVNir, gathas 49-50 ; 89 et seq., 137. 2 The term 'mati-jnana' seems to be older than the terms abhinibodhika'. The karma-theory speaks of mati-jnanavarana but never abhinibodhika-jnanavarana. Had the term been as old as 'mati', the karma-theory which is one of the oldest tenets of Jainism must have mentioned it with reference to the avarana that veils it. 3 ViBh, 95. 4 TSu, I. II and the Bhusya thereon. Page #68 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II] MATI-INANA 31 (sensuous direct cognition) they counted only five types of knowledge born of one or other of the five senses. The knowledge born of manas (mind) does not find place under indriya-pratyaksa (sensuous direct cognition). This fact points to the truth that the Jaina Agamas contain a faithful record of the ancient views as recorded in the Vaisesikal and the NyayaSutra that there are only five senses. Furthermore, the Jainas themselves recognize manas (mind) as only a quasi-sense (anindriya or no-indriya). It is only Vatsyayanat who contended that the fact of mind being a sense-organ naturally follows from the lack of repudiation as well as enumeration of it as a sense-organ in the works of other schools (tantrantara). Perhaps the Buddhist thinkers were the first to recognize mind as a sense-organ. Vatsyayana seems to be indebted to the Buddhists for his awareness of this. Isvarakrsna, in the Sankhyakarika,5 clearly states mind as a sense-organ. And it may be that Vatsyayana refers to this Karika as tantrantara. The Carakasamhita which is undoubtedly older than the Sankhyakarika, however, does not recognize mind as a sense-organ though it recognizes it as one of the karanas instruments).? In the Mahabharata also we find manas as separately enumerated from the ten sense-organs in connection with the evolution theory of the Samkhya system. It is difficult to ascertain whether mind was designated as a sense-organ by the authors of the Yogadarsana and its Bhasya.' The Gita also enumerates mind separately from the other sense-organs. 10 Sankaracarya'l says that mind also is included under sense-organs on the authority of Smrti (text embodying tradition). The Jainas, as we have already mentioned, regarded mind as only a quasisense (anindriya or no-indriya). It seems that when the problem whether mind should be designated as a sense-organ presented itself before the non-Buddhist thinkers, they tried to clarify their position by deducing its status of a sense-organ from the implication of their own ancient texts. The Jainas, however, adhered to their old position of regarding mind as anindriya or no-indriya i.e. quasi-sense. Thus whereas Vatsyayana referred to tantrantara and Sankaracarya to some Smrti-text, the Jaina thinkers thought it proper to admit it as an anindriya (quasi-sense). This investigation helps us to ascertain the chronological order of the development of philosophical thought. The Samkhya as presented by Isvarakrsna is found to be a development of the Samkhya found in the Carakasarhita and the Mahabharata. Isvarakrsna perhaps profited by Buddhist criticism of counting mind as 1 VS, III. 2. 4. 2 NS, I. 1. 12. 3 TSu, J. 14, 19 and Bhasya. 4 NBh, I. I. 4. 5 SK, 24, 27. 6 Caraka, Sarirasthana, I. 17, 64. 7 Ibid., I. 56. & Santiparva, 204. 10; 210. 29. 9 Vide YD. II. 19 and 54 with Bhasya. 10 BhG7, III. 42 ; XV. 7. 11 SBh on BS, II. 4. 17. Page #69 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 32 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. separate from the category of indriyas by the authors of the Vai esika and the Nyaya Sutra as well as the old Sarkhya thinkers. As regards the Jaina thinkers, it is not possible to ascertain whether their conception of mind as a quasi-sense is indebted to Buddhist criticism. The antiquity of the Jaina conception depends upon the antiquity of their conception of the twenty-eight types of abhinibodhika-jnana (perceptual cognition) which include no-indriyaja avagraha (quasi-sensuous indeterminate perception), no-indriyaja iha (quasi-sensuous speculation) etc. Perhaps the Jaina conception of mind as a quasi-sense is as old as the Buddhist conception of mind as a sense-organ. The antiquity of the Jaina conception of manahparyaya-jnana (intuition of the mental modes) points to the antiquity of the Jaina conception of manas (mind). Of course, the recognition of mind as a separate category by all the systems of Indian thought is as old as the origin of the systems themselves. But the difference lies in their various conceptions and their later developments. Now a problem arises as to why the different schools took so much pains to win the title of a sense-organ for mind, while the Jainas did not care for it? The non-Jaina schools unanimously agreed that the knowledge born of the contact of the sense-organs with the objects is pratyaksa (direct cognition). Now when the problem of regarding the cognitions of pleasure, pain etc., which are obviously independent of the sense-organs, as cases of pratyaksa (direct cognition) presented itself, it was but natural that the mind should be accorded the status of a sense-organ for otherwise the cognition of pleasure, pain etc. would not fall under pratyaksa-jnana (direct cognition). Besides this the yogaja pratyaksa (transcendental perception) was also to be accounted for. In order to meet this contingency, the non-Jaina thinkers had to accord the status of a sense-organ to the mind.. But this presented no difficulty to the Jainas who did not regard pratyaksa (direct cognition) as dependent upon the sense-organ or mind. The soul alone was held responsible for the status of pratyaksa (direct cognition). Now let us come to our abhinibodhika (perceptual cognition or mati-jnana (sensuous cognition). Bhadrabahu's Niryukti gives the following synonyms of abhinibodhika (perceptual cognition): iha (speculation), apoha (exclusion), vimamsa (=vimarsa, enquiry), maggana (margana, searching), gavesana (gavesana, fathoming), sanna (sannna, recognition), sai (smrti, memory), mai (mati, sensuous cognition), and panna (prajna, wisdom).2 The Tattvarthasutra mentions only mati (sensuous cognition), smrti (recollection), cinta (thought), and abhinibodha (perceptual cognition) as synonymous. The Nandi Sutra only follows Bhadrabahu. It is Umasvati who gives for the first 1 Cf. NBh, I. 1.4. 2 See Vibh, 396. 3 TSu, I. 13. Page #70 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II] time the definition of mati-jnana (sensuous cognition). Of course, he does not state anything new. He only gathers up the scattered views of the Scriptures in a logical way. He defines matijnana (sensuous cognition) as 'knowledge caused by the senses and the mind."1. It is rather a statement of the condition of matijnana (sensuous cognition) than a definition proper. But it serves quite well the purpose of a definition. It further states the two varieties of mati-jnana (sensuous cognition) viz. (1) knowledge born of senses and (2) knowledge born of mind, as the author himself informs us in his Bhasya.2 The commentator Siddhasenaganin, however, attempts to distinguish three categories of matijnana viz. (1) exclusively due to the sense-organs (indriya), (2) exclusively due to the mind (anindriya), and (3) due to the joint activity of the senses and the mind." Umasvati cites the cognitions of the fivefold sense-data viz. sparsa (touch), rasa (taste) etc: by the five sense-organs of sparsana (touch-sense), rasana (taste-sense) etc. as instances of mati-jnana due to sense-organs (indriya). Knowledge independent of the activity of the sense-organs is called 'knowledge due to anindriya (non-sensuous).' Thus knowledge which involves the activity of the mind alone falls under this category. Similarly, instinctive incipient intuitions of the plant world as well as the undeveloped animal organisms, which are independent of both the sense-organs and the mind, also fall under it.4 The commentator distinguishes an additional category comprising cognitions born of the joint activity of the mind and the senses. But this is also implied in the statement of the Bhasya. Thus in all there are four categories of matijnana viz. (1) cognition without the help of both mind and senses, (2) cognition due to the activity of the senses alone, (3) cognition due to the activity of the mind alone, and (4) cognition due to the joint activity of the mind and the senses. One fact is to be noticed here. All cognitions are nothing but different states of the soul and as such are only cases of emergence and not origination proper. They depend upon the activity of the soul alone, the senses and the mind being only auxiliary conditions. We shall discuss the problem at some later stage. MATI-JNANA Pujyapada Devanandi, the author of Sarvarthasiddhi, does not supplement the synonyms of mati as given by Umasvati.5 Akalanka supplements the list by pratibha (grasp), buddhi (intellect) and 14. 1 tad indriyanindriyanimittam-TSu, I. 14. N.B. We have translated anindriya by 'mind'. But strictly speaking it means 'what is other than a sense-organ'. Knowledge independent of both senses and the mind also falls under knowledge due to anindriya. 2 Bhasya, ibid. 3 See Tika, ibid. 33 See Tika, ibid. 4 Cf. anindriyanimittam manovrttir ogha-jnanam ca-Bhasya on TSu, I. See also Siddhasenaganin's Tika. See SSi on TSu, I. 13. JP-5 Page #71 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 34 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. upalabdhi (perception), and refers to others by using the term et cetera (adi). Vidyanandi in his Tattvarthaslokavarttika, however, adds buddhi (intellect), medha (retentiveness), prajna (reasoning), pratibha (grasp), abhava (non-perception), sambhava (probability) and upamiti (analogy) to the synonyms given by Umasvati. In this connection the view of Bhatta Akalanka deserves special attention. Akalanka, in his Laghiyastraya, divides pramana (valid knowledge) into pratyaksa (direct) and paroksa (indirect) and recognizes pratyaksa (direct knowledge) as twofold viz. mukhya (transcendental) and samuyavaharika (empirical) also called atindriya-pratyaksa (super-sensuous intuition) and indriyanindriya-pratyaksa (sensuous and quasi-sensuous perception) respectively. Avagraha (perception), iha (speculation), avaya (perceptual judgment) and dharana (retention) are subsumed under indriya-pratyaksa (sensuous perception), while smrti (memory), sanjna (recognition), cinta (discursive thought) and abhinibodha (perceptual cognition) are put under anindriya-pratyaksa (quasi-sensuous or mental perception). Sruta (scriptural knowledge), arthapatti (presupposition), anumana (inference), upamana (analogy) etc. are put under paroksa (indirect knowledge). Mati-jnana thus is recognized as pratyaksa. Memory, recognition, discursive thought etc. are cases of mati-jnana so long as they are not associated with language. They come under sruta (scriptural knowledge) as soon as they are associated with words, and as such they become paroksa. No other Jaina thinker has tried to subsume memory, recognition, discursive thought etc. under pratyaksa. Akalanka stands alone in this respect. He has not even a single supporter among his successors who admired him so much. On the contrary some of his successors have attempted to find a different meaning of the statements of Akalanka in this connection.. We shall now state in brief the nature of the subdivisions of matijnana' viz. avagraha (perception), iha (speculation), avaya (perceptual judgment) and dharana (retention) which are nothing but so many stages of the development of mati-jnana. (a) Avagraha (Perception) The Nandi Sutra gives these as the synonyms of avagrahaavagrahanata (receiving), upadharanata (holding), sravanata (hearing), 1 matih smrtih sanjna cinta 'bhinibodhadaya ityarthah. ke punas te? pratibha-buddhy-upalabdhyadayah.--TRA on TSu, 1. 13. 2 Sloka 3 on Tsu, I. 13. 3 LT, 3 and 4 (also see Vivyti on it composed by Akalanka himself). 4 LT, 61 (with Vivyti). 5 See LT, 10-11 (with Vivyti). 6 Cf. NKC on karika io and the first half of karika 11 (pp. 403 et seq.). 7 For Acarya Kundakunda's classification see Pancastikayasura, 41. Page #72 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 11] MATI-JNANA : AVAGRAHA 35 avalambanata (grasping), and medha (gradual awareness). Umasvati, however, gives the following synonyms: avagraha (receiving), graha, grahana, alocana (intuition) and avadharana (holding).2 Avagraha can be of two kinds viz. vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness) and arthavagraha (object-perception). The Nandi Sutra does not clearly define avagraha, but only clarifies the implication by illustrations. It seems to quote Avasyakaniryukti of Bhadrabahu, which defines avagraha as 'cognition of sense-data' (atthanam uggahanan). It also states that avagraha is instantaneous, that is, it lasts only for one instant which is an infinitesimal and further indivisible point of time, beyond ordinary human conception. But it is to be understood that this instantaneousness relates to arthavagraha (object-perception) and not to vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness) which continues for an asamkhyeya (countless) number of instants, gradually proceeding towards the plane of consciousness. Suppose, for instance, that a man is asleep and is to be awakened by call. The sound, which the Jaina thinkers regard as composed of material atoms, of the call reaches his ears and he is awakened. But the sound-atoms reach his ears in succession, and countless instants elapse before the ears are sufficiently saturated with these atoms so that the person may be awakened to consciousness. As soon as the person becomes conscious, vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness) is over as then there occurs arthavagraha object-perception) which lasts, as has already been stated, only for one instant. Now the question is whether this object-perception is determinate or indeterminate. Contact-awareness, as we have seen, is only stirring of the consciousness. It is only awakening of consciousness. Of the five sense-organs, the sense-organ of sight is incompetent for contact-awareness inasmuch as there is no physical contact between this sense-organ and its object viz. coloured shape (rupa). Contact-awareness is possible only when there is physical contact between the sense-organ and its object. On the same ground the mind (manas) is also incompetent for contact-awareness. Thus there can be only four types of it, there being left only four sense-organs viz. ear, taste, smell and touch competent to have contact-awareness. Objectperception, however, is possible by all the five sense-organs as well as the mind, and consequently can be of six types. According to Umasvati and Jinabhadra, both of whom are staunch supporters of Agamic conceptions, avagraha is indeterminate cognition. So far as 1 NSu, 30. 2 TSuBh, I. 15. 3 NSu, 27; TSu, I. 17-18 ; Vibh, 193. 4 NSu, 36 (gatha 83. Cf. ViBh, 179. We give this number instead of the serial number of the gatha of the Avasyakaniryukti for convenience of reference). 5 NSu, 36 (gatha 84). Cf. Vibh, 333. 6 See Vibh, gathas 333 with the Sisyahita Brhadurtti. Also see NSu, 35. 7 NSA, 29; Vibh, 204. 8 See NSi, 29. Page #73 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 36 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. our knowledge goes, among the later Jaina logicians there has been none to uphold this old position, except Siddhasenaganin, the commentator of Umasvati's Tattvartha-sutra-bhasya, and Upadhyaya Yasovijaya of the seventeenth century, who has only summarized arguments of Jinabhadra in his Jaina-tarka-bhasa. Thus our enquiry will be based on the works of Umasvati, Jinabhadra, Siddhasenaganin and Yasovijaya. We shall refer to the works of Pujyapada Devanandi, Akalanka, Vidyanandi, Vadi-Devasuri and Hemacandra only by way of contrast. In this chapter we are mainly concerned with the Agamic conception and as such should leave the details of the theories of the later logicians out of account in the present context. Umasvati defines avagraha as 'indeterminate intuitional cognition of their respective objects by the sense-ogans.'1 The avagraha cognizes only the general features of an object. It is indeterminate. The distinctive characteristics of the object are not cognized by it. The object presented in it is indeterminate and free from association with names. The Nandi Sutra cites the sound-consciousness of a man just awakened from sleep by hearing the sound as an example of arthavagraha (object-perception by the sense-organ of ear. The man is conscious of some sound, but he does not cognize the definite nature of the sound at this stage. According to Jinabhadra, the consciousness of such a person has not even taken the form of 'This is sound' inasmuch as the cognition 'This is sound' is determinate and discursive and requires more than one instant for developing such form which is possible only in the third stage called apaya (perceptual judgment).* The arthavagraha (object-perception), being instantaneous, cannot be considered to have developed such a form. The object of arthavagraha is some common feature, indefinite and devoid of any individual characteristic, name etc.5 What then is the exact nature of arthavagraha (object-perception)? Object-perception is the consummation of vyanjanavagraha (contactawareness and as such can be properly understood only when the nature of the latter is properly understood. Now what is vyanjana? What reveals an object even as a lamp reveals a jar is vyanjana. It is the relation of the physical sense-organ with the substance transformed into its sense-data such as sound-(atoms).' The vyanjanavagraha is not unconscious inasmuch as it is this that finally develops 1 tatra 'vyaktam yathasvam indriyair visayanam alocanavadharanam avagrahah-TSuBh, I. 15. 2 Cf. yad vijnanam.. samanyasya 'nirdesyasya svarupa-kalpanarahitasya namacikalpanarahitasya ca vastunah paricchedakam so 'vagrahah-Tika on TSuBh, I. 153 NSu, 35. 4 Sce ViBk, gathas 252-3. 3 samannam aaiddesam saruva-namai-kappanarahivari--Vibh, 252. u ViBh, 194 Page #74 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II] MATI-NANA : AVAGRAHA 37 into arthavagraha (object-perception). The consciousness is there from the very instant of inception, though it is not felt due to its undeveloped existence.2 It is not possible for any ordinary man to know all the contents of the mind even when he is wide awake, inasmuch as a countless number of conscious states emerge during the course of a single day. Let us now come to arthavagraha (objectperception). The Nandi Sutra states that in the last instant of the vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness) there emerges a cognition such as 'This is sound' though the exact nature of the sound is not cognized there. This is called avagraha. Jinabhadra interprets this statement as recording only the occurrence of the cognition and not its specific content. The arthavagraha (object-perception) lasts only for an instant, and it is not possible that an instantaneous flash should be of the determinate form 'This is sound'. The cognition 'This is sound' is not arthavagraha (object-perception) but apaya (perceptual judgment) inasmuch as it is determinate cognition having the exclusion of everything else other than sound' as its characteristic.6 Jinabhadra refutes at great length the position of the opponent who regards arthavagraha (object-perception) as determinate cognition. We do not know of any logical treatise, prior to the Visesavasyakabhasya of Jinabhadra, which regards avagraha as determinate cognition, except the Sarvarthasiddhi of Pujyapada Devanandi, which defines avagraha as 'the first cognition after the instant of the contact of the object and the sense-organ' and further says 'On the contact of the object and the sense-organ, there occurs intuition (darsana) and the cognition of the object thereafter is avagraha, for instance, the cognition 'This is white colour' by the organ of sight is avagraha.'8 The Sarvarthasiddhi regards vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness) as 'indeterminate and arthavagraha (object-perception) as determinate.'' Jinabhadra, however, as an exponent of the Agamic conceptions, insists on the indeterminateness 1 Cf. ViBh, 195. Yasovijaya, however, concedes as an alternative that vyanjanavagraha is a cognition only by transference of epithet, being the condition of arthavagraha which is a cognition.-JTBh, p. 3. 2 Cf. ibid., 196. 3 jagganto vi na janai chaumattho hiyayagoyaram savvam jam tajjhavasanaim jam asamkhejjaim divasena.-Vibh, 199. 4 Cf. se jahanamae kei purise avvattam saddar sunijja tenam saddotti uggahie, no ce 'va nam janai ke vesa saddai--NSu, 35. 5 Cf. ViBh, 253. & Cf. Vibh, 254. ? vinaya-visayi-sannipata-samayanantaram adya-grahanam avagrahah. =SSi, I. 15. A visaya-visayi-sannipate sati darsanam bhavati, tadanantaram arthasya grahanam avagrahah, yatha saksusa suklam rupam iti grahanam avagrahah. -Ibid. 9 arthavagraha-vyanjanavagrahayor vyaktavyaktakrto visesah ---SSi, I. 18, Page #75 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 38 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. of avagraha. He is not prepared to allow the least reference even to a relative particular in avagraha, because even relative particularity is enough to put it into the category of apaya (perceptual judgment). If relative particularity is the criterion of the status of avagraha, then the possibility of apaya (perceptual judgment) will be ruled out inasmuch as in that case any cognition of a particular characteristic will be a case of avagraha, there being always available a cognition of a still more particular characteristic. It is not possible to ascertain all the particulars of an entity even in the course of a very long time. An entity reveals more and more specific characteristics along with the advancement of our knowledge. It is therefore more logical to concede the status of avagraha only to those cognitions which are totally free from even negligible reference to some particular characteristic. The cognition that contains the least particular as its content is apaya (perceptual judgment), and not avagraha. Jinabhadra quotes the view of some thinkers who held that the avagraha of a new-born child cognizes only the general features while that of a person sufficiently familiar with the objects cognizes the particular characteristics even in one single instant. But he refutes the view on the ground that it will entail the postulation of an indefinite number of avagrahas each varying according to the richness of the knowledge of the cognizer. The richer the knowledge of a person the more will be the number of particular characteristics cognized in his avagraha.? But this is certainly a fantastic position. Jinabhadra further quotes an opinion which regarded avgraha as bringing up the rear of alocana (intuitional cognition) which cognizes the general feature (samanya) and as cognizing its object as excluded from everything else. He criticizes the theory on the grounds already given and says that this alocana (intuitional cognition) cannot be identified with vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness) inasmuch as the latter has none as its object while the former has 'general feature' as its object. It can, therefore, be nothing but our arthavagraha (object-perception) under different nomenclature.3 Now avagraha-like iha (speculation), apaya (perceptual judgment) and dharana (retention)-has been characterized as 'cognizing quickly', 'cognizing slowly', 'cognizing many', 'cognizing some' etc. and this is not possible unless avagraha is regarded as lasting for more than one instant and as cognizing the particular characteristics. Jinabhadra gets over this difficulty by stating that these are called cases of avagraha only by transference of epithet (upacarena). A genuine (naiscayika) arthavagraha (object-perception) lasts only for a 1 Cf. ViBh, 255-6. 2 Cf. ibid., 268-9. 3 See ViBh, 273-7 with the Brhadurtti. * See ibid., 280 with the Byhadurtti; also see TSu, I. 16. Page #76 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II] Ks MATI-JNANA: AVAGRAHA single instant and cognizes the general feature alone. It is only by way of metaphor that an apaya (perceptual judgment) is called avagraha with reference to the succeeding iha (speculation) and apaya (perceptual judgment). In the case of genuine avagraha only the general feature is cognized. Then through the process of iha (speculation) and apaya (perceptual judgment) the cognition becomes determinate. In this determinate cognition which is an apaya (perceptual judgment) a particular characteristic is cognized. Thereafter if the cognizer strives for a further specific characteristic, he has to pass through new iha (speculation) to new apaya (perceptual judgment). In this case the former determinate cognition which was the starting point of this second process is called avagraha by transference of epithet. It can also be called a case of relative avagraha. But by no means can it be called a genuine avagraha. Siddhasenaganin has also raised the same problem and given the same answer in his commentary on the Tattvarthasutrabhasya.2 Upadhyaya Yasovijaya has summarized the position of Jinabhadra very excellently in his Jaina-tarka-bhasa.3 We have already given the view of Pujyapada Devanandi and have also stated that he regards avagraha as determinate cognition. It is interesting to note that all the eminent Jaina logicians such as Akalanka, Vidyanandi, Vadi-Devasuri and Hemacandra regard avagraha as determinate. Akalanka defines avagraha as 'determinate cognition of the distinctive nature of an object, following in the wake of intuitional cognition of pure existence, consequent upon the contact of the sense-organ with the object.' On the contacts of the senseorgan with the object there arises an intuitional cognition of pure existence (sanmatra-darsanam). This intuitional cognition then develops into determinate cognition of the object. This is called avagraha." Vidyanandi defines avagraha as 'the cognition of the individuality of a thing, following in the wake of the cognition of thing in general born of the contact of the sense-organ and the object." Vadi-Devasuri 1 See ViBh, 282-4. 2 See Tika on TSuBh, I. 16: nanu ca 'vagraha ekasamayikah sastre nirupito na cai 'kasmin samaye cai 'vai 'kavagraha evamvidho yukto 'lpakalatvad iti. ucyate-satyam evam etat, kintu avagraho dvidha-naiscayiko vyavaharikas ca-etc. 3 See JTBh, p. 4-5. 4 aksarthayoge sattaloko 'rthakaravikalpadhih avagraho 39 ..-LT, 5. > Here 'contact' does not mean physical contact, but such proximity as is competent for the rise of cognition. 6 See Vivrti on LT, 5. aksarthayogajad vastumatra-grahana-laksanat jatam yad vastubhedasya grahanam tad avagrahah. -TSIV, p. 219. Page #77 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. so defines avagraha as the first cognition of an object as determined by a secondary common characteristic, born of the intuitional cognition following in the wake of sense-object contact and having pure existence as its object.1 Acarya Hemacandra defines avagraha as 'the cognition of an object, which follows in the wake of indeterminate intuition due to the contact of the sense-organ with the object.'? We thus find that these Jaina thinkers unanimously hold avagraha to be determinate cognition. The Agamic conception of avagraha as indeterminate cognition was not upheld by the Jaina logicians in view of its indefiniteness and lack of pragmatic value. This is apparent from the conception of valid knowledge (pramana) of the Jaina logicians. This subject, however, is not relevant and so we do not discuss it here. (b) iha (Speculation) Iha (speculation) follows in the wake of avagraha (perception). In avagraha, as we have seen, there is only an indeterminate cognition, or an indistinct awareness of the object. In iha the object is known distinctly. For instance, in avagraha (perception) a person simply hears a sound while in iha he cognizes the nature of the sound also." The indistinct awareness of the avagraha (perception) cognizes only a part of the object while iha, being a determinate cognition, cognizes the rest and strives or enquires for a particular characteristic. The process of iha continues for a certain period of time, though it never exceeds one muhurta." The Nandi Sutra gives these five as the synonyms of iha: abhoganata (leaning towards), marganata (searching), gavesanata (fathoming), cinta (discursive thought) and vimarsa (enquiry).6 Umasvati, however, gives quite different synonyms which are: iha (speculation), uha (reasoning), tarka (reasoning), parikna investigation), vicarana (thinking) and jijnasa (enquiry).' Pujyapada Devanandi defines iha as 'the striving for a specific characteristic of the object cognized by avagraha (perception).'8 The Avasyakaniryukti defines iha as 'speculation (vicaranam)'.' Jinabhadra, commenting upon it, says 'Tha means enquiry for the distinctive feature, '10 Vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness) is the beginning of awareness, 1 PNT, II. 7. 2 PMi, I. 1. 26. 3 se jahanamae kei purise avvattam saddam sunijja tenam saddotti uggahie, no ceva nam janai ke vesa saddai, tao iham pavisai, tao janai amuge esa saddeNSu, 35. 4 Cf. avagrhite visayarthaikadesac chesanugamanam niscayavisesa-jijnasa cesta iha-TSuBh, I. 15. 5 NSu, 34 : ViBh, 333 (Avasyakaniryukti-gatha). One muhurta is equal to forty-eight minutes. 8 NSu, 31. 7 TSuBh, I. 15. 8 SSi, I. 15. 9 ViBh, 179 (Niryuktigatha). 10 bheya-magganam ahe 'ha--ViBh, 180. Page #78 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II] MATI-JNANA : APAYA arthavagraha (object-perception) is the dawning of awareness, and iha is determinate tendency towards the ascertainment of the particular nature of the object. Though iha is a kind of speculation, it is to be distinguished from samsaya (doubt). Jinabhadra has drawn this very fine line of distinction between samsaya (doubt) and iha. 'The mental state which relates to many (mutually contradictory) objects, which is stupefied owing to its incapacity for exclusion (of the false), and which seems to retire into a perfectly supine condition, is noncognition (ajnana) of the nature of doubt. And the mental state which strives for the ascertainment of the truth by means of reason and logic, which is destined to be successful, and which tends towards the acceptance of the true and avoidance of the untrue is called iha.' Siddhasenaganin also draws the same line of distinction between iha and samsaya (doubt).2 All the Jaina logicians have unanimously given the same view of iha and so we do not mention their definitions separately. (c) Apaya or Avaya (Perceptual Judgment) After iha (speculation) there arises apaya which excludes the nonexistent characteristics. Tha (speculation) is enquiry about right and wrong. Apaya is ascertainment of the right and exclusion of the wrong. It, therefore, is a determinate cognition of the object. Apaya can be rendered as "perceptual judgment'. The Avasyakaniryukti defines apaya as determinate cognition'.4 Apaya involves determination of the existent qualities and exclusion of the non-existent qualities. For instance, when on hearing a sound one determines that the sound must be of the conch and not of the horn, because it is accompanied by such qualities as sweetness, it is a case of apaya (perceptual judgment).5 The Sarvarthasiddhi defines it as 'cognition of the true nature on account of the cognition of the particular characteristics'. Jinabhadra quotes an opinion which regarded apaya as only excluding the non-existent characteristics and attributed the function of cognizing the existent characteristics to dharana (retention) which brings up the rear of apaya.? He criticizes the opinion as absurd and states that 1 jam anegatthalambanam apajjudasaparikumthiyam cittam seya iva savvappayao tam samsayaruvam annanam. tam ciya sayatthaheu-vivattiva varatapparamamoham bhuyabhuya-visesayana-ccayabhimuham iha. -Vibh, 183-84. 2 Tika on TSuBh, I. 15. 3 avagrhite visaye samyag asamyag iti guna-dosa-vicarana-'dhyavasayapanodo 'payah-TSuBh, I. 15. 4 vavasayam ca avayah--Vibh, 179 (Niryuktigatha). 5 ViBh, 290. * visesa-nirjnanad yathatmyavagamanam avayah,SSi, I. 15. ? Vibh, 185. JP-6 Page #79 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 42 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. whether a cognition simply excludes the non-existent characteristics, or simply determines the existent characteristics, or does both the funcLions, it is apaya and nothing else. Umasvati gives the following synonyms of apaya: apagama, apanoda, apavyadha, apeta, apagata, apaviddha, apanutta (all these expressions having the same meaning viz. determinate judgment). The Nandi Sutra gives these as the synonyms: avartanata (limited determination), pratyavartanata (repeated determination), avaya (determination), buddhi (vivid determination), vijnana (determinate cognition). A comparison of these two sets of synonyms leads us to the hypothesis that the above opinion, as quoted and criticized by Jinabhadra on the nature of apaya, was upheld by those who regarded the first set as the synonyms of apaya. Of course, it is difficult to say whether Umasvati himself was a staunch supporter of that view, although we have a glimpse of his predilection for it from the definition of apaya given by him in his Tattvarthasutrabhasya* which has been quoted above. The synonyms of dharana (retention) as given by Umasvati in the same place also deserve consideration in this connection. They support the opinion quoted by Jinabhadra. Jinabhadra, however, is undoubtedly a staunch supporter of the Agamic conceptions, and it is apparent from the consideration of the synonyms as given by the Nandi Sutra that he agrees with the view of the Nandi Sutra. The problem deserves a closer attention. But as it does not fall within the scope of our present study, we leave it for discussion elsewhere. (d) Dharana (Retention) Apaya (perceptual judgment) is followed by dharana (retention) which means retention of the perceptual judgment for a number of instants, samkhyeya (countable) or asamkhyeya (countless). The Nandi Sutra gives the following synonyms of dharana: dharana (retention), dharana (holding), sthapana (placing), pratistha (fixing), and kostha (firmly grasping). Umasvati defines dharana as 'final determination of the object, retention of the resultant) cognition and recognition (of the object on future occasions)' and gives the following synonyms: pratipatti (continued cognition), avadharana (memory), avasthana (retention), niscaya (continued cognition), avagama (retention) and avabodha (cognition). The Avasyakaniryukti also defines 1 Vibh, 186. 2 TSuBh, I. 15. 3 NSu, 32 41. 15. s Cf. tao dharanam pavisai, tao nam dharei samkhejjam va. kalam asamkhejjam va kalam-NSu, 35. & NSu, 33. 7 dharana pratipattir yathasvam matyavasthanam avadharanari ca. dharana pratipattir avadharana 'vasthanam niscayah avagamah avabodha ity anarthantaram.--TSuBh, I. 15. Page #80 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 11] MATI-JNANA : DHARANA 43 dharana as 'retention'.1 Jinabhadra says that dharana means absence of lapse of the perceptual judgment. This dharana is threefold according to him. The absence of lapse (avicyuti) of the cognition of the object, the resultant) emergence of mental trace (vasana), and the on (anusmarana) of it again in future all these which follow in the wake of that (viz. perceptual judgment) constitute dharana". 3 Thus avicyuti (absence of lapse), vasana (mental trace) and smrti (recollection)--these three are included in the conception of dharana. Siddhasenaganin has accepted this view.4 Pujyapada Devanandi defines dharana as the condition of nonoblivion in future of what has been cognized by avaya (perceptual judgment)'s Akalanka defines it as the condition of recollection, which is called samskara (trace). Vidyanandi also admits the same definition. This 'trace' is not unconscious. It is, like iha (speculation), of the nature of knowledge, inasmuch as it is the condition of another knowledge called recollection.8 Vadi-Devasuri criticizes the view of Akalanka and Vidyanandi that dharana is the condition of recollection. He defines it as 'gradual consolidation and absence of lapse for a certain length of time of the apaya (perceptual judgment) on account of the mindfulness of the cognizer'.9 Dharana is only concentrated persistence of the apaya (perceptual judgment) for a certain length of time. It is not by any means the condition of recollection in future, inasmuch as it, being a case of perceptual cognition, cannot last up to the time of recollection. And again if it were to last up to that time, then it would be impossible to cognize anything else during that interval, inasmuch as even the upholders of the said view do not admit the presence of two cognitions simultaneously. 10 Vadi-Devasuri does not accept the existence of any 'trace' as the condition of recollection. Recollection is attributed to the special i dharanam puna dharanam-Vibh, 179 (Niryuktigatha). 2 tassa 'vagamo vao aviccui Jharana tassa.-Vibh, 180. 3 tayanamtaram tayatthaviccavanam jo ya vasanajogo kalamtare ya jam punar anusaranam dharana sa u.-Vibh, 291. 4 See Tika on TSUB, I. 15. 5 avetasya kalantare 'vismarana-karanam dharana-SSi, I. 15. 6 dharana smitihetuh-LT, 6; smstihetur dharana samskara iti yavatSvopajna-Vivyti. See TSIV, verse 4 on TSu, I. 15. 8 Cf. ibadharanayor api jnanatmakatvam unneyam tadupayogavisesatVivyti on LT, 6. Cf. T$IV, verse 22 on TSu, I. 15. 9 Cf. sadarasya pramatus tathavidhopacaya-kramena kincitkalam apracyavamano dharane 'ty abhidhiyate--SVR, II, 10. 10 Cf. tatha cet tarhi yasya padarthasya kalantare smstih sa pratyaksatmika dharana tavatkalam yavad anuvartata iti syat. etac ca 'aupapannam. evam tarhi yavat pata padartha-samskara-rupam pratyaksam puruse bhavet tavat padarthantarasya. samvedanam eva na syat. ksayopasamikopa yoganam yugapadbhava-virodhasya 'bhyam api pratipannatvat.-SVR, II. 10. Page #81 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ [CH. capacity of the soul to remember past events. He, however, has no objection if this capacity of the soul is given the name of samskara (trace). Besides, if dharana is considered as a remote cause of recollection, even then he has no grievance, inasmuch as it is only the conception of dharana as the immediate cause of recollection that he does 44 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS not support.1 Hemacandra, however, has followed Vidyanandi.2 Upadhyaya Yasovijaya, following the Brhadvrtti on Jinabhadra's Visesavasyakabhasya, admits that vasana (trace) in itself is of the nature of non-cognition (ajnanarupa), but it is recognized as a species of cognition only by transference of epithet. Vasana (trace) produces knowledge called recollection and as such the nature of its product is transferred to itself.3 We have now described the main features of avagraha (percep-tion), iha (speculation), avaya (perceptual judgment), and dharana (retention). Each of these four can again be of six types inasmuch as it can be due to any of the five sense-organs or the mind. Thus we get four multiplied by six or twenty-four types. Again, as already stated, there is vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness) of four types. Thus in all there can be twenty-eight types. Each of these again can have twelve different kinds of data as its objects. Thus totally there can be twenty-eight multiplied by twelve or three hundred and thirtysix types of abhinibodhika or matijnana (sensuous cognition). THE FOUR BUDDHIS . Now, these avagraha (perception), iha (speculation) etc. can be either srutanisrita (backed by scriptural learning) or asrutanisrita (not backed by scriptural learning). The Sthananga Sutra classifies abhinibodhika (perceptual cognition) into srutanisrita and asrutanisrita and subdivides each of the latter two into arthavagraha (object-perception) and vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness). It does not include iha (speculation), avaya (perceptual judgment), and dharana (retention). But they can be understood as implied, inasmuch as they naturally follow in the wake of avagraha (perception). Besides, the Sthananga could not have mentioned more than two subdivisions, inasmuch as the chapter which deals with the subject follows, as a rule, the principle of dichotomy." The Nandi Sutra, however, does not subdivide 1 tasmad atmasakti-visesa eva samskara-'paraparyayah smrter anantaryena hetuh, na dharana. paramparyena tu tasyas taddhetutabhidhane na kincid dusanam-SVR, II. 10. 2 See PM, I. 1. 29. 3 Cf. ... vasanayah svayam ajnana-rupatve 'pi karane karyopacarena jnanabhedabhidhanavirodhad iti-JTBh, p. 6; see also Brhadvrtti on ViBh, 189. 4 See TSu, I. 16. 5 See TSuBh, I. 19. 6 SthSu, 71. dvisthanaka-nurodhat Cf. ihadayo 'pi srutanisrita eva, na tuktah, Abhayadevasuri's commentary on SthSu, 71. Page #82 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IT] FOUR BUDDHIS 45 asrutanisrita into arthavagraha (object-perception) and vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness), but gives the subdivisions of autpattiki-buddhi (instantaneous comprehension), vainayiki-buddhi (intellect born of faithful service), karmaja-buddhi (intellect developed by practical experience) and parinamiki-buddhi (mature intellect). Jinabhadra gives the same viewo but holds that avagraha (perception), iha (speculation) etc. are common to srutanisrita and asrutanisrita. Of course, we do not find anything in the Nandi Sutra that goes against the statement of Jinabhadra whose view seems to be a consistent development of the view given by the Sthananga Sutra. The Avasyakaniryukti4 gives the four kinds of buddhi (intellect) in quite a different context. But there is nothing there which can contradict the claim of these buddhis (intellects) to be regarded as asrutanisrita matijnana (sensuous cognitions not backed by scriptural learning). These buddhis are special gifts of nature, and are not due to education or learnings and as such their claim to be asrutanisrita (not backed by scriptural learning) is but selfevident. Jinabhadra quotes an opinion which replaced the fourfold vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness) included in the twenty-eight types of mati (sensuous cognition) by these fourfold buddhis intellects) in order to keep the traditional number twenty-eights intact and at the same time to find a suitable place for the fourfold asrutanisrita as well." The Avasyakaniryukti, however, does not include the fourfold buddhis (intellects) in the twenty-eight types of mati (sensuous cognition).8 Nor does it recognize them as a separate type of it. The opinion quoted by Jinabhadra seems to be an attempt to accommodate the new comer in the old scheme. Of course, we do not know exactly when this new conception of asrutanisrita mati crept in. But undoubtedly it came after the time of Bhadrabahu, the author of the Avasyakaniryukti. Jinabhadra criticizes the opinion as unnecessary because according to him asrutanisrita is not a separate category but it is only a variety of avagraha (perception), iha (speculation) etc. and as such is included in them and consequently does not need separate counting. Abhayadevasurio says that vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness) is not possible in the case of buddhis (intellects), inasmuch as they are cases of mental perception. 11 Instances of asrutanisrita vyanjanavagraha (contactawareness), however, are available in the cases of cognitions due to the sense-organs other than sight and mind. For the differentiation of Srutanisrita from asrutanisrita Jinabhadra says 'That (cognition) which 1 NSu, 26. 2 See Vibh, 177. 3 Cf. ViBh, 303-4. 4 ANir, 932.. 5 Cf. ANir, 933. 6 Vide supra p. 44. 7 See ViBh, 301-302. & See ANir, 16. 9 See ViBh, 303. 10 See his commentary on SthSu, 71. 11 We have already given the reason why mind is incompetent for vyanjapavagraha on p. 35. Page #83 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH at present is devoid of verbal association and belongs to one whose intellect has been previously trained by the study of the scriptures is srutanisrita. The opposite of it is anisrita and comprises the four matis or intellects (viz. autpattiki etc.).' The srutanisrita is so called because the perceptual cognitions that come under it are possessed by those whose minds have been educated by the instructions of others regarding verbal usage and other sources such as scriptures, although the verbal knowledge has no direct bearing and influence upon them. The sensuous intuitions are not generated by the knowledge of language as verbal judgment (sruta) is. The conditions of perceptual cognitions are the same in the case of the instructed as well as the uninstructed, but the knowledge of language and the culture embodied in it enriches the content of perception by implicit or explicit association with linguistic symbols and their suggestive reference and consequently it cannot but have its effects on the capacity of cognition.3 The asrutanisrita perceptions are those which are devoid of the background of previous education of the perceiver. They fall into two categories according as they are purely mental or cases of sensuous perceptions. The former category comprises the fourfold buddhis (intellects) viz. autpattiki, vainayiki, karmaja and parinamiki, each having the stages of avagraha (perception), iha (speculation), avaya (perceptual judgment), and dharana (retention), but never vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness). The latter category comprises cases of perceptions due to the five senseorgans including vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness) also in the cases of the sense-organs other than the eye. This is the finally developed form of the conception of asrutanisrita mati intellect) and is found in Abhayadevasuri's commentary on the Sthananga referred to above. Let us now state in brief the meanings, with illustrations, of these fourfold buddhis (intellects). The Avasyakaniryukti defines autpattiki intellect as the intellection which comprehends instantaneously the true nature of a thing never seen, heard of, or even reported heretofore and is crowned with unhindered success.'s The Nandi Sutra only quotes the same definitions as those of the Avasyakaniryukti and so we shall not refer to the Nandi Sutra in order to avoid repetitions. There are given many illustrations 1 puvvam suyaparikammiya-matissa jam sampayam suyaiyam tam suyanissiyam iyaram puna anissiyam maicaukkan tam. ViBh, 169. 2 Cf. tatra srutam sariketakalabhavi paropadesah srutagranthas ca. purvan tena parikarmitamater vyavaharakale tadana peksam eva yad utpadyate tat srutanisritam-Byhadvytti on Vibh, 177. 3 Cf. svasamanakara-srutajnana-hita-vasana-prabodha-samana kalinatve sati srutopayogabhava-kalinam srutanisritam avagrahadi-caturbhedam.-JBP, p. 6. 4 Cf.ukta-(svasamanakara-srutajnana-hita)-vasana-prabodha-'samana kalinam ca matijnanam autpattikyadi-caturbhedam asrutanisritam.--JBP, p. 7. 5 ANir, 933. Page #84 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ FOUR BUDDHIS of each of the intellects (buddhis) but we shall give only one instance in each case. Among the numerous instances of autpattiki, given by the Avasyakanir yukti, there is one of 'kukkuta (cock).'! Once Rohaka, the son of Bharata-nata was asked by the king of Avanti to make a cock fight alone. Rohaka was quite a boy. But his instantaneous intellect suggested the solution. He put a mirror before the cock, and it began to fight with its image. Jinabhadra refers to this instance, and shows how the mind passes through the stages of avagraha (perception), iha (speculation) etc. in such a case. 'How can it fight in the absence of another cock? With the image--this is avagraha (perception). What (sort of image is) most suitable?--this is iha (speculation). Image reflected in a mirror_this is apaya (perceptual nent).'? Here Jinabhadra attempts to give the psychology of solution of problems. It is by a flash of genius that the solution of a difficult problem dawns upon the mind. This is the stage of avagraha (perception). The intellectual application of the solution presents a number of alternatives and consequently there is speculation or inquisitive pursuit--this stage can be called iha (speculation). Again, there is the final settlement of the mind-this is a paya (perceptual judgment). Then follows dharana (retention). The vainayiki is defined as "the intellection which is capable of completing a difficult task, can comprehend the spirit and letter of the trio of dharma (religion), artha (material prosperity) and kama (sensual pleasure) and is fruitful in this world as well as the world hereafter.'3 This buddhi is born of humility and faithful service. The ancient literature of India abounds in stories of acquisition of high knowledge by mere faithful service of the preceptor (guru). This knowledge has been called vinayasamuttha or vainayika (born of humility and service). The Avasyakaniryukti refers to a story of two students of astrology, one of whom became more efficient by faithful service of his preceptor while the other remained stupid in spite of his learning. The karmiki or karmasamuttha is defined as 'the intellection which comprehends the truth due to its attentive consciousness and breadth of vision of both the practical and the theoretical sides of actions (karman) and which has received appreciation of competent critics.'4 The intellect developed due to practical experience is called karmiki. People appreciate such intellect when it is extraordinarily developed. It is not learning that is responsible for the development. But it is practical experience that lies at the back of such intellect. An experienced goldsmith can easily differentiate between pure gold and an alloy, while a layman is easily deceived. 1 See ANir, 935 and the Tika. 3 ANir, 937 2 ViBh, 304. 4 ANir, 940. Page #85 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 48 [CH. The parinamiki is defined as 'the intellection which fulfils (its purpose) by means of inference, reasoning, and analogy, which develops with the maturity of age, and which results in well-being and salvation."1 The common feature of all these intellects is this that none of them is inspired by learning. They are either due to spontaneous suggestion, or modesty and humility, or practical experience, or natural maturity of the power of reasoning. It is on account of this common characteristic that they are called asrutanisrita. We have now dealt with the types of mati-jnana (sensuous cognition). It is not possible to give all the possible types. Only the most apparent ones can be enumerated. The types vary according to the nature of the perceptual cognition which can be infinitefold. Perception of the same object varies with each individual, and so its types cannot be enumerated in full. EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS SRUTA-JNANA (SCRIPTURAL OR VERBAL KNOWLEDGE) Sruta-jnana originally meant knowledge embodied in the scriptures.3 Knowledge of the scriptures was also called sruta-jnana. Umasvati says that sruta-jnana is preceded by mati (sensuous cognition) and falls into two categories viz. angabahya (other than the original scripture) and angapravista (included in the original scripture) which again are manifold and twelvefold respectively and comprise the whole of the Jaina scripture. He further says that mati-jnana (sensuous cognition) cognizes only what is present while the sruta-jnana comprehends what is present, past and future. The Jainas regarded their scriptures to contain all the truths, much in the same way as the Brahmins considered their Sruti or the Vedas to possess all possible knowledge. Such was the conception of sruta-jnana in the beginning. The Avasyakaniryukti says that the types of sruta-jnana are as many as the number of letters and their various combinations, and as such it is not possible to enumerate all the types. It then enumerates fourteen salient characteristics of sruta-jnana viz. aksara (alphabet), samjnin (discursive or cognitive or scriptural), samyak (right), sadika (having beginning), saparyavasita (having end), gamika (containing repetitions) and angapravista (included in the original scripture) with 42. 1 ANir, 942. 2evam bajjha-jjhamtara-nimitta-vaicittao maibahuttam kimcimmetta-visesena bhijjamanam puno 'nantam.--ViBh, 311. 3 Cf. SthSu, 71 (21); ADv, 3 et seq.; TSu, I. 20 and the Bhasya. 4 See TSuBh, I. 20. For Kundakunda's classification see Pancastikayasara, sampratakalavisayam 5 Cf. utpanna-vinasta-rthagrahakam matijnanam sruta-jnanam tu trikalavisayam utpannavinasta-nutpanna-rthagrahakam iti-Ibid. 6 ANir, 17-18. Page #86 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II] SRUTA-JNANA their opposites viz. anaksara, asanjnin etc. Inhaling, exhaling, spitting etc. are given as instances of anaksara-sruta so far as they are indices of the mental dispositions of the person. Eight qualities of the intellect are recognized as necessary for the acquisition of srutajnana. They are: desire for hearing, repeated questioning, (attentive) hearing, grasping, enquiry, conviction, retention and right action. The Avasyakaniryukti thus recognizes the words as well as other symbols such as physical gestures as sruta and also lays down the means of the acquisition of sruta-jnana. It, however, does not state the meanings of all the fourteen characteristics. It is in the Nandi Sutra that we find the meanings clearly stated.* In the Nandi Sutra, aksarasruta is given as threefold: sarjnaksara, vyanjanaksara and labdhyaksara. The shape of the letter, in other words, the script or alphabet is samjnaksara; sound of the letter, in other words, the spoken letter is vyanjanaksara; labdhyaksara is possessed only by one who is competent to learn alphabet (aksaralabdhika) and can be possible through all the five sense-organs as well as the mind." As regards anaksarasruta, the Nandi Sutra gives no new information. The first two categories of aksarasruta are only material symbols written or spoken, and as such are called dravya-sruta. The labdhyaksara is a kind of knowledge, and is sruta-jnana proper (bhavasruta). It can be produced through any of the sense-organs and the mind. If it is a sound that conditions it, then it is produced through the sense-organ of ear. If it is a coloured shape that conditions it, then it is produced through the sense-organ of sight. If it is a smell that conditions it, then it is produced through the sense-organ of smell. And so on. Only those who possess the gift of language can have labdhyaksara. When one hears a sound or sees a coloured shape, there arises in the wake of the perceptual cognition, a cognition couched in appropriate words composed of syllables (aksara) following the conventional vocabulary. This cognition is called labdhyaksara.? Knowledge of the conventional vocabulary and conscious application of it are the conditions of sruta-jnana. In other words, conscious exercise of the 1 ANir, 19. 2 Ibid., 20. 3 Ibid., 22. 4 Haribhadra in his Vytti on NSu, 38 (37 according to Hastimalla Muni's edition) says that although the characteristics of aksara and anaksara include all other characteristics, yet they are enumerated separately for only the pupils of slow understanding (na ca bheda-dvayad eva 'vyutpannamatinam sesabhedavagamah). 5 NSu, 38. 6 Cf. tatra samjna-vyanjanaksare dravyasrutam, labdhyaksaram punar bhavasrutam, labdher jnanarupatvat.-NSuVy on sutra 39. ? Cf. sabdadigrahana-samanantaram indriya-manonimittam srutagranthanusari sankha ityadyaksaranusaktam vijnanam utpadyate, tac ca 'neka prakaram, tad yatha srotrendriya-labdhyaksaram ityadi-NSUV? on sutra 39. JP-7 Page #87 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 50 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. gift of language is the indispensable condition of sruta-jnana. The cognitions which, in spite of their being couched in words, do not involve conscious attempt on the part of the cognizer at application of vocabulary, fall in the category of mati-jnana (sensuous cognition) and not sruta-jnana. Of course this distinction was stressed by later logicians.1 The samjni-sruta is considered in three ways, inasmuch as there are these three varieties of samjna (cognitional activity): () discursive thinking that takes into account the past, the present and the future, (2) consciousness that can discriminate between what is to be avoided and what is to be accepted for the maintenance of life, but cannot think of the past or the future, and (3) consciousness due to knowledge of the right scriptures (samyak sruta). The first is called (dirgha)kaliki (lasting for a long time), the second hetupadesiki (discriminating) and the third drstivadopadesiki (backed by scriptural knowledge). Those who possess these samjnas are called sarjnins. The sruta-jnana possessed by these samjnins is samjni-sruta. The asamjnins also fall in three categories. The mind is the organ of thinking. The more developed the mind is the more one is capable of thinking. Those whose mind is weak and incapable of thinking fall in the first category of asamjnins. Those who are totally devoid of mind and live on mere instincts fall in the second category of asarjnins. Again those who believe in false scriptures and thus possess perverted knowledge fall in the third category of asamjnins.5 sruta-jnana possessed by the asarjnins is asamjni-sruta. The twelvefold ganipitaka (scripture compiled by the ganadharas) containing Acaranga, Sutrakytanga etc. is samyak-sruta (right scripture) while the other books such as Bharata, Ramayana, the Vedas etc. are enumerated as mithya-sruta (false scriptures). It is further said that the samyaktva (rightness) or mithyatva (wrongness) depends upon the 1 Cf. sanketakalapravsttam srutagrantha-sambandhinam va ghatadi-sabdam anusstya vacya-vacaka-bhavena samyojya 'ghato ghatah' ityadi antarjalpakaram antahsabdollekhanvitam indriyadinimittam yaj jnanam udeti tac chrutajnanam iti-Byhadvytti on Vibh, 100 ; see also JBP, p. 6. $ 15. 2 See NSu, 39 and its Vrtti by Haribhadra. We are giving only the central idea. 3 Cf. yasya nasti iha 'poho margana ga vesana cinta. vimarsah so 'samjni 'ti labhyate, ayam ca sammurchima-pancendriya-vikalendriyadir jneyah, alpamano-labdhitvad abhavac ca... so 'yam kalikyupadesena---NSuV, on sutra 40 (39 according to Hastimalla Muni's edition). 4 yasya nasti abhisandharana purvika karanasaktih so 'samjni 'ti labhyate, ayam cai 'kendriya-prthivyadir avaseyo, manolabdhi-rabitatvat......so 'yam hetu-'padesena-Ibid. 5 Cf. na hi mithyadnsteh samjnanam asti, hitahitapravstti-nivsttyabhavat. ... asamjnisrutasya ksayopasamena 'samjni 'ti labhyate... SO'yam drstivadopadesena.-Ibid. Page #88 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 11] SRUTA-JNANA 51 attitude of the knower. If his attitude is right, whatever he knows becomes right and if his attitude is wrong (mithya), his knowledge also becomes wrong. Similarly if the result of the knowledge of mithyasruta (false scripture) by a mithyadysti (person of perverse attitude) turns out in the end to be the abandonment of the perversity (mithyadrsti), the mithyasruta (false scripture) is to be considered as samyak sruta (right scripture). The characteristics of sadika 'having beginning' and anadika 'having no beginning'-saparyavasita 'having end' and aparyavasita 'having no end' are considered variously. But the discussion is unimportant for our purpose and so we do not enter into it. It is, however, to be noticed in this connection that the Jaina thinkers held that a soul could never (except when it has attained perfect knowledge) be bereft of mati (sensuous) and sruta (verbal) knowledge. Even the one-sensed organisms are held to be possessed of these. To be bereft of these is to lose the nature of soul and become non-soul. Now, the one-sensed organism has the feeling of touch and so can have matijnana (sensuous cognition), but how can it possess sruta-jnana (verbal knowledge)? This is a difficult problem to answer. Jinabhadra says that although the one-sensed organisms do not possess dravya-sruta (symbols--written or spoken) they possess bhava-sruta (potential verbal knowledge) which can be likened to the verbal knowledge of a sleeping ascetic (yati). But even bhava-sruta is possible only with those who have the capacity to speak and to hear and with none else, and it is nothing but the mental disposition that precedes a speech or follows a hearing. 5 And as such how can it be possible for the one-sensed organisms who have neither the capacity to speak nor the capacity to hear? Jinabhadra answers this objection as follows; 'Even as subtle internal sensuous cognitions are possible in spite of the absence of the external physical sense-organ, so 'potential verbal knowledge' is possible even for (the one-sensed) such as the earth-bodied (beings) in spite of the absence of dravya-sruta.' It is admitted that the one-sensed 1 NSu, 41. 2 Cf. egindiya niyayam duyannani, tam jaha-mai-annani ya suya-annani ya--quoted from Agama in Byhadurtti, Vibh, IOI. Also see BhSu VIII. 2 (317). The mati and sruta of the one-sensed organisms are, as a rule, called ajnana 'perverted knowledge' inasmuch as they are mithyadrsti and the jnana of a mithyadrsti is held to be ajnana. See Prajnapanasutra, pada 29. 3 Cf. savvajivanam pi ya nam akkharassa anantabhago niccugghadio citthai. jai puna so 'vi avarijja tenam jivo ajivattam pavija--NSu, 42. 4 davvasuyanubhavammi vi bhavasuyam sutta-jaino vya-ViBh, IOI. 5 bhavasuyam bhasa-soya-laddhino jujjae na iyarassa bhasabhimuhassa jayam souna ya jam havejjahi.-Vibh, 102. 6 jaha suhumam bhavimdiyananam davvimdiyavarohe vi taha davvasuyabhave bhavasuyam patthivainam.-Vibh, 103. Page #89 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. organisms have neither the tongue to speak nor the ear to listen, nor have they any symbols of their own. But nevertheless, according to the Jaina thinkers, the one-sensed organisms are capable of potential verbal thinking. Though we are unable to know the exact nature of the process of their thinking, yet we can have some inkling of its nature by the consideration of the external activities of the one-sensed organisms. The Brhadvrtti1 gives a number of instances from the plant world to prove by inference that even the one-sensed plants can hear sound, see colour, smell odour, and experience taste, and says that as in these cases the sensuous functions are carried out by the internal capacity of the organisms even in the absence of the external sense-organs so also can there be possible the existence of bhavasruta in the absence of dravya-sruta.2 Dravya-sruta is the exponent of thinking while bhava-sruta is such thinking itself. The question whether thinking without language is possible is the upshot of our enquiry. The Jaina scriptures recognize ten instincts (sanna) in the one-sensed organisms-such as the instincts of hunger, fear, sex attraction, possession etc. The Brhadvrtti says that these instincts are impossible without bhava-sruta 'internal capacity for verbal thinking"." The famous commentator Malayagiri maintains that the instinct is a kind of desire and quotes a passage from the Avasyakatika, which says that the instinct for food means 'desire for food', is born of the feeling of hunger, and is a particular disposition of the soul." He further maintains that a desire is a determinate willing for the acquisition of the object of desire. It is of the form 'such and such object is wholesome for me; it will be good if I can secure it'. Of course, in the case of one-sensed organisms the desires are not couched in articulate language. But nevertheless they must have some sort of instrument 52 1 On ViBh, 103. 2 Cf. tatas ca yathai 'tesu dravyendriyasattve 'pi etad bhavendriyajanyam juanam sakala-jana-prasiddham asti, tatha dravyasrutabhave bhavasrutam api bhavisyati-Brhadvrtti on ViBh, 103. N.B.-Bhavendriya is the capacity of the soul to have various sensuous experiences, dravyendriya means the external physical sense-organ. 3 kati nam bhamte! egimdiyanam sannao pannattao? goyama! dasa, tam jaha aharasanna bhaya-sanna mehunasanna pariggaha-sanna koha-sanna manasanna maya-sanna lobha-sanna oha-sanna loga-sanna ya tti-Quoted in NSVr on sutra 40. Also see BhSu, VII. 8 (295); Prajnapana, samjnapada (8). 4 na cai 'tah samjna bhava-srutam antareno 'papadyante-Brhadvrtti, ViBh, 103. 5 samjna ca abhilasa ucyate yata uktam Avasyakatikayam-ahara-samjna aharabhilasah ksudvedaniya-prabhavah khalv atmaparinama-visesah-Malayagiri's tika (p. 140) on NSu. 6 Ibid. Page #90 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ NATURE OF SAINA 53 for their formation. This leads us to the postulation of a peculiar capacity of the soul. This capacity is called bhava-sruta. The other characteristics viz. gamika and agamika-angapravista and angabahya refer to peculiar categories of scriptural texts and so, being unimportant for our purpose, are not discussed here." We have now seen how sruta which originally meant 'scripture' gradually came to mean any symbol, written or spoken, and finally was even identified with inarticulate verbal knowledge. This development of meaning is not, strictly speaking, chronological. It is the gradual subtlety of speculation that is responsible for this development. The self-same thinker could have started from the conception of sruta as scripture and reached the conception of sruta as inarticulate verbal knowledge. The speculations recorded in Jaina scriptures on this subject are so rich, subtle and varied that it is difficult to ascertain the original contributions of the later Jaina authors. Almost every idea that we have been dealing with can be traced in the Agamas in some form or other. Our statement about development is to be judged with this proviso. We have hitherto based our enquiry on the Avasyakaniryukti and the Nandi Sutra and have referred to the other sources only occasionally for the sake of elucidation. After the Nandi Sutra we come to the Visesavasyakabhasya of Jinabhadra. It presents the theory in a developed form as will be apparent from what follows. We shall end our enquiry of the sruta-jnana by drawing a clear line of demarcation between the mati-jnana and the sruta-jnana. NATURE OF SAM JNA We have referred to samjni-sruta and asamjni-sruta. Here asarjna does not mean total absence of any samjna, but only an indistinct presence of it. The capacity by which one remembers t bygone past and ponders over the coming future is dirghakaliki (or simply kaliki) sarjna.3 Only those who have mind4 can possess this capacity. A being possessing this samjna enjoys the capacity for the utilization of all the sense-organs including mind. The human beings as well as the sub-human beings born of wombs (garbhaja) possess this For information see NSu, 43 et seq. The first Karmagrantha (gatha 7) records an additional mode of considering sruta-jnana, which, however, has no epistemological value and so is omitted here. 2 Cf. Vibh, 506-7. 3 Ibid., 508. 4 The mind, according to the Jainas, is an instrument of thinking, which a soul makes for itself out of the groups of material atoms fit for the purpose and becomes capable of thinking through its agency. Of course only the developed souls have the capacity to form minds. Page #91 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 54 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. samjna. The five-sensed sammurchanaja beings i.e. gross-bodied beings born without sex relation) possess this capacity in a very small measure and as such are regarded as asamjnins in comparison with those possessing a developed capacity. Those beings who can discriminate between the desirable and the undesirable and can act accordingly for the maintenance of their bodies, but cannot think on the past or future, are called hetuvada-sarjnins. The organisms having two or more sense-organs are included in this category. The comparatively inactive one-sensed organisms such as the earth-bodied beings are called asamjnins in comparison with the organisms possessing two or more sense-organs. Now we come to the destivadopadesiki sarjna. A being having right faith and possessed of knowledge due to subsidence-cum-destruction of karmic veil is called sarjnin from the point of view of drsti (faith); and such being having wrong faith is called. asamjnin. A being possessed of perfect knowledge born of complete destruction of all karmic veil is not samjnin inasmuch as he, being omniscient, cannot possess the functions of recollection and pondering of future, which constitute samjna.5 A being having wrong or perverted faith is mithyadrsti, and is also called asamjnin, because his samjna, though competent to discriminate between what is wholesome and what is unwholesome, is, from the point of view of dysti (faith), perverted or misplaced. We have thus studied the three types of samjna. There remains now one more type called uha orogha-sarjna. We have translated this sarnjna as instinct and have also enumerated its varieties.? Jinabhadra says that this uha or ogha-sanjna (which belongs to such beings as the earth-bodied) is not to be called sarjna in comparison with the hetuvada-samjna ; similarly, the hetuvada-samjna is not to be called samjna in comparison with the kaliki-sarjna ; and similarly the kalikisamjna is not be called samjna in comparison with the drstivadasamjna. The samjnins and asamjnins are thus to be considered relatively. Jinabhadra gives the following classification of sarjnin beings. The five classes of one-sensed organisms possess uha-sarjna ; the organisms possessing two or more sense-organs possess hetu-sarjna ; the denizens of heaven and hell as well as the beings born of womb possess kaliki-sarjna ; the samjna of the samyagdrsti chadmastha (a 1 See Byhadvitti, Vibh, 509. 2 Ibid., Vibh, 511. 3 See Vibh, 515-516 and Byhadurtti. 4 sammaditthi sanni samte nane khauvasamiyammi asanni micchattammi ditthivaovaesena.-Vibh, 517. 5 See Vibh, 518. Cf. Vibh, 519-520. ? Supra p. 52. Oha orogha is a particular kind of samjna (instinct). But Jinabhadra uses the term to indicate the ten instincts. 8 Vibh, 522. Page #92 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II MATI AND SRUTA 55 being involved in the world but having right faith) is sruta-jnana (in other words, such a being possesses drstivada-samjna); the kevalins (omniscient beings), however, are free from the function of mati-jnana (sensuous cognition) and as such are beyond samjna. MATI AND SRUTA As regards the relation of mati and sruta, Umasvati says that sruta is, as a rule, accompanied by mati while it is not necessary that a mati should be accompanied by sruta. But the Nandi Sutra says 'Where there is abhinibodhika-jnana (that is, mati), there is sruta-jnana, and where there is sruta-jnana there is abhinibodhika-jnana. Both these are mutually involved. But nevertheless the preceptors (Acaryas) notice this distinction: abhinibodhika is so called because it perceives directly (abhinibudhyate), while sruta is so called because it hears (srnoti). And as sruta is preceded by mati, mati cannot be preceded by sruta.'3 According to Nandi-Sutra thus the relation between mati and sruta is one of mutual concomitance. The one is necessarily accompanied by the other. Pujyapada Devanandi and his follower Akalanka also endorse this view. But here the question is whether it is the matyupayogas and srutopayoga that are upheld to accompany each other or it is their labdhis that are referred to. We do not get any clear statement on this in the above references. But it is very probable that it is the labdhis that are held to accompany each other. The fact that the Jaina thinkers unanimously maintain the impossibility of the simultaneous occurrence of two upayogas also lends support to our hypothesis. Moreover, mati and sruta qua labdhis are unanimously held to accompany each other. Furthermore, on this hypothesis, the above statement of Umasvati that mati is not necessarily followed by sruta also finds proper explanation, because in that case there would be no objection against admitting that matyupayoga is not necessarily followed by srutopayoga. It is beyond doubt that Umasvati refers to upayoga and not to labdhi in the above statement. It will not be out of place in this connection to add a short paragraph on the conception of upayoga and labdhi. The consciousness in 1 Vibh, 523-524. 2 srutajnanasya matijnanena niyatah sahabhavah tatpurvakatvat. yasya srutajnanam tasya niyatam matijnanam yasya tu matijnanam tasya srutajnanam syad va na ve 'ti-TSubh, I, 31. 3 NSu, 24 4 See SSi, I. 30. Of course, it does not state the view in so many words. But it follows easily from what it states; TRa, I. 9 (varttika 20) states.... yatra matis tatra srutam yatra srutam tatra matir iti. 5 Upayoga means 'active consciousness'. 6 Labdhi means 'dormant consciousness'. 7 iha laddhimai-suyaim samakalaim na tu 'vaogo sim-ViBh, 108. Page #93 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 56 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. its state of dormancy is called labdhi. In other words, the dormant capacity of the soul for knowledge is labdhi. Upayoga, on the other hand, is consciousness in its state of activity. The soul is called upayukta or upayogavan when it is actually engaged in knowing something. Mere capacity for knowledge without actual knowledge is labdhi. Now we come to the problem of differentiation between mati and sruta. DIFFERENTIATION OF MATI AND SRUTA Siddhasena Divakara, in his Niscayadvatrimsika, maintains that sruta is not anything over and above mati, because the admission of the separate identity of sruta is futile and involves undesirable consequences.' Among the later logicians it is only Upadhyaya Yasovijaya who elaborates this position of Siddhasena. We shall deal with this view of Yasovijaya in the concluding portion of this topic. Jinabhadra says that the knowledge that is due to the activity of sense-organs and the mind, is couched in proper words in accordance with conventional usage), and is capable of expressing its object (to others) is bhavasruta while the rest is mati. Tha (speculation), avaya (perceptual judgment) etc. are also couched in proper words, but nevertheless they fall in the category of mati, inasmuch, as there is no deliberate application of language in these cases of knowledge. Simple verbal association is not considered sufficient to raise a cognition to the status of sruta. In our ordinary perceptions we associate the object with its name as soon as we perceive it. But we do not go any further. But there are cases of perceptual cognitions which do not stop at simple verbal association, but continue further into discursive thought with the help of language. This continuation leads them to the category of sruta-jnana. Thus those cognitions of objects, which are totally free from all verbal association or at best are conversant with the mere names of their objects, fall in the category of mati, while their further continuations with the help of the language fall in the category of sruta. In fact, the versatile knowledge of the objects, that follows in the wake of perceptual cognition of these objects and whose versatil proportion to the learnedness of the cognizer is sruta-jnana.3 The more learned a person is the more versatile will be his sruta-jnana. 1 vaiyarthyatiprasangabhyam na matyabhyadhikam srutam. --Niscayadvatrimsika, 12. 2 imdiyamano-nimittam jam vispanam suyanusarena niyayatthutti-samattham tam bhavasuyam mai sesam.-ViBh, 100. 3 Cf. . . . srutam apurvavisayam, ekam ghatam indriyanindriyabhyam niscitya 'yam ghata iti tajjatiyam anyam anekadesa-kala-rupadi-vilaksanam apurvam adhigacchati yat tac chrutam, nana-prakararthaprarupanaparan yat tad va srutam... TRa, I. 9 (varttika 32). Page #94 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II] The sruta-jnana, according to the Jaina thinker, is as a rule preceded by mati-jnana. This conception owes its origin perhaps to the old conception of sruta as the knowledge born through the sense-organ of hearing. But in fact the knowledge of the object meant by the sound (word) perceived by the sense-organ of hearing is sruta proper. And it is also admitted to be so. The simple perception by the sense-organ of hearing is a case of mati. It is maintained that all cases of verbal cognitions born through whatever sense-organ are to be regarded auditory perceptions, inasmuch as verbal expressions accompanying these cognitions are by their nature competent to be cognized by the auditory organ. Articulated words are perceived through the auditory organ without doubt. But words, which clothe our thoughts, though not actually perceived by the auditory organ, are also potentially the objects of auditory cognition. The employment of words in thought, therefore, is symptomatic of auditory cognition, and the operation of the auditory organ is more or less an accident. It is in this sense that every sruta-jnaana is preceded by mati-jnana of the type of auditory sense-perception. Even pure mental thinking can be considered to be accompanied by such virtual auditory sense-perception, because of the association of words which fall. within the province of auditory perception. Jinabhadra says 'The knowledge of the speaker or the hearer, that is informed with his previous learning, is sruta. And the knowledge of the self-same person, free from association with language, is mati'. Jinabhadra quotes an opinion which sought to differentiate mati from sruta on the ground that the latter is associated with words and the former is devoid of them, and refutes it by saying 'If all types of mati were regarded as bereft of association with words there would be lack of iha (speculation) etc. (which follow in the wake of avagraha and are bound up with verbal association) because without verbal expressions there can be no conceptual thinking which invariably affiliates a particular with a class-character. And consequently the discrimination between the characteristics of a post and a man will be an impossibility.' If all perceptual cognitions were free from verbal association there would be total lack of determinate cognitions. The determination of the specific characteristics requires help of language, and as such our perceptions are, as a rule, associated with words when they become determinate. If all perceptions were dumb, they would serve no purpose of life. Jinabhadra concludes that with reference to 1 Cf. soimdiovaladdhi hoi suyam.-ViBh, 117. 2 Cf. DIFFERENTIATION OF MATI AND SRUTA sabhilapa-vijnanam sesendriya-dvarena 'pyutpannam yogyataya srotrendriyopalabdhir eva mantavyam, abhilapasya sarvasya 'pi srotrendriyagrahanayogyatvat-Brhadvrtti on ViBh, 117; also see ViBh, 125. bhanao sunao va suyam tam jam iha suyanusari vinnanam donham pi suyaiyam jam vinnanam tayam buddhi-ViBh, 121. 4 ViBh, 162-163. JP-8 57 Page #95 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 58 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. words qua concepts (knowledge the mati can be 'associated with' as well as 'bereft of' words but with reference to words qua articulated symbols, the mati is, as a rule, bereft of words; the sruta, on the other hand, whether it is dravya-sruta or bhava-sruta, can be both saksara (associated with words) as well as anaksara (bereft of words). 1 Avagraha falls in the category of mati bereft of words while iha etc. fall in the category of mati associated with words qua concepts (knowledge). Articulated symbols are not concepts and thus a fortiori they are excluded from the category of mati-jnana Dravya-sruta is saksara when it consists of written or spoken words, and it is anaksara when it consists of physical gestures. The bhava-sruta is called saksara because it contains words qua concepts and it is also called niraksara because it does not contain words qua external symbols written or spoken. Jinabhadra further quotes an opinion which distinguished mati from sruta on the ground that the former, like a dumb person, can reveal its content to the cognizing self alone, while the latter, like a talking man, can reveal its contents to others as well. This reminds us of the position of Pujyapada Devanandi who maintains that, as distinguished from other pramanas (organs of knowledge), the sruta serves the twofold purpose of enlightening the cognizing self as well as others the former function being done on account of its self-revealing nature and the latter through the instrumentality of language. The Sruta qua knowledge reveals its contents to the cognizing self alone while the sruta qua verbal expression reveals its contents to others as well.But Jinabhadra says that both mati and sruta are essentially cases of knowledge, and as such cannot reveal their contents to others. Of course, sruta qua words can convey its meaning to others. But Jinabhadra says that physical gestures, which can cause mati, also reveal their meaning to others. These physical gestures stand to matijnana in the same relation as the words stand to sruta-jnana, and as such can be compared to the latter. Thus the cause of mati can reveal its meaning to others exactly in the same way as the cause of sruta does. The above line of demarcation between mati and sruta thus is proved invalid.4 But finally Jinabhadra concedes that dravya-sruta is a unique instrument of conveying knowledge to others, that it is designated as sruta by established convention and that there is nothing known as dravya-mati.5 In view of these considerations it is advisable to accept the line of demarcation. Furthermore, he says that physical I ubhayam bhavakkharao, anakkharam hojja vamjanakkbarao mainanam, suttar puna ubhayam pi anakkhara-kkharao.---Vibh, 170. 2 See ViBh, 171. 3 tatra svartham pramanam srutavarjyam. srutam punah svartham bhavati parartham ca, jnanatmakam svartharn vacanatmakam parartham.-SSi, on TSu, 1. 6. 4 See ViBh, 173. 5 Ibid., 174. Page #96 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II] NON-DIFFERENCE OF MATI AND SRUTA 59 gestures also are words with meanings, because they too convey the intention and the agent also makes use of them for lack of words in order to convey his intention." NON-DIFFERENCE OF MATI AND SRUTA We have now drawn a line of demarcation between mati and sruta, which is more or less in accordance with the traditional way of thought. But let us now study the logical implications of the traditional conception. We have seen that iha (speculation) etc., though they are associated with words, fall in the category of mati and not sruta. The ground given is that the scriptures recognize them to be so and, furthermore, that language does not play the determining role of a condition of mati as it does regarding sruta. In iha etc. there is only the minimum possible association with words, which is rather the outcome than the generating condition. Words come in only in order to make the cognition determinate and firm'. The perceptual character still remains there. The background of cognizer's learning plays only a silent part. It does not actively influence the cognition like the senseorgan. But this position is not without its weakness. The difficulty can be put thus: Can our cognitions be associated with words, and at the same time remain free from the influence of our previous training in verbal usage? If not, why should not such cognitions as are associated with words be considered as sruta? It is perhaps in order to avoid this difficulty that Akalanka held the view that our cognitions are mati so long as they are free from verbal association, and fall in the category of sruta as soon as they are associated with words.2 Pujyapada Devanandi says that all organs of valid knowledge excepting sruta are for one's own self and not for others, inasmuch as they cannot express themselves to others. This statement of Pujyapada does not mean to say that all cases of knowledge except sruta are devoid of words. It only means that they are not expressed in language to outsiders and that they fall in the category of sruta when they are So expressed. We can interpret the above statement of Akalanka in this light. It will then mean that all processes of knowledge, perceptual or otherwise, fall in the category of mati so long as they are not expressed in words, and that they are transformed into sruta as soon as they are so expressed. This meaning follows from the statement of Akalanka himself as well. Akalanka thus widens the scope of mati and at the same time distinguishes it from sruta on the ground that mati is confined to the knower himself while sruta reveals its contents to others as well. In one word, mati is subjective and private (svartha) while sruta is 1 Ibid., 175. 3 Cf. tatra svartham pramanan 4 Cf. LT, 10-11 and Viviti. 2 LT, 10-II. srutavarjyam.-SSi on TSu, 1. 6. Page #97 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 60 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. subjective as well as objective (parartha), private as well as public. But this line of demarcation is too superficial. It is immaterial whether a knowledge is expressed in words or not. Mere verbal expression cannot be taken to confer a new status on knowledge. To be logical, therefore, all such knowledge should be regarded as mati. This is the logical consummation of Akalanka's position. And this was anticipated by Siddhasena Divakara when he said, as we have already stated, that there is no sruta over and above mati. Upadhyaya Yasovijaya has elaborated this position in his Jnanabindu-prakarana. Siddhasena Divakara had asserted that the admission of sruta as separate from mati involves the faults of redundancy (vaiyarthya) and unwarranted extension (atiprasanga). Yasovijaya only amplifies and illustrates these faults. He says that the conception of sruta as separate from mati is futile inasmuch as the function of the former can be adequately fulfilled by the latter. Moreover, if the non-difference of mati and sruta be admitted, the necessity of the postulation of a separate avagraha for the apaya (perceptual judgment) bringing up the rear of a generic verbal cognition (sabda-jnana or sruta-jnana) on account of a further enquiry for a more specific characteristic of the same object is also avoided, because in this new conception the generic verbal cognition itself will serve as the basic avagraha of the whole process which is a case of mati-jnana." The unity of the process will remain undisturbed even when it becomes intricate due to the entrance of verbal knowledge (sruta-jnana), because, says Yasovijaya, when it is acknowledged that there is no disturbance in the unity of the process of srutopayoga (verbal knowledge) even when it is interspersed with more than one process of mati, what possible harm can there be if the process of mati is conceived to preserve its integrity even when the srutopayoga follows in the wake of it.3 Besides, if a separate status were accorded to verbal knowledge on the ground that it is non-perceptual the undesirable consequence of the admission of a respective separate category for inference, recollection, recognition etc. would follow, because these also are non-perceptual. But the Jaina thinkers cannot accept this consequence without throwing overboard their whole theory of knowledge. The Jainas accept inference, recollection etc. to belong to the category of mati. What then is the ground for treating sruta as a separate category from mati? Again, if mati is 1 vaiyarthyatiprasangabhyam na matyabhyadhikam srutam. -Niscavadvatrimsika, 12. 2 Cf. navyas tu srutopayogo matyupayogan na prthak, matyupayogenai 'va tatkaryopapattau tatparthakya-kalpanaya vyarthatvat, ata eva sabda janyasamanya-jnanottararn visesa-jijnasayam tanmulaka-matyapayamsa-pravsttau na pithagavagraha-kalpanagauravari sabdasamanya-jnanasyai 'va tatra avagrahatvat, JBP, p. 16. 3 Ibid. Page #98 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ AVADHI 61 conceived as twofold viz. (1) perceptuali and (2) non-perceptual, and avagraha, iha etc. are held to fall in the former and inference, recollection etc. are held to fall in the latter group, then logic will demand that sruta also should be treated as a case of non-perceptual mati and not as a separate category. Thus does Yasovijaya vindicate the position of the great logician Siddhasena Divakara whom he often quotes in his treatises with great veneration, and sometimes refers to him by the term navya (neo-logician). Siddhasena was a great logical genius and Yasovijaya, as an inspired admirer of him, gives him the status of a neo-logician of ancient times in view of his pure logical speculations that were the characteristic of the age that was to come after a millennium from his own time. AVADHI The Jainas believe in the capacity of the soul to know all things irrespective of temporal and spatial distance. The past as well as the future can be perceived as vividly as the present. The soul is inherently capable of perceiving all things with all their characteristics -past, present and future. But this capacity of the soul is obstructed by jnanavaraniya karman which veils the soul and permits it only an imperfect comprehension of the world. The nature and extent of the knowing capacity of a soul, therefore, depend upon the nature of the veil. But never can the veil obstruct the knowing capacity completely because in that case the soul would become as good as non-soul. The knowledge of the soul is never totally obstructed by the veil even as the light of the sun or the moon is never totally obstructed even by the darkest clouds. There is always some glimpse of the external world, however imperfect or sometimes even perverted it may be. For the sake of systematic investigation, the various states of knowledge, ranging from the most imperfect and perverted knowledge of the onesensed organisms up to the most perfect knowledge of the kevalin (omniscient), have been classified into five categories viz. mati, sruta, avadhi, manahparyaya and kevala. Of these, we have dealt with mati and sruta which, as we have seen, are dependent upon the help of the various external organs. But now we come to those categories which do not depend upon any sense-organ. Of course, even in the case of 1 samvyavaharika-pratyaksa. 2 yadi ca avagrahadibhedah samvyavaharika-pratyaksarupasyai 'va matijnanasya sutre proktah, anumanadikam tu paroksa-matijnanam arthatah siddham iti 'syate, tarhi srutasabda-vyapadesyam sabda-jnanam api paroksa-mati-jnanam eva 'ngikriyatam.--JBP, p. 16. 3 The term navyah in footnote 2 page 60 refers to Siddhasena. 4 jai puna so 'vi avarijja tenam jivo ajivattar pavijja.-sutthu vi mehasamudaye, hoi pabha carda-suranam' -NS, 42. Page #99 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 62 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. mati and sruta, the role of the sense-organs is a subordinate one because they ony serve to eliminate the veil which envelops the knowledge of the object already there. But nevertheless they have some function of their own, in the absence of which knowledge would be impossible. The other three categories of knowledge, however, are completely free from the dependence upon the sense-organs, and as such, as we have already stated, are called pratyaksa proper. The conception of these categories will certainly appear dogmatic, but nevertheless it should be borne in mind that the vital source of the Jaina theory of knowledge lies in this conception. If the soul has the capacity to know, it must know independently of any other external condition. Knowledge is not spatial or temporal relation, but is a capacity. Distance, spatial or temporal, is not a hindrance for the soul. It can obstruct physical movement. But on the capacity to know it cannot have any such influence. If the soul cannot penetrate into the past or future, or see through distance, it is due to the delimitation of its knowing capacity by the obstructive veil, and not due to any inherent privation. Knowledge is as independent as existence. As existence does not depend upon some other existence for its existence, so knowledge does not depend upon something else for its knowledge. Knowledge is there in its own right as its objects are there in their own right. No physical contact, direct or indirect, with objects is necessary for the emergence of knowledge. The question of physical contact or limited distance or size comes in only when the inherent capacity is delimited. And this delimitation even is not ultimately due to some extraneous condition. It is due to the soul itself which has acquired the karmic veil by its own activity. Let us now revert to our subject proper. The possession of avadhi-jnana is a birthright of the denizens of heaven and hell. The avadhi-jnana in their case is bhava-pratyaya (due to birth). The avadhi of the human beings as well as of the fivesensed sub-human beings is due to the destruction-cum-subsidence of the relevant karmic veil (ksayopasama-nimitta). It is acquired by merit and is also called guna-pratyaya (due to merit). The distinction, however, is only apparent. The denizens of heaven and hell are endowed with avadhi by their very birth and hence their avadhi is called bhava-pratyaya. Other beings get it only occasionally and as a It is interesting to note that Bhutabali in his Mahabandha (p. 24, Kashi, 1947 edition) admits the instrumentality of manas in manahparyaya. But Akalanka interprets in his TRa, p. 58) manas as atman. So far as my knowledge goes Bhutabali had no following. 2 SthSu, 71; NSu, 7; TSu, I. 22. 3 SthSu, 71; NSu, 8; TSu, I. 23 and its Bhasya. 4 See NSu, gatha 63 ; also see TRa, I. 20: dvividho 'vadhir bhava-gunapratyaya-bhedat. See also Vibh, 572. Page #100 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II] result of special merit and hence in their case it is called ksayopasamanimitta or gunanimitta. In fact, however, avadhi is, as a rule, ksayopasama-nimitta in all cases. It is necessary in the case of the denizens of heaven and hell because they have secured the destruction and subsidence of the veiling karman by the acquisition of requisite merits and only occasional in the case of other beings for the reason already given, and as such is classified into two separate categories.' AVADHI By avadhi-jnana one can intuit only those things which have shape or form (rupin). The intuitions differ in scope and durability with different persons on account of the difference of their merits. One endowed with the highest type of avadhi can intuit all the things having form. In point of space his intuition extends over a space that could be occupied by a countless number of space-units of the size of loka (the inhabited universe) and as regards time it penetrates countless number of cycles, both past and future. But as regards the modes, it cannot know all. It knows only an infinitesimal part of them though, of course, even this tiny part consists of an infinite number of modes.* The Jainas conceive infinity as having infinite gradation and as such there is no absurdity in this conception. The lowest type of avadhi can extend to a very small fraction of an angulas and know the infinite number of things having form (ruvi davvaim) that lie therein. In point of time it can penetrate only a small part of an avalika (a small measure of time less than a second) and as regards modes it can know an infinite number of them.7 63 In this connection it is essential to have some idea of the Jaina conception of the relative subtlety of time, space, matter and modes. The ultimate constituent of time is an infinitesimal indivisible unit called samaya 'time-point' or 'instant'. This time-point is beyond human comprehension and can be intuited only by the omniscient. In the same way space is also conceived as having pradesas (spacepoints) as its ultimate indivisible units. But these space-points are subtler than the time-points. It is conceived that the number of spacepoints of a small space of one angula is equal to the number of time 1 Cf. ViBh, 574 TRa, I. 22. 3. 2 Cf. ANir, 45; NSu, 16; TSu, I. 28. 3 The NS uses both the terms janai and pasai in order to distinguish between avadhi-jnana and avadhi-darsana. We shall, however, use both 'know' and 'intuit' without discrimination.. In fact, the distinction between avadhijnana and avadhi-darsana is not very essential too in this context. 4 See ANir, 45 (ViBh, 685); NSu, 16. 5 amgulassa asamkhijjai bhagam janai pasai. An amgula is a very small measure. An infinite number of atoms can exist in one point of space according to the Jainas. We shall make the point clear in the next paragraph. 7 See NSu, 16. Page #101 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 64 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. . points of a countless number of cycles of time. But an atom of matter is still subtler. An infinite number of atoms can be accommodated in one space-point. Again, every atom has an infinite number of modes and as such the modes are conceived as subtler than the atoms. Thus of a time-point, space-point, a material atom and a mode, the succeeding one is subtler than the preceding one.' It, therefore, naturally follows that with the increase of the capacity for penetration into time, there is necessarily an increase in the capacity for extending over space, and comprehending more of matter and modes ; but extension in space does not necessarily involve more penetration into time, nor does comprehension of more matter and modes involve necessary spatial extension and temporal penetration. The rationale of the argument can be brought out as follows: A time-point is more extensive as compared with a space-point and so it is held that it is easier to extend over one space-point than to penetrate one time-point. So it is conceived that temporal penetration is necessarily accompanied with spatial extension. But the reverse is not true. Now as each space-point can contain an infinite number of atoms, and each atom has an infinite number of modes, it is conceived that with the increase of scope in space, there is necessarily an increase in the number of things and their modes that are comprehended, but the comprehension of a greater number of things and modes does not necessarily involve more penetration into time and extension in space. Comprehension of a greater number of things and modes may be due to the clarity of the intuition as well and this is another reason why it does not necessarily involve spatial or temporal extension. Similarly, although the highest type of avadhi can comprehend all the atoms of a space-point, it cannot comprehend all their modes because the comprehension of all the modes is possible only on the attainment of the maximum of clarity which materializes only on the dawn of omniscience. We have stated that by avadhi one can know only those things which have form or shape. The formless things such as the souls, dharma (substance that helps motion) and adharma (substance that helps rest), space and time, are not intuited by avadhi. It is only the rupin contents of space and time that are known by it. Its scope and durability is determined by the capacity of the person possessed of it. The Avasyakaniryukti gives a detailed description of avadhi from fourteen points of view viz. its varieties, its spatial extension, shape of space it extends over etc.3 The Nandi Sutra, however, gives only six varieties of avadhi that are possible in the case of a meritorious homeless mendicant with a few sub-varieties. We do not enter into details 1 See ANir, 37 ; also see Vibh, 621-3. ? See A Nir, 36. See ANir, 26-28. 4 See NS, 9-15 ; see also TSuBh on I. 23. Page #102 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 11] MANAHPARYAY A-JNANA 65 in view of the fact that they have little bearing on epistemological enquiry. Besides, they easily follow from what we have aiready stated, and as such do not afford important information. MANAHPARYAYA-JNANA In order to understand the nature of the manahparyaya-jnana it is necessary that the nature of the stuff of which the mind is made up should be properly understood. The Jainas conceive an infinite number of groups, called varganas, of atoms. The first vargana is conceived to contain only such atoms as remain alone and solitary and have not formed composite bodies with others. The second group contains composites of two atoms. The third group contains composites of three atoms. And so on. By this process, we arrive at a group which contains composites of an infinite? number of atoms, which is fit for the making up of the audarika (gross) body such as of men and animals. This group is followed by an infinite number of groups which are all competent for making the stuff of audarika body. Then follows a number of groups which are incompetent for any kind of body. Again, by the same process we reach an infinite number of groups which are competent to form the stuff of the vaikriya (subtle) body such as of celestial beings. And by following the same process, as above, another infinite number of groups are reached which are capable of forming the stuff of aharaka body such as of an ascetic having special powers. Similarly by repeating the same process we obtain groups which are competent for taijasa (luminous) body, bhasa (speech), anapana (respiration), manas (mind) and karman. It is to be noticed in this connection that a composite body of the group that follows consists of greater number of atoms but occupies less space in comparison with a composite body of the group that precedes. Thus a composite body of the karma-vargana consists of more atoms but occupies less space in comparison with a composite body of manovargana, which, again, consists of more atoms but occupies less space in comparison with a composite body of the anapana-vargana. And so on. From this description we can have an idea of the constituent stuff of the manas (mind). The Avasyakaniryukti says that the manapajjavanana (=manahparyaya-jnana) is the revealer of the objects thought by the minds of the people, is limited to the manusakhitta (abode of human beings), is due to merit and is possessed by one having character (that is, a 1 We also get the terms manahparyaya and manah paryava. Cf. Vibh, 83. 2 The Jainas, as we have already stated, conceive an infinite gradation of 'infinity'. 3 See ANir, 39. Also see ViBh, 631-37 and the Byhaduytti. JP-9 Page #103 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 66 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. homeless ascetic). The Sthananga recognizes two varieties of it viz. rjumati and vipulamati.? Umasvati distinguishes the former from the latter on the ground that the latter is purer and everlasting that is, lasts up to the dawn of omniscience), while the former is less pure and sometimes falters too.3 Distinguishing between avadhi and manahparyaya, Umasvati says 'One possessed of manahparyaya knows only an infinitesimal part of the objects of avadhi. He knows a greater number of states of the material objects that form the contents of the invisible thinking process of the mind and are situated in the region inhabited by human beings.'4 According to him also, thus, it is the material objects and their states, thought of by the mind of others, that are intuited by manahparyaya.5 The mind undergoes a process of change while thinking, and the objective contents of this process are intuited by the manahparyaya. Jinabhadra, however, says that one possessed of such knowledge intuits the states of the mind-substance directly, but knows the external objects thought of by the mind only by way of inference. The Byhadurtti argues: 'A thinker may think of a material as well as a non-material object (e.g. a cognition). But it is not possible for one who is not omniscient to intuit directly a nonmaterial object. And, therefore, it follows that one possessed of manah paryaya knows the object thought of (by others) only by way of inference."? Pujyapada Devanandi, however, holds a different view. Defining manahparyaya he says: "Due to its association with the manas (mind), the object of the manas (mind) of others is called manas and the paryayanam 'knowledge of that (object) is manahparyaya. It is not a mati-jnana because the mind is only an inactive background and does not make any contribution in such knowledge). It is exclusively due to the potency of destruction-cum-subsidence, although it is designated by means of the manas of oneself or of another on account of its association with it). The case is on a par with the usage in the proposition 'Behold the moon in the sky' in which the moon is 1 manapajjava-nanam puna jana-mana-pari-cintiyattha-payadanam manusa-khitta nibaddham guna-paccaiyam carittavao.-ANir, 76. 2 SthSu, 71. 3 See TSuBh on I. 25 and the sika. 4 avadhi-jnana-visayasya 'nantabhagam manahparyaya-jnani janite, rupidravyani manorahasya-vicaragatani ca manusa-ksetra-paryapannani vieuddhatarani ceti.-TSuBh on I. 29. 5 The commentator Siddhasenagamin, however, interprets Umasvati in the light of Jinabhadra's conception of manahparyaya as intuiting the mental modes and knowing the objects thought of by the mind by means of inference. See Tika on TSuBh, I. 24. 6 tenavabhasie una janai bajjhe 'numanenam-Vibh, 814. 7 cintako hi murtam amurtam ca vastu cinta yet. na ca chadmastho 'murtam saksat pasyati, tato jnayate anumanad eva cintaniyar vastv avagacchati. Brhadvytti on Vibh, 814. Page #104 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 11] MANAHPARYAY A-JNANA pointed out by means of the sky.' He thus maintains, like Umasvati, that the external object itself is intuited by manahparyaya. Akalanka supports this view and seems to refute the position of Jinabhadra. He says that all the characteristics of a pratyaksa are present in the manahparyaya inasmuch as it is independent of the sense-organs and the mind, and as such it should not be regarded as an inference (anumana) which depends upon the instruction of others (for the knowledge of the relation between the probans and the probandum) as well as upon the sense-organs such as the eye. It is, however, to be noticed in this connection that this contention refers only to the object of manahparyaya and not to the nature of it as pratyaksa. Both Jinabhadra and Akalanka regard it as pratyaksa but the contention is whether the external objects are intuited by it. Jinabhadra holds that the external objects are known by inference while Akalanka maintains that they are directly intuited by manahparyaya as they are associated with the mind being thought of by it. Jinabhadra holds that the function of manahparyaya is limited to the intuition of the states of the mind engaged in thinking, while it is the function of inference to know the external things thought of by the mind. Akalarka, following Pujyapada Devanandi, extends the function of manahparyaya to the intuition of the external things as well, and it is but natural that he has to meet the objection of those who hold that it is confined to the mental states which serve as the ground of inference of external objects. Akalanka explains away the difficulty by asserting that the states of the mind are only the medium through which the external objects are intuited, and as such they need not be given the position of a middle term of an inference. Jinabhadra denied the possibility of the intuition of external objects by admitting that the knowledge of the external objects is a case of inference, but at the same time asserting in clear terms that manahprayaya has a different function, and that function is the intuition of the states of the mind that is engaged in thinking of the external objects. It is but natural that the manahparyaya should be conceived as intuiting the paryayas (states) of the manas (mind) alone, and not the external objects also. Jinabhadra adhered to this, perhaps original, conception, and when faced with the problem of the knowledge of the external objects thought of by the mind asserted that 1 parakiya-mano-gato 'rtho mana ity ucyate sabacaryat tasya paryayanam parigamanari manahparyayah. mati-jnana-prasanga iti cen na, apeksa-matratvat. ksayopasamasakti-matra-vijtmbhitam tat kevalam sva para-manobhir vyapadisyate. yatha abhre candrarnasath pasye 'ti--SSi on TSu, I. 9. 2 TRa, I. 23, 6-7. Here although Akalanka does not mention the name of Jinabhadra, it is almost certain that he refers to the view of Jinabhadra, because, to our knowledge, there is none among the predecessors of Akalanka, who states so clearly as Jinabhadra does that one possessed of manahparyaya knows the external object only by means of inference. Page #105 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 68 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. it is only by inference that one knows the external objects. Akalanka, however, takes the position of Pujyapada Devanandi and rejects the solution of Jinabhadra as unnecessary and uncalled for. It is, however, not possible for want of sufficient relevant pre-Pujyapada literature to trace the origin of Pujyapada's position. Maybe he took the suggestion from the Tattvarthabhasya of Umasvati. It is also plausible that Pujyapada followed the view embodied in the Avasyakaniryukti (gatha 76). We can assert with some measure of certainty that he was familiar with this work, inasmuch as we find him quoting from the work, and as such our conjecture is not totally unfounded. According to Pujyapada, the objects intuited by manahparyaya include objects of the activities of the sense-organ of speech, body and mind. Distinguishing between rjumati and vipulamati he says that the latter knows less number of objects than the former, but knows them more vividly and thoroughly. The vipulamati is more lucid and penetrating than the rjumati. The former is infallible while the latter falters. The former is possessed by one who gradually ascends the spiritual ladder while the latter is owned by one who is destined to fall in the grip of passions and go down. Akalanka only elucidates the view of Pujyapada. Vidyanandi repeats Akalarika. It seems that the development of the conception of manahparyaya stopped with Pujyapada on the one side and Jinabhadra on the other. The later Jaina thinkers only took side with the one or the other, but did not make any further development. Only human beings are competent to possess manahparyaya. The Nandi Sutra says that only those uterine human beings who are born in the karmabhumis (i.e. lands where tirthankaras are born), possess longevity and have fully developed organs, who are of right faith, selfcontrolled and free from passions (apramatta) and who are possessed of rddhis (extraordinary powers) are entitled to possess this manahparyaya. Even gods are not competent to possess manahparyaya. It is the special privilege of the gifted among the human species. Like avadhi, it has also gradation of spatial extension and temporal penetration." AVADHI AND MANAHPARYAYA Now let us see whether there is any essential distinction between avadhi and manahparyaya. Avadhi, as we have seen, intuits the 1 Vide supra footnote 1, p. 66. 2 He quotes ANir, gatha 5 in SSi on TSu, I. 19. Of course, here Pujyapada does not mention the specific name of the work but introduces the reference as agamatas tavat. 4 See SSi on TSu, I. 24. 3 See SSi on TSu, I. 23. * See NSu, 17. 5 See TRa, I. 23. 7 See NSu, 18. Page #106 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 11] KEVALA-JNANA 09 material substance and modes. Manahparyaya, as stated above, intuits the modes only of the material substance that constitutes the mind. It is further admitted that the material substance, intuited by avadhi, includes the manodravya (matter constituting mind) also.' . Thus we find that both avadhi and manahparyaya can intuit the states of the material substance that constitutes the mind. The distinction between them, therefore, is only one of scope. Avadhi intuits other varganas viz. the audarika, vaikriya etc. as well, while manahparyaya cannot do so. Besides, only a qualified human being can possess the manah paryaya while the avadhi belongs to the denizens of heaven and hell and sometimes even to the subhuman creatures. But in our opinion these are only superficial points of distinction. They cannot be held as constituting a qualitative distinction. They can at best prove a quantitative difference. The great logician Siddhasena Divakara who, as we have seen, does not recognize the distinction between mati and sruta has refused to recognize any distinction between avadhi and manahparyaya as well. The orthodox view is that the manahparyaya is limited to the intuition of the minds or the objective contents of the minds of the human beings alone. But Siddhasena objects that the subhuman organisms possessed of two or more sense-organs also are found to strive by means of attraction and repulsion, and thus are possessed of minds and as such it will be proper to extend the scope of manahparyaya to the minds or the objects of the minds of them as well, or otherwise it will be improper to postulate manahparyaya as a separate category of knowledge. Moreover, the avadhi can well serve the purpose of manahparyaya and so it is not necessary to admit the latter as constituting a separate category of knowledge. It can at best be considered as a specific type of avadhi. KEV ALA-JNANA Of the three classes of pratyaksa, we have described the first two, viz. avadhi and manahparyaya. Now we come to kevala (omniscience, the consummation of all knowledge. The total destruction of the mohaniya (deluding) karman is followed by a short interval lasting for less than a muhurta (fortyeight minutes) after which the karmans veiling jnana and darsana as also the antaraya (obstructive) karman are destroyed. And then the soul shines in its full splendour and attains omniscience which intuits 1 See ANiv, 42 ; see also Vibh, 669 and the Byhadvytti. 2 See A Nir, 6 which states that the manahparyaya reveals the object thought of by the janamana 'human mind'. 3 prarthana-pratighatabhyam cestante dvindriyadayah manahparyaya-vijnanam yuktam tesu na ca 'nyatha. -Niscayadvatrimsika, 17 as quoted in JBP ; also see JBP, p. 18. 4 See t'Sa, X. I with Bhasya and Tika ; see also SthSu, 226. Page #107 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 70 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. all substances with all their modes. Nothing remains unknown in omniscience.2 Umasvati quotes an opinion that maintained that on the emergence of kevala the other four kinds of knowledge viz. mati, sruta etc. are overpowered much in the same way as the other luminaries of the sky are overpowered on the appearance of the sun in the firmament, but himself supports the view that they are absolutely impossible in the omniscient on the ground that the kevala is due to the total destruction while the other four are due only to the destruction-cumsubsidence of the jnanavarana-karman. Total destruction bars the possibility of destruction-cum-subsidence.3 The Jainas hold that each and every entity is related to all entities other than itself in the universe in some relation or other. These relations are called paryayas (modes) of the entity. In order to know an entity completely, these relations or paryayas are to be completely known. And hence it follows that the complete knowledge of one entity involves the complete knowledge of other entities as well. If the relations are real and if it is also possible to know these relations, it logically follows that omniscience is possible. Omniscience is perfectly consistent with the Jaina conception of emergence of knowledge as the removal of veil. As realists the Jainas believe in relations as objective links that relate each and every entity with all that is other than the entity. Symbolically, the relations are links between A and the contents of not-A. This means that the complete knowledge of A implies the complete knowledge of not-A and this is obviously the knowledge of the whole universe. In other words, the perfect knowledge of one entity means the perfect knowledge of all entities. This has been very characteristically expressed by the Acaranga in the following terms: One who knows one knows all, and one who knows all knows one.4 There is no controversy regarding the nature of kevala among the different Jaina thinkers, and so we do not state their views separately. JNANA AND DARSANA Upayoga (consciousness) is the defining characteristic of a soul." This upayoga can be sakara 'determinate' as well as anakara 'indeterminate'." The former is called jnana and the latter darsana.' 1 See TSu, I. 30 with Bhasya; see also Nir, 77. 2 na ca kevala-jnana-visayat param kincij jneyam asti-TSuBh, I. 30. 3 ksayopasamajani catvari jnanani purvani, ksayad eva tu kevalam. tasman na kevalinah sesani jnanani bhavanti 'ti.-TSuBh, I. 31. 4 je egam janai se savvam janai, je savvam janai se egam janai--ASu, I. 3. 4 also see ViBh, 320 and the Brhadvrtti. See BhSu, II. 10; TSu, II. 8. See BhSu, XVI. 7; TS, II. 9 and Bhasya. 7 See TSuBh on II. 9. Page #108 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ JNANA AND DARSANA 71 We propose to render jnana as determinate knowledge and darsana as 'indeterminate intuition' although we are fully conscious of the inadequacy of the translation. For the sake of convenience we shall sometimes use simply 'knowledge' for jnana and intuition' for darsana. The hoary antiquity of the Jaina conception of jnanavarana and darsanavarana points to the antiquity of the distinction between jnana and darsana. The Jaina Agamas use the terms janai and pasai in order to express the two faculties of the soul. The Prajnapana Sutra recognizes a peculiar faculty called pasanay, and in this connection we should notice the contents of its two chapters dealing severally with upayoga and pasanaya (rendered pasyatta in Sanskrit). It is recognized that both upayoga and pasyatta can be sakara as well as anakara. This means that both jnana and darsana can belong to both the categories of upayoga and pasyatta. Distinguishing between upayoga and pasyatta, the commentator Malayagiri says: "Sakara upayoga consists of five classes of knowledge (viz. mati, sruta, avadhi, manahparyaya and kevala) and three classes of non-knowledge (viz. mati-ajnana, Sruta-ajnana and avadhi-ajnana or vibhanga). Sakara pasyatta, on the other hand, consists only of six classes (out of the eight just mentioned) inasmuch as mati-jnana and mati-ajnana are not included therein. Pasyatta is derived from drs and means preksana and, by convention, connotes prolonged vision' with reference to determinate knowledge and clear vision' with reference to indeterminate intuition. Mati-jnana and mati-ajnana cognize only what is present and cannot be prolonged to what is past or future, and as such cannot possess pasyatta. Similarly, anakara upayoga consists of four classes of darsana (intuition) viz, caksurdarsana (eye-intuition), acaksur darsana intuition by the mind as well as the sense-organs other than the eye), avadhi-darsana and kevala-darsana. Anakara pasyatta, on the other hand, consists only of three classes (out of these four), inasmuch as acaksurdarsana being devoid of 'clear vision cannot possess pasyatta, and as such is excluded from the category of anakara pasyatta.'3 1 PYSu, padas 29 and 30. 2 sagaro-'vaoge ya anagaro-'vaoge ya-PySu, pada 29. sagarapasanaya anagara-pasanaya-PySu, pada 30. 3 panca jnanani triny ajnanani 'ty astavidhah sakara upayogah sakarapasyatta tu sadvidha, matijnana-matyajnanayoh pasyattayoh anabhyupagamat, kasmad iti cet, ucyate, iha pasyatta narna pasyato bhava ucyate, pasyato bhavas ca drair preksane' iti vacanat preksanam iha rudhivasat sakarapasyattayam cintyamanayam pradirgha-kalam anakara pasyattayam cintyamanayam prakrstam parisphutarupam iksanam ava seyam. ...... matijnanamatyajnane tu utpannavinastartha-grahake sampratakala-visaye..... tatha caksurdarsanam acaksurdarsanam avadhi-darsanamkevala-darsanam iti caturvidho 'nakaropayogah, anakara-pasyatta tu trividha, acaksur-darsanasya 'nakarapasyatta-sabda-vacyatvabhavat, kasmad iti cet-acaksur-darsane parisphutarupam iksanam na vidyate-Malayagiri's Tika on PrSu, pada 30. Page #109 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 72 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. Pasyatta thus means 'prolonged vision' or 'clear vision'. It can also be called 'direct vision'. The Prajnapana Sutra gives the divisions and subdivisions but does not clarify the meaning of pasyatta and its difference from upayoga. It is only the commentator Malayagiri who attempts to demarcate the line of distinction between upayoga and pasyatta. As regards the distinction between jnana and darsana, however, the Agamas are very clear and definite, and unanimous too. The great Acarya Kundakunda, however, records a quite original conception. His leaning is towards the absolutist standpoint. He asks, with reference to the omniscient, whether his knowledge reveals the non-self, his intuition reveals self, and his soul reveals both the self and the non-self. He considers the problem from the empirical as well as the transcendental standpoint and concludes that the atman, its knowledge, and its intuition (darsana)--all these are identical and hence each can reveal the self as well as the non-self. He does not refer to the sakara-ana kara (determinate-indeterminate) relation, and so it is not possible to ascertain whether he distinguished between jnana and darsana on that basis. Acarya Virasena in his commentary called Dhavala on Satkhandagama of Puspadanta says 'What comprehends an external object of the nature of the universal-cum-particular is jnana. And the comprehension of the self of the same nature is darsana.'4 Reality consists of universal-cum-particular and as such the valid cognition of it must consist in the comprehension of both these characteristics. Jnana and darsana are both cases of valid cognition, and so each must be regarded as comprehending both the aspects of reality. Those who hold that jnana comprehends only the particular features while darsana comprehends only the universal ones are criticized as upholding wrong conception of the nature of jnana and darsana. A particular without the universal is a figment, and so the knowledge which comprehends a particular bereft of the universal is invalid, nay unreal. Similarly the intuition of a universal without the particular is also unreal.5 Virasena thus maintains that each of the two, jnana and darsana, comprehends reality as it is, that is, a complex of universalcum-particular, the difference between them consisting in the fact that a jnana knows the external reality while a darsana intuits the internal 1 Niyamasara, 160. 2 Ibid., 161-169. 3 This is the implication of Niyamasara, 170 which runs : appanam vinu nanam nanam vinu appago e sardeho tamha sa parapayasam nanam taha dam sanam hodi. 4 samanya-visesatmaka-bahyartha-grahanam jnanam, tadatmaka-svarupagrahanam darsanam iti siddham.-Dhavala on Satkhandagama, I. I. 4. 5 Cf. na jnanam pramanam samanya-vyatirikta-visesa.sya 'rthakriya-kartrtvam praty asamarthatvato 'vastuno grahanat. na tasya grahanam api samanyavyatirikte visese hy avastuni kartskarma-rupabhavat. tata eva na darsanam api pramanam. Ibid. hanan jnanadugama, I. 1Aiva-karti Page #110 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 11] JNANA AND DARSANA 73 self. Darsana is antarmukha (turned inside, introvert) while jnana is bahirmukha (turned outside, extrovert). If the jnana knows the external world darsana intuits the internal self. The internal reality is as much a complex of universal-cum-particular as an external entity. Thus the object of both a jnana and a darsana is a complex of universalcum-particular. Brahmadeva in his Vytti on the Dravyasangraha of Nemicandra upholds a similar position. In his commentary on Dravyasangraha, gatha 43, he recognizes the darsana as intuition of a universal characteristic. But in his commentary on gatha 44, he distinguishes two views_(I) according to logic (tarkabhiprayena), and (2) according to scripture (siddhantabhiprayena). The usual view of darsana as intuition of the universal, for instance satta (existence), is referred to as according to logic. The conception of darsana according to the scripture is given as follows: Awareness or vision of one's self, consisting in the striving for the genesis of knowledge in its wake, is darsana 'intuition' and the subsequent determinate knowledge of the external object is jnana.? The soul knows as well as intuits much in the same way as fire burns as well as illumines. The selfsame consciousness is called darsana as well as jnana with reference to the difference of its object. It is called darsana when it is engaged in intuiting the self, and jnana when engaged in knowing the non-self. Knowledge would lose its validity if it were admitted that darsana and jnana are confined to the comprehension respectively of the universal and the particular exclusively. The ground given is the same as already mentioned by us. Now as jnana and darsana, viewed from the transcendental point of view, are identical with the self, it can be aid that the self itself, being of the nature of knowledge free from all doubt, delusion and error, is the ultimate organ of knowledge.3 Darsana and jnana thus ultimately lose their identity in the self. Brahmadeva gives yet another explanation of this twofold interpretation of darsana. He says that the samanya-visesa (universalparticular) relation of darsana and jnana is for the non-Jaina logicians who are unable to understand the real significance. For those of subtle intelligence, however, the other explanation which is in strict accord 1 evan tarkabhiprayena sattavalokana-darsanam vyakhyatam-Vytti on Dravyasamgraha, 44. 2 ata urdhvar siddhantabhiprayena kathyate. tatha hi uttara-jnanotpattinimittam yat prayatnam tadrupam yat svasya 'tmanah paricchedanam avalokanari tad darsanam bhanyate. tadanantaram yad bahirvisaye vikalparupena padartha-grahanam taj jnanam iti varttikam-Ibid. 3 siddhantena punar niscayena gunaguninor abhinnatvat samsayavimohavibhrama-rahita-vastu-jnana-svarupatmai 'va pramanam.-Ibid. JP-10 Page #111 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. other ance with the scripture is propounded. It is to be noted in this connection that all these proponents of the new conception belong to the Digambara school. So far as our knowledge goes, we do not find any Svetambara exponent of this conception. Among the Digambaras also, only the above-mentioned thinkers propound the theory, the great thinkers unanimously admitting the sakara-anakara (determinate-indeterminate) relation between jnana and darsana. Of course, it has not been possible for me to examine the whole relevant literature on the subject and so my above remark may be liable to contradiction. But in view of the fact that such great exponents as Pujyapada, Samantabhadra, Akalanka and Vidyanandi unanimously accepted the conception, we can, with confidence, say that there was little controversy regarding the sakara-anakara (determinate-indeterminate) relation of jnana and darsana among the Digambara thinkers as well. We do not know whether there is any basic affinity between the upayoga-pasyatta conception of the Prajnapana Sutra and the apparently original theory of Kundakunda and others. In spite of the explanation of Malayagiri regarding the distinction between upayoga and pasyatta, we are not sure of the original relation between the two. It is also a problem to be decided whether there is any affinity between pasyatta and darsana. It is a difficult problem and I confess my inability to solve it ad hoc. 74 Now we come to the problem of the temporal relation between jnana and darsana. Jnana and darsana are conscious activities, and it is an Agamic principle that two conscious activities cannot occur simultaneously. The Avasyakaniryukti says that (even) the kevalins (the omniscient) cannot have two conscious activities simultaneously.2 The Agamas, therefore, unanimously admit the impossibility of the simultaneous occurrence of jnana and darsana.s The later Jaina thinkers also unanimously admitted the impossibility in the case of the chadmastha (non-omniscient) but there is controversy among them regarding the case of the kevalin (omniscient). The Digambara thinkers unanimously hold that the jnana and the darsana of a kevalin occur 1 Cf. tarke mukhya-vrttya para-samaya-vyakhyanam. tatra yada ko 'pi parasamayi prcchati jainagame darsanam jnanam ce 'ti guna-dvayam jivasya kathyate tat katham ghatata iti ... tesam pratityartham sthulavyakhyanena bahirvisaye yat samanya-paricchedanam tasya sattavalokana-darsana-samjna ... siddhante punah ... suksmavyakhyane... atmagrahakam darsanam vyakhyatam ity atra 'pi doso nasti.-Ibid. 2 savvassa kevalissa jugavam do natthi uvaoga-ANir, 973. The other reading is kevalissa vi (See Tika on TSuVh, I. 31). 3 See BhSu, XVIII. 8; PrSu, pada 30. 4 Literally chadmastha means 'one involved in the world'. But we write the word 'non-omniscient' for the sake of contradistinction. Besides, a chadmastha is necessarily non-omniscient. Page #112 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II] JNANA AND DARSANA 75 simultaneously. But among the Svetambara thinkers, some stick to the Agamas, while others go astray and assert either that a kevalin's jnana and darsana are simultaneous or even that they are mutually identical and have no separate identity. We shall here briefly refer to the authors of these views. The Avasyakaniryukti, as we have already stated, does not admit the possibility of simultaneous occurrence of jnana and darsana of a kevalin. Then, we come to Umasvati who says: 'The conscious activities manifesting themselves as mati, sruta, avadhi and manahparyaya occur in succession, and not simultaneously. The conscious activities of the omniscient lord, possessed of integrated jnana and darsana, however, in respect of 'pure knowledge' and 'pure intuition'-- which comprehend all objects and are independent occur simultaneously in every point of time'.1 It follows from this quotation that Umasvati admitted simultaneous Occurrences of jnana and darsana. The commentator Siddhasenaganin, however, gives a different interpretation in accordance with the Agamas, although he refers for the sake of refutation to some old commentators, possessed of logical intelligence, who interpreted the relevant statements of the Agamas otherwise and denied succession of conscious activities of a kevalin. The great Digambara Acarya Kundakunda clearly states that the jnana and darsana of a kevalin occur simultaneously even as the light and heat of the sun occur simultaneously. Pujyapada Devanandi follows Kundakunda. He says: 'Jnana is sakara 'determinate' while darsana is anakara 'indeterminate'. They occur in succession in the chadmastha (i.e. one who is under the influence of the obstructive karmans) while in the niravarana (i.e. one who is completely free from the obstructive karmans) they occur simultaneously.'5 4 Now we come to the great logician Siddhasena Divakara who refused to admit the separate identity of jnana and darsana because of logical difficulties. 'We can distinguish between jnana and darsana up to manahparyaya. Kevala-jnana, however, qua jnana and qua darsana is identical.' According to Siddhasena Divakara, those who, 1 matijnanadisu catursu paryayeno 'payogo bhavati, na yugapat. sambhinnajnana-darsanasya tu bhagavatah kevalino yugapat sarvabhava-grahake nirapekse kevala-jnane kevala-darsane ca anusamayam upayogo bhavati.-TSuBh, I. 31. 2 See Siddhasenaganin's Tika on the passage quoted above. 3 Cf. kecit panditammanyah sutrany anyathakaram artham acaksate tarkabalanuviddha-buddhayo varamvareno 'payogo nasti, tat tu na pramanayamah, yata amnaye bhuyamsi sutrani varamvareno 'payogam pratipadayanti.-Ibid. 4 jugavam vattai nanam kevala-nanissa damsanam ca taha dinayara-payasa-tapam jaha vattai taha muneyavvam.-Niyamasara, 159. 5 See SSi on TSu, II. 9. manapajjava-nanamto nanassa ya darisanassa ya viseso kevala-nanam puna damsanam ti nanam ti ya samanam-STP, II. 3. Page #113 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 76 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. on the authority of the scriptures, maintain that the emancipated one (jina) does not know and intuit simultaneously make no scruple to flout their tirthankara. In other words, he finds logical difficulties in the position and asks those who stand by the old position to reinterpret the Agamic statement and thus remove the inconsistencies. If kevalajnana dawns on the complete destruction of the relevant obscuring karman it stands to reason that kevala-darsana also should dawn immediately upon the destruction of the relevant obscuring karman. And as both the destructions are simultaneous, it logically follows that the dawnings of kevala-jnana and kevala-darsana also synchronize.2 As it is said that there can be no mati-jnana in the omniscient jina who has completely destroyed the veil, so (should it be admitted that) there can be no separate darsana in one who has completely destroyed the veil.'3 "Moreover,' says Siddhasena Divakara, in the scriptures, kevala has been said to have beginning but no end, and those afraid of going against the scriptures should take note of this fact.'4 Admission of succession in the occurrence of jnana and darsana means admission of break of continuity of both of them, and this obviously goes against the scriptures which prescribe non-break (aparyavasitatua), that is, continuity of both jnana and darsana." The jnanavarana and darsanavarana are destroyed simultaneously, and the problem arises which of the two, kevala-jnana and kevala-darsana, should arise first? Logically we cannot give priority to anyone of them. Nor is it possible to admit the synchronous emergence of both, because two conscious activities cannot occur simultaneously. If an omniscient soul knows all in one instant, he should continue to know all for ever, or otherwise, he does not know all.? The contention that jnana (knowledge) is distinct and determinate while darsana (intuition) is indistinct and indeterminate has no scope in the case of one who has destroyed all karmic veils. The distinction of 'determinate and indeterminate', 'distinct and indistinct', applies to the knowledge of imperfect beings, and not to that of the perfect ones. And hence there can be no distinction between jnana and darsana of the omniscient. There are other difficulties as well. Supposing that even in a kevalin the jnana and the darsana are quite distinct from one another, they must occur either in succession or simultaneously. In the former case, the kevalin could not be held to speak out complete reality, because his statement, being i Ibid., II. 4. 2 Ibid., II. 5. 3 bhannai khinavarane jaha mainanam jise na sambhavai taha khinavaranijje visesao damsanam natthi.--Ibid., II. 6. 4 Ibid., II. 7. 5 Cf. ibid., II. 8. 6 Cf. damsana-nana-'varana-kkhae samanammi kassa puvvaaram hojja saman uppao hamdi duve natthi uvaoga.-Ibid., II. 9. Cf. ibid., II. IO. 8 Cf. ibid., II. II. Page #114 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II] JNANA AND DARSANA in strict conformity with his awareness, would exclude the object of jarsana when it would synchronize with knowledge, and it would exclude the object of jnana when synchronizing with intuition. And even in the case of simultaneity of jnana and darsana, the difficulty of simultaneous statement of the contents of both would still remain.1 Omniscience would be only an ill-conceived notion if it were admitted that the omniscient arhat intuits the unknown and knows the unintuited.2 The conception of separate identity of jnana and darsana implies that the object of darsana remains for ever untouched by jnana and the object of jnana remains for ever untouched by darsana and consequently it follows that the whole reality ever remains unknown even to the kevalin. The various scriptural statements contradicting our position, however, are to be interpreted with reference to various standpoints. The scriptures do not recognize darsana in the case of manahparyaya, inasmuch as the manahparyaya cognizes only particular features of the mind-substance of others, and not its universal forms. They further recognize only four classes of darsana viz. caksurdarsana, acaksurdarsana, avadhi-darsana and kevala-darsana. Siddhasena then quotes an opinion which recognized darsana as 'avagraha, simple and pure', and jnana as 'determinate description' of the form 'This is a jar', and distinguished darsana from jnana on the ground that the latter can be due to the former while the former can never be due to the latter.4 He refutes the opinion on the ground that avagraha has been recognized as a sub-type of mati-jnana, and as such if darsana were held to be nothing but avagraha, it would follow that darsana is a type of mati-jnana." Siddhasena then formulates his own definition of darsana which runs as follows: 'Darsana is jnana (cognition) of external objects untouched by, or unamenable to the sense-organs, provided the cognition does not cognize the past and future events by means of a linga (probans).' The definition does not overextend to manahparyaya, because the external objects are not directly known by it.7 Mati and sruta have no corresponding darsana. But avadhi can have darsana inasmuch as avadhi intuits objects that are untouched by the sense-organs." The omniscient (kevalin) knows as well as intuits addittham annayam ca kevali eva bhasai sayavi ega-samayammi hamdi vayana-vigappo na sambhavai.-Ibid., II. 12. 2 Cf. ibid., II. 13. 3 Cf. ibid., II. 18. 4 damsanam uggahamettam ghado tti nivvannana havai nanam, etc. -STP, II. 21-22; Yasovijaya, however, gives a quite different explanation of gatha 22 (see his JBP, p. 43). 5 Ibid., II. 23. 77 6 nanam aputthe avisae ya atthammi damsanam hoi mottuna limgao jam anagayaiyavisaesu.-Ibid., II. 25. See also the commentary of Abhayadeva. 7 Cf. ibid., II. 26. 8 Cf. ibid., II. 27-28. 9 Cf. ibid., II. 29. Page #115 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 78 EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [CH. objects inasmuch as he is aware of all objects irrespective of their amenability or unamenability to sense-organs. Siddhasena Divakara, therefore, concludes that jnana and darsana of a kevalin arise simultaneously and last for ever. He further says that this interpretation does not violate the scriptures while the view that jnana and darsana of a kevalin arise in alternate succession is not faithful to the scriptures and is to be understood as the position of the non-Jainas. 2 We have already stated how he proves the non-difference between jnana and darsana in order to avoid logical difficulties. Next we come to Jinabhadra, the great upholder of the Agamic view. He deals with the problem in his Visesanavatis and Visesavasyakabhasya. He mentions all the three positions viz. (1) simultaneous occurrence of jnana and darsana, (2) alternate occurrence of them, (3) non-difference between them.5 He records arguments for and against all the three positions. But he supports the alternate occurrence of jnana and darsana of a kevalin on the basis of scriptural texts. We do not examine his elaborate arguments here, because they do not contain any new speculation. All his objections are based on the scriptural texts and established traditions which unanimously recognize alternate occurrence of jnana and darsana as we have stated at the outset of our enquiry about their temporal relation. Akalanka and Vidyanandi, the great Digambara logicians, support simultaneous occurrence of jnana and darsana in a kevalin. Commenting upon Samantabhadra's Aptamimarsa, verse 101, Akalanka says 'If the jnana and darsana (of a kevalin) were to occur alternately in succession, his omniscience would be only a contingent occurrence.'6 There is no reason why the universal and the particular should not reveal themselves simultaneously to the omniscient who has destroyed all his karmic veils.? Vidyanandi says: 'Awareness of the universal form is darsana, and the awareness of the particular features is jnana. Jnanavarana and darsanavarana obscure these faculties. There is absence of kevala-jnana and kevala-darsana in people like us because of the presence of these two. And it goes beyond understanding why the universal and the particular should be revealed only in alternate succession when it is established that the two (avaranas) are destroyed simultaneously due to a special kind of absolute purification of the soul ?'8 Haribhadra, 1 Cf. ibid., II. 30. 2 Cf. ibid., II. 31. 3 Gathas 184-280. 4 Gathas 3089-3135. 5 See Visesanavati, 184-5. 6 tajjnana-darsanayoh kramavsttau hi sarvajnatvam kadacitkam syatAstasati on AMi, 101. samanya-visesa-visayayor vigatavaranayor yugapat pratibhasayogat pratibandhakantarabhavat-Ibid. 8 Astasahasri on the passage quoted in footnote No. 7. Page #116 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II] JNANA AND DARSANA 79 commenting on Jinadasagani-Mahattara's Curni1 on Nandi Sutra 22, says that Acarya Siddhasena and others were the upholders of simultaneous occurrence of jnana and darsana, that Jinabhadraganiksamasramana and others were the upholders of the alternate occurrence of these, and that the old Acaryas upheld non-difference of jnana and darsana.2 It is difficult to ascertain from the available Jaina literature as to who this Siddhasena and the old Acaryas were whom Haribhadra refers to. Siddhasena Divakara, as we have seen, supported the position of non-difference and so cannot be regarded as referred to by Haribhadra as the upholder of simultaneity of both. Besides, we do not know of any old Acaryas who were the supporters of nondifference between jnana and darsana. Again in his commentary on the Sanmatitarkaprakarana (II. 10), Abhayadevasuri mentions Jinabhadra as the supporter of alternate succession, and Mallavadin as the supporter of simultaneity. This Mallavadin also is not known to us. The commentator Malayagiri, however, follows Haribhadra in assigning the positions to different authors. This problem of identification of Haribhadra's Siddhasena and Abhayadeva's Mallavadin has been thoroughly discussed by the great savant Pandit Sukhlalji in Jnanabindu-paricaya the introductory portion (pp. 54-62) of his excellent edition of Yasovijaya's Jnanabindu and we refer to that for fuller information. In Yasovijaya we find the last Jaina logician who supported the position of Siddhasena Divakara at great length and practically wrote a commentary on almost the whole of the second Kanda of his Sanmatitarka-prakarana, which deals with the problem. Yasovijaya refers to the statement of Haribhadra or Malayagiri that Acarya Siddhasena was the supporter of simultaneity, and says that here only the prima facie position of Siddhasena is referred to." He supplements the arguments of Siddhasena Divakara and strongly supports his position. But what is most striking is the tone of comprehensive reconciliation of conflicting views with which he winds up the discussion. He says: 'Mallavadin 1 The Curni quotes gathas from the Visesanavati of Jinabhadra already referred to by us. Haribhadra has commented upon these gathas in his Nandisutravrtti. 2 kecana Siddhasenacaryadayah bhananti, kim? yugapad ekasminn eva kale janati pasyati ca, kah? kevali, na tvanyah, niyaman niyamena, anye Jinabhadragani-ksamasramana-prabhrtayah ekantaritam janati pasyati ce 'ty evam icchanti .... anye tu Vrddhacarya na naiva visvak prthak taddarsanam icchanti-NSuVr, p. 52. 3 See Malayagiri's Nandivrtti, p. 134. 4 See JBP, pp. 33-47 5 yattu yugapadupayogavaditvam Siddhasenacaryanam Nandivrttav uktam tad abhyupagamavadabhiprayena...kramakramopayogadvaya-paryanuyoganantaram eva svapaksasya Sanmatau udbhavitatvad iti drastavyam-JBP, p. 33. Page #117 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE AGAMAS [ch. (who admitted separate identity of jnana and darsana but did not admit succession) has resorted to vyavahara naya (empirical standpoint) which comprehends distinction, the Revered (Jinabhadra) has resorted to pure rjusutra (analytic standpoint) which lies at that is, distinguishes) the borderline between cause and effect, while Siddhasena has accepted sangraha which tends to obliterate distinction. None of these three positions of the Acaryas, therefore, are improper." We have now described the main features of the Agamic epistemology. We do not attempt at a comparative estimate, mainly because the Agamic conceptions are so peculiar and original that they do not allow themselves to be dovetailed into the scholastic scheme of epistemology. It is only the later systematization of the pramanas by the Jaina schoolmen which can lend itself profitably to comparative evaluation. We therefore content ourselves by giving a systematic exposition of the Agamic scheme trying to throw light on tangled spots with the help of documentary evidence and independent judgment both. In the beginning of the chapter we adverted to the problem of the validity of knowledge. The Agamic epistemology, as we have stated, regards the rightness or the wrongness of knowledge as ultimately dependent upon the rightness or the wrongness of the attitude. If the soul is possessed of perverted attitude (mith yatva) its knowledge is necessarily wrong. If it is possessed of right attitude (samyaktva) its knowledge is right. Knowledge is the intrinsic characteristic of the soul. But it is vitiated by mith yatva which is the Jaina equivalent of the principle known as avidya in the other systems. The mithyatva vitiates, as it were, the very texture of the soul and all the imperfections of worldly existence are ultimately due to it. A comparative estimate of the nature and function of this mithyatva with those of the avidya of the other systems is necessary in order to understand the fundamental characteristic of the Jaina thought. We shall therefore address ourselves to the comparative evaluation of the principle of mithyatva or avidya in the chapter that follows. 1 bheda grahi-vyavahrtinayam saririto Malla vadi Pujyah prayah karana-phalayoh simni suddharjusutram. bhedocchedonmukham adhigatah samgraham Siddha senas tasmad ete na khalu vinamah suripaksas trayo 'pi.-JBP, p. 48. Page #118 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CHAPTER III THE PROBLEM OF AVIDYA I INTRODUCTORY India is the land of spiritualism. Nothing bereft of spiritual value could satisfy the Indian mind. Spiritual conviction and a constant urge for the ultimate truth inspired the manifold branches of Indian thought. Science, Arts, Logic, Philosophy-all possible branches of thought--were inspired by one common aim of freedom from worldly bondage. To get rid of spiritual darkness is the end of all science. An art is not an art if it does not give glimpses into the beauty of truth. And it achieves this objective by removing the conflict between the good and the agreeable, between beauty and truth-which conflict is unreal and accidental. It shows that departure from the truth and beauty is nescience and the recovery of the unity is the natural end and consummation. The common end of all arts is to remind us of the supreme state which is beyond this worldly existence. Logic is! nothing but an instrument for the interpretation of the spiritual vision. It is a necessary discipline, because there are people who are not prepared to take anything on trust. Logic is the creation of higher' minds. It is the expression of the laws of human thought. It is the organ by which the mind discriminates truth from error. No experience, however exalted, will pass for truth unless it is sanctioned by the canons of logical thought. It is unambiguously admitted that logic is rather an instrument of criticism and can never rise to the level of an organ of discovery. But as the human mind is subject to the influence of emotion and habits fostered by unquestioning beliefs, its discovery is liable to be distorted by passions and impulses, dogmatic faith and intellectual inertia which is frightened by a discovery that is calculated to upset one's vested interests in religion. Indian philosophers have never been remiss in acknowledging supreme value of logic as a corrective of vagaries of dogmatism. In fact, one cannot get rid of logic, however one may decry it. One can hope to convince the other only by means of reasoning. But as reasoning is only an instrument of criticism it can operate only on the data supplied by organs of knowledge. Logic has not been neglected or derided in India, though philosophers were alive to its limitations. Logic cannot find the truth unaided and independently. But it can tell us that a position is not true because it is contradicted. The criterion of logic is non-contradiction in the main. Because the ordinary experience of man is not found to satisfy the intellectual demands of noble minds, as it fails to satisfy the criteria of logic, the necessity of philosophical speculation was felt as imperative. Man has the capacity for finding JP-11 Page #119 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 82 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. the truth, which is attested and approved by logical thought. That is the truth which satisfies the whole man--the rational man in particular. As the emotional and active man in us is liable to be swayed by his ancient habits into untruth, logic comes in to his rescue. Logic clarifies the vision of truth, corrects it of illogical accretions, and purifies our knowledge of reality. Logic is not opposed to spiritual vision, though it is not a direct means to this consummation. The differences among the seers and mystics are rather due to interpretation. A strong logical attitude is thus a necessary propaedeutic to the realization of truth. The value of philosophy is enhanced in proportion to its love of logic, which is nothing but the will not to take anything as truth unless the reason is satisfied. But the majority of mankind is noted for the inertia and incuriosity. They do not feel an urge and inspiration for truth. Why is this difference between the thinking and the unthinking man? Why should there be people who hug their ignorance and make a pet of it? There must be a reason for this. Confronted with this fundamental fact and in full realization of it, all the systems of Indian philosophy admit, in some form or other, the existence of a principle which acts as hindrance against the apprehension of truth. If the experiences of those who have realized the truth are reliable, what is it that hides the truth from us? There must be some reason or explanation for our common ignorance or perverse knowledge. If the truth is not unknowable, if the records of the experiences of the gifted souls are trustworthy, there must be something which obstructs our innate capacity to know the truth. If this worldly existence is a degradation and a fall because of its hiatus from perfection, there must be some perfect state of existence which we have failed to reach as yet and the realization of which is the ultimate goal and objective of a spiritual aspirant. This again leads to the further enquiry as to what is it that is responsible for the failure. The Indian thinkers are unanimous as regards the cause of this degeneration or descent. It is turning away from the truth. It is looking in the opposite direction. It is going towards the darkness. It is admitted that perfection is integral to the spirit and realization of the same is not a new creation in the sense of emergence of an absolutely unprecedented state. Yet the soul has been hindered from selfrealization, which is the same as the discovery of its infinite glory, from eternity. The spirit has been oblivious of itself and has been wandering in the wilderness. The question 'What was the first fall due to?' is avoided by admitting the beginninglessness of the process. The historical beginning of the process is unknown because the spirit is an uncreated entity and exists from the eternal past, but the end is clearly envisaged. The spirit must realize itself. There is no controversy on Page #120 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 83 AVIDYA IN THE YOGA SCHOOL III. II] this point. The worldly career is sustained and nourished by the ignorance or perverted knowledge of the spirit and it lasts as long as the ignorance or perverted knowledge lasts. It is a wonder why the spirit clings to the fall and deviation from the norm and is so unwilling to look backward to itself. The Indian mind had always been conscious of the innate potentiality of perfection of the spirit and the possibility of realization of self-perfection. It is this consciousness that moulded the culture and thought of India. It is this spiritualism that fostered tolerance and the spirit of mutual understanding in the Indian mind. The principle which acts as hindrance against the apprehension of truth has been differently conceived in different systems under various names such as avidya (nescience), mithyatva (perversity), ajnana (ignorance), mithya-jnana (perverted knowledge), viparyaya (perversion), moha (delusion), darsana-moha (delusion of attitude) etc.1 The fundamental unity of all the conceptions lies in the fact that all of them refer to the principle commonly called avidya (nescience) or moha (delusion) which hides truth, deludes the spirit and lures it in the wrong direction. The immediate effect of this nescience is to create the soul's interest in the world process and to make it cling to it as the source of happiness. The spirit sticks to the world due to its influence. This leads to the cycle of rebirths. The common aim of all the systems of Indian thought is to show the way out of this cycle, and this can be done only by showing the means of destroying or getting rid of the nescience. The nature of this nescience is conceived in accordance with the conception of the nature of ultimate reality. The function of nescience is to present reality in a form which it has not, and thereby to misguide the spirit. In order to get rid of this nescience the first thing that is necessary is possession of spiritual conviction. Once this conviction lays hold upon the soul, it turns back and treads upon the right path. We now address ourselves to the appraisal of the various conceptions of nescience in the well-known schools of Indian thought with particular reference to the Jaina position. In the interest of the convenience of procedure and clarification of relevant issues we propose to undertake an examination of the conception of avidya system by system. II AVIDYA IN THE YOGA SCHOOL This school recognizes two primordial categories viz. purusa and prakrti. Purusa is the principle of consciousness which witnesses the 1 Vide verse 83 and the prose portion as well of TSIV on TSu I. 13; also see Yasovijaya's Vrtti on YD, II. 3. et seq. Page #121 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 84 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. world process of which prakrti is the ground. Purusa is drasta (witness) and is pure consciousness (dysimatra) and even though it is eternally pure and unchanging it witnesses the transformations of buddhiwhich is the first evolute of prakrti and the instrument for presenting the objects to the purusa. In the process of witnessing the activities of the buddhi it loses hold of itself and apparently identifies itself with them. The objective world (drsya) is constituted of the three primal elements or energies, which have been cyclically evolving the subjective and the objective orders of being. These manifest themselves in the subjective plane as pleasure, pain, and dullness-cum-stolidity and in the physical plane as reposeful equilibrium, motion, and inertia. The entire psycho-physical order exists for the enjoyment and final release of the purusa' according as it succeeds in enlisting his interest by its meretricious charms or in disabusing him by the discovery of its unspiritual character as not-self absolutely unattached to the spirit. The twofold world process is guided by a blind teleology and actually subserves the interests of the purusa. The relation between the purusa and the prakrti is one of the enjoyer and the enjoyed, the seer and the seen, or the subject and the object. There is no actual relation between them in the ordinary sense of the term. The prakrti unfolds and presents its processes to the purusa through the sense-organs and the buddhi which resembles to a great degree the purusa in purity and luminosity. The purusa's relation to praksti serves to cater for the enjoyment (bhoga) of the former, which consists in illumining and appropriating the world process. And it leads to final release (apavarga) when the purusa realizes its natural difference and distinction from the world process by realizing its own inalienable spiritual nature. This relation between the inherently pure purusa and the prakrti is beginningless and is due to nescience (avidya)5 which has been defined to be a perverted knowledge which comprehends non-eternal as eternal, impure as pure, sorrow as pleasure, and nonsoul as soul. The Bhasya says Avidya (nescience) is neither knowledge nor negation of knowledge. But it is wrong cognition as opposed to true cognition and as such falls in the category of cogni i We shall refer to purusa by the pronoun 'it' as well as 'he' according to our convenience. 2 drasta disimatrah suddho 'pi pratyayanupasyah-YD, II. 20. 3 prakasa-kriya-sthiti-silam bhutendriyatmakam bhogapavargartham drsyam. -YD, II. 18; also cf. tadartha eva drsyasya 'tma-YD, II. 21. 4 Cf. sva-svamisaktyoh svarupopalabdhi-hetuh samyogah--YD, II. 23. Also cf. Bhasya thereon: purusah svami drsyena svena darsanartham samyuktah, tasmat samyogad drsyasyo 'palabdhir ya sa bhogah, ya tu drastuh svarupopalabdhih so 'pavargah. 5 Cf. tasya hetur avidya---YD, JI. 24. 6 YD, II. 5. Page #122 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. II] AVIDYA IN THE YOGA SCHOOL tion.' It further describes nescience as a mental) trace or a predisposition left by wrong cognition. The buddhi, under the influence of this wrong cognition, cannot comprehend the separate identity of the purusa, and repeats its course. It is only when the distinctive identity of the purusa is realized that the buddhi reaches consummation of its activity and does not repeat its course. The prakrti now has fulfilled its purpose and is disengaged from the purusa. It now lies disenchanted with the cessation of nescience, and ceases to entangle the purusa in the meshes of the world process. And as a result the purusa is emancipated. The purusa does not witness the world process any more inasmuch as the buddhi that presented it to the purusa is not there. This is called moksa emancipation) or kaivalya (self-isolation) which has been defined as either the final reversion of the gunas (elements or energies) to their original ground prakrti in view of the discontinuation of the service to the purusa, or as the self-recovery of consciousness in its intrinsic nature.4 In this connection it is necessary to explain in brief the nature of the subject and the object and their relation according to the Yoga school. Buddhi, as we have stated, is an evolute of prakyti and as such is unconscious in itself. But due to the association with the purusa it becomes, as it were, capable of such conscious activities as knowing, feeling and willing. The psychical activities cannot be affiliated to purusa, as it is not susceptible to change. Activity is an attribute of matter and consequently the psychical activities are the inherent characteristics of the buddhi. They are as unconscious as the cerebral activities. But they become spiritualized by the reflection of the spirit in the buddhi. The spiritualization is apparent and conditional-an extrinsic determination due to the presence of the purusa and to the innate nature of the buddhi which, on account of its luminosity and reposefulness, has the capacity to catch the reflection light of the purusa. The light belongs to the purusa and the buddhi shines in the borrowed light like a satellite of the sun. The sense of personal identity is due to the association of the unchanging Bhasya, YD, 11.,24 world process. See SPB, 1 avidya na pramanam na pramanabhavah kintu vidya-viparitam jnanantaram avidye 'ti--Bhasya, YD, II. 6. 2 viparyaya-jnana-vasana--Bhasya, YD, II. 24. N.B. Avidya qua vasana leads to the world process. Avidya qua wrong cognition is possible only after the process has taken place. See SPB, I. 55. 3 See Bhasya, YD, II. 24. 4 Cf. purusartha-sunyanam gunanam pratiprasavah kaivalyam svarupapratistha va citi-baktir iti---YD, IV. 34. 5 Cf. sarvarthadhyavasayakatvat triguna buddhis trigunatvad acetane 'tiBhasya, YD, II. 20. Page #123 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. spirit with the ever-changing buddhi. The buddhi is a changing identity a variable constant which maintains its integrity and selfidentity in spite of the changes that happen to it. We could dispense with the purusa or the spirit if the buddhi were possessed of intelligence in its own right and conversely we could dismiss the buddhi as an unnecessary and superfluous appendage if the spirit were a dynamic principle. Our personality is a composite entity-a complex of the spirit and the dynamic buddhi. We can account for the intelligence and consciousness by means of the spirit and the growth and evolution and progress of the individuated self by means of buddhi. 86 We have seen how the Yoga system explains the emergence of the personalized self-the psychical and the logical subject. We are now to consider how the school accounts for the knowledge of the external world. The objects attract the buddhi even as a magnet attracts iron, and modify it.1 And then citi, the principle of consciousness, which per se is incapable of transference and movement (seemingly) assumes the modifications of the buddhi either by its reflection in the buddhi or by the reflection of the buddhi upon it, and thus occurs the cognition of the modifications of the buddhi.2 Consciousness remains unmoved. But the buddhi appears to be conscious in its presence. This apparent consciousness of the buddhi is called knowledge. The Bhasya quotes the following passage which is attributed by Vacaspati to Pancasikha: 'The enjoyer is immutable and incapable of transferring itself to the buddhi. But it seems to assume the modifications (of the buddhi) by reason of its reflection upon the latter and appears to transfer itself to it that is to say the self seems to transfer its identity to the buddhi and its changes. The activities of the buddhi are then transferred to the purusa (the conscious self) and the purusa seems to own them up as its own functions." Thus the transference of identity is not unilateral. It is a bilateral process. On the side of the buddhi the seeming identification of the buddhi with the purusa is effected by reason of the spiritualization of the changes of the buddhi by the reflection of the spirit upon it. As the processes of the buddhi are not distinguished from the purusa due to the seeming identification of the spirit with it, the activities of the buddhi (intellect) are felt, to all intents and purposes, as the activities of the self. The purusa (spirit) becomes 1 Cf. ayaskanta-mani-kalpa visaya ayah-sadharmakam cittam abhisambadhyo 'paranjayanti-Bhasya, YD, IV. 17. 2 Cf. citer apratisankramayas tadakarapattau svabuddhi-samvedanam-YD, IV. 22. 3 aparinamini hi bhoktr-saktir apratisankrama ca parinaminy arthe pratisankrante 'va tadvrttim anupatati tasyas ca praptacaitanyopagraha-rupaya buddhivrtter anukaramatrataya buddhivrttyavisista hi jnanavrttir ity akhyayate -Bhasya, YD, II. 20. Our rendering is not literal, but gives only the central meaning. Page #124 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. II] AVIDYA IN THE YOGA SCHOOL 87 seemingly identified with the buddhi and the buddhi becomes identified with the spirit. This mutual identification is responsible for the intelligization of the unintelligent changes and for their being not felt as distinct. Thus as a witness of the world process as presented by the buddhi, the purusa appears to have a knowledge-modification (jnanauitti) in common with the buddhi. And this knowledgemodification is nothing but the buddhi-modification as intelligized by consciousness of the purusa and has clearly these two elements as its constituents: (1) the buddhi-modification, and (2) the apparently transferred consciousness. The second element of 'apparently transferred consciousness' has been interpreted by the commentators as the reflection of the purusa. Thus commenting upon the passage 'The spirit (purusa) is the witness of the buddhi",2 Vacaspati says 'The spirit's witnessing of the buddhi (buddhipratisarveditvam) is nothing but the transmission of the image of the spirit to the buddhi-mirror.'3 Vijnanabhiksu, however, holds a radically different view. Let us now make a critical estimate of the Yoga epistemology of perception, which is necessary for the understanding of the problem of bondage and consequent emancipation from it. The epistemology of perception of the Sankhya-Yoga school is based upon a theory which has been borrowed by the Vivarana School of Sarkara Vedanta almost in toto. It is the direct antithesis of the theories sponsored by the Naiyayikas and the Jainas. The SankhyaYoga view may be called the representative theory of perception in contradistinction to the presentative theory of the latter who do not believe that the object is known through the medium of an There is, however, no inherent improbability in the buddhi being transformed into a structural form after the pattern of the object, because the buddhi or the mind-stuff is after all a material thing like the external object of cognition. The theory postulates that nothing can be known without a similar transformation of the mind ; in other words, the mind can know its own modification directly and immediately and through this the object which is the pattern. According to Vacaspati the modus operandi is rather simple. The buddhi or the mind becomes transformed into the likeness of the object with which it comes in contact. This likeness is called the vytti or modification or function. The vitti by itself cannot make the object known since it is as blind and unknowing as the material object. The real illumination takes place when the light of the spirit falls upon it. The vrtti is almost as transparent as the spirit and as such the former is capable of catching 1 Cf. YD, I. 4; III. 35 ; also Bhasya thereon. 2 sa puruso buddheh pratisamvedi-Bhasya, YD, II. 20. 3 buddhi-darpane purusa-pratibimba-sankrantir eva buddhipratisarveditvam pumsan. Page #125 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. the image of the latter. This reflection at once illumines the mental modification and this illumination is knowledge. The cognition of an object is thus equivalent to the illumination of the mental modification called vrtti. This cognition is at once objective and subjective and is a unitary act. It may express itself as 'This is pen' and 'I know the pen' according as the emphasis is put on the reflection or the mental modification. According to Vijnanabhiksu, who quotes texts from the Puranas and ancient authority in support, knowledge is possible only through mental modification which acts rather as the medium. Knowledge of an external object is possible if the mind is transformed into a structural likeness of it. This mental modification is by itself blind and unknowing. It becomes a cognition when it is reflected on the purusa (spirit). The objective judgment e.g. 'This is pen' takes place when the mental modification is imaged in the purusa. The purusa is the locus of the cognition. As for the subjective cognition or self-consciousness 'I know the pen' it is a different cognitive act. According to the epistemological postulate a thing can be known if the buddhi is transformed into its shape. The same rule applies to purusa also. Purusa or the self, in order to be known, must induce a structural modification in the buddhi. This modification of the buddhi after the pattern of the purusa is then imaged in the self and selfcognition, that is, the subjective judgment 'I know the pen' takes place. The locus of cognition is always the purusa as it is the locus of the image of the mental modification. So according to Vijnanabhiksu the objective cognition and the subjective cognition are numerically two different acts and the mental modifications are also two. To sum up, Vacaspati's theory is that both for the subjective and the objective cognition one mental modification is enough and the cognition takes place always in the mind. It is the spiritual illumination of the mental modification by the reflection of the spirit in it that constitutes cognition. Vijnanabhiksu, like the Naiyayika, thinks that the cognition of the subject and that of the object are two different acts, for which there are two different mental modifications. The cognition is not the illumination of the mental change by the imaging of the spirit upon it as Vacaspati holds. It is when the mental modification is imaged in the spirit that cognition takes place. The determination of the cognition as of an object or of the subject, that is, the purusa, is due to the nature of the object. If the object be an external entity it is an objective cognition. If it be the subject, it is subjective. The modus operandi is the same. The mind must be modified into the shape and form of the object and this modification must be imaged in the purusa or the self. The cognition always takes place in the purusa, whether the object of it is purusa or other than purussa. There is no departure from the rule that the content of 88 Page #126 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. II] AVIDYA IN THE YOGA SCHOOL 89 cognition is always the reflected image of the mental modification in the self even when the object happens to be the purusa i.e. the self itself. conscious. After this long digression let us now return to our subject proper. We have stated that the buddhi possessed of the trace of wrong cognition cannot comprehend the separate identity of the purusa. We also stated what this wrong cognition or nescience (avidya) consists in. It essentially consists in mistaking the process for the eternal, the ugly for the beautiful, the evil for the good and the unconscious for the The fundamental characteristic of nescience, however, consists in mistaking the unconscious for the conscious. The Bhasya quotes a passage, attributed to Pancasikha by Vacaspati, which runs as follows: 'Comprehending the manifest or the unmanifest buddhi as the self (conscious principle), a person revels in its prosperity thinking that the prosperity belongs to the real self, and he mourns over its misfortune thinking that the misfortune belongs to the self. All such is unawakened and unenlightened." Neither the prosperity nor the misfortune belongs to the purusa. But, under the influence of nescience, it appears that they belong to him. This nescience (avidya) is a klesa (affliction), and the root of other klesas at that viz. asmita (egoism), raga (attachment), dvesa (aversion) and abhinivesa (desire for life).2 The Bhasya says 'All the klesas (afflictions) are only the varieties of avidya inasmuch as avidya pervades them all. The other klesas relate to the same object which is related to avidya. They emerge with the emergence of avidya and are destroyed with the destruction of it."3 Egoism, attachment, aversion, desire for life or will to survive all these are essential factors for the sustenance and promotion of the world process, and avidya is at the root of all these. The world process loses its meaning and purpose when the avidya is uprooted and the buddhi reverts to its pristine state of prakrti. The evolution of the prakrti is for the enjoyment of the purusa and the enjoyment is possible only if the two absolutely separate and distinct principles of purusa the enjoyer and buddhi the enjoyed become, though indeed only apparently, identical. This apparent identity of the purusa and the buddhi or the principles of the seer and the seen is called asmita (egoism). If 4 1 vyaktam avyaktam va sattvam atmatvena 'bhipratitya tasya sampadam anunandaty atmasampadam manvanas tasya vyapadam anusocaty atmavyapadam manyamanah sa sarvo 'pratibuddha iti-Bhasya, YD, II. 5. 2 See YD, II. 4. 3 See Bhasya, YD, II. 4. 4 Cf. YD, II. 6. Also cf. Bhasya: puruso drksaktir buddhir darsanasaktir ity etayor ekasvarupapattir iva 'smita-klesa ucyate, bhoktr-bhogyasaktyor atyanta-vibhaktayor atyantasankirnayor avibhagapraptav iva satyam bhogah kalpate. Also cf. sattvapurusayor atyantasankirnayoh pratyayaviseso bhogah. -YD, III. 35. JP-12 Page #127 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 90 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [ch. avidya is the seed, asmita (egoism) is the sprout. We have spoken of the mental trace of avidya. Asmita (egoism) can be considered as the actualization of that trace. Raga (attachment) and duesa (aversion) can be viewed as the necessary corollaries of egoism. Abhinivesa (will to survive) can be taken as the cumulative effect of all the other klesas (afflictions). The klesas work together, help each other, and evolve an ego which would live for ever. This will to live for ever is called abhinivesa. The klesas nourish one another and perpetuate the world process. The Bhasya says: "The (five) klesas are five viparyayas (perversions). When active, they strengthen the potency of the gunas (viz. sattva, rajas and tamas--the three fundamental elements constituting primordial prakrti), inaugurate evolution, originate the causal chain, and produce the fruits of karman (viz. jati 'birth', ayus 'longevity and bhoga 'enjoyment'), being subordinate to one another. The klesas lie at the root of the world process. The equilibrium of prakyti is disturbed by the strengthening of the potency of the gunas i.e. by the elevation of one above another. The evolution begins with the disturbance of the equilibrium. Then originates the causal chain of buddhi or mahat, ahamkara etc. The whole evolution is for the enjoyment of the purusa and buddhi is the instrument which presents the world to the purusa. The evolution lasts so long as the separate identity and absolute disinterestedness of the purusa is not comprehended. But as soon as the purusa is found out to be absolutely untouched and unaffected by the world process, the evolution retraces its steps and becomes quiescent never to evolve again. Thus we find that according to the Yoga school it is the avidya or nescience about the fundamental distinction between purusa and prakyti that is responsible for the worldly existence which loses all its meaning and purpose when the truth is realized. The Yoga prescribes various ways for the realization of this truth. But we need not discuss them here in view of their lack of bearing on our enquiry which is strictly restricted to the study of the function of avidya. Let us now turn to the Sankhya school. III AVIDYA IN THE SAMKHYA SCHOOL There is no essential difference between the metaphysical positions of the Sankhya and the Yoga as we find them in the Sankhyakarika of Isvarakrsna and the Yogadarsana of Patanjali. The fact that the two 1 See YD, II. 9 and Bhasya. 2 klesa iti. panca viparyaya ity arthah, te syandamana gunadhikaram drachayanti, parinamam avasthapayanti, karyakaranasrota unnamayanti, parasparanugrahatantribhuya karmavipakam ca 'bhinirharanti 'ti-Bhasya, YD, II. 3. Page #128 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. 111] AVIDYA IN THE SAMKHYA SCHOOL 91 schools developed a common metaphysic from very early times is attested by such statements of the Mahabharata as 'The adherents of the Sankhya follow the same (principles) as are recognized by the followers of the Yoga. He who sees the Sankhya and the Yoga as one is wise.' But at the same time the Mahabharata clearly states the difference between their attitudes towards the necessity of spiritual discipline. Thus Bhisma, in reply to Yudhisthira's question about the difference between the Sankhya and the Yoga, says: "The adherents of the Sankhya extol Sankhya while the adherents of the Yoga extol Yoga. And they give plausible reasons for the establishment of their respective positions. He then elaborately states the principles of the two schools in two separate chapters. The main objection of the Yoga against the Sankhya is 'How can one devoid of self-mas emancipated?'3 Emancipation requires perfect control of the physical and the mental forces that hinder the progress towards emancipation. And as this can be achieved only by developing supernormal powers, the Yoga prescribes certain practices for the development of spiritual strength. According to the Yoga, it is only the strong who can be emancipated, the weak are sure to perish.4 Thus Bhisma says: 'As a weak and a meagre flame of fire, O King, is extinguished when covered by a heavy mass of fuel, so does a weak yogin (ascetic) perish, O lord. But as, again, the selfsame fire, O King, when it gathers strength and is accompanied by favourable wind can instantly consume even the whole world, exactly so can a yogin who has gathered strength, manifested potency, and is possessed of supreme power dry up the whole creation even as the sun does at the time of world dissolution.'5 The Yoga requires that one should exert oneself and attain superhuman powers of self-control in order to destroy the forces of evil. Otherwise one will share the fate of the weak and helpless creatures, perpetually entangled in a trap. Simple comprehension of truth without the development of adequate strength to cut asunder the trap of bondage is not sufficient to lead to emancipation. The answer of the Sankhya to the Yoga, on the other hand, is stated in the following terms: 'Only one who has comprehended all the processes and is unattached to the objects is indeed emancipated after death. Not otherwise.' The 1 yad eva Yogah pasyanti Sankhyais tad anu gamyate ekam Sankhyam ca Yogam ca yah pasyati sa buddhiman. -santiparva, 305. 19; also see 307. 44 & 316. 2-4. 2 Sankhyah Sankhyam prasamsanti Yoga Yogam dvijatayah vadanti karanam srestham sva paksodbhavanaya vai.-Ibid., 300. 2. 3 anisvarah katham mucyet-Ibid. verse 3. 4 Cf. abala vai vinasyanti mucyante ca balanvitah.-Ibid., verse 18. 5 Ibid., verses 19-21. & Cf. ibid., verses 15-17. ? vijnaye 'ha gatih sarva virakto visayesu yah. urdhvam sa dehat suvyaktam vimucyed iti nanyatha.-Ibid., verses 4-5. Page #129 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 92 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. Sankhya requires that the merits (guna) and the demerits (dosa) of the various developments of sattva, rajas and tamas should be comprehended for the sake of final emancipation. It gives only a secondary place to yogic practices. The summum bonum, however, of both the schools is identical, and both the systems are declared to be equally competent to lead the aspirant to it. Bhisma states the points of agreement and difference between the two schools in the following terms: 'Sauca (purification), tapas (austerity), compassion for the living beings, and observance of the vows--all these are common, O sinless (Yudhisthira), to both of them. But their darsana (attitude) is not identical.'3 If the Yoga believes in the efficacy of yogic practices, the Sankhya lays stress on philosophic understanding. But this difference in the basic attitude did not hinder the attempt at mutual understanding and development of common metaphysics. The Yoga school accepted the philosophical speculations of the Sankhya school while the latter accepted the practical code of the former. This process of mutual engrafting is clearly visible in such statements as we quoted at the outset of this section. The Bhagavadgita says: "It is only the ignorant, and not the wise, who consider the Sankhya and the Yoga as mutually opposed. One rightly depending upon the one attains the fruits of both. The Sankhyas and the Yogas attain to the same place, One who sees Sankhya and Yoga as one sees rightly. If the Yoga had no elaborate metaphysics, the Sankhya had no practical code for spiritual realization. Each borrowed from the other its own requirement, and the result was a fusion of the two. If the Mahabharata bears testimony to the process of this fusion, the later systematic expositions of the two systems record the fact of their fusion. We find detailed descriptions of the Sankhya speculations and the Yoga practices in the Mahabharata on more than one occasion. But there we do not find any attempt at systematization of the conceptions. It is only in the Sankhyakarika of Isvarakrsna and the Yogadarsana of Patanjali that we find the two schools in systematic forms. Of course, 1 Ibid., Chap. 301. 2 Cf. ubhe cai 'te mate jnate nopate sista-sammate anusthite yathasastrarn nayetam paramam gatim.-Ibid., 300, verse 8. 3 tulyam saucam tapoyuktam daya bhutenu ca 'nagha vratanam dharanam tulyam darsanam na sama tayoh.-Ibid., verse 9. 4 Cf. for gross exaggeration of this stress: hasa piva lala moda nityam vinayan upabhunja kuru ca ma sankam yadi viditam te Kapilamatam tat prapsyase moksa-saukhyam ca. ---Mathara on Ska, 37. 5 Sankhya-Yogau prthag balah pravadanti na panditah ekam apy asthitah samyag ubhayor vindate phalam. yat Samkhyaih prapyate sthanam tad Yogair api gamyate ekam Samkhyam ca Yogam ca yah pasyati sa pasyati.-BhGi, V. 4-5. 6 santiparva, Chapters 210 etc. ; 300-318 ; etc. Page #130 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 111. 111] AVIDYA IN THE SAMKHYA SCHOOL 93 these finished expositions must have been preceded by other earlier attempts at systematization. But unfortunately they are not available to us. Our enquiry of this section will be based on the Sankhyakarika of isvarakrsna, the Yuktidipika and the commentaries of Mathara, Gaudapada and Vacaspati as well as Vijnanabhiksu's works. The Sankhya conception of avidya is substantially the same as that of the Yoga. But we give a separate treatment to the subject only because of the difference of terminology. The selfsame five klesas viz. avidya, asmita, raga, dvesa and abhinivesa of the Yoga are respectively called tamas, moha, mahamoha, tumisra and andhatamisra in the Sankhya. The Sankhyakarika enumerates tamas, moha etc. as the five varieties of viparyaya while the Yogabhasya first enumerates avidya, asmita etc. as the varieties of the same and then gives the terms viz. tamas, moha etc. as their respective synonyms. Isvarakrsna or even the commentators Mathara and Gaudapada do not mention the terms avidya, asmita etc. It is only Vacaspati who expressly compares tamas, moha, etc. with avidya, asmita etc.? In order to understand the nature of viparyaya (perverted knowledge, elsewhere known as avidya or nescience) according to isvarakrsna, it is necessary to state in brief the scheme of psychical factors that make up what is called pratyaya-sarga (psychical creation).3 Mahat or buddhi is the first evolute of prakyti, and it has eight forms-- four sattvika and four tamasa. Dharma (what leads to prosperity and emancipation),4 jnana (discriminating knowledge), viraga (non-attachment), and aisvarya (supernormal powers) are the sattvika forms. The opposites of these viz. adharma, ajnana, aviraga and anaisvarya are the tamasa forms. These eight are called bhavas or psychical factors. They determine the nature of the buddhi and lead the linga (subtle body) to various forms of existence. These psychical factors produce various psychical complexes which have been classified into four broad categories viz. viparyaya (perverted cognition), asakti (mental disability due to deficiency of sense-organs), tusti (idle 1 See SKa 48. Cf. avidya-'smita-raga-dvesa-'bhinivesah klesa iti eta eva svasannabhis tamo moho mahamohas tamisro 'ndhatamisra iti-Bhasya, YD, 1. 8. Also cf. Yuktidipika (p. 154): se 'yam avidya pancaparva. 2 See TKau on Ska, 47-48. The Yuktidipika does so only implicitly. 3 Isvaraklspa mentions three distinct types of creation viz. lingasarga 'subtle physical creation' (Ska, 40-41), pratyaya-sarga (also called bhava-sarga) 'psychical creation' (SKA, 46, 52), and bhautika-sarga gross physical creation' (SKa, 53-54). The psychical, according to the Sankhya, is an evolute of the nonconscious praketi, and as such should not be confounded with immutable consciousness. (For an enumeration of nine types of sarga see santiparva, 310. 16-25). . 4 dharmo 'bhyudaya-nihsreyasa-hetuh-TKau, Ska, 23. 5 See SK, 23. 6 Cf. SKa, 43. See also Matharavrtti and TKau. - See Ska, 40-45. 8 Mathara defines viparyaya as samsayabuddhi 'doubt'.-Vytti on Ska, 46. Page #131 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. complaisance), and siddhi (consummation of knowledge). Of these four, the first three are the hindrances to the attainment of the fourth.2 Perverted cognition, mental disability and idle complaisance stand in the way of the attainment of consummate knowledge. Fifty subcategories of these four complexes are noticed in the Sankhyakarika.3 But we shall not deal with all these inasmuch as they have little bearing on our subject of enquiry, which is concerned only with the nature of viparyaya. The Sankhyakarika notices five sub-categories of viparyaya viz. tamas, moha, mahamoha, tamisra and andhatamisra. Of these five, again, each of the first two is divided into eight, the third into ten, and each of the last two into eighteen types. The illustrations of these sixty-two types are found in the commentaries.5 (1) Comprehension of the eight categories of prakrti, mahat, ahankara (ego) and the five tanmatras (subtle elements) as identical with the immutable soul is eightfold tamas, and is also called avidya. (2) The gods, on their attainment of eightfold supernormal powers, develop false belief in the immortality of the ego and permanence of their eightfold supernormal powers. This is moha and is also called asmita. (3) There are five subtle and five gross objects of enjoyment, the former for the gods and the latter for human and sub-human beings. Attachment to these objects is called tenfold mahamohaR or raga. (4) These ten objects together with eightfold supernormal powers constitute eighteenfold objects of tamisra. When an individual fails to achieve these objects, and feels rebuff, he develops anger or hatred for the objects. This hatred is called eighteenfold tamisra or dvesa. (5) When one attains the eighteenfold objects mentioned above, and is haunted by the fear of losing all these, one develops a complex called andhatamisra or abhinivesa which is eighteenfold due to its reference to the eighteenfold objects. These are the five sub-categories of viparyaya which are given in the Sankhyakarika. Vacaspati recognizes the identity of this fivefold viparyaya with the five-knotted avidya of the sage Varsaganya. And this fact is also established even by the nature of 94 1 Cf. tato 'sya niscaya utpadyate sthanur ayam ity esa siddhih-Mathara, SKa, 46. 2 Cf. SKa, 51. 4 See SKa, 48. 5 See Matharavrtti and TKau, SKa, 48. .evam 6 Cf. devanam sabdadayah panca tanmatrakhya visaya avisesah kevalanandarupah manusyanam bhautikasarirataya sukhaduhkhasampannah ity esa dasavidho mahamohah-Mathara on SKa, 48. Also cf. sabdadisu pancasu divyadivyataya dasavidhesu visayesu ranjaniyesu raga asaktir mahamohah-TKau, ibid. 7 See TKau on SKa, 47- Also cf. se 'yam pancaparva bhavaty avidya.-- Bhasya on YD, 1. 8; also see Tattvavaisaradi on it. Also cf. tamo moho mahamohas tamisro hy andha-sanjnakah avidya panca-parvai 'sa pradurbhuta mahatmanah.-Visnupurana quoted in Yogavarttika, YD, I. 8. 3 See SKa, 46-7. 1 Page #132 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. III] AVIDYA IN THE SAMKHYA SCHOOL 95 the illustrations of Mathara and Gaudapada. Vacaspati gives the same illustrations and furthermore supplies the corresponding Yoga terminology. Unfortunately we do not find clear definitions of tamas, moha etc. in the Sankhyakarika itself, and have to depend upon the commentaries. But we find nothing against our view that the Yoga and the Sankhya do not differ as regards their conception of viparyaya or avidya. Vijnanabhiksu, however, has attempted to differentiate between the Yoga and the Sankhya conception of viparyaya. Thus, commenting on the Yoga aphorism viz. viparyayo mithyajnanam atadrupapratisthamVijnanabhiksu says: 'In this (Yoga)-sastra anyathakhyati is the doctrine (of error) and not avivekamatra as propounded by the Sankhya'. He quotes the aphorism Avidya consists in the comprehension of non-eternal as eternal, impure as pure, sorrow as joy and non-soul as soul'' in order to show that the Yoga conception of avidya implies the doctrine of anyathakhyati which holds that error consists in the cognition of one thing in the character of another, or the superimposition of one thing upon another. He further distinguishes the Yoga anyathakhyati from the Vaisesika anyathakhyati on the ground that in the Yoga doctrine the content of the cognition is held to be superimposed upon the external thing while in the Vaisesika doctrine one external object is superimposed upon another external, object.5 Vijnanabhiksu further substantiates his position while commenting on the statement of the Yogabhasya that avidya is neither 'valid cognition' nor 'absence of cognition', but it is a 'false cognition' and as such is a category of cognition. There he says: 'In this (Yoga) system the term avidya does not mean aviveka i.e. non-discrimination in the sense of negation of discrimination as it does with the followers of Sankhya. But it (viz. avidya) is a species of determinate cognition or judgment as it is with such schools as the Vaisesika. This follows from both the Sutra and the Bhasya'.' Let us try to understand Vijnanabhiksu's conception of aviveka, Yoga anyathakhyati and Vaisesika anyathakhyati. According to Vijnanabhiksu, the absolutely non-existent such as square-circle cannot be the object of knowledge, and so he holds that in such cases as the erroneous cognition of silver in conch-shell, dreams and imaginations, . it is the mind-transformation that is the object or content of knowledge, See Also Yogavarttika, YD, I. 8. 2 His disciple Bhavaganesa follows him. See his commentary Dipika, YD, I. 8. 3 YD, I. 8. 4 YD, II. 5. 5 Cf. Vaisesikac ca 'tra 'yam viseso yad bahya-raja tader na 'ropah kintv antarasyai 've 'ti-Varttika, YD, I. 8. 6 YD, II. 5. 1 asmims ca darsane Sankhyanam iva 'viveko na 'vidyasabdarthah kim tu Vaisesikadivad visista-jnanam eve 'ti Sutra-B hasyabhyam avagantavyamVarttika on YD, II. 5. Page #133 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 96 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. and not something absolutely non-existent. Accordingly, he defines aviveka as 'knowledge of two things with their difference uncomprehended.'? Thus the erroneous cognition of a piece of conch-shell as silver consists in the cognition of both the piece of conch-shell and the mind-transformation with their difference uncomprehended. The mind takes the shape of silver. This mental silver and the piece of conchshell lying in front are both the objects of the wrong cognition 'This is silver'. The non-comprehension of the difference between the silver as mental content and the external conch-shell is responsible for the error. This is Vijnanabhiksu's interpretation of aviveka. The doctrine of Yoga anyathakhyati, on the other hand, as interpreted by Vijnanabhiksu would hold that the erroneous cognition 'This is silver' does not refer to two unrelated objects, but it refers to only one object, the related object--the objective substratum with mental content superimposed upon it as the predicate. The mind transformed into the shape of silver is the predicative content of the cognition 'This is silver' in which this stands for the real object and silver for the mental transformation or the idea. In other words, the judgment 'This is silver' is a complex of an objective fact, which is the subject, and a subjective idea, which is the predicate. The judgment is false because the predicate is not an objective real and so does not belong to it. In the veridical perception, the subject and the predicate are both objective facts and are related by an objective relation. The false judgment or error is one in which the predicate is a mental content which has no true relation with the logical subject (this) but still is superimposed upon it. The predicate and its relation are both unreal. The doctrine of Vaisesika anyathakhyati, on the other hand, would hold that it is the piece of silver that exists elsewhere that is superimposed on the subject of the erroneous cognition 'This is silver'. Vijnanabhiksu seems to criticize this Vaisesika doctrine when, commenting on the Sankhyasutra viz. nanyathakhyatih svavacovyaghatat (V. 55), he says: 'It is also not proper that one thing should be cognized in the form of another because that would involve contradiction of one's own statement .... Even the upholders of anyathakhyati admit that the non-existent cannot be cognized. The meaning is this: the non-existence of a thing in front cannot condition the cognition of the existence of the thing elsewhere.'3 Vijnanabhiksu Cf...... narastagadinam abhanat . . sukti-rajata-svapna-manorathadau ca manah-parinamarupa eva 'rthah pratiyate na 'tyanta 'sann iti vaksyatiSPB, V. 52. 2.... aviveko 'glhitasamsarga kam ubhayajnanam-SPB, I. 55. 3 anyad vastv anyarupena bhasata ity api na yuktam, svavaco-vyaghatat ... asato bhana-'sambhavasya 'nyatha-khyati-vadibhir api vacanad ity arthah. purovartiny asattve 'nyatra tatsattaya bhanaprayojakatvam iti bhavah---SPB, V. 55 Page #134 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. III] AVIDYA IN THE SAMKHYA SCHOOL 97 does not criticize the Yoga doctrine anywhere, though he always differentiates it from the doctrine of aviveka of the Sankhya system. And as we have stated above he quotes the Yogasutra II. 5 in order to show that the Yoga system upholds the doctrine of anyathakhyati. But there are passages in the Yogabhasya which imply the doctrine of aviveka as well. On the other hand, there is a passage? quoted in the Yogabhasya and ascribed to the great Sankhya exponent Pancasikha by Vacaspati, which can easily be interpreted as implying the doctrine of anyathakhyati for the Sankhya system. The truth seems to be that both the systems, the Yoga and the Sankhya, had a common theory of error, and that was the theory of aviveka. Both the systems regard viveka (discrimination) as the condition of emancipation. And there is no reason why both of them should not regard aviveka (non-discrimination) as the condition of bondage. Of course, had the doctrine of aviveka gone counter to the fundamental position of the Yoga, it would have been plausible to deduce a different doctrine of error. But when the fundamental position of both the systems is identical, we fail to understand why Vijnanabhiksu is so keen on differentiating the Yoga doctrine from the Sankhya one. Vijnanabhiksu makes capital out of Patanjali's definition of avidya. But from a consideration of the general philosophical position of the Yoga system as found in the Yogasutra and the Bhasya, we can easily establish that the doctrine of aviveka is not inconsistent with the Yoga system. We can also easily interpret the Yoga definition of avidya as implying the doctrine of aviveka, or at least as not against such interpretation. Let us briefly attempt to see what the Yoga system points to. According to the Yoga system, as we have already stated, the evolution of the prakrti is for the enjoyment of the purusa, and the enjoyment is possible only if the two absolutely separate and distinct principles of purusa and prakyti become apparently identical. Now what this apparent identity is due to? It is certainly due to avidya. The function of avidya thus is found to be 'to make appear as identical what are not really identical'. And how can this function of avidya be possible? Avidya belongs to the buddhi, and so it cannot operate upon the external object. Therefore it follows that avidya operates For instance, the passages--(I) ya tu kaivalya-pragbhara vivekavisayanimna sa kalyanavaha, samsara-prag-bhara 'vivekavinaya-nimna papavaha (Bhasya, YD, I. 12); (2) buddhitah param purusam akara-silam vidyadibhir vibhaktam apasyan kuryat tatra 'tma-buddhim mohene 'ti (quoted in the Bhasya, YD, II. 6)--can easily be interpreted as implying the doctrine of aviveka. 2 vyaktam avyaktam va sattvam atmatvena 'bhipratitya tasya sampadam anunandaty atmasam padam manvanah... sa sarvo 'pratibuddhah-Bhasya, YD, II. 5. 3 See YD, II. 26; Ska, 2, 64-66. JP-13 kaivalya-pragua-nimna Padibhir Page #135 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 98 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. upon the buddhi in order to produce the appearance of identity. Now this operation can be possible in two ways: (1) by arresting the normal activity of the buddhi and (2) by misguidance of the buddhi. By the first kind of operation, buddhi is thwarted and made incapable of cognizing the difference, and by the second kind of operation the buddhi is made to mistake the one for the other. The Yogasutra and the Bhasya do not affirm one and negate the other of these possible operations of avidya and so we are at liberty to accept any or both of the two operations. If we admit avidya as having the capacity of thwarting the buddhi, the doctrine of aviveka will follow. And if we ascribe to the avidya the capacity of misguiding the buddhi the doctrine of anyathakhyati will be the logical deduction. Let us now see what Patanjali's definition would imply. The definition can symbolically be expressed as avidya=cognition of A as B. Now this definition can imply either (I) that both A and B are the objects of cognition which has failed to cognize their difference and consequently they appear as one, or (2) that only B is the object of cognition and consequently it alone appears. In the first case the doctrine of aviveka is the implication, and in the second the doctrine of anyathakhyati is implied. Thus it is established that the doctrine of aviveka is not inconsistent with the Yoga system, and also that Patanjali's definition of avidya can be interpreted as implying the doctrine of aviveka as well. Vijnanabhiksu's insistence, therefore, that the Yoga accepts the doctrine of anyathakhyati as distinguished from the doctrine of aviveka of the Sankhya is not based upon valid grounds. It is beyond doubt that the Sankhya theory of error called avivekakhyati or viveka-'khyati is not to be confounded with Prabhakara's theory. Prabhakara believes that there is no error possible and the proposition 'This is silver' does not point to a unitary judgment. This stands for the substratum which is real and 'silver' is the object of recollection without being felt as recollected. Thus this recollected silver is real because only a perceived fact can be recollected. But 'this' which is a perceived fact and 'silver' which is the remembered fact are not realized as distinct. The copula 'is' in the judgment symbolizes the non-apprehension of unrelatedness. The pseudo-subject and the pseudo-predicate are not felt as unrelated which they are in point of reality. So there is no perversion in the objective plane. And on the subjective plane also there is no confusion which would have n had the subject and the predicate been felt as related. There is perception of the substratum and recollection of silver, and these two acts of cognition are not felt as distinct. But mere non-perception of nitya-suci-sukha-'tma 1 The definition is anitya-'suci-duhkha-'natmasu khyatir avidya-YD, II. 5. Page #136 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. III] AVIDYA IN THE SAMKHYA SCHOOL 99 distinction is not tantamount to perception of identity. Thus there is no error because all our cognitions do correspond to objective facts as they are. There is an unfortunate tendency to interpret the Sankhya theory of error on substantially the same lines with Prabhakara's theory. There is not the slightest warrant for this supposition. The Sankhya must believe in positive error. In the Sankhya theory, the self (purusa), left to itself, is absolutely unattached to prakrti, and so is unaffected by the vicissitudes of the latter. The self per se whether in bondage or in the emancipated state is absolutely free and pure. That in bondage the self does not feel its freedom is due to the fact that it mistakes the vicissitudes of prakyti to be the real incidents of its own career. This mistake is cured and corrected by the realization of the absolute distinction of the self from the not-self. In bondage, the self does not and cannot feel its distinction and difference from the not-self (prakrti and its evolutes), because it identifies itself with the not-self. This identification of self with not-self is due to transcendent illusion which cannot be set down to any historical occasion. The self and not-self are eternal verities, and have a parallel existence. The relation between them is unreal and there is no reason why it should occur at all. But it is a question of fact and not of reason. The illusion of identity, which is called, in the favourite Sankhya terminology, aviveka or non-discrimination, also is an uncaused fact. It is a source of gratification and comfort that it is liable to be destroyed by vivekakhyati or the realization of difference. The reason for the illusion being called aviveka-khyati seems to be due to the antithesis between viveka-khyati 'the realization of difference' and the negation of it in illusion. As a matter of fact all who believe in the possibility of error, however variously they may interpret it, must admit that nondiscrimination of the subject and the predicate is the condition of it. The illusion of identity is the result of non-discrimination. It is not therefore wide of the mark to describe error as non-discrimination, because without it no error is possible, and because in every case of error it is immanent. In the Sankhyasutra' error is called sad-asat-khyati because the predicate is real taken by itself, and the reality of the subject is universally acknowledged ; but though both the subject and the predicate are true, the contradiction of the error proves that the predicate is falsely attributed to the subject. In other words, the relation between the predicate and the subject is unreal in the context. The theory seems to be the analogue of the theory of Vacaspati Misra as propounded by him in the Tatparyatika. He also regards the terms to be real, though the relation is not so. 1 V. 56. Page #137 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 100 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. As regards the characterization of the Yoga theory of error as anyathakhyati thinking the predicate to be a mental fact by Vijnanabhiksu we are not quite sure of the correctness, both traditional and logical, of the theory. We must take it as Vijnanabhiksu's interpretation. The elaborate attempt made by Vijnanabhiksu to prove that it is different from the aviveka-khyati attributed to the Sankhya school has been shown by us to be not necessarily warranted by the texts. Furthermore, it has been ignored by Vijnanabhiksu that aviveka in the sense of non-discrimination is the universal condition of error and as such can be accepted without prejudice to their metaphysical commitments by all schools of philosophy including the Nyaya realists and the Vedantist illusionists. We think it safe not to attempt to classify it under any of the recognized theories of error, because the original authoritative works have not expressed their predilection for anyone of them. One thing is certain, namely, that the Sankhya or the Yoga theory of error is not the same as Prabhakara's theory which denies the very possibility of error. We have now finished our enquiry about the Sankhya conception of avidya. When this avidya disappears knowledge becomes perfect. And this perfect knowledge leads to final emancipation of the soul. The soul then shines in its own splendour. Isvarakrsna describes kevala-jnana (perfect knowledge) and kaivalya (final emancipation) in the following terms: 'By constant exercise in the knowledge of truth and due to the absence of nescience (viparyaya) there arises such pure (visuddha), perfect (kevala) and complete knowledge as 'not am, not mine, not I'. By such knowledge the purusa, self-possessed and like an onlooker, witnesses the prakrti made barren and devoid of the seven formst because of the fulfilment of the twofold) purpose (of the purusa). The one i.e. purusa is indifferent because of the knowledge 'She (i.e. prakrti) has been seen by me' and the other (i.e. prakrti) retires because of the knowledge 'I am seen'. And there is no more the condition of creation even though the two exist side by side. Thus in final realization prakyti stands disenchanted before the purusa who is disabused of his illusion. On dharma etc. having been deprived of the conditions of their existence) because of the attainment of perfect knowledge, the purusa remains embodied (for some time) due to the residual traces (of dharma etc.) just like the revolution of a wheel due to impetus (even after the real force has been withdrawn). And with the shuffling off of the mortal coil, the prakrti retires on the fulfilment of her purpose, and purusa attains kaivalya (final emancipation), i The seven forms are: dharma, adharma, ajnana, vairagya, avairagya, aisvarya and anaisvarya. The eighth form is jnana which disappears last of all. 2 The reference is to the eight bhavas of dharma, adharma, jnana, ajnana, vairagya, avairagya, aisvarya and anaisvarya. Page #138 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. IV) AVIDYA IN THE NYAYA SCHOOL IOI absolute and eternal.'! The kaivalya or emancipation of the self is rather a rediscovery of its own nature, and not the acquisition of unprecedented condition or the relinquishment of a real limitation. Let us now turn to the Nyaya conception of avidya. IV AVIDYA IN THE NYAYA SCHOOL This school does not believe in blind teleology of the SankhyaYoga. The soul itself is responsible for its bondage. Although it is as ubiquitous and eternal as the soul of the Sankhya-Yoga, it possesses the non-eternal qualities of consciousness, desire etc. much in the same way as the material substance possesses colour, taste, smell, etc. The Nyayasutra enumerates the following as the specific qualities of the soul: desire, aversion, effort, pleasure, pain and knowledge. Besides these, the qualities of dharma (merit) and adharma (demerit), jointly designated as samskara (trace), are also recognized as the uncommon characteristics of the soul. These two accrue respectively from the morally good and bad actions of the organ of speech, mind and body. They inhere in the soul and condition the creation of a new body in the next birth out of the material elements. In addition to these, there are a number of defects (dosas) that are classified into three groups viz. raga (attachment), dvesa (aversion) and moha (delusion). Of these three, moha (delusion) is the most debasing, inasmuch as it is the root of the other two.5 Moha is mithyajnana (wrong assessment of values). Vatsyayana says: "The pleasant thoughts of objects cause raga (attachment) and the painful thoughts of objects cause dvesa (aversion). Both these thoughts, being of the nature of wrong assessment of values, are not different from moha (delusion). The two viz. raga (attachment) and duesa (aversion) spring from moha (delusion)." Moha lies at the root of raga and dvesa. These three dosas (defects) goad one to action, good or bad, pleasant or painful. In other words, dosa leads to pravrtti (volitional activity),s that is, the threefold action of the organ of speech, mind, and body.' Dharma (merit) and 1 SK, 64-68. 2 iccha-dvesa-prayatpa-sukha-duhkha-jnanany atmano lingam-NS, I. I. IO. These characteristics are uncommon signs which prove the existence of soul and as such are considered as the specific qualities of it. See Bhasya and Vitti. 3 See NS, III. 2. 61 and Bhasya. 4 Ibid., IV. I. 2-3. 5 Cf. ibid., IV. 1. 6. See Bhasya on NS, IV. 1. 3. 7 visayesu ranjaniyah sankalpa raga-hetavah, kopaniyah sarkalpa dvesahetavah, ubhaye ca sankalpa na mithya-pratipatti-laksanatvan mohad anye, tav imau moha-yoni raga-dvesav iti--Bhasya, NS. IV. 1. 6. 8 Cf. NS, I. 1. 18 with Bhasya. 9 See NS, I. 1. 17. Page #139 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. adharma (demerit) accrue from this pravrtti. Now this pravrtti qua dharma and adharma together with the dosas produce the feelings of pleasure and pain as well as their conditions such as the body, senseorgans, sense-objects and consciousness. These products are repeatedly accepted as well as rejected and the process has no end till the soul is emancipated. The worldly life (loka) is carried on by the current of this ceaseless process of acceptance and rejection. Mithyajnana (wrong assessment of values), dosa (defects), pravrtti (volitional activity), janma (birth) and duhkha (suffering) are the recurring links of the chain of worldly life (samsara).2 102 Thus the primal and most fundamental condition of the worldly career punctuated by birth and death in unbroken succession is delusion or perverted belief which accepts the evil for the good and rejects the good for the evil masquerading as good. Under the influence of this overpowering passion the soul identifies itself with the psycho-physical organism and the external environment and develops love and hatred, sympathy and antipathy, desire and aversion for whatever is found to be conducive or otherwise to the temporary well-being of its embodied existence. The body may be gross or subtle according as its material varies, but the result is the same viz. its limitation to the little environment in which it is placed. The besetting sin of worldly career is that the self does not distinguish itself from the body and thus develops an inordinate love for what is pleasant and useful to the body and antipathy for what is harmful and unpleasant. The embodied existence necessarily generates a possessive impulse and goads the soul to acquire the good things of the earth. This love of property eventually leads to faction and feud when a competitor arrives to contest the claim. These worldly activities which absorb all the interest of the person produce in their turn merit and demerit according as the activities are good or bad. Disinterested service of fellow creatures generates religious merit and the opposite course of action produces religious demerit. These again necessitate the fresh birth in a new body and environment which are calculated to produce the consequences of the moral values acquired in the past lives. But as this fresh life again is also the occasion for the acquisition of fresh merit and demerit, it invariably leads to another birth. Birth means enjoyment and suffering, growth and decay, and lastly death which is nothing but the dissolution of the physical body. So the worldly career necessarily entails suffering and pain. It may be disputed whether the balance of happiness is greater than unhappiness. But Indian philosophers have unanimously condemned worldly career, because it is not one of 1 See NS, I. 1. 20 with Bhasya. 2 Cf. ta ime mithyajnanadayo duhkhanta dharma avicchedenai 'va pravarta. manah samsara iti-Bhasya, NS, I. 1. 2. Page #140 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. IV) AVIDYA IN THE NYAYA SCHOOL 103 unalloyed happiness. Even if it be granted that the proportion of pleasure is greater than that of pain, yet the very fact that pain is unavoidable shows that worldly career cannot be regarded as a perfect condition of life. It is the supreme prerogative of the soul, whether encased in a human or divine body, that it is not satisfied permanently with anything short of a state of existence free from all taint of suffering and pain. It is this divine discontent with the relative values that augurs for the realization of perfection. This perfection free from the shackles of the not-self is the final salvation of the soul, which is achieved when the soul entirely overcomes and transcends delusion (mithyajnana). Now what is the nature of this delusion and how is it responsible for the metempsychosis (samsara)? Explaining the nature of this delusion and describing the origin of the metempsychosis, Vatsyayana says: 'Delusion (mith yajnana) consists in mistaking the not-self for the self. It is a falso belief (moha) of the form 'I am the body'. It is egoism (ahamkara) which consists in looking upon the not-self as identical with the real self. What are the contents of this ego-consciousness? It is the body, sense-organs, mind, feeling and cognitions, in one word, the psycho-physical appurtenance which is felt as identical with the self. Why is this ego-consciousness, that is to say, the self's identification with what is not-self the cause of the unbroken chain of births and deaths ? The soul develops the conviction that it is none other than the body, sense-organs etc. and consequently is constantly obsessed with the fear of self-annihilation on the annihilation of the body and its concomitant organs and faculties. The self cannot think that it is immortal in its own right and because of its identification with the mortal body is perpetually tormented by the fear of death. The soul, therefore, seeks to preserve the body from death by all means. But this clinging to the body in spite of its inevitable end leads to the recurrence of a fresh life in a fresh body and consequent death. The reason for this is that a deep-rooted desire (vasana) cannot go unsatisfied. The desire for the body is satisfied not by the preservation of the previous one because of its mortality, but by the acquisition of a fresh body. And this means the perpetuation of the worldly career.'1 We have seen that delusion which induces perverted belief is the 1 kim punas tan mithya-joanam? anatmany atmagrahah, aham asmi 'ti moho 'hankara iti. anatmanam khalv aham asmi 'ti pasyato drstir ahankara iti. kiin punas tad arthajatam yadvisayo 'hankarah? sarirendriya-mano-vedanabuddhayah. katham tadvisayo 'hamkarah samsara-bijam bhavati? ayam khalu sariradyartha-jatam aham asmi "ti vyavasitas taducchedena "tmocchedam manyamano 'nuccheda-trsnapariplutah punah punas tad upadatte, tad upadadano janma-maranaya yatate, tena 'viyogan na 'tyantam duhkhad vimucyata iti-Introductory Bhasya, NS, IV. 2. I. Page #141 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 104 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. fountain-head of worldly career. We have also seen how this primal nescience, like the Christian counterpart of Original Sin, produces all sorts of evils. The supreme evil is the ego-consciousness which works like the hydra-headed monster. It generates love and hatred and lastly delusion which consists in thinking what is unwholesome as wholesome. The ego-consciousness is not confined to the self but embraces not-self as well. It is the outcome of the identification of the self with not-self beginning with the physical organism which encases it and ending with the external objects which produce feelings of pleasure and pain. This mistaken identity with the body and the senses and the objects of experience is made possible by the idea that they belong exclusively to the self. The material objects are thought to be its exclusive property by the deluded self though they are experienced and enjoyed by all persons without distinction. The external objects by themselves are not an evil. It is only when they are invested with false values by the deluded self that they become a potent source of bondage. The self develops love and attraction for the external objects including the body because it is deluded into thinking that they serve to promote its well-being. It is this belief in the intrinsic value of these brute material facts which are neither pleasant nor unpleasant without a self to contemplate them in these terms, that makes them a snare and a trap for the self, They induce attachment when they are believed to be pleasant and useful and produce revulsion and antipathy when they are conceived to be hostile to the self. The utility or hostility of the sense-data is a matter of false belief fostered by a long-drawn delusion which has been the companion of the soul from beginningless time. The delusion can be removed only by the proper appraisement of the intrinsic nature of the objects as they are without reference to the psychical reactions they are found to produce. When the self dispassionately contemplates these objects as brute facts which have no emotional or volitional satisfaction then the self will cease to be drawn by them. The body, for instance, is an exceedingly unlovable object. It is a mass of flesh and bones and blood, which should by themselves have no charm. It is subject to illness and decay and is bound to be dissolved into its elements by the operation of inexorable physiological and biological laws. It is impure, unclean and ungainly. This is no less true of one's own body than of other objects. But the fundamental and basic ignorance which forms, as it were, the original capital of the worldly existence of the self leads it astray and induces it to ascribe false values to things of experience. Beauty is one such value. Thus when a person looks at a member of the opposite sex he does not think that the human body is a mass of flesh and blood and bones. On the contrary he thinks that the person 1 Cf. dosanimittam rupadayo visayah sankalpakstah-NS, IV. 2. 2. Page #142 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. IV] AVIDYA IN THE NYAYA SCHOOL 105 is a beautiful damsel whose intimate association and friendship will satisfy all his desires and wants. The same is the case with a woman regarding a man. The human body ought to have no charm for a wise man who can size up things and appraise them at their proper value. It is the fool who is deluded into thinking that not only the body of the man or the woman, but even several parts of the same such as the teeth or the nose or the eyes have got a special fascination. But the wise man will analyse the human body into its component parts and will see in it nothing but flesh, blood, bone, tendons, veins, bile, phlegm and excreta. Viewed in this perspective the whole thing appears to be disenchanted and by its sheer ugliness will repel a prospective lover. So ultimately it is the self which is responsible for its station in life, whether it is free or in bondage. The original sin of ignorance which is responsible for so many and various perversities of our beliefs and dispositions and tastes must be got rid of. And the oniy antidote of this masterful malady is the knowledge of reality of self and not-self in their proper and true character. Now a question arises. But is knowledge of reality possible of achievement? If knowledge of reality means knowledge of any particular individual thing and if this be regarded as the instrument o salvation, then there will be no living creature in bondage, because everyone has got true knowledge of something or other. It must, therefore, be accepted that knowledge of reality means knowledge of the entire range of reality, that is, of each and every real that may exist. This is a covetable state no doubt. But it is not possible for ordinary mortals with their thousand and one limitations and imperfections to achieve this infinite knowledge. Infinite knowledge presupposes infinite life and unlimited opportunities for self-culture and the compresence of all the conditions of knowledge. But we do not see, however lucky a person may be, he can command all these resources. Our span of life is limited and that even frequently punctuated with illness, worries and various sorts of wants and tribulations which make the pursuit of knowledge an exceedingly difficult task. So we find that only one man is really learned and wise in a million. So knowledge of reality in its entire range and scope is only a counsel of perfection. If, on the other hand, it is conceded that a person acquires true knowledge of a limited number of things, it is possible to argue that he will have no delusion with regard to these objects and he will be ee to that extent. Freedom after all is spiritual, and such spiritual and intellectual freedom can be bestowed by knowledge no doubt. But this limited freedom is not true salvation which is the goal and consummation of our aspiration. A person may lose all illusion regarding things he knows. But as regards things unknown, and their name is Legion, he will be subject to delusion and JP-14 Page #143 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 100 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. attachment and aversion, and consequently to the full catalogue of worries and tribulations that are attendant upon ignorance. The remedy prescribed by the philosophers of the Nyaya school thus transpires to be a false hope, the will-o'-the-wisp, which will for ever elude the aspirant. Thus the remedy is more intractable than the disease. In reply to this formidable criticism, Uddyotakara, following Vatsyayana, asserts that the difficulty proceeds from a fundamental misconception of the nature of knowledge of reality and of the nature of delusion. Delusion is not equivalent to negation of knowledge, but it means false knowledge and false belief. Now we shall have to consider what sort of delusion is the cause of bondage which is exemplified by worldly life. It is delusion regarding the true nature of a limited number of reals such as the self, the body etc., that is responsible for our bondage. So it is the correct knowledge of these reals and the correct appraisement of their values which will put an end to our ignorance and the consequential emotional and volitional perversions. And thus our worldly career and the ties which bind us down to the miserable condition of life will be snapped asunder. As has been said more than once, the primal source of our misery is our ignorance of the nature of our own self and our perverted identification of the self with the not-self. It is not an impossible task to acquire this knowledge even with the aid of our limited resources. The worldly career of a soul, therefore, means identification of the soul with the material product such as the body. So long as the soul does not become conscious of this false identification, it remains in bondage. But how can the soul become conscious of its own separate identity? How can it comprehend that the world does not belong to it? In other words, how is the knowledge of truth possible? The Nyayasutra says: 'It is possible by the practice of a particular kind of meditation and ecstasy (by means of the concentration of mind)."1 Mere logical disquisition or philosophical understanding is not sufficient for realizing the truth. The soul has to exert itself for its realization. The mind is to be forcibly removed from the sense-organs, and kept in conjunction with the soul with ardent desire to know the truth. This is meditation or ecstasy (samadhi). It is the result of the accumulated strength of endeavours spread over countless number of lives in the past. 3 The soul progressively gains strength and gradually becomes capable of more and more successful meditation and ecstasy. The 1 samadhi-visesabhyasat-NS, IV. 2. 38. 2 Cf. sa tu. (samadhi-vesesah) pratyahrtasye 'ndriyebhyo manaso dharakena prayatnena dharyamanasya 'tmana samyogas tattvabubhutsa-visistah-Bhasya, NS, IV. 2. 38. 3 Cf. purvakrta-phala-'nubandhat tadutpattih-NS, IV. 2. 41. Page #144 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 111. Iv] AVIDYA IN THE NYAYA SCHOOL 107 Nyayasutra also prescribes mental and physical discipline in the shape of restraint of the external activity of the senses and mind for the purification of the soul. The truth is also to be known from and discussed with the wise by means of questions and answers. It is to be sedulously nurtured and guarded at least in the initial stages from the wanton attacks of sceptics and unbelievers. If the opponents possess superior intellectual resources and if the votary of truth is found unequal to disarm the critic, it is sanctioned by the logical code of the Naiyayika that the opponent should be gagged into silence even by resort to disputation and wrangling, though they may not be unexceptionable forms of debate. It is to be understood that these devices are adopted by an elderly person who does not wish that the spiritual career of the neophyte should be upset by the onslaughts of designing persons whose sophistical arguments he finds himself unable to refute. When the truth is thus known and realized, the soul gets rid of nescience or delusion (mithyajnana). The Nyayasutra prescribes the practice of both ecstasy (samadhi) and pursuit of knowledge (jnana) for the realization of the truth. If the practice in philosophical pursuit illumines the path, the practice in meditation and ecstasy leads to the attainment of the goal. When the knowledge of truth dawns upon the soul, the nescience or delusion ceases to exist. Describing the process of the cessation of the worldly life, the Nyayasutra says: "Apavarga (final emancipation) is attained when of these (factors) viz. duhkha (suffering), janma (birth), pravrtti (merits and demerits born of volitional activities)," dosas (defects) and mithyajnana (nescience or delusion)-the preceding one ceases on the cessation of the succeeding one.' With the cessation of nescience, defects i.e. the evil predispositions such as attachment cease. With the cessation of defects merits and demerits cease. With the cessation of merits and demerits, birth and death cease. With the cessation of birth and death, misery and suffering cease. With the cessation of birth the body ceases and how can the suffering exist when the instrument of suffering and misery viz. the body and the like has ceased to exist? This absolute cessation of suffering and misery is called final emancipation (apavarga).5 We have now related in brief the conception of the nature and function of nescience in the Nyaya school. Let us now turn to the Vaisesika school. 1 See NS, IV. 2. 46. 2 See NS, IV. 2. 47-51. 3 Pravrtti means action, good and bad. But, according to Vatsyayana, here it means dharma and adharma which accrue from those actions. See Bhasya, NS, I. I. 2. 4 duhkha-janma-pravrtti-dosa-mithya-jnananam uttarottarapaye tadanantarapayad apavargah-NS, I. I. 2. 5 tadatyanta-vimokso 'pavargah--NS, I. 1. 22. Page #145 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 108 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. AVIDYA IN THE VAISESIKA SCHOOL This school did not develop any separate conception of nescience (avidya). The Vaisesikasutra is mainly busy with the examination of the generic and specific characteristics of the categories and refers to the problem of knowledge only incidentally. At the outset it proposes to examine the nature of dharma (religious merit) which it then defines as what conditions the attainment of well-being and final emancipation. The scripture (amnaya) is held valid because it speaks of dharma.3 Final emancipation is due to the true knowledge (of the categories), born of dharma." After this brief statement about dharma and its instrumentality for final emancipation through the knowledge of truth, the Vaisesikasutra suddenly proceeds to divide, define, and examine the categories and their sub-categories. It comes back to the problem of dharma only in the sixth chapter where, very briefly, some features of dharma are considered. Again from the seventh chapter onward it plunges into its main theme of examination of the nature of the categories and the sub-categories and, curiously enough, reverts to the problem of dharma only in the last two sutras of the last ahnika (lecture) of the last chapter. The main purpose of the Sutra thus is not the examination of dharma, although the author pledges at the outset that he would examine dharma. It is difficult to ascertain the reason why the author did not redeem his pledge. The examination of dharma is the subject of the Mimamsa school and it seems anomalous why the Vaisesikasutra should propose to examine it. This anomaly becomes still more puzzling when we find that the Vaisesikasutra gives so little attention to the topic of dharma which ought to have been given a very important position in view of the initial enunciation of the Sutra. But we can hazard a guess. The author of the Sutra seems enamoured of the Mimamsa conceptions of dharma (religious merit) and adrsta (unseen religious potency) which he utilizes so frequently for the explanation of apparently unexplainable phenomena, both natural and supernatural.5 Many controversial metaphysical problems are settled by reference to the Vedas. Such ultimate issues as the initial motion of the atoms and the minds after universal dissolutions 1 atha 'to dharmam vyakhyasyamah--VS, I. I. I. 2 yato 'bhyudaya-nihsreyasa-siddhih sa dharmah-VS, I. 1. 2. 3 VS, I. 1. 3. 4 Cf. dharma-visesa-prasutad dravya-guna-karma-samanya-visesa-samavayanam padarthanam sadharmya-vaidharmyabhyam tattvajnanan nihsreyasamVS, I. I. 4. 5 About adrsta cf. VS, V. I. 15; V. 2. 2, 7, 13, 17. About dharma cf. IV. 2. 7; IX. 2. 9. C Cf. VS, II. 1. 17; III. 2. 21 ; IV. 2. IL; V. 2. 10 Page #146 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. v] AVIDYA IN THE VAISESIKA SCHOOL 109 and the attainment of the knowledge of truth are held as due to adrsta and dharma.' Besides this, the Sutra refers to some Vedic rites for the acquisition of adrsta.2 In view of such importance of the conception of dharma for the exposition of philosophical problems dealt with in the treatise, it was not unnatural that the author should propose dharma as the main theme of it and accept the validity of the Vedic Scripture (amnaya) that contained it. Religious potency (adysta) lies at the root of creation and if the creation is beginningless, the potency also is beginningless. It is this potency which is responsible for new creations after dissolutions. The Sutra does not define adrsta and this is perhaps due to the fact that its meaning was well known at that time. The Vedic rites have results, immediate or remote, known or unknown. Where the result is not immediate and known it should be regarded as remote and unknown prosperity. Such performances as ablution, fasting, celibacy, living at preceptor's house for study of the scriptures, and the like produce religious potency. These rites and duties of the fourfold stages of life (asramas), moral degradations and their opposites also produce assta. One sets to perform good and bad actions resulting in merit and demerit impelled by desire for gain and hatred for loss. 6 Both dharma and adharma produce adrsta. The terms dharma and adharma are also used in the sense of adrsta,' that is, the result produced by dharma and adharma. Dharma and adharma qua cause are respectively identical with the rites and duties prescribed by the Vedic injunctions and their violations while dharma and adharma qua effect are respectively identical with the result of those rites and duties and their violations. In other words, dharma and adharma qua effect are adysta. It is in these senses that the terms adrsta, dharma and adharma are used in this treatise. The relevant meanings are to be understood with reference to the context. After this digression let us come to our subject proper viz. the problem of avidya. We have stated at the outset that the Vaisesika school did not develop its own theory of avidya. The Nyaya school had great influence on the development of the Vaisesika school and in later times 1 VS, V. 2. 13; 1. 1. 4. 2 VS, VI. 2. 2. 3 Cf. drstadssta-prayojananam drstabhave prayojanam abhyudayaya-VS, VI. 2. I. 4 abhisecanopavasa-brahmacarya-gurukulavasa-vanaprastha-yajna-dana - proksana-dinnaksatra-mantrakalaniyamas ca 'distaya---VS, VI. 2. 2. 5 caturasramyam upadha anupadhas ca, VI. 2. 3. The next sutra defines upadha as bhavadosa and anupadha as adosa. 6 iccha-dvesa-purvika dharmadharmayoh pravittih-VI. 2. 14. Upaskara, however, interprets the sutra in a different way. The interpretation can be summed up as iccha-dvesa-purvika pravittih dharma-dharmayoh karanam. 7 See IV. 2. 7; IX. 2. 9. Page #147 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 110 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. both the schools coalesced, and consequently developed a common theory. But let us collect together the relevant materials that are in the Vaisesikasutra, and see their implication. The Padartha-dharmasangraha (also known as Prasastapadabhasya) of Acarya Prasastapada. is an excellent rearrangement and interpretation of the topics of the Vaisesikasutra, and is of great value for the understanding of the original Sutra. Our enquiry accordingly will be based on these two works. The enquiry of the whole chapter has limited itself to the most original sources, and as such it is proposed to withstand the influence of the later developments and innovations as much as possible. The Vaisesi kasutra recognizes two kinds of cognition viz. vidya (right cognition) and avidya (wrong cognition). Of these, the right cognition is divided into four sub-classes viz. perceptual (pratyaksa), 2 inferential (laingika),3 recollection (smrti) and supernormal spiritual intuition (arsa-jnana). The wrong cognition, on the other hand, is subdivided into fourfold species viz. doubt (samsaya), perverted cognition (viparyaya or avidya), indecision (anadhyavasaya) and dream-cognition (svapna). We shall not discuss the conceptions of all these topics, our main interest being limited to the conception of wrong cognition (avidya). The Vaisesikasutra says that avidya is due to the defects of sense-organs and the perverted influence of the memoryimpressions.? Prasastapada refers to avidya by the term viparyaya which he recognizes to be of two kinds viz. perceptual and inferential. He defines viparyaya as cognition of the form 'It is A' with regard to what is other than A', and enumerates the following as the conditions of such erroneous cognition: (1) blurred vision of two objects possessed of many well-known distinctive features by one whose sense-organs are overpowered by the bodily humours in disorder, (2) conjunction of soul and mind accompanied with the awakened) memory-impression produced in the past) by the past cognition of an object not present at the time), and (3) religious demerit (adharma).10 For instance, the 1. VS, IX, 2. 10-12. We are treating the subject on the basis of Prasastapadabhasya, although we have referred to the original Sutra as far as possible. 2 Cf. VS, VIII. I. 4-11; about yogi-pratyaksa see IX. I. 11-15. For the terms pratyaksa and laingika see X. I. 3. 3 Gf. IX. 2. 1-5; III. I. 7-17. 4 IX. 2. 6. 5 IX. 2. 13. 6 See PB, P. 520 ; see VS, II. 2. 17-20 (samsaya) : IX. 2. 10 (avidya); IX. 2. 7 (svapna). 7 indriyadosat samskaradosac ca 'vidya--VS, IX. 2. 10. 8 viparyayo 'pi pratyaksanumana-visayi eva bhavati--PB, p. 538.' atasmims tad iti pratyayo viparyayah--PB, p. 538. 10 prasiddhaneka-visesayoh pitta-kaphanilopahatendriyasya ayatharthalocanad asannihita-visayajnanaja-samskarapeksad atmamanasoh samyogad adharmac ca-PB, P. 538. Page #148 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. V] AVIDYA IN THE VAISESIKA SCHOOL misperception of a cow for a horse. A cow is possessed of many wellknown distinctive features that can easily differentiate it from a horse. But due to the defects of the sense-organs, one can have a blurred vision wherein a cow is wrongly intuited as a horse. This intuition is further strengthened by the stimulation of a past memory-impression of a horse, and the result is a full-fledged cognition of a horse. Religious demerit also plays its part in the production of error. This is an instance of perceptual error. The wrong inference of fire from vapour mistaken for smoke is given as an instance of inferential error. The miscomprehension of body, sense-organs and mind as the self is also a case of wrong or perverted cognition (viparyaya). In one word, perverted cognition consists in mistaking one thing for another. This conception is identical with the conception of the Nyaya school. We are perhaps beating about the bush. The fact is that the Vaisesikasutra or even Prasastapada does not put forth the basic problem in clear terms, although it is clearly implied in their expositions. We have indulged in this apparently irrelevant digression in order to make the background of the Vaisesika thought clear and vivid in order to see its implication. We shall now refer to the statement of Prasastapada on worldly life and emancipation (apavarga), which will clearly show the Vaisesika attitude towards the problem of ultimate nescience. But before that we shall refer to the very brief account of the Vaisesikasutra itself about samsara and moksa. The Vaisesikasutra says that one acquires dharma and adharma by one's actions inspired by desire and hatred, and that these dharma and adharma are responsible for the cycle of birth and death.1 Adrsta is responsible for the conjunction of soul, sense-organs, mind, and the sense-objects, and this conjunction is responsible for the experience of pleasure and pain, which is an essential factor of worldly life. When the external activity of the mind is stopped and it is in undisturbed union with the soul, there is absence of pain, and this is called yoga which may mean either the arrestation of mental activity or the self-possession of the spirit. But so long as the last vestiges of adrsta are not destroyed, there cannot be final emancipation. The Vaisesikasutra says 'Absence of conjunction of the soul with the body, and the non-origination of new body on the exhaustion of adrsta is moksa (final emancipation).'4 The Sutra also refers to the transcendental knowledge born of meditation (samadhi). Prasastapada puts this Vaisesika position tinged, of III 1 See VS, VI. 2. 14-15. 2 Cf. atmendriya-mano-'rtha-sannikarsat sukhaduhkhe-V. 2. 15. 3 tadanarambha atmasthe manasi sarirasya duhkhabhavah sa yogah V. 2. 16. 4 tadabhave samyogabhavo 'pradurbhavas ca moksah.-V. 2. 18. 5 See IX. I. 11-15. See also PB, p. 553: asmadvisistanam tu yoginam. Page #149 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ II2 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [ch. course, with Puranic ideas developed in between the time, in the following terms: A soul under the sway of nescience (avidya) and possessed of attachment and hatred gets covetable body, sense-organs, sense-objects, pleasure etc. according to the forces of its past actions (asaya) in the different worlds of the Creator (Brahman), the gods, the Prajapati, the manes (pitys) and human beings, due to abundant creative religious merit? in conjunction with a little of demerit. On the other hand, due to abundant religious demerit in conjunction with a little of merit, it gets an uncovetable body, sense-organs, sense-objects, pain etc. in the worlds of devils (pretas) and brutes. Thus due to creative merit in conjunction with demerit, the worldly life continues unceasingly with repeated births among gods, men, animals and denizens of hell. But due to emancipative? merit acquired with full comprehension (of truth) and without any desire for result, one is born in a pure family, with ardent desire to know the means of ending (all) pain. He approaches a master and is enlightened with the knowledge of the true nature of the six categories. Thus his nescience is eliminated, and he becomes free from attachment. Now because of the absence of attachment and aversion, new dharma and adharma, owing their existence to them, do no more accrue, while the stored ones are exhausted by 'enjoyment'. After this, on the cessation of attachment and the like, the pure emancipatory dharma, causing happiness of contentment and non-attachment to the body, itself ceases by producing joy born of the intuition of the supreme reality viz. the soul.* Then due to the cessation of all merit and demerit, the body and the organs of the self with all the seeds of worldly life parched and exhausted fall apart. And there being no more origination of new body and the like, there is final emancipation much like the final extinc tion of fire which has consumed all its fuel.'5 The soul is now bereft of all its specific qualities which derived their genesis from the conjunction of the soul with the mind, which is the starting point of worldly career. Emancipation is absolute and eternal quiescence. 1 pravartakad dharmat has been translated as 'due to creative dharma'. 2 nivartaka. 3 nivsttilaksanah kevalo dharmah. 4 paramartha-darsanajam sukham kstva nivartate. Vyomavati explains this as paramarthah sarvapadarthanam atma, taddarsanajatam paramarthadarsanajam. The Nyayakandali says paramarthadarsanajam atmadarsanajam. 5 PB, pp. 643-44: aviduso ragadvesavatah... moksa iti. Page #150 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. VI] AVIDYA IN THE VEDANTA SCHOOL II3 VI AVIDYA IN THE VEDANTA SCHOOL In this section, our enquiry will be confined to the Upanisads and the works of Gaudapada and Sankara. The seeds of the Vedanta conception of avidya and maya can be traced in the Upanisads, and as such we shall refer to those passages of the Upanisads where the traces of the conception are apparent. Gaudapada, in his Agamasastra, developed the conception, and finally Sankara unfolded its implications and made a consistent theory of it. We shall not refer to the postSankara developments in view of the limited scope of our enquiry. We shall deal only with the most salient features of the problem and avoid the subtle dialectics on which Sankara based his theory. Our treatment thus will in no sense be full or complete, not to speak of its perfection. Let us begin with the Upanisads. The ultimate reality, according to the Upanisads, is devoid of all plurality, and it is only perverted outlook that is responsible for our perception of plurality. The Upanisads denounce plurality in the strongest possible terms. The Brhadaranyaka says 'By the mind alone is it to be comprehended. There is in it no plurality. He who sees any semblance of plurality in it goes from death to death.' Plurality is only apparent. One goes from death to death, that is, one is subject to birth and death, so long as one does not cease seeing plurality. The cycle of birth and death ceases only when oneness is realized. The Isa Upanisad says: 'But one who sees all things in the self and the self in all things is not repulsed by it because of the realization of truth. When to him, who knows, the self has become all things, how can any more there be delusion and sorrow for him who sees oneness?'2 Delusion and sorrow, in one word, the worldly life, can appear only if there is perception of plurality. Worldly life ceases when oneness is realized. But what is responsible for this perception of plurality? What is this perversity of vision due to? The world is a fact and a beginningless fact at that. But what does its nature consist in? Why do we see plurality and not the oneness? Why do we see the world and not the basis that sustains it? The Upanisads are fully conscious of the problems, and also the difficulty of formal enunciation of their answers, and it is I manasai 'va 'nudrastavyar ne 'ha nana 'sti kincana motyoh sa motyum apnoti ya iha nane 'va pasyati. ---ByUp, IV. 4. 19. Also cf. Kaup, II. 4. 10-11. 2 yas tu sarvani bhutany atmany eva 'nupasyati sarvabhutenu ca "tmanam tato na vijugupsate. yasmin sarvani bhutany atmai 'va 'bhud vijanatah tatra ko mohah kah soka ekatvam anupasyatah. --IUP, 6-7. JP-15 Page #151 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. because of this that sometimes they speak in parables. Speaking of the reason why one sees the world and not the self the Katha Upanisad says: 'Svayambhu (the self-subsistent principle who has all the conditions of self-existence in himself) cut open the out-seeing organs and so one sees outward (paran) and not the self inside (antaratman). A wise man, however, desirous of immortality sees the inside self with his eye turned away from the external world. The stupid, however, follow the external desires. They enter the outspread trap of death. The wise, however, seeing immortality, the eternal among the noneternal, do not desire (for any thing) in this world." Perception of the external and attachment to the world are the legacy handed down by Svayambhu and none is responsible for that. But the legacy is not a perpetuity. Nor is it an ultimate truth. One is only to turn away and turn back to get rid of that legacy. This is the teaching of the Upanisads. The face of truth is covered by a golden vessel." We live in truth and yet are ignorant of it. We tread upon truth and yet do not recognize it. The Chandogya says: 'Even as those who are ignorant of the secret contents of the earth do not have access to the hidden store of gold even though they tread upon the surface of it, exactly so all these common people carried away by untruth (anrtena pratyudhah), even though they daily go there, do not have access to the Brahmaloka (region of the Brahman or truth).'" Truth is very near us. We ourselves are truth. One does not know it because one does not care to lift the veil covering it. 'The stupid, falsely considernig themselves wise and learned, reside within the fold of avidya, and meet misfortunes running to and fro.'4 Avidya is a knot to be cut asunder, and it is not beyond our power to do so. oneness of the world with the self dispels all darkness. come from Purusa, the Absolute, and so is identical with It. It has no existence of its own, and as such cannot persist for one who has realized the Absolute, or rather become the Absolute. The Mundaka Upanisad says: 'The Purusa is all this-karman (sacrifice), tapas (austerity) and Brahman, the highest immortal. He who knows this as hidden in the cave cuts asunder, O darling, the knot of avidya even (while living) here (in this world).'5 Realization of The world has 114 paranci khani vyatrnat svayambhus tasmat paran pasyati nantaratman. kascid dhirah pratyagatmanam aiksad avrtta-caksur amrtatvam icchan. paracah kaman anuyanti balas te mrtyor yanti vitatasya pasam atha dhira amrtatvam viditva dhruvam adhruvesv iha na prarthayante. -KUP, II. 4. J-2. 2 hiranmayena patrena satyasya 'pihitam mukham.-IUP, 15. 3 ChUp, VIII. 3. 2. 4 KUP, I. 2. 5. 5 MuUp, II. I. TO. Page #152 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. VI] AVIDYA IN THE VEDANTA SCHOOL 115 Now let us see the Upanisa dic conception of maya. In the Rgveda, wherever the word maya occurs it is used only to signify the might or the power. Indra takes many shapes quickly by his maya. Yet sometimes maya and its derivatives mayin and mayavat are employed to signify the will of the demons, and we also find the word used in the sense of illusion or show. The Svetasvatara Upanisad conceives maya as the power of the Almighty God. "The Mayin (God) creates all this--the sacred verses, the offerings, the sacrifices, the penances, the past, the future, and all that the Vedas declare_from this (aksara or the immutable one); and the other (i.e. the individual jiva) is bound up with that (aksara) through maya. Know that prakrti is maya and Mahesvara (the Great Lord) is the Mayin. The whole world is filled with what are His members.'? This God spreads His trap and lords it over the world by means of His divine powers. The world is one Great Maya. This Cosmic Maya (visva-maya) can be ended by meditating upon, joining, and finally becoming one with that Great God. This is what we get about the conception of maya in the Upanisads. To sum up: Avidya is perversity of vision and attachment to the world. Maya is the cosmic force that brings forth the world of plurality. If the maya conditions the universe, avidya keeps one attached to it. There is maya because there is avidya. With the cessation of avidya, maya seases. The existence of a magician and his art depends upon the existence of their dupes. If there is no dupe there is no art of magic, Let us now see the vicissitudes of this conception in later times. We now come to Gaudapada. The Upanisadic conception of reality as beyond reach of mind and intellect had much influence on later Buddhist thought. Nagarjuna developed the seeds of the Upanisadic thoughts into full-fledged dialectic, and criticized every metaphysical concept as untenable and self-contradictory. This dialectic had great influence on the philosophy of Gaudapada who utilized the art with much ability. He accepts the logic of Nagarjuna and applies it to the world and the Upanisadic texts alike and thus he gives us for the first time the philosophy of the Upanisads in the proper sense of the term. He rejected the phenomenal world as illogical and self-contradictory. The doctrine of causality, in all its forms, is found to be untenable and absurd. We shall not discuss all these problems here, our enquiry being limited to the particular problem of avidya 2 SUP, IV. 9-10. 1 IP, Vol. I, pp. 103-4. 3 Cf. ya eko jalavan isata isanibhih sarvan lokan isata isanibhih.-Ibid., III. I. * Ibid., I. 10. 5 See AS, IV from karika 3. Also cf. V. 3. Page #153 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. and maya. The Brhadaranyaka held that there is neither subject nor object in the state of final realization, and that one can know another, that is, there can be subject-object consciousness only when there is appearance of duality, and also that the ultimate knower cannot become an object of knowledge. This suggestion was developed by Gaudapada into a full-fledged Absolutism with the help of Nagarjuna's dialectic. It is not that Absolutism was not already there in the Upanisads. What the Upanisads lacked was a complete critique of the empirical conceptions. Gaudapada supplied that critique, and restated the Upanisadic finding in the logical background. The Brhadaranyaka as well as other Upanisads clearly stated Absolute Non-duality as the ultimate reality and duality as only an appearance but they did not give cogent reasons for their position. Gaudapada, on the other hand, criticizes all conceptions of duality as absurd and illogical. He maintains the doctrine of non-origination of the Absolute. According to Gaudapada the ultimate reality is one, and the plurality is only a false appearance. Whatever is a departure from this monism is accordingly bereft of ultimate validity. Religion is based upon the concept of duality in the shape of the worshipper and the worshipped. And so it has value only in the phenomenal plane. One who thinks that by worship one will realize the ultimate consummation must be declared to be a fool-an object of pity. After all there can be no worshipper and object of worship which presupposes dualism that has been declared to be a false superstition by Gaudapada. In order to refute this superstition Gaudapada maintains that Brahman which is the ultimate reality is neither born nor created. It is the eternal reality unborn and uncreated. The worshipper is nothing different from Brahman in point of reality. But when he thinks that he is born in a certain family and a certain caste, he is entirely deluded, because birth is only an illusion. To demonstrate the absurdity involved in the conception of birth, Gaudapada launches upon an elaborate discourse to prove that nothing can really originate or perish. 116 According to Gaudapada creation is a false appearance and the duties and prohibitions in the Vedic scripture are intended only for the ignorant and superstitious people who believe in the reality of birth and progression in the grades of existence, which the conception of heaven and hell presupposes. The self is like space and the plurality of empirical selves is due to the limitations imposed by maya just like the divisions of space enclosed in jars and the like." It is the limitations 1 Cf. yatra hi dvaitam iva bhavati tad itara itaram pasyati. yatra va asya sarvam atmai jighret, tat kena kim pasyet.... vijnataram are kena vijaniyad iti-BrUp, 11. 4. 14. Also cf. IV. 5. 15. 2 AS, III. I. 3 Cf. AS, III. 3-4. itaram jighrati, tad itara 'va 'bhut tat kena kim Page #154 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. VI] AVIDYA IN THE VEDANTA SCHOOL 117 of the bodily organism and its members which serve to make one eternal self appear as many selves. So when these limitations imposed by the physical organisms are destroyed the seeming plurality of selves is dissolved into the one eternal self, just as the spaces enclosed within the different enclosures are restored to their identity with one eternal space on the cessation of the enclosures. As the space occupied by jar (ghatakasa) is neither a transformation nor a part of the one homogeneous space (akasa) so is always an individual self (jiva) neither a transformation nor a fraction of the eternal self (atman). As the space appears to be soiled with dirt to the ignorant, so appears the self (atman), too, with impurities, to those who are not enlightened.' The self exists unaffected amidst death, birth and other movements even as the space remains unaffected by its connections with various things. All the sanghatas (conglomerations of limbs etc.) are like dream, being projected by the maya of the atman. There is therefore) indeed no ground for greatness or smallness among things.'? Gaudapada refers to the fivefold kosas of the Taittiriya Upanisad and the madhuvidya of the Brhadaranyaka and says that they reveal the supreme Brahman. The Upanisads extol absolute identity of the individual self (jiva) and the Absolute (Brahman) and censure all plurality. This is proper only if the Absolute Brahman is postulated.4 The Upanisadic statements about creation are to be understood in the context of the Absolute Brahman. They are all only a means for an introduction to truth. There is no plurality. The dualists are realists, that is to say, they believe in the reality of the empirical world--the world of our senses and understanding. They think that the world is as it appears and it exists even when it is unperceived. In other words, the objective world has got both empirical and metempirical reality. The non-dualists, on the other hand, do not deny the actuality of appearance and accordingly accord to the world an empirical reality, though they deny ultimate metempirical reality to it on account of contradictions. The non-dualist does not contradict experience, but only reinterprets it, while the dualists quarrel among themselves because 1 na "kasasya ghatakaso vikaravayavau yatha nai va "tmanah sada jivo vikaravayavau tatha. yatha bhavati balanam gaganam malinam malaih tatha bhavaty, abuddhanam atma 'pi malino malaih.-AS, III. 7-8. 2 sanghatah svapnavat sarve atma-maya-visarjitah adhikye sarvasamye va no 'papattir hi vidyate.-AS, III. IO. 3 AS, III. II-I2. 4 Cf. AS, III. 13. 5 Cf. AS, III. 14-15. 6 Cf. svasiddhanta-vyavasthasu dvaitino niscita drdham parasparam virudhyante tair ayam na virudhyate. advaitam paramartho hi dvaitam tadbheda ucyate tesam ubhayatha dvaitam tena 'yam na virudhyate.-AS, III. 17-18. Page #155 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 118 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [cH. of their failure to harmonize experience in the light of their prejudiced outlook of duality. But the problem still remains as to why the non-dual (advaita) appears as dual (dvaita). The non-dual (advaita) is unborn (aja). But why does it appear as born? Why, again, should we not regard duality as real? Gaudapada answers: 'It (i.e. the advaita) becomes different only through maya, as the unborn (non-dual) can in no other way become dual ; for if it becomes in reality dual the immortal would become mortal.' How can the unborn (ajata) be born? The unborn is immortal. How can it become mortal? 'The immortal does not become mortal, nor likewise the mortal immortal. In no way can nature change.'? The Upanisads declare creation from the existent as well as the non-existent, but we are to understand the logical implications of the statements. The Vedas unambiguously declare that there is no plurality, that Indra took many shapes through maya, and also He is variously born, though (in fact) he does not take birth'. It, therefore, follows that the unborn is born through maya." The scripture denies the birth as well as the cause of birth of the unborn (aja). It further declares: "That atman is to be described by means of negation of its opposites. It is not amenable to apprehension, and it is never apprehended like an external object.' The following, again, points to the unborn nature of the atman. The real can appear to be born only through maya (or illusion). The meaning is that the birth of a real is self-contradictory, because to be born means to come into reality. If a real were again to come into reality it would be useless. So there can be no birth of a real. Real is always unborn. If birth were to be real it must appertain to what is born because birth has been found to be incompatible with the unborn reality. But to affirm ihe birth of what is already born is to assert an unmeaning nonsense because the possibility of fresh birth of what is already born will involve the incessant repetition of births--a position which is as nonsensical as the assertion of reality superadded to reality. Origination of the real thus involves self-contradiction, and as such is to be rejected. But even then we cannot dismiss the appearance of origination, and must account for it. Gaudapada holds that the existent appears as born through maya. But then, one may ask, "Why don't you admit that the non-existent appears as born through maya?' In reply to such an 1 mayaya bhidyate hy etan na. 'nyatha 'jam kathancana tattvato bhidyamane hi martyatam arrtam vrajet..AS, III. 19. 2 AS, III. 21. 3 AS, III. 24. 4 AS, IIT. 25 with annotation and footnotes. 5 sa esa ne 'ti ne 'ty atma. 'grhyo na hi gshyate.-ByUp, III. 9. 26. 6 sato hi mayaya janma yujyate na tu tattvatah tattvato jayate yasya jatam tasya hi jayate. -AS, III. 27 Page #156 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. VI] AVIDYA IN THE VEDANTA SCHOOL 119 objection Gaudapada says: 'The birth of the non-existent is not reasonable at all through maya or in reality. The son of a barren woman is not born either through maya or in reality.'1 The same inaya as is responsible for the appearance of duality in dream is responsible for the appearance of duality in the waking state. As the mind is indeed advaya (without a second) in dream, exactly so is the mind advaya (without a second) even in the waking state. The dvaita (duality) in whatever form, comprising the movable and the unmovable, is perceived by the mind (manas). But when the mind becomes nonmind (i.e. ceases to exist and function as a mind), duality ceases to be experienced." When the self is realized as the sole reality, the mind ceases to be because then there is nothing external which it can conceive. The mind's occupation is gone with the cessation of what can be apprehended. The meaning seems to be this: "The mind conjures up various things which it seems to apprehend so long as it fails to realize the ultimate truth which is One Absolute. But when the self is realized to be identical with the Absolute, the multiplicity of phenomena with which the mind occupies itself disappears like the objects of dream. The mind also as distinct from the self disappears like fire without fuel.' In other words, everything that appears as other than the self is false and unreal and is bound to vanish. This is also the case with the mind itself qua other than the self.4 Gaudapada describes the Absolute in the following terms: "The ultimate reality is the Absolute which has to be realized. It is unborn and eternal. Time has no relation to it. It is the ultimate knowable and this knowledge is bound to dissolve the whole fabric of illusion built by maya. But the knowledge of the Absolute is equally eternally existent and without birth and death. It is not bipolar like our empirical cognitions. It is pure consciousness without subject-object determination (akalpakam). It is identical with the Absolute--its object. So the realization of the Absolute is effected by eternal unborn consciousness and thus the unborn is said to be known by the unborn.'s Reality is one, unborn 1 asa to mayaya janma tattvato nai 'va yujyate vandhya-putro na tattvena mayaya va 'pi jayate. -AS, III. 28. 2 AS, III. 29-30. It should, however, be noticed in this connection that Gauda pada recognizes distinction between the objects of the waking experience and those of dreams (vide AS, II. 13-15). While the objects of waking experience are common to us all, those of the dreams belong exclusively to the dreamer. 3 manodrsyam idam dvaitam yat kincit sacaracaram manaso hy amanibhave dvaitam nai 'vo 'palabhyate. -AS, III. 31. 4 AS, III. 32. 5 Cf. akalpakam ajam jnanam jneyabhinnam pracaksate brahma jneyam ajar nityam ajena 'jam vibudhyate.-AS, III. 33. Page #157 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ I20 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. and eternal. This state of non-mind is to be distinguished from the state of deep sleep wherein the mind simply falls into a state of oblivion. The state of non-mind is not a lapse of the waking state. It is the condition of the mind subdued and freed from all imaginative constructions in which there is clear distinction of the self and the not-self. It is entirely different from the condition of dreamless sleep in which the mind lapses into perfect inaction. But in the state of realization the mind does not lapse into a supine state but, on the contrary, it becomes thoroughly illuminated with the light of the Absolute and is free from all taint of fear. The mind merges in the Absolute with its separate identity dissolved. From what we have stated above we can easily understand Gaudapada's conception of maya. Gaudapada introduces maya in order to explain appearance. There can be no mutation of the immutable Brahman. Plurality cannot come out of the Absolute. Phenomena cannot in any way be related to the Eternal. What is the explanation then of the world of experience? What causality stands for? How should we explain the ordered universe? It is in order to bring home the anti-rational character of the phenomenal world that Gaudapada introduced the conception of maya. He based his enquiry on the experiences of the Vedic seers (rsis). He utilized the dialectic developed by the Buddhist thinkers in order to satisfy the sceptic intellect. He does not accept the findings of the Yogacaras or the Madhyamikas, but only utilizes their critique. This is in short Gaudapada's conception of the objective world and its prius maya---the principle of irrationality and negativity. Now the problem is 'Why does one have this notion of duality? Why does there occur this relation of subject and object?' Gaudapada says that it is the irrational predilection (abhinivesa) for the phenomenal appearance of duality, in spite of the fact that it does not exist, that is responsible for this notion. When this predilection goes away the notion of duality along with its associates disappears. Gaudapada says: "Owing to this false predilection for the unreal the mind occupies itself with the equally unreal phenomena. But as soon as the unreality of the phenomenal world is realized the self with its mind retires to itself alone and unattached to anything external.' This predilection for the unreal can be taken as the nescience (avidya) of Gaudapada. If the world appears through maya, one sticks to the world due to this predilection (abhinivesa). The maya and abhinivesa of Gaudapada stand in the same relation as the maya and avidya of the Upanisads. If avidya or nescience be interpreted as the root 1 AS, III. 34-35. 2 Cf. AS, IV. 75: abhutabhiniveso 'sti dvayam tatra na vidyate. 3 AS, IV. 79; also cf. IV. 55-56. Page #158 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. VI] AVIDYA IN THE VEDANTA SCHOOL 121 principle of subjectivity and to work out its programme through a false belief in and attachment to the not-self and the subjective and the objective world constructed by it, then it can be equated with Gaudapada's concept of abhutabhinivesa--the bias and predilection of the subject for the unreal plurality. After all it should be thought as subjective when personal as opposed to maya which may be regarded as the substitute of the Sankhya conception of prakyti. In other words, maya is the principle of cosmic illusion and avidya is rather its product responsible for the creation of different subjects. Let us now turn to Sankara. That the world of plurality and subject-object consciousness is there is a fact too obvious and too apparent to explain away. Scepticism leads to subjectivism, subjectivism to solipsism, and solipsism leads nowhere. Gaudapada showed that it is only the existent that can appear. The non-existent cannot appear. Sankara examines experience and distinguishes the real from the apparent. Our experience contains truth as well as untruth, reality as well as appearance. The world is an illusion in the sense that it is a compound of truth and untruth. The unreal is superimposed upon the real. This superimposition or adhyasa, as it is called, is the prius of experience. Sankara's famous Bhasya on the Brahmasutra opens with a subtle analysis of our common experience. There he says: 'Object (visaya) and subject (visayin), having as their province the presentation of the 'thou' (yusmat) and the l' (asmat), are of a nature as opposed as darkness and light. The transfer of the object, which has as its province the 'thou' (or the not-self), and its qualities to the pure spiritual subject, which has for its province the idea of the 'T' (or the self), and, conversely, the transfer of the subject and its qualities to the object, is logically false. Yet in mankind this procedure, resting on false knowledge (mithyajnana-nimitta), of pairing together the true and the untrue (the subject and the object) is natural (naisargika), so that they transfer the being and qualities of the one to the other.'1 Our practical life depends upon this mutual transference or superimposition (adhyasa). Our common experience is based on this adhyasa. In ordinary cases of error also something is superimposed upon another, and in this respect there is no difference between the empirical and the transcendental error. The transcendental error can, in brief, be defined as the mutual identification of the not-self and the self. This transcendental error is called avidya.2 On the nature and the function of this transcendental error (adhyasa) Sarikara says: Adhyasa we have described as cognition of that in not-that. For 1 SRh, Introduction to BS. This translation has been copied from IP, Vol. II, p. 506. tam etam evamlaksanam adhyasam pandita avidye 'ti manyante-Ibid. JP-16 Page #159 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 122 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. instance, one imposes the external attributes upon the atman (self) when one says 'I am crippled (vikala) or whole (sakala)' when it is only his son or wife that is so; or sometimes the attributes of the body as in I am fat, 'I am thin', and so on ; or sometimes the attributes of the sense-organs as in 'I am dumb', 'I am one-eyed', and so on ; or sometimes the attributes of the mind (antahkarana) such as desire, intention, doubt and the like. Thus one superimposes the ego upon the self which is only the transcendental witness of the mind and its activities, and then again reversely superimposes the self, the witness of all, upon the ego. Thus there is this beginningless, endless, natural (naisargika) adhyasa (superimposition) of the nature of wrong cognition (mithyapratyayarupah), the cause of agency and enjoyment (of the individual souls) and patent to all.' This beginningless adhyasa or avidya, consisting in the mutual identification of the self and the not-self, is the presupposition of all ordinary or scriptural distinctions between means and ends, subjects and objects, in one word, between one thing and another. Even our philosophical and spiritual enquiries presuppose this avidya.? It is indeed a palpable absurdity to imagine that the not-self is superimposed upon the self and vice versa. But nevertheless it is a fact that our ordinary experience presupposes this identification. Otherwise we cannot explain such experiences as I am fat', 'I am dumb' and the like. The object is superimposed upon the conscious subject, and the conscious subject is seemingly superimposed upon the object. The not-self is identified with the self and so is known and expressed, though the not-self has not the capacity to reveal or express itself. But this identification is not one-sided. Were it so, there would be a complete merger of one in the other. In other words, either it will be the object and the not-self, or the subject and the self. But however intimately the self and the not-self are connected, the self does not become the not-self, and conversely the not-self does not become the self. The two poles exist side by side and because they are related, they must be accepted to become identical or not-different. The not-self is a non-entity. Yet it appears to be an entity because it is felt as identical with the self. And in this act of identification, the self also has to contribute a part. And this contribution consists in the seeming transference of being and manifestation to the not-self 1 adhyasonama atasmims tadbuddhi ity avocama ... evam ahampratyayinam asesa-svapracara-saksini pratyagatmani adhyasya tam ca pratyagatmanam sarva-saksinam tadviparyayena antahkaranadisv adhyavasyati, evam ayam anadir ananto naisargiko 'dhyaso mithyapratyayarupah kartstvabhoktrtva-pravartakah sarvaloka-pratyaksah-Ibid. 2 Cf. tam etam avidyakhyam atmanatmanor itaretaradhyasam puraskrtya Sarve pramana-prameya vyavahara laukika vaidikas ca pravsttah sarvani ca sastrani vidhi-pratisedha-moksaparani-Ibid. Page #160 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 111. vi] AVIDYA IN THE VEDANTA SCHOOL 123 identified with it. It should be borne in mind that though there is mutual identification of the self and the not-self, which is deducible from the fact that the self appropriates the attributes and limitations of the not-self (as is evident in the judgment 'I am fat' and the like) and the not-self appears as existent which means that the not-self, though a non-entity, derives the attribute of appearance and existence from the self, yet the identification or superimposition has not the same ontological status and meaning. The not-self is per se (svarupena) superimposed upon the self and all existence it appears to have is derived from the self with which it is identified. It has no being outside the self and as such cannot even appear independently. But the identification of the self does not mean the total identification of being, because the self is intrinsically real, and its identification with the not-self only means that the self owns up the not-self and vests it with its own existence. In other words, it only means that the self becomes related (samsysta) to the not-self. And as relation is not intelligible in terms of difference it is interpreted as identification. There can be no relation between things which are different and also if the two are absolutely identical. If the terms were to be identical, they would forfeit their duality, and if they were as different as two unrelated things are from one another, then also there would be no relation. A relation, therefore, cannot be defined as a case of total identity or total difference. It is said to be a case of nondifference or identity because it is not a case of difference. So though identification is bilateral, the not-self is always a content and a predicate which being unreal cannot even appear outside the context. Appearance means seeming existence. And the term can seem to exist when the existence is borrowed. The identification of the self with the not-self is necessary to account for the appearance of existence of the content superimposed upon it. How can the attribute of one appear to be the attribute of another unless there be a relation which means identification as opposed to difference? In all cases of error the substratum is real and the predicate is falsely superimposed upon it. We have seen how superimposition presupposes mutual identification. But the identification of the substratum with the content is not the same thing as identification of the content with the substratum. And it is this distinction which accounts for the reality and truth of the substratum and the unreality and falsity of the content. Even our most abstract thought is not free from this identification (adhyasa). Adhyasa is the very texture of our experience. Sankara drives home this truth very convincingly and with various arguments drawn from natural life. Life presupposes action and action depends upon identification. One cannot act with his body unless one's self is superimposed upon it. The self, which is only reality ex hypothesi, can have no raison d'etre for performing an action, which presupposes Page #161 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ [CH. several distinct factors the agent, the act and the object and also the purpose and so on. But this plurality is itself an appearance and hence a case of superimposition. Unless the self feels that it is the body it cannot act. Action is possible only for the body, and the self can appear to act or believe itself to be the agent only if it identifies itself with the body. The maxim is that the attribute of one can belong to the other only if there is identity between the two-identity being understood as a relation which is different from difference. Our actions are for the fulfilment of our own purpose. If we could find that we are acting simply for the interests of those that have nothing in common with ourselves, we would forthwith stop functioning. If one realized that one had nothing in common with one's body or the sense-organs, one would at once stop all activities for their preservation. The function of knowing also depends upon the adhyasa. Sankara says: 'One free from the notions of 'I' and 'mine' with reference to the body, sense-organs etc. is incapable of being a subject of knowledge (pramata) and thus the activity of knowing is impossible for him. The activity of perception and the like is not possible without the owning up of the sense-organs. Nor are the sense-organs capable of acting without the substratum (viz. the body). Nor can one take to activity without superimposing one's self upon the body. Nor in the absence of all this can an absolutely unrelated self become the subject of knowledge. And without the subject there can be no activity of knowledge. It, therefore, follows, that all such activities as perceptual knowledge and spiritual enquiries are possible only with reference to one possessed of avidya." This transcendental adhyasa is common to both the animal and the human world, and lasts until the Self (Atman) is realized and all subject-object relationship disappears. It is this avidya that is the seed of worldly life. This is Sankara's conception of avidya. Now let us turn to his conception of maya. We have briefly referred to Sankara's critique of the nature of our experience. It was found on analysis that mutual identification of the self and the not-self is the foundation of experience. But now the problem is: Why does this duality of self and not-self appear at all? Is there any separate entity called not-self? The answer of the Vedanta to such a question is well known. Duality is false. There is only One Self without a second. What is then this not-self? Why does it appear? In other words, why is there this world of phenomena? The analysis of experience shows that we refer everything to one constant and abiding Self although mostly we do so unknowingly. We unknowingly identify the Self with the world and the world with 124 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA 1 dehendriyadisv aham-mama-'bhimana-rahitasya .. tasmad avidyavadvisayany eva pratyaksadini pramanani sastrani ca-Ibid. Page #162 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. Vi] AVIDYA IN THE VEDANTA SCHOOL 125 the Self, and this mutual identification is responsible for all our activities. But why is there this process of identification? Before answering this question let us see what is the implication and condition of this process of identification. Suppose the process ceases. What happens? Subject-object consciousness ceases. But why should the process cease at all? It could cease if there were any condition of it, and also if that condition could be removed. We, however, cannot conceive any condition of the beginningless process. Much less can we hope to discover it. It is incomprehensible. But yet we can gauge its nature by other means. There is a strong urge in us for freedom from the world process. The scriptures inform us of the reality of that freedom. Presuming the possibility of freedom, let us imagine what happens of the process when one is free. Suppose one is free, there is now no more process of identification for him. But does this state of freedom imply that the process of identification has ceased because there is now no tendency for it, or does it imply that there is no second to be superimposed upon? In the first alternative the possibility of the repetition of the process would still remain, and moreover freedom would become a farce. Freedom in this alternative means freedom from tendency. But what is this tendency? Why was it there? These ultimate questions remain unanswered. In the second alternative, however, there is no reason for such difficulties. Presuming the possibility of the second alternative, we can equate freedom to Absolute Existence without a second. Now if this is the ultimate state, what is the nature of the not-self and the beginningless process of identification? It was all indeed an illusory appearance. But the problem still remains What does this illusory appearance consist in?' It consists in maya. Sankara says: 'It is maya, pure and simple, that the Great Self (Atman) appears as the threefold states (viz. waking, dreaming and dreamless sleep) even as a rope appears as a snake and the like', and quotes the following from Gaudapada's Agamasastra : 'When the individual self (jiva), sleeping on account of maya which has no beginning, is awakened, it realizes the state (of turya--the transcendental state of the self called the fourth state in contradistinction to the above three) which is unborn and in which there is neither sleep nor dream, nor duality. Nama (name) and rupa (form)--the elements of the world process belong to the Lord and are known as His maya. Sankara says: "Belonging to the nature, as it were, of the 1 mayamatram hy etad yat paramatmano 'vasthatrayatmana 'vabhasanam rajiva iva sarpadibhavene "ti. atroktam Vedantartha-sampradayavidbhir Acaryaih: anadimayaya supto yada jivah prabudhyate ajam anidram asvapnam advaitam budhyate tada. --SBH, BS, JI. I. 9. See also AS, I. 16. Page #163 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ [CH. Omniscient Lord, there are nama (name) and rupa (form), the figments of avidya, indefinable either as identical with or as different from the Lord, the germs of the world process, and known in the scripture (Sruti) and the traditional literature (Smrti) as maya, sakti (energy) and prakrti (the primordial nature) of the Omniscient Lord."1 Maya thus is the cosmic force belonging to the Lord. It is nama and rupa. It is the appearance of the great Atman. Or, we can say, maya is the appearance of Reality. This is Sankara's conception of maya. Now let us end this section with a remark or two on the relation of avidya and maya. Sankara does never attempt to draw a line of distinction between avidya and maya. But it seems that he postulates maya mainly for explaining the origination of the world appearance and avidya for explaining the attachment of the individual to that appearance. If this is the case, then we can say that maya and avidya are complements each of the other. Let us now turn to the Buddhist conception of avidya. 126 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA VII AVIDYA IN THE BUDDHIST SCHOOL 'Just as in a peaked house (kutagara), O Brethren, whatever rafters there are, all converge to the roof-peak, resort equally to the roofpeak, all go to junction there, even so, whatever wrong states there are, all have their root in ignorance, all may be referred to ignorance, all are fixed together in ignorance, all go to junction there."" 'Whatever misfortunes there are here in this world, or in the next, they all have their root in ignorance (avijjamulaka), and are given rise to by longing and desire." The Buddhist chain of pratityasamutpada (dependent origination) begins with avidya (ignorance) which is considered as the root of the world process. From avidya (ignorance) originate samskaras (predispositions), from samskaras originates vijnana (seed-consciousness), from vijnana originates nama-rupa (mind and body), and similarly sadayatana (the six sense-organs), sparsa (contact), vedana (feeling), trsna (craving), upadana (clinging), bhava (coming to be), jati (birth) and jaramarana (old age and death) originate. This process of origination is beginningless, and avidya (ignorance) and trsna (craving) are the parents of this process. Trsna (craving) is the mother and 1 sarvajnasye 'svarasya 'tmabhuta iva 'vidyakalpite namarupe tattvanyatvabhyam anirvacaniye samsara-prapanca-bijabhute sarvajnasye 'svarasya maya saktih prakrtir iti ca srutismrtyor abhilapyete--SBh, BS, II. I. 14. 2 SNi, XX. J. Translation by Mrs. Rhys Davids. 3 Itivuttaka ($40), p. 34. The Basic Conception of Buddhism, p. 57. 4 We have referred to this chain in Chap. I, p. 10. Page #164 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. VII] AVIDYA IN THE BUDDHIST SCHOOL 127 avidya (ignorance) is the father.' Maitreyanatha gives a very impressive idea of the functions of the twelve factors of avidya, sarskara etc. when he says: "The world is afflicted due to the obscuration of the intuition of truth by avidya), implantation (of the vasana or will to live due to the sarskaras), transference of the vasana-seed to the place of birth by vijnana), the consequent formation (of the nama-rupa or body and mind), development (of the sadayatana), the threefold feeling (due to the mutual contact (sparsa) of the senses, the object and the consciousness), enjoyment or suffering (due to vedana), acquisition (of rebirth due to tysna), tying down (of the vijnana to desires by the upadanas), turning towards (fruition of the past action due to bhava), and sorrow (caused by jati and jaramarana).'? Avidya covers the capacity of intuiting the truth. It is of the nature of adarsana (nonintuition)." Avidya is the cause of perversion (of truth).5 One under the sway of avidya mistakes the impermanent for the permanent because of one's delusion about truth.6 Samskaras (predispositions) can lead to rebirth only if there is avidya. Otherwise they are unproductive. Samskaras implant the seed of rebirth in the vijnana which then takes the seed to the place of rebirth. The mind and body (nama-rupa) form themselves. And so the process of origination goes on. The avidya is also called delusion (moha).' Nagarjuna says: 'It is due to thinking the things which have no independent nature as eternal, possessed of self, and pleasant (nitya-'tma-sukha-sanjna) that this ocean of existence (bhava) appears to one who is enveloped by the darkness of attachment and delusion (moha).'8 In another place he says: The aggregates do not arise from desire, nor from time, nor from nature (prakrti), nor from themselves (svabhavat) nor from Lord (isvara), nor yet are they without cause ; know that they arise from ignorance (avidya) and desire (tysna).'9 Avidya ceases when the knowledge of the reality (dhamma) dawns. 'Even as a man i Cf. tatra Mahamate mata katama sattvanam yad uta trsna paunarbhaviki nandiraga-sahagata matstvenotisthate avidya pitrtvena yatanagramasyo 'tpattaye, etc.--LA, P. 138. 2 chadanad ropanac cai 'va nayanat samparigrahat puranat (triparicchedad) upabhogac ca (sangrahat) nibandhanad abhimukhyad duhkhato klisyate jagat.-MVS, I. 11-12a-b. 3 avidyaya yathabhuta-darsana-vibandhanad iti-MVSBh, p. 29. 4 avidyaya hy adarsanatmakatvad-MVSBT, p. 29. 5 viparyasahetur avidya-MVSBh, p. 35. 6 avidyagato hi tattvasammohad anityadin nityadirupena viparyasyati ---MVSBT, p. 35. Cf. tattve 'pratipattir mithyapratipattir ajnanam avidya. Salistambasutra quoted in SS, p. 222 ; BAP, p. 352 ; MKV, p. 564. 7 Visuddhimagga, XVII. 293 8 Mahayanavimsika, verse 21. 9 Stanza 50 from Nagarjuna's Suhrllekha as translated by Wenzel (PTS, 1886) from the Tibetan translation. Dr. Dasgupta's A History of Indian Philosophy, Vol. I, pp. 144-5. Page #165 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 128 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. born blind, and unfamiliar (with the right path), sometimes treads upon the right path and sometimes upon the wrong, so does the fool, ignorant of the world (samsara), sometimes commit punna (good act) and sometimes apunna (bad act) in the world. But when he knows the reality (dhamma) and attains the truth his ignorance ceases, and he roams unperturbed.' With the cessation of avidya, trsna (craving) naturally ceases. If the truth is known desire for the illusory cannot exist. One seeks for permanence so long as the truth of impermanence does not dawn upon him. Ego-centric activity ceases when the falsity of the notion of a static self is comprehended. Desire for happiness disappears when the truth of universal suffering is realized. Avidya consists in mistaking suffering for happiness, an ever-changing aggregate of vedana (feeling), vijnana (consciousness), samjna (coefficients of consciousness) and sarskaras (predispositions) for an abiding ego, perpetual fiow for unchanging staticity. But if this perverted outlook ceases, tysna (craving) naturally disappears. This is the general outlook of Buddhism towards avidya. But along with the development of thought, it was but natural that the meaning of avidya should change. Avidya means ignorance or wrong cognition of truth, and hence its meaning would naturally change along with the change in the conception of the nature of truth. It, therefore, follows that the meaning of avidya cannot remain constant. Let us now see the nature of avidya in later Buddhist thought. We shall begin with the Vijnanavadins. The Buddhists distinguish between the samurti satya (empirical truth) and the paramartha satya (transcendental truth). The function of samurti is to cover the knowledge of the truth. Samurti covers the real nature of truth and reveals it only as covered by itself, and is also called avidya (ignorance), moha (delusion), and viparyasa (perversion). The Buddhists further distinguish three characteristics (laksana) or natures (svabhava) of a thing viz. (I) parikalpita (imagined), (2) paratantra (dependent), and (3) parinispanna (real or true), sometimes briefly called kalpita, tantra and nispanna respectively.* Vasubandhu gives 1 Visuddhimagga, XVII. 119. 2 Cf. dve satye samupasritya buddhanam dharmadesana. lokasamvrti-satyam ca satyam ca paramarthatah.-MK, XXIV. 8. duve saccani akkhasi sambuddho vadatam varo sammutim paramattham ca tatiyam nupalabbhati. Quoted by Buddhaghosa in Asthakatha on KV, p. 30. For further references see AS, p. 162, footnote 5. 3 Cf. samvriyata avriyate yathabhutaparijnanam svabhavavaranad avitaprakasanac ca 'naye 'ti samvrtih avidya moho viparyasa iti paryayah-BAP, pp. 352 ff. 4 Cf. buddhya vivecyarnanam hi na tantram na 'pi kalpitam nispanno na 'sti vai bhavah katham buddhya prakalpyate. -LA, X. 374. kalpitah paratantras ca parinispanna eva ca-MVS, I. 68-b. Page #166 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ JII. VII] an apt illustration of these three. Suppose one creates an elephant by dint of one's spell. Now the elephant appears, but that is only a phantom of the elephant, and in no way the elephant itself. Here the elephant is parikalpita (imaginary), the form of the elephant is paratantra (dependent), and the absence of the elephant is parinispanna (real). An object, according to the Madhyamikas and the Yogacaras, is sunya i.e. devoid of any intrinsic reality, yet we know it as a particular object. This appearance of it as a particular object is an imagined one (parikalpita). Vasubandhu says: 'Whatever thing is imagined by whatever imagination, all that is only parikalpita. That is not the true nature (svabhava) of the real." An imaginary (parikalpita) object, although, in essence, it is non-existent, yet exists for practical purpose, and as such is said to have a characteristic (svabhava) by way of concession to the practice of the common people who are ignorant of the truth. A dependent (paratantra) characteristic is so called because it originates depending upon its cause and conditions.4 The parinispanna (real) characteristic consists in the true nature of a thing, completely free from all imagined characteristics, and is comprehended by avikalpa-jnana (non-constructive intuition).5 Let us now come to the Vijnanavadin's conception of avidya. The Vijnanavadins denounce the duality of perceiver and perceived as false. The Lankavatara says: 'All this is only consciousness (citta). The consciousness functions in two ways as perceived and perceiver. There is neither the subject nor what belongs to the subject." In another place, it says: "There is consciousness alone, there is no external object (drsya). The consciousness itself is seen twofold as perceived and perceiver, and is bereft of eternality and annihilation." The creation of the external world is due to the influence of vasana 1 mayakrtam mantravasat khyati hastyatmana yatha akaramatram tatra 'sti hasti na 'sti tu sarvatha. svabhavah kalpito hasti paratantras tadakrtih AVIDYA IN THE BUDDHIST SCHOOL 2 yas tatra hastyabhavo 'sau parinispanna isyate.-TSN, 27, 28. yena yena vikalpena yad yad vastu vikalpyate parikalpita eva 'sau svabhavo na sa vidyate.-Tk, 39. Also cf. LA, pp. 163-4: na Mahamate yatha balaprthag-janair bhavasvabhavo vikalpyate tatha bhavati. parikalpita eva 'sau Mahamate na bhavasvabhava-laksanavadharanam. 3 Cf. parikalpita ity ucyate. sa punar dravyato 'sann api vyavaharato 'sti 'ti svabhava ucyate-MVSBhT, p. 19. 4 Cf. paratantrah paravaso hetupratyaya-pratibaddha-janmakatvat-Ibid. 5 kalpitena svabhavena tasya ya 'tyantasunyata svabhavah parini (spanno 'vikalpa-jnanagocarah). -Quoted in MVSBhT, p. 19. 6 cittamatram idam sarvam dvidha cittam pravartate grahyagrahakabhavena atmatmiyam na vidyate.-LA, III. 121. 7 cittamatram na drsyo 'sti dvidha cittam hi drsyate grahyagrahakabhavena sasvatoccheda varjitam.-LA, III. 65. JP-17 129 Page #167 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ [CH. (predisposition) which is beginningless. The consciousness becomes twofold, or rather appears as twofold due to its vasana. The Lankavatara says: "There is no external object as the fools imagine. The consciousness functions as the appearance of objects, being influenced by vasana."1 The objective world is like an elephant called up by illusion (maya-hastin). It appears to the consciousness perfumed by ignorance (ajnana). The things (dharmas) are unborn. They are non-existent. They are like a city of gods appearing in the clouds, a dream, and a creation of maya. It is the consciousness that functions variously, it is again the consciousness that is emancipated. The consciousness, and none else, is born, and again it is the consciousness that ceases to be." For those who can see through reason, both the perception and the perceived cease.1 The consciousness moves round the objects even as an iron rotates round a magnet, being ever rooted in and nourished by the vasanas.5 But now, the problem is, why should all this illusion appear at all? What is responsible for this glamorous appearance, this unending dream, this gorgeous sky-flower, this dazzling city in the sky? Of course, such a question is obviously absurd in view of the unreality of the world so frankly admitted by the Vijnanavadins. But even then the question could not be avoided. The Buddhist postulation of the threefold characteristics, described above, is an attempt at explanation of the appearance of the gorgeous show. The consciousness ideates and imagines and creates out of itself, and the creations follow definite laws. The creations are imaginary, but nevertheless they abide by certain order and have definite conditions for appearance. They are not haphazard and chaotic. They are pratitya-samutpanna (causally determined). Parikalpana (imagination) lies at the root of creation. But this does not mean that the creation is whimsical. It certainly proceeds in a definite direction and has well-defined causes and conditions. Although the nature of this creation is not definable, yet it is 130 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA 1 bahyo na vidyate hy artho yatha balair vikalpyate vasanair luditam cittam arthabhasam pravartate.-LA, X. 154-155. 2 Cf. maya-hasti yatha citram patrani kanaka yatha tatha drsyam nrnam khyati citte ajnanavasite.-LA, X. 126. 3 Cf. anutpanna hy ami dharma na cai 'vai 'te na santi ca gandharvanagara-svapna-mayanirmana-sadrsah. cittam pravartate citram cittam eva vimucyate cittam hi jayate na 'nyac cittam eva nirudhyate.-LA, X. 144-5. 4 yuktya vipasyamananam grahagrahyam nirudhyate.-LA, X. 154. Maitreyanatha gives the following argument in order to prove the nonexistence of artha and its vijnana: arthasattvatma-vijnapti-pratibhasam prajayate vijnanam na 'sti ca 'sya 'rthas tadabhavat tad apy asat.-MVS, I. 4. 5 Cf. vasanair brmhitam nityam baddhva mulam sthirasrayam bhramate gocare cittam ayaskante yatha 'yasam-LA, X. 14. Page #168 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. VII] AVIDYA IN THE BUDDHIST SCHOOL 131 not independent and groundless. It is paratantra (causally determined) and is the object of empirical perception. There is one common defect, a basic fault, that compels the consciousness to project this universe and keeps it tied to it. The process of projection begins with duality. Now there is appearance of subject and object, perceiver and ved, and all that duality implies. What is that common defect, that basic fault? The Vijnanavadins say that it is abhutaparikalpa, the conjuring up of the imaginary unreal. In answer to Mahamati's question about the nature of the abhutaparikalpa, the Lord said: "Due to the persistent predilection for the imaginary unreal objects, various and multiform, O Mahamati, the imagination, being active, functions. It functions due to a strong predilection and bias for the perception of external multiform objects as also due to a strong inclination for the subject as well as what belongs to the subject, in the case of those who are strongly rooted in the belief in the reality of the perceived and the perceiver, O Mahamati.'? Maitreyanatha says: 'The prius of constructive ideation or unreal imagination (abhutaparikalpa) exists in reality). Duality does not exist there in the prius). The basis of the negation of duality (sunyata), however, exists in reality). The unreal imagination (somehow) exists even in that (negation of duality).' Vasubandhu says that all afflictions (sanklesa) originate from the unreal imagination (abhutaparikalpa).4 Sthiramati explains this abhutaparikalpa as the locus or the instrument of the imagination of unreal duality.' He further says 'Generically, abhutaparikalpa consists in pure consciousness and its concomitant associates (citta-caitasikas) such as feeling and willing that are liable to metempsychosis ; it exists from beginningless time and ends in final emancipation (nirvana). Specifically, it consists in the imagination of the perceived and the perceiver.' The abhutaparikalpa qua the prius of unreal imagina1 Cf. kalpitah pratyayotpanno 'nabhilapyas ca sarvatha paratantra-svabhavo hi suddhalaukikagocarah.--MVSBT, p. 19. 2 artha-vividha-vaicitrya-'bhuta parikalpa-'bhinivesan Mahamate vikalpah pravartamanah pravartate. nrnam grahya-grahaka-'bhinivesa.-'bhinivistanam ca Mahamate.... bahya-vicitrarthopalambha-'bhinivesat... atmatmiya-'bhinivesat--LA, p. 150. 3 abhutaparikalpo 'sti dvayam tatra na vidyate sunyata vidyate tv atra tasyam api sa vidyate.-MVS, I. 2. We have translated the term abhutaparikalpa in a number of ways. Thus sometimes we have translated it as 'the prius of constructive ideation or unreal imagination, sometimes simply as 'unreal appearance' or 'unreal imagination'. The term conveys all these meanings and therefore we shall select one or the other in accordance with the context. 4 esah sarvah samkleso 'bhutaparikalpat (pravartate)--MVSBh, p. 37. 5 abhutam asmin dvayam parikalpyate 'nena ve 'ty abhutaparikalpahMVSBT, p. 12. 6 anadikalika nirvanaparyavasanah samsaranurupas citta-caitasika nirvisesena 'bhuta parikalpah. visesas tu grahya-grahaka-vikalpah-Ibid. Page #169 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 132 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. tion is free from the duality of the perceived and the perceiver. It is called sunya (void) because it does not contain the duality. It is not sunya (absolute negation) in itself. The prius of unreal imagination is void (sunya) of the perceived and the perceiver (grahya-grahaka) even as a rope is void of snakeness. It can be defined by existence (sattva) as well as by non-existence (asattva). It exists as well as does not exist. It exists qua itself. But it does not exist qua the perceiver and the perceived (grahya-grahaka), because there is no duality in it.? There is absolute non-existence of duality. But the awareness of duality cannot be denied. This awareness is abhutaparikalpa qua unreal imagination or constructive ideation. It cannot but be illusory inasmuch as it is an awareness of the unreal duality. But then the objection naturally arises: Why should not this illusory awareness (bhranti-vijnana) itself be condemned to be as unreal as the perceived and the perceiver? Maitreyanatha says that the abhutaparikalpa qua unreal imagination cannot be absolutely non-existent because emancipation is held to be due to the destruction of it. If there were no illusion (bhranti) at all, there would be no afflictions (sanklesa) and hence no bondage (bandha). Consequently there would be no emancipation because emancipation presupposes bondage. And in that case the reality should be taken as it appears, or it should be condemned as an absolute nothing. The postulation of illusion (bhranti), therefore, is necessary for the establishment of emancipation. This illusion, as we have said above, consists in the awareness of duality. If the awareness of the duality of the perceived and the perceiver were an absolute reality (paramartha) there would be eternal afflictions (sanklesa) and consequently there would be absence of emancipation (nirvana). On the other hand, if that were an absolute non-entity there would be total absence of afflictions (sanklesa) and consequently eternal freedom from afflictions (vyavadana). But both these consequences of absence of emancipation and eternal freedom from afflictions are undesirable, because both of them imply futility of all endeavours for emancipation. On these grounds, it is established that the abhuta (grahya-grahaka)-rahitata 'bhuta parikalpasya sunyata. na khaly abhutaparikalpo 'pi na bhavati. yatha rajjuh sunya sarpatvabhavena tatsvabhavatvabhavat sarvakalam sunya da tu rajjusvabhavena tathe 'ha 'pi.Ibid. 2 abhuta parikalpo 'sti 'ti. tena 'bhutaparikalpasya sattvam nirdisyate ity arthah . . . . tat punar grahyagrahakabhavena 'sattvam yasmad abhutaparikalpe dvayam na 'sti tasmad abhutaparikalpo 'pi dvayatmana nasti 'ty uktam bhavati-Ibid., p. 14. 3 kimartham punas tasya bhranti-vijnanasya 'bhava eva ne 'syate grahya-grahakavat-Ibid., p. 18. 4 na tatha sarvathabhavas tatksayan muktir isyate.-MVS, I. 50-d. 5 Cf. bhrantimatre 'py asati samklesabhavad bandho 'pi nasti, purvasmaddhi bandhanan muktir iti muktir api nasti, kimiti yatha prakhyatis tatha bhavo ne 'syate, sarvatha va 'bhava iti-MVSBT, p. 18. Page #170 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. VII] AVIDYA IN THE BUDDHIST SCHOOL 133 parikalpa (awareness of the duality) exists and also that duality does not exist. That there is sanklesa (afflictions is a fact too apparent to deny, and it is also a verity that this sanklesa is due to the awareness of the duality of the perceived and the perceiver. On the cessation of this awareness there is cessation of sanklesa and consequently there is emancipation. But how can this awareness cease if it is there in its own right? If the awareness of duality is an immutable fact, there is no possibility of emancipation. Again, if this awareness did not exist at all there would be no real existence of sanklesa. It, therefore, follows that the awareness is neither an immutable fact nor an unreal fiction. It is there qua basic defect or a fault or abhutaparikalpa (unreal imagination) as it is called. The logical argument of this position can be put in this form: 'There is sanklesa as well as an urge from within to get rid of this sanklesa and attain mukti (emancipation). The sanklesa presupposes some defect as its cause. The nature of this cause is deduced from the consideration of the conditions of this sorrowful and miserable existence. There is misery and sorrow so long as there is the awareness of the duality of the perceiver and the perceived, subject and object, I and mine ; and if this duality is an immutable fact, there is no reason why the awareness of it should cease to exist. It is, however, established by the evidence of experience as well as logical arguments that there is no duality. Now the awareness of duality remains. This awareness is the ultimate cause of all sanklesa.' But then the problem is, why is there this awareness of duality at all? This question has not been dealt with explicitly. But, as is usual elsewhere, the Buddhists took resort to the conception of the beginninglessness of the world and consequently to the beginninglessness of this awareness of duality. But the problem can be answered in yet a different way. The reality is as it is. The world is only an appearance. There is, in reality, neither sanklesa (afflictions) nor vyavadana (freedom from afflictions), neither bandha (bondage) normoksa (emancipation). Hence there is also not the awareness of duality. It is as much an appearance as its product viz. the phenomenal universe. The Lankavatara says: 'There is neither sanklesa (impurity) nor suddhi (purification) because there is non-existence of all things (dharmas).'? There is neither emancipation nor bondage.'' i Cf..... grahya-grahakatvena pasvadeh pratibhaso yadi punar evam paramarthatah syad evam sati nityah samklesah syat. tatha ca nirvanabhavah, evam bhrantimatrasya py abhave sam klesabhavo nityarn ca vyavadanam prasajyate. evam co 'bhayatha 'pi moksarthinam vyartho yatnah syat. ato 'bhutaparikalpo 'sti dvayam ca na vidyata ity avasyam abhyupagantavyam.-Ibid., pp. 18-19. ? abhavat sarvadharmanam samkleso na 'sti suddhi ca.-LA, X. 137a-b. 3 na mokso na ca bandhanam-LA, X. 275. Page #171 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 134 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. In this connection, it will not be irrelevant to mention the Vijnanavadin's conception of twofold avaranas (veils) viz. jneyavarana and klesavarana on the disappearance of which depends enlightenment. The word jneya means 'knowable' i.e. the dharmas elements of existence' which are not substantial and thus have no reality. The avarana 'cover' in the form of jneya is called ineyavarana. Sometimes the term jneyavarana is also explained as 'avarana regarding the knowable'.? In this case the knowable (jneya) is the reality or the things in their true nature. Similarly, klesavarana means the avarana in the form of klesas. On the question of the purification of these avaranas, the Lankavatara says: 'The jneyavarana, O Mahamati, is purified due to a special kind of intuition of dharma-nairatmya or unsubstantiality of things as they appear. The klesavarana, on the other hand, is destroyed due to the practice of intuition of pudgalanairatmya 'the unreality of the individual ego'.4 These avaranas are also conceived to be as unreal and illusory as the abhutaparikalpa (unreal imagination), because the consciousness is pure and luminous (prabhasvara) by nature." This is the nature of avidya of the Vijnanavadins. Let us now study the conception of avidya in the Tathata philosophy of Asvaghosa. Asvaghosa held that in the soul two aspects may be distinguished --the aspect as thatness (bhutatathata) and the aspect as the cycle of birth and death (samsara). The soul as bhutatathata means the oneness of the totality of all things (dharmadhatu). Its essential nature is uncreate and eternal. All things simply on account of the beginningless traces of the incipient and unconscious memory of our past experiences of many previous lives (smrti) appear under the forms of individuation. If we could overcome this smrti the signs of individuation would disappear and there would be no trace of a world of objects. All things in their fundamental nature are not namable or explicable. They cannot be adequately expressed in any form of language. They possess absolute sameness (samata). They are subject neither to 1 See AS, p. 210. 2 Cf. jneyam ca "vrtir avaranam ... jneyam eva samaropitarupatvad avitih-BAP, p. 447. jneyavaranam api sarvasmin jneye jnanapratibandhabhutam aklistam ajnanam-Tk, p. 15. 3 klesa eva "vstih--BAP, p. 447. 4 jneyavaranam punar Mahamate dharma-nairatmya-darsana-visesad visudhyate, klesavaranam tu pudgala-nairatmyadarsanakhyasapurvakam prahiyateLA, p. 241. 5 Cf. prakrti-prabhasvarar cittam-LA, X. 750, 753, 754. 6 This study is based on Dr. Dasgupta's A History of Indian Philosophy, Vol. I (First edition), pp. 129-138. Dr. Dasgupta's statements are based on Awakening of Faith, an English translation by Suzuki of the Chinese version of Sraddhotpadasastra of Asvaghosa. Page #172 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. VII] AVIDYA IN THE BUDDHIST SCHOOL 135 transformation nor to destruction. They are nothing but one soulthatness (bhutatathata). The soul as birth and death (samsara) comes forth from the tathagata womb (tathagatagarbha), the ultimate reality. But the immortal and the mortal coincide with each other. Though they are not identical they are not duality either. Thus when the absolute soul assumes a relative aspect by its self-affirmation it is called the all-conserving mind (alaya-vijnana). It embraces two principles, (I) enlightenment, (2) non-enlightenment. Enlightenment is the perfection of the mind when it is free from the corruptions of the creative instinctive incipient memory (smrti). It penetrates all and is the unity of all (dharmadhatu). That is to say, it is the universal dharmakaya of all Tathagatas constituting the ultimate foundation of existence. The multitude of people (bahujana) are said to be lacking in enlightenment, because ignorance (avidya) prevails there from all eternity, because there is a constant succession of smrti (past confused memory working as instinct) from which they have never been emancipated. But when they are divested of this smrti they can then recognize that no states of mentation viz. appearance, presence, change and disappearance, have any reality. They are neither in a temporal nor in a spatial relation with the one soul, for they are not self-existent. The enlightenment shows itself imperfectly in our corrupted phenomenal experience as prajna (wisdom) and karma (incomprehensible activity of life). Though all modes of consciousness and mentation are mere products of ignorance, ignorance in its ultimate nature is identical and non-identical with enlightenment; and therefore ignorance is in one sense destructible though in another sense it is indestructible. When the mind of all creatures, which in its own nature is pure and clean, is stirred by the wind of ignorance (avidya), the waves of mentality (vijnana) make their appearance. These three (i.e. the mind, ignorance and mentality) however, have no existence, and they are neither unity nor plurality. When the ignorance is annihilated, the awakened mentality is tranquillized, whilst the essence of wisdom remains unmolested. It is by the touch of ignorance (avidya) that the truth assumes all the phenomenal forms of existence. Non-enlightenment is the raison d'etre of samsara. In describing the relation of the interaction of avidya (ignorance), karmavijnana (activity consciousness -the subjective mind), visaya (external world--represented by the senses), and the tathata (suchness), Asvaghosa says that there is an interperfuming of these elements. Thus Asvaghosa says 'By perfuming we mean that while our worldly clothes (viz. those which we wear) have no odour of their own, neither offensive nor agreeable, they can vet acquire one or the other odour according to the nature of the substance with which they are perfumed. Suchness (tathata) is Page #173 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 136 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. likewise a pure dharma free from all defilements caused by the perfuming power of ignorance. On the other hand ignorance has nothing to do with purity. Nevertheless we speak of its being able to do the work of purity because it in its turn is perfumed by suchness. Determined by suchness ignorance becomes the raison d'etre of all forms of defilement. And this ignorance perfumes suchness and produces smrti. This smri in its turn perfumes ignorance. On account of this reciprocal) perfuming, the truth is misunderstood. On account of its being misunderstood, an external world of subjectivity appears. Further, on account of the perfuming power of memory, various modes of individuation are produced. And by clinging to them various deeds are done, and we suffer, as the result, miseries mentally as well as bodily.'! This is Asvaghosa's idea of the genesis of the world process. Suchness determines ignorance, and this determined ignorance causes all forms of defilement. There is apparent perfuming of suchness by ignorance, and the result is the production of smrti. This smyti together with the ignorance then produces misunderstanding of truth by the process of mutual perfuming. This misunderstanding of truth in its turn is responsible for the appearance of the external world of subjectivity. Then follow all sorts of mental and physical miseries, in one word, samsara. But this samsara has to be got rid of. Asvaghosa describes the process leading to nirvana as follows. 'Suchness perfumes ignorance, and in consequence of this perfuming the individual in subjectivity is caused to loathe the misery of birth and death and to seek after the blessing of nirvana. This longing and loathing on the part of the subjective mind in turn perfumes suchness. On account of this perfuming influence we are enabled to believe that we are in possession within ourselves of suchness whose essential nature is pure and immaculate ; and we also recognize that all phenomena in the world are nothing but illusory manifestations of the mind (alayavijnana) and have no reality of their own. Since we thus rightly understand the truth, we can practise the means of liberation, can perform those actions which are in accordance with the dharma. We should neither particularize, nor cling to objects of desire. By virtue of this discipline and habituation during the lapse of innumerable (asankhyeya) kalpas we get ignorance annihilated. As ignorance is thus annihilated, the mind (alayavijnana) is no longer disturbed, so as to be subject to individuation. As the mind is no longer disturbed, the particularization of the surrounding world is annihilated. When in this wise the principle and the condition of defilement, their products, and the mental disturbances are all annihilated, it is said that we attain nirvana and that various spontaneous displays of activity are accomplished." Quoted from Awakening of Faith in HIP, Vol. I, p. 135. 2 Quoted in HIP, Vol. I, pp. 135-136. Page #174 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. VIII] AVIDYA IN THE SAIVA SCHOOL 137 This is Asvaghosa's conception of the nature, function and annihilation of avidya. On the difference of general outlook of the idealism of Lankavatara and the doctrines of Asvaghosa and Nagarjuna, Dr. Dasgupta says: "The Lankavatara admitted a reality only as a make-believe to attract the Tairthikas (heretics) who had a prejudice in favour of an unchangeable self (atman). But Asvaghosa plainly admitted an unspeakable reality as the ultimate truth. Nagarjuna's Madhyamika doctrines which eclipsed the profound philosophy of Asvaghosa seem to be more faithful to the traditional Buddhist creed and to the Vijnanavada creed of Buddhism as explained in the Lankavatara.'' There is nothing peculiar in the conceptions of avidya of the other schools of Buddhist thought such as the Madhyamika and the like, and so we do not refer to those schools. Of course, there is difference among them as regards the nature of reality and as such there is consequent difference in their conception of the nature and function of avidya. But our above enquiry is sufficient to give an idea of the various Buddhist conceptions of avidya inasmuch as those conceptions are only restatements in some form or other of the conceptions we have already discussed. Let us now study the Saiva conception of avidya. VIII AVIDYA IN THE SAIVA SCHOOL There are two schools of Saiva philosophy: (I) monistic and (2) dualistic. We shall deal with the dualistic school in the beginning and in the end briefly notice the standpoint of the other school. Dualistic saivism Dualistic Saivism accepts the duality of spirit and matter and also believes in the plurality of spirits (souls). It also believes in the existence of a transcendent Being, known as Paramasiva (or simply Siva), Mahesvara or Pasupati, who is eternally free and is of the nature of pure consciousness and perfect will. Besides this transcendent Being and the plurality of individual souls, there is bindu or mahamaya (pure matter) which is the material stuff of the higher and pure order of evolution, and maya (impure matter) which is the material stuff of the lower and impure order of creation. The innate nature of every soul is similar to that of Siva. But it lies obscured and is to be recovered and reinstated. The search for 1 HIP, Vol. I. p. 138. JP_18 Page #175 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 138 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [ch. the ultimate cause of this obscuration leads to the postulation of avidya which, in Saivism, is regarded as a positive entity, called mala (taint or contamination), whose essential function is to reduce the inherent powers--such as omniscience, omnipotence, absence of desires and freedom from spatial and temporal limitations-of the soul to their minimum. Under the stress of mala, the soul loses its freedom of consciousness and will and is known as anu (atomic) because of the reduction of its innate powers to anutva (atomic measure). It has lost its sivatva (perfection) and is known as pasu (animal). The mala that reduces the powers of the soul to anutva (atomicity) is known as anavamala. This is the most fundamental form of pasa (trap that binds the soul to the wheel of worldly existence). There are other forms of pasa as well. Let us study in brief the nature of these forms. Let us begin with the mala-pasa, the fundamental function whereof has been just stated. Mala-pasa is a unitary entity with manifold powers. It obscures the power of consciousness and the freedom of will. It lies mixed up with the soul. Even as the husk lies mixed up with rice and is the cause of the further production of root, sprout etc. of rice, exactly so the mala lies mixed up with the soul and is the cause of its ever-repeating embodied mundane existence. It can, however, be disentangled from the soul, thereby enabling it to regain its divine nature, even as the dark colour of copper can be removed from it resulting in its restoration to its pristine nature of pure gold. Mala is beginningless and is responsible for the pasutva (animality) of the soul" which is potentially of the nature of Siva with unlimited consciousness and power. It is the existence of this mala that justifies the Divine Will of Siva to actuate the evolution of the material stuff for the sake of those souls that are associated with it." Mala is uncaused, constant and eternal. It is one, but because of its varied powers it can cover the different souls so that the emancipation of one soul does not involve the emancipation of all others. Next we come to the second form of pasa called karma-pasa. The obscured and suppressed omnipotence (sarvakartytva) of the soul, associated with mala, finds expression in imperfect activities of the body, the sense-organ of speech and mind, which lead to the acquisi1 Cf. eko hy anekasaktir dIk-kriyayos chadako malo pumsani tusakambukavaj jneyas tamrasritakalimavad va.--TP, p. 56. 2 atha 'nadi-malah pumsam pasutvam parikirtitam.-Sataratnasangraha, p. 36. 3 Cf. evam mayayah Sivecchavasad avapasya prasavabhimukhabhavasya kaladi-karyades ca tan-(malarupam pankam) nimittam iti-Ibid. 4 Cf....... tasman na karmavat pravahanaditvam malasya. kintu karanabhavad eva 'naditvam mayavat-Ibid. (Commentary), p. 37. malasyai 'katve 'pi tadiyavaraka-saktinam anantyat tadavaryanam api bhedad nai 'kamuktau sarvamuktiprasangah--Ibid. (Commentary), p. 38. Jain. Education International Page #176 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. VII] AVIDYA IN THE SAIVA SCHOOL 139 tion of invisible merits (dharma) and demerits (adharma) according as they are good or bad. These merits and demerits constitute karmapasa which is responsible for the worldly vicissitudes--the happy and unhappy experiences of the soul. The soul involved in the worldly process has lost its self-contained complacency (aptakamatva) and is consequently driven into perpetual quest of the good things of the world in order to regain the lost paradise. It gets into possession of these good things in conformity with its deserts. Each soul has its own karma-pasa which is beginningless in the sense that it had an unbroken continuity in the past and not in the sense that it is an unchanging invariable constant. Karman is ever changing. But its continuity had no break, because that would have resulted in the emancipation of the soul. It cannot be an invariable constant because in that case emancipation would never be possible.? Karman matures during the period of dissolution and fructifies during the period of creation. It remains embedded in the principle of maya (impure matter) during the dissolution and does not suffer attrition or destruction until its effects are experienced by the soul concerned.? The third form of pasa is known as maya-pasa. Maya (impure matter), as we have said, is the material stuff of the lower order of evolution. The soul ensnared by mala and karman gets entangled in the cosmic order evolved out of maya. The body and sense-organs and the external world in which it has to live out its predetermined career are all evolved out of maya which is their matrix. This maya is not an unreal fiction. It is an eternal real entity which is ultimate and uncaused. It is as real and independent as mahamaya (pure matter) which is the material stuff of the higher order of evolution. Maya is a pasa (trap) inasmuch as it encases the soul and keeps it enmeshed by itself. The fourtho form of pasa is constituted by mahamaya (pure matter) which is the material stuff of the pure order of creation. Mahamaya is pure matter and the bodies formed out of it are luminous. Only those souls which have destroyed their karma-pasa and maya-pasa are entitled to have the luminous bodies evolved out of mahamaya, on the maturation of their mala and the consequent descent of the Divine Grace. 1 Cf. karma. 'nadi pravaharupena, na cai 'kasyai 'va karmanah sarvada 'vasthanena. tatha sati bhavarupasya karmano 'naditvena 'tmavan nityataya nirmoksa prasangat-TP (Commentary), p. 58. 2 Cf. svape vipakam abhyeti tat srstav upayujyate mayayani vartate ca 'nte na 'bhuktam ksayam eti ca. --Sataratnasangraha, p. 57. 3 maya sa vasturupa mulam visvasya nitya sa.-TP, p. 58. 4 Sometimes only the above three forms of pasa are mentioned. But in that case the fourth and the fifth forms of pasa viz. mahamaya and the Lord's Yodha-sakti, are to be understood by implication. Vide TP (Commentary), p. 32. Page #177 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 140 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. The power of obscuration (rodha-sakti) belonging to the Lord Siva is recognized as the fifth form of pasa. Lord Siva is not responsible for the obscuration of the innate nature of the souls. But obscuration continues in the absence of the descent of His Grace and so the nondescent of Grace, because it apparently imitates the nature of a pasa, is conceived as the positive power of obscuration. Thus it is said that although the power of Mahesvara is auspicious and beneficent to all, yet because of its apparent imitation of the functions of mala, it is known as a pasa.? These are the five forms of pasa recognized in Saivism. Of these, mala is the most fundamental. It corresponds to the avidya of the other sistems. The soul that is associated with the three pasas viz. mate karman and maya is known as sakala. The soul that is associated with only the two pasas viz. mala and karman is known as pralayakala. And the soul that has transcended the category of maya and has only the mala-pasa is called vijnanakala. The vijnanakala soul, on the maturation of its mala and the consequent descent of the Divine Grace, rises up to the levels of the categories of vidya (suddha), isvara or sadasiva according to the extent of its spiritual development revealed in the manifestation of its kriyasakti or the power of action (the manifestation of jnanasakti or the power of knowledge being uniform in all cases). The consummation of spiritual development is reached on the attainment of sivatva (divine nature). It will not, in this connection, be out of place to relate in brief the way in which the soul gets rid of mala. On the maturation of the mala and the approach of the termination of the influence of the obscuring power (tirodhana-sakti) of the Lord, there is descent of Lord's Grace (anugraha-sakti).2 On the descent of the Grace, the soul begins to take interest in the attainment of emancipation and abhors worldly life. It can now discriminate the self from the not-self. And consequently an inquisitiveness for the nature of truth is born in it. Now the soul easily finds out a competent preceptor (guru) who gives diksa (initiation) which ultimately disentangles it from the pasas. Saivism regards diksa as the most essential condition of emancipation. Pure consciousness and perfect will are inherent in a soul, but on account of its association with mala, these powers suffer obscuration which can be removed only by the Grace of Siva. It is Siva who, by means of His Supreme 1 Cf. tasam mahesvari saktih sarvanugrahika siva dharmanuvartanad eva pasa ity upacaryate.--Sataratnasangraha, p. 38. 2 Cf. tamah-saktyadhikarasya nivittes tat-paricyutau vyanakti dIk-kriyanantyam jagadbandhur anoh Sivah.--Ibid., p. 65. 3 Cf. yesam saririnam Saktih pataty avinivsttaye tesam tallingam autsukyam muktau dveso bhavasthitau. ---Ibid., p. 65. Page #178 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. VIII] Power (sakti), awakens the soul from its eternal sleep of delusion. And this is done through the instrumentality of a preceptor (guru) during the cosmic process, or directly without any such medium during the cosmic dissolution. The former is called sadhikarana-diksa (initiation through medium), and the latter niradhikarana-diksa (initiation without medium). Diksa removes the pasutva (animality) of the soul and restores it to its pristine sivatva (divine nature). The corrupting power of mala is destroyed by diksa even as the killing power of poison is destroyed by incantation or antidotes, although the mala qua an innocuous appendage is still there.1 The karmans accumulated in the past are destroyed and the karmans that might occur in the future are rendered impossible owing to the absence of their conditions. The karmans which are responsible for the present life, however, are to, be exhausted by experience. As a potter's wheel goes on revolving, even after the jar has been produced for which it was set in motion, on account of the momentum, exactly so the present body continues to survive on account of the traces of past merits and demerits that are responsible for the present life. And on the fall of the body the soul shines in its eternal and all-comprehensive consciousness as siva even as a lamp illumines all directions after the jar that covered it has been destroyed.2 AVIDYA IN THE SAIVA SCHOOL Monistic Saivism In the monistic school of Saivism, the Supreme Reality is Paramasiva the Absolute whose nature consists of pure consciousness and freedom.3 This Supreme Principle of free unimpeded consciousness reveals itself in the form of infinite worlds. By its twofold functions of self-concealment (sva-gopana) and self-limitation (svasankoca) it conceals its own nature and manifests itself in different forms, both subjective and objective. In the process of manifestation, sometimes the aspect of consciousness is dominant over self-limitation and sometimes the aspect of selflimitation is dominant over consciousness. The dominance of consciousness, again, can be natural (sahaja) or acquired through effort (samadhi-prayatnoparjita). The natural dominance of consciousness may, again, be with or without the expression of power (paramarsa) inherent in it. In the former case, the resultant subject is known as vidyapramata. In the latter, it is vijnanakala. When the self-limitation 1 Ibid., karika 87 and commentary (pp. 89-90). 2 bhagne ghate yatha dipah sarvatah samprakasate dehapate tatha ca "tma bhati sarvatra sarvada.-Ibid., p. 92. 141 3 Cf. citih svatantra visvasiddhi-hetuh-Pratyabhijnahrdaya, p. 2. 4 Cf. cid eva bhagavati svaccha-svatantra-rupa tat-tad-anantajagadatmana sphurati-Ibid., p. 3. Page #179 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ [CH. isvara. of the vidyapramata is eliminated to a small extent, the resultant is When the elimination of self-limitation is carried to a greater extent the resultant is sadasiva. And when the self-limitation is eliminated to the fullest extent, sivatva follows. The dominance of consciousness, acquired through effort, leads to the attainment of the different grades of spiritual development in the pure order (suddhadhvan). The dominance of self-limitation, on the other hand, results in the formation of lower grades of subjects viz. pralayakala and sakala,1 142 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA Imperfection in the subject is consequent upon the intermixture of the elements of subjectivity (ahanta) and objectivity (idanta). Pure subject absolutely divorced from objectivity is siva. Subjectivity and objectivity are mutually antagonistic and can respectively be compared to light and darkness. The supremacy of subjectivity necessarily preThe supposes subordination of the objective element and vice versa. absolute supremacy of subjectivity, as in the transcendent state of siva, is accompanied with a total negation of objectivity. Similarly, the absolute supremacy of objectivity, as in the case of pralayakala and the lower states of the soul, is accompanied with the subordination of pure subjectivity. This antagonism of subjectivity and objectivity is resolved in the state of Paramasiva which is at once transcendent (visvottirna) and immanent (visvatmaka).2 Let us now study the genesis of the threefold mala-anava, mayiya and karma-which is responsible for the worldly career of the soul. When the Supreme Reality by the free exercise of its own autonomous will elects to submerge its pervasion of identity and adopts differentiation of itself, its powers of will, and the like, though unrestricted, appear to be restricted and it appears in the role of an individuated self caught in the meshes of transmigration." The selfchosen diminution of will-power is the imperfection called anava-mala -the dirt inducing atomicity. Under its influence the unchecked freedom of will suffers attrition in scope and intensity and induces a sense of incompleteness and imperfection (apurnammanyata). When the infinite knowledge-power of the Supreme Reality likewise undergoes progressive contraction and diminution it loses the character of omniscience and deteriorates into a limited capacity for knowledge of limited objects, and the climax is reached when the knowledge-power 2 Ibid., pp. 7-8. 1 Ibid., pp. 11-12. 3 Cf. yada cidatma Paramesvarah svasvatantryad abhedavyaptim avalambate tada tadiya icchadisaktayo 'sankucita api sankocavatyo bhanti tadanim eva ca 'yam malavrtah samsari bhavati-Ibid., p. 21. 4 Cf. tatha ca 'pratihata-svatantrya-rupa icchasaktih sankucita sati apurnammanyata-rupam anavam malam.--Ibid. . Page #180 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. VIII] AVIDYA IN THE SAIVA SCHOOL is reduced to the status of the inner sense (the mind) and the external senses of cognition. The consequence of this stage is the appearance of objects as numerically different from the subject and this is called mayiya-mala. Similarly when the unlimited power of action suffers a set-back, omnipotence is reduced to the form of motor organs (karmendriya). In consequence of this limitation, performance of deeds (good and evil) becomes possible. This constitutes the karmamala. On the other hand, the limitation of omnipotence, omniscience, self-contained complacency, eternality and ubiquity in the Supreme Self results in the genesis of the five principles of kala (limited power of action), (asuddha-) vidya (imperfect knowledge), raga (attachment), kala (time) and niyati (spatial limitation) respectively. This is the process whereby the Supreme Reality imposes upon itself the limitations of worldly life and appears as an imperfect mundane soul devoid of powers (sakti-daridra). Of the three forms of mala, anava-mala is the most fundamental. It corresponds, as we have already noticed, to the principle of avidya of the other systems. Broadly speaking, the Highest Reality has two aspects, Consciousness and Freedom, which in the supreme state are mutually inseparable and in fact identical. But before the first cosmic process sets in the two are split up so that Consciousness is divorced from Freedom, and Freedom is divorced from Consciousness. Consciousness without Freedom and Freedom without Consciousness are therefore rightly regarded as the two forms of anava-mala.1 as Now it is clear that oblivion of true nature of Self as Consciousness-cum-Freedom is anava-mala. This oblivion is also known spiritual ignorance (paurusa-ajnana). There is yet another type of ignorance known as intellectual ignorance (bauddha-ajnana) which originates after the soul has been involved in mundane existence under the influence of karma-mala and mayiya-mala both of which derive from anava-mala. It is the removal of the spiritual ignorance only that leads to emancipation. The spiritual processes such as diksa (initiation) and the like lead to the removal of the spiritual ignorance. In the presence of intellectual ignorance, the removal of spiritual ignorance is unable to produce jivanmukti or emancipation during life. True emancipation in this case takes place on the fall of the present Cf. jnanasaktih 2 kriyasaktih -Ibid., p. 22. 4 Cf. svatantryahanir bodhasya svatantryasya 'py abodhata dvidha "navamalam idam svasvarupapahanitah. 5 Vide ibid., pp. 55-57. 143 bhinnavedyapratharupam mayiyam malam -Ibid. subhasubhanusthanamayam karmam malam 3 Ibid. -Quoted in Tantraloka (Commentary), Vol. I, p. 55. Page #181 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ [CH. body. If, however, in the mean time the intellectual ignorance has disappeared on account of the rise of intellectual enlightenment through yoga and other processes, the soul attains to a sense of its identity with the Supreme Reality and consequent emancipation in that very condition of embodied existence (i.e. jivanmukti).2 Monistic Saivism has chalked out a number of processes for the attainment of emancipation, which have distinctive originality of their own. But in order to avoid unnecessary prolixity we do not relate them in this connection. We now come to the Jaina conception of avidya. 144 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA IX AVIDYA IN THE JAINA SCHOOL 'I am this, this is I, I am of this, mine is this everything that is non-self, living, non-living or mixed. Mine was all this formerly; I was all this in the past; again will this be mine and I shall again be this. The deluded one (sammudha) possesses all these false notions about the self. The undeluded, however, knowing the truth, does not do so.'3 In Jainism the term mithyatva (perversity) is generally used to denote the idea of avidya. The terms mithyadarsana or mithyadrsti (wrong view), darsanamoha (delusion of vision), moha (delusion) etc. are also used in the same sense. The opposite of mithyatva is samyaktua, also known as samyagdarsana (right view). The soul is associated with various kinds of karmans and darsana-moha is one of them.* The karmans obstruct the various capacities of the soul and keep it tied to the wheel of worldly existence. Thus the jnanavarana (knowledgecovering) karman covers the soul's capacity to know, the darsanavarana (intuition-covering) karman covers the capacity to intuit, and so on. The function of darsanamoha is to delude the soul and misguide it. Many wrong notions about truth and reality arise due to its influence. It vitiates the whole outlook and is responsible for the wrong assessment of ultimate values. Mithyatva (perversity of outlook) expresses itself in various ways. Under its influence, one accepts the adharma (wrong religion) as the dharma (right religion), the amagga (wrong path) as the magga (right path), the ajiva (non-soul) as the jiva (soul), 1 Cf. tatra diksadina paumsnam ajnanam dhvamsi yadyapi tathapi taccharirante tajjnanam vyajyate sphutam.-Ibid., p. 79. 2 Cf. bauddha-jnanena tu yada bauddham ajnana-jrmbhitam viliyate tada jivan-muktih karatale sthita.-Ibid., p. 81. 3 Kundakunda's Samayaprabhrta, 25-27 with commentaries (Kashi, 1914). Vide infra, Chap. IV. Section III, 2nd paragraph. Page #182 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. IX] AVIDYA IN THE JAINA SCHOOL the asahu (sinner) as the sahu (saint), the amutta (unemancipated) as the mutta (emancipated) and vice-versa. Umasvati divides mithyadarsana into two categories viz. abhigrhita (firmly held) and anabhigrhita (lightly held). The acceptance of a wrong view and obstinate tenacity for it is abhigrhita and the opposite of it is anabhigrhita.2 The difference between the two is determined by the degree of the intensity and tenacity of the adherence to perversity. Kundakunda says that mithyatva (perversity), ajnana (nescience), and avirati (intense attachment) are the three beginningless forms of the consciousness informed with moha (delusion). Pujyapada Devanandi notices twofold mithyadarsana viz. (1) inborn (naisargika) and (2) acquired from instructions of others (paropadesa-purvaka). What is due simply to the rising of the mithyatva (vision-deluding) karman is naisargika (inborn), while there are four varieties of the latter according as it belongs to a kriya-vadin (believer in moral and spiritual action), akriyavadin (non-believer in moral and spiritual action), ajnanin (agnostic), or vainayika (credulous person). Pujyapada notices also a different way of classification of mithyadarsana into (1) ekanta, (2) viparita, (3) samsaya, (4) vainayika, and (5) ajnana. Absolutistic prejudice is ekanta-mithyadarsana. Perverted conviction is viparita. Scepticism is the third. Indiscriminate faith in every god and every scripture is vainayika. Absence of discrimination between good and bad is ajnanika-mithyadarsana.1 The fourth Karmagrantha, however, notices these five varieties: (1) abhigrahika, (2) anabhigrahika, (3) abhinivesika, (4) samsayika, and (5) anabhoga. Obstinate insular attachment to the wrong view is abhigrahika-mithyadarsana. The opposite of this, that is, indiscriminate faith in the veracity of each and every view is anabhigrahika. Attachment to a view in spite of the knowledge that it is wrong is abhinivesika. Sceptic attitude even towards what is well established is samsayika. What is due to the incapacity of the mind to think and is found in such organisms as have not developed all the sense-organs is anabhoga-mithyadarsana.5 These different ways of classification do not mean different conceptions. They are at best various modes of illustrating the workings of the selfsame mithyatva (perversity). Mithyadarsana (perverse view) lies at the root of all evils, and whatever misery there is in the life of a soul is ultimately due to it." It is the darkest period of a soul's life when 1 SthSu, X. 1. 734. 2 Bhasya, TS, VIII. I. 3 uvaogassa anai parinama tinni mohajuttassa micchattam annanam aviradibhavo ya nadavvo.-Samayasara, 96. 4 SSi on TS, VIII. I. Cf. also SuKr, Samosaranajjhayana. In this connection see also the Bhasya and Siddhasenaganin's Tika on TSu, VIII. 1. 5 Fourth Karmagrantha, 51. See also the svopajna commentary. 6 Cf. samsaramula-biam micchattam-Bhattaparinnaya, IV. 59. JP-19 145 Page #183 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 146 [CH. there is unhindered working of this mithyatva. The soul gropes in the darkness, formulates wrong views about truth, and treads upon many a path, none leading to the region of light. The mithyatva-karman lies heavy on it, and blockades all paths leading to light. Samyaktva or samyagdarsana dawns only when the potency of this mithyatvakarman is reduced and made ineffective to an appreciable extent in course of time naturally or due to the influence of the instructions of persons who know the truth. The mithyatva has no beginning in time. It is there from all eternity. Why a soul is subject to it is a question too difficult to answer, or rather it is too much to ask because it is a question of fact and not of reason. And because it is coeval with the self it cannot be set down to an adventitious condition which is the usual mode of solution of problems. In one sense, the question is as absurd as the question 'Why should the self exist?' The existence of the self is an ultimate fact and the existence of delusion coevel with it is equally an ultimate fact to which no question of origination can be relevant. The mithyatva is there, and it is not that we do not know its nature. Its nature and functions are well known. We also know its conditions. We do not know the beginning because it has no beginning. Why should we hesitate to accept a fact if our experience does not contradict it? The Jaina attitude is too realistic to abandon the verdict of experience, to speculate about possible answers to such ultimate issues, and as a result to adjust or compromise the facts of common experience. The Jaina philosophers, in matters of logical thinking, strictly follow the verdict of experience and do not surrender experience to abstract reasoning. The mithyatva, therefore, is accepted as beginningless on the basis of uncontradicted experience and also because no beginning can be postulated without self-contradiction. In course of time, the soul attains purification, and the samyagdarsana (right attitude) dawns upon it. The soul naturally proceeds towards it, and depends very little upon extraneous help. Of course, sometimes the progress is hastened due to the influence of the instructions of others. The main urge, however, comes from within. The dawning of samyaktva (right attitude) is attended by radical change in the outlook. The whole horizon changes. Samyagdarsana (right attitude) is a kind of purified state of consciousness, that enables the soul to realize and comprehend the things as they are. Samyagjnana (right knowledge) presupposes samyagdarsana (right attitude). In the absence of right attitude, the knowledge cannot be right. How can there be pure knowledge if the self that knows is impure? Similarly, samyakcaritra (right conduct) presupposes right attitude and right knowledge. And these three viz. right attitude, .right knowledge, and right conduct constitute PROBLEM OF AVIDYA 1 See Haribhadra's Dharmasangrahani, gathas, 570-575. Page #184 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ JII. IX] AVIDYA IN THE JAINA SCHOOL 147 Let us now study the problem more the pathway to emancipation. closely. Mithya-darsana (perverse attitude), avirati (non-abstinence), pramada (spiritual inertia), kasaya (passions), and yoga (activity) these five are the conditions of bondage. Of these five, the succeeding ones necessarily exist on the existence of the preceding ones, although it is not necessary that the preceding ones should exist on the existence of the succeeding ones. We can also classify the causes of bondage into these three viz. mithya-darsana (perverse view), mithya-jnana (perverse knowledge) and mithya-caritra (perverse conduct). The worldly existence is due to the joint working of these three and so it is the destruction of all these three that leads to emancipation. Perverse view or wrong attitude vitiates the whole outlook, and consequently whatever knowledge or action there is becomes vitiated (mithya). The perversity of knowledge and conduct depends upon the perversity of attitude. The perverse attitude (mithya-darsana) defiles, as it were, the very texture of the soul, and it is but natural that all the functions of the soul should be defiled. Purification of the attitude (darsana), therefore, is regarded as the sine qua non of the purification of the knowledge (jnana) and conduct (caritra). Explaining the reason why the selfsame mati-jnana, sruta-jnana and avadhi-jnana become matyajnana, sruta-'jnana and avadhy-ajnana (or vibhanga), Umasvati says: *These (mati, sruta and avadhi), when informed with mithya-darsana (wrong attitude), comprehend the thing as it is not, and thus are ajnana (wrong cognition).'s Even as the knowledge of a mad man is necessarily ajnana, although by chance sometimes it hits upon the truth, exactly so the knowledge of one whose soul is vitiated by mithya-darsana (perverse attitude) is of necessity ajnana in spite of its empirical validity by accident. The knowledge can be right (samyak) only if the attitude or outlook (darsana) is right. Similarly, the rightness of conduct depends upon the rightness of knowledge. On the relation of right attitude (samyag-darsana), right knowledge (samyag-jnana) and right conduct (samyak-caritra), Umasvati says: 'Of these, the succeeding one is not necessarily acquired on the acquisition of the preceding one. The acquisition of the preceding one, however, is of necessity there on the 1 samyag-darsana-jnana-caritrani moksa-margah---ISu, I. I. . 2 TSU, VIII. I. 3 Bhasya on TSu, VIII. 1. 4 Cf. samyag-darsana-jnana-caritrani moksamarga ity adyasutra-samarthyat mithya-darsana-jnana-caritrani samsaramarga iti siddheh-Tsiv, p. 72 (TSu, I. 1.). Smithya-dardana-parigrahad viparita-grahakatvam etesam, tasmad ajnanani bhavanti-Bhasya, TSu, I. 32. Also see NSu, 25, 41 : Vibh, 527, 528, 534 6 Cf. Bhasya, TSu, I. 33 ; also Vibh, 115. Page #185 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ [CH. 1 acquisition of the succeeding one.' Siddhasenaganin records two different interpretations of this statement of Umasvati. In the first interpretation, right attitude is regarded as quite distinct and separate from right knowledge. In the second, the right attitude is considered as simply a specific determinate state, of the nature of inclination, of the mati-jnana. Accordingly, in the first interpretation, the above statement of Uinasvati is held as referring to the relation among the three viz. (1) right attitude, (2) right knowledge and (3) right conduct while, in the second, it is interpreted as referring to the relation between the two viz. (1) right attitude together with right knowledge and (2) right conduct. The first interpretation seems to be more natural and faithful to the text although in view of Umasvati's conception of right attitude the second interpretation is not altogether incompatible. Umasvati defines right attitude (samyag-darsana) as sraddhana for the truth, and explains sraddhana as pratyayavadharana, that is, discursive determination.^ He further characterizes samyagdarsana as 'invariable grasping of all the objects of the sense-organs and the mind." Umasvati thus clearly admits samyag-darsana as a kind of knowledge. In this connection the view of Siddhasena Divakara that the term darsana is used for the abhinibodhika (i.e. mati-jnana) of a person who takes to heart the principles revealed by the omniscient deserves careful notice. Jinabhadra says that samyaktva is to be distinguished from sruta (scriptural knowledge) even as the determinate knowledge (jnana) is to be distinguished from indeterminate intuition (darsana). Even as apaya (perceptual judgment) and dharana (retention) are regarded as knowledge (jnana) while avagraha and iha are (relatively) considered as darsana so also samyaktva is to be regarded as predilection for the truth (tattva-ruci) while what grasps that truth should be regarded as jnana. Samyag-darsana and samyag-jnana are born simultaneously. But even then they are not identical. They are related as cause and effect. 'Even as a lamp and its light, though simultaneously born, are separate as cause and effect, so is samyaktva, though simultaneously born, the logical prius, as opposed to chronological priority, of (samyag) jnana. The samyaktua, though simultaneously born, purifies 148 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA 1 esam ca purvasya labhe bhajaniyam uttaram uttaralabhe tu niyatah purvalabhah-Bhasya, TS, I. I. Also cf. UtSu, XXVIII. 30. 2 See Tika on Bhasya, TSu, I. 1. 3 mati-jnanasyai 'va rucirupo yo 'payamsas tat samyagdarsanam, jnanad rte 'nyat samyag-darsanami na samasti. 4 See TSu, I. 2 with Bhasya. 5 avyabhicarini sarvendriyanindriya-'rthapraptih-Bhasya, TS, I. 1. 6 Sanmatitarka, II, 32. The gatha runs as follows: evam jinapannatte saddahamanassa bhavao bhave purisassa 'bhinibohe damsana-saddo havai jutto. ViBh, 535-6. Page #186 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. IX] AVIDYA IN THE JAINA SCHOOL 149 the jnana even as the powder of kataka (Strychnos Potatorum) purifies turbid rain-water'.! Pujyapada Devanandi, admitting the simultaneous emergence of samyag-darsana (right attitude) and samyag-jnana (right knowledge), says that as soon as the consciousness gets possession of samyag-darsana (right attitude) due to the subsidence, destruction, or subsidence-cum-destruction of the darsana-moha (attitude-deluding karman), its maty-ajnana and sruta- jnana disappear and there emerge mati-jnana and sruta-jnana just like the emergence of heat and light of the sun on the displacement of the clouds.2 Samyag-darsana (right attitude) is superior to samyag-jnana (right knowledge) inasmuch as the latter derives its appellation 'samyak' from the former. There is unanimity among the Jaina thinkers as regards the simultaneous occurrence of samyag-darsana and samyag-jnana. And we have noticed above the view of Siddhasena Divakara and the alternative interpretation referred to by Siddhasenaganin in his commentary on the nature of samyag-darsana and its relation with samyag-jnana. Samyag-darsana can be considered as that purified state of consciousness which enables it to know the truth as it is. It is the state of freedom from wrong intuition of truth. It is the ground of samyagjnana (right knowledge). Then comes samyak-caritra (right conduct). The Jaina philosophers gave as much importance to caritra (conduct) as to jnana (knowledge) and darsana (predilection for truth). If samyag-darsana turns the soul in the right direction and samyag-jnana illumines the path, samyak-caritra (right conduct or rectified will) leads to the goal. Let us study the problem of the relation of darsana, jnana and caritra in some detail. The Uttaradhyayana says:' 'One devoid of right attitude (darsana) cannot have right knowledge (jnana) and there cannot be rectitude of will (carana-guna) without right knowledge (nana). One devoid of the rectitude of will cannot have emancipation from evil will, and one devoid of emancipation from evil will (induced by karman) cannot attain final emancipation.': 'We have seen how closely samyagdarsana and samyag-jnana are related. Let us now see the respective functions of jnana (knowledge) and caritra (conduct). The Avasyakaniryukti says that conduct (carana) is the fulfilment of the scriptural knowledge (sruta-jnana), while emancipation (nirvana) is the fulfilment 1 karana-kajja-vibhago diva-pagasana jugavajamme vi jugavuppannam pi taha heu nanassa sammattam. jugavam pi samuppannam sammattam ahigamam visohei jaha kayagamamjanai jala-vutthio visohimti. --Quoted in Byhadurtti on Vibh, 536. 2 See SSi on TSu, I. 1. 3 Ibid 4 nadarnsassa nanam nanena vina na hunti carana-guna. agunissa natthi mokkho natthi amokkhassa nivvanam. -Utsu, XXVIII. 30. Of he do Pectii Page #187 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 150 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA of conduct.1 'One, even though possessed of scriptural knowledge, does not attain emancipation if one fails to bear the austerities of tapas (penance) and samyama (restraint and discipline) which constitute right conduct. Just as a vessel, although having an expert pilot, does not cross the great ocean and reach the shore desired by the trader in the absence of wind, even so a soul-vessel, although competent, being possessed of jnana (knowledge) as its guide, does not reach the abode of the emancipated in the absence of the wind of spiritual penance and discipline.'2 Training and discipline of the intellect without the training and discipline of the will does not lead to freedom. The disciplined will is rather the logical condition of the disciplined reason, and one finds its fulfilment in the other. Without this fulfilment, the mere intellectual culture is a cripple and mere moral culture implied by discipline of the will without intellectual illumination is blind. Even as a donkey carrying sandalwood enjoys only the weight and not the sandalwood itself, exactly so does one, possessed of knowledge (jnana) without will (carana), enjoys only the knowledge and not its consummation viz. emancipation. Futile indeed is knowledge without will (kriya). Even so is will futile without knowledge. A lame man was burnt in spite of his sight while a blind man caught fire even though fleeing.'s Knowledge enlightens, penance purifies, and restraint protects. Even omniscience is not immediately followed by emancipation. Jinabhadra says that right conduct (caritra) is even superior to right knowledge (jnana) inasmuch as the soul is not necessarily emancipated immediately after attaining complete and perfect knowledge while it is at once freed on the acquisition of complete and consummate discipline (samvara), that is, caritra. Right knowledge and spiritual discipline (kriya) are equally necessary for emancipation, although the latter is considered as the immediate condition of it. The soul has to destroy by means of the perfection of discipline (caritra) the residual karmans even when it has destroyed the mohaniya (deluding), jnanavarana (knowledge-covering), darsanavarana (intuition-covering) and antaraya (obstructing) karmans, and has attained perfect and pure knowledge and intuition. Thus technically speaking caritra is the proximate condition of emancipation. This is, in brief, the mutual [CH. 1 tassa vi saro caranam saro caranassa nivvanam.-ViBh, 1126 (ANir gatha). 2 ViBh, 1143, 1145, 1146 (ANir gathas). 3 ViBh, 1158-9 (ANir gathas). 4 nanam payasayam sohao tavo samjamo ya guttikaro. 5 ViBh, 1131. -ViBh, 1169 (ANir gatha). One who has attained perfection of knowledge and has become omniscient is necessarily possessed of right conduct. The conduct, however, has not reached its consummation which is attained only in the last moment of worldly existence, when the soul is in the fourth stage of sukladhyana. (Vide infra, Chap. V. Section II, last paragraph but three). Page #188 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. 'ix] AVIDYA IN THE JAINA SCHOOL 151 relation of samyag-darsana (right attitude towards truth), samyagjnana (right knowledge), and samyak-caritra (right conduct). We have now seen that, according to the Jaina thinkers, mithyadarsana (perverse attitude), mithya-jnana (perverse knowledge), and mithya-caritra (perverse conduct or will) are the conditions of bondage, that is, worldly existence while samyag-darsana, samyag-jnana, and samyak-caritra constitute the pathway to emancipation. The soul possesses a number of capacities such as consciousness, vision, knowledge, intuition, energy, bliss and the like, which are obstructed by the different karmans, and the result is worldly existence. These capacities find expression in their mutilated and imperfect forms while the soul is in bondage. On the attainment of emancipation, the soul reveals these capacities in their natural form. When the capacity for right vision arsana) is obstructed, there is mithya-darsana. When the capacity for right knowledge is mutilated there is mithya-jnana. When there is obstruction of the energy of the soul there is mithya-caritra. Bondage, in the ultimate analysis, consists in the obstructed and mutilated condition of the various capacities of the soul. That the soul has these capacities is a matter of common experience. On many an occasion we feel that there is something wrong in our attitude, that there is some flaw in our knowledge, that there is some check on our energy. On many an occasion, again, we become conscious of our capacity for right vision, our competency for infinite knowledge, our strength against the corruptions of the world. On the basis of these experiences, we can postulate different capacities of the soul. And this is what the Jaina thinkers did. The capacities of the soul are obstructed in various ways due to various causes. These capacities can be classified into three groups viz. right (samyak) attitude or predilection (darsana), right knowledge, and right conduct, their corresponding mutilated forms being perverted (mithya) attitude, perverted knowledge, and perverted conduct. Accordingly, the Jaina thinkers did not accept the view that perverted knowledge (mithya-jnana) alone is the cause of bondage. Perverted knowledge is only one of the three causes of bondage, the other two being perverted attitude (mithya-darsana), and perverted conduct (mithya-caritra). We shall now record in brief the objections of the Jaina philosopher against the view that perverted knowledge alone is the cause of bondage. Vidyanandi sums up the implication of the position of the upholders vledge alone as the cause of emancipation as follows: The philosophers who hold that knowledge alone is the ole cause of emancipation must have to admit that the exhaustion, by enjoyment, Page #189 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 152 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. of the operative karman which is responsible for the embodied existence is only an ancillary condition of emancipation. The soul remains embodied for a while even after it has attained the knowledge of the truth (tattva-jnana) in order to enjoy the fruits of the operative karians. The Sankhya maintains that the self (purusa) remains embodied for some time, even after the attainment of perfect knowledge, due to the residual traces of dharma (religious merit) etc. just like the revolution of a wheel due to momentum even after the actual impetus has been withdrawn. The Vaisesika upholds that the soul has to exhaust, by enjoyment, the stored merit (dharma) and demerit (adharma) before it attains final emancipation on the rernoval of its nescience (ajnana). The Vedantins also admit the existence of embodied beings who are free from bondage (jivanmukta). The Buddhists too have to admit some interval between the dawning of truth and the attainment of emancipation (nirvana). Vidyanandi now asks: 'How is that enjoyment of the fruits of the operative and stored) karmans possible? Is it done (automatically) in due time? Or is it due to special effort?' He who has realized the truth (tattva-jnana) does not accept rebirth for the enjoyment of the residual karmans, and therefore he has to enjoy the karmans in that very life. And this implies capacity for special effort to enjoy the karmans before time. Otherwise there would be no emancipation in all times to come. The karmans which generally give fruits in different births are to be enjoyed in this very life, for it is unanimously admitted that one who has realized the truth does not take rebirth for the enjoyment of these karmans. This enjoyment of fruits before due time presupposes an effort on the part of the soul. And this effort is a type of caritra. The Yoga admits enjoyment of the accumulated karmans by a special kind of effort. That special effort is nothing but the practice of samadhi (meditation and ecstasy). Special powers are achieved by samadhi. By these powers, one creates a number of bodies and enjoys the fruits of the accumulated karmans by means of them. The Naiyayika also admits the creation of a plurality of bodies (kayavyuha) for the enjoyment of the karman which is in course of fruition (prarabdha) for the sake of speedy attain 1 Cf. phalopabhogena sancitakarmanam praksayah samyag-jnanasya muktyutpattau saha kari jnana-matratmaka-moksakaranavadinam isto na punar anyo 'sadharanah kascit-TSIV, p. 66. In this passage sancita should be interpreted as operative (prarabdha) karman. 2 Vide supra, p. 100. 3 Vide supra, p. 112. 4 sa ca phalopabhogo ya thakalam upakramavisesad va karmanam syat -TSIV, p. 66. 5 Cf. yasmad upakrama-visesat karmanam phalopabhogo yogino 'bhinnatah Sa samadhir eva tattvatah sambhavyate, samadhav utthapita-dharma-janitayam ddhau nana-sariradi-nirmanadvarena sancita-karma-phalanubhavasye 'statvat -TSIV, p. 66. See also YD, IV. 4 with Bhasya. Page #190 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. IX] AVIDYA IN THE JAINA SCHOOL 153 ment of emancipation (apavarga). The Brahmasutra too admits that the prarabdha-karman is to be destroyed by enjoyment (bhoga). It is thus admitted by all that the soul remains embodied for some time even after the realization of the truth (tattva-jnana), and some of them also admit the efficacy of yoga or samadhi to enable one to enjoy the fruits of the karmans before the due time of their fruition. The continued embodiment of the soul even after the realization of the truth implies that there is yet some defect to eradicate. The Jainas maintain that this defect is to be eradicated by samyak-caritra consisting in the third and the fourth stages of sukladhyana,3 which corresponds to the final samadhi of the Sankhya-Yoga and the Nyaya-Vaisesika. We are thus led to admit mithya-caritra-consisting in non-abstinence (avirati), passions (kasaya), spiritual inertia (pramada), and activity (yoga)-in addition to perverted cognition (mithya-jnana) as the condition of worldly existence. If perverted cognition were the only condition of worldly existence, there must occur final emancipation immediately on the attainment of complete and perfect knowledge. But as the soul continues with its embodied existence for some time even after the attainment of complete and perfect enlightenment, it has got to be admitted, as has been shown, that there was some other defect that did not disappear with the disappearance of the perverted cognition. This defect is the absence of the total stoppage of physical activities (technically known as yoga in Jaina philosophy). The perfect state is to be achieved by the perfection of all the three viz. predilection or attitude (darsana), knowledge (jnana), and conduct (caritra). The perfect conduct is attained when all the activities cease and the soul attains final emancipation. Until then the bondage exists. Moreover, if the perverted cognition alone were the condition of the worldly existence, there would be no enlightened person to reveal the truth. Vidyanandi says: 'Those who maintain that perverted cognition (viparyaya) is the main cause of worldly existence (bhava) cannot (logically) postulate the existence of the enlightened one living in the world." How can one exist in the world when the condition of existence therein is not present? Viparyaya or the perverted cognition was the condition, and that condition is not present in the enlightened one. How can he then continue to exist in the world? If it is contended that on the attain ment of complete and perfect knowledge there is only further nonorigination of new perverted cognition while the past perverted 1 See Bhasya on NS, III. 2-19. MM Phanibhusana Tarkavagasa's Nyayaparicaya (2nd edition), p. 18. 2 See BS, IV. I. 19. 3 Infra, Chap. V. Section II, last paragraph but three. 4 maulo hetur bhavasye 'sto yesam tavad viparyayah tesam udbhutabodhasya ghatate na bhavasthitih.-TSIV, p. 72. JP_20 Page #191 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ [CH. cognition due to past demerit still continues and so the existence in the world is not incompatible with the attainment of perfect knowledge, then it would follow that there yet exist defects (dosa) originating from the perverted cognition (viparyaya), unseen potency (adrsta) originating from the defects, birth (janma) originating from the unseen potency, and manifold suffering (duhkha) originating from birth. It is again a self-contradiction to say that the past perverted cognition exists and not its consequences such as defects, unseen potency, and the like, because why should the cause continue to exist and not produce its effect without anything to impede its natural function?1 There were both perverted cognition and its effects present in the past, and how can now there be only the perverted cognition and not its effects too? Of course, a cause can exist without its effects if any of the auxiliaries be absent or an obstructive factor be present to thwart its activities. But it is not true of those causes which are self-sufficient. Perverted cognition (viparyaya) cannot be conceived to have existence without its effects making up the worldly existence because you cannot point to the absence of an auxiliary condition or the presence of an impediment which can suspend its activity. Perverted cognition and realization of the truth are incompatible and so cannot coexist even as darkness and light cannot coexist. There can be no perverted cognition when there is realization of the truth. It, therefore, follows that the existence in the world even after the attainment of the knowledge of the truth is not due to the perverted cognition. There must be some other condition of it. Vidyanandi says that there are some who distinguish between two kinds of perverted cognition (viparyaya): (1) the original one possessed of the potency of producing predilection for the untrue, attachment (raga) etc., and (2) the last or dying one that is devoid of such potency. The original perverted cognition produces defects (dosa) of the nature of predilection or inclination for the untrue. Defects produce demerit (adharma). Demerit produces birth (janma) which again is responsible for the worldly existence (samsara) fraught with miseries. The last or the dying perverted cognition, however, is impotent and cannot be the condition of worldly existence. Vidyanandi asserts that this position is not different from that of the Jainas. The upholders of this position have to admit threefold conditions of the worldly existence (bhava). Perverted cognition 154 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA 1 Cf. samutpanna-tattva-jnanasya 'pi asesato anagataviparyayasya 'nutpattir na punah purvabhavopattasya purvadharma-nibandhanasya, tato 'sya bhavasthitir ghatata eve 'ti sambhavanayam... tatsthiter eva pramanatah siddhehTSIV, p. 72. 2 Cf. vitathagraha-ragadi-pradurbhavana-saktibhrt 3 maulo viparyayo na 'ntya iti kecit prapedire-TSIV, p. 72. 3 Cf. tesam prasiddha eva 'yam bhavahetus trayatmakah sakti-trayatmatapaye bhavaletutyahanitah-TSIV, p. 72. Page #192 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. X] CRITICISM OF THE SAMKHYA-YOGA AVIDYA 155 (viparyaya), in this view, means what is possessed of the potency of producing perverted predilection (mithyabhinivesa), attachment (raga) etc., and is the condition of worldly existence. This, when analysed, turns out to be the threefold condition of the nature of wrong attitude (mithya-darsana), wrong cognition (mithya-jnana) and wrong conduct (mithya-caritra); because the potency of perverted predilection is nothing but the wrong attitude, the perverted cognition itself-being an untrue cognition--is wrong cognition, and the potency for producing attachment (raga) etc. is wrong conduct. It is thus maintained by the Jainas that all these three-wrong attitude, wrong cognition and wrong conduct should be regarded as the condition of worldly existence. And the condition of worldly existence being threefold, the condition of emancipation also should be regarded as threefold. Vidyanandi says that the threefold conditions of the worldly existence, such as wrong attitude (mithya-darsana), and the like, require threefold antidotes such as right attitude (samyag-darsana) and the like for their cessation. Or, in other words, the unitary condition of worldly existence, having threefold potencies, requires for its annihilation another unitary condition consisting of threefold counter-potencies.3 We have now stated the Jaina conception of the threefold cause of bondage and its threefold antidote. We also recorded the objections of the Jaina against those who maintain a unitary principle as the cause of bondage. Now let us see how far the metaphysical position of those who regard nescience (ajnana) alone as the cause of bondage is consistent with their conception of nescience. Let us begin with the Sankhya-Yoga. X CRITICISM OF THE SAMKHYA-YOGA CONCEPTION OF AVIDYA In the Sankhya-Yoga school the relation between the world. process and the purusa is not a very concrete one. The world process somehow belongs to the purusa who enjoys it though keeping quite 1 ya eva viparyayo mithyabhinivesa-ragadyutpadana-saktih sa eva bhavahetur na nya iti vadatam prasiddho mithya-darsana-jnana-caritratmako bhavahetuh, mithya-'bhinivesasakter eva mithya-darsanatvat, mithyartha-grahanasya svayam viparyayasya mithya-jnanatvat, ragadi-pradurbhavana-samarthyasya mithyacaritratvat-Ibid. 2 Cf. tadvipaksasya nirvana-karanasya trayatmata-TSIV, p. 74. 3mithya-darsanadinam bhavahetunam trayanam pramanatah sthitanam nivrttih pratipaksabhutani samyag-darsanadini triny apeksate, anyatama paye tadanupapatteh; sakti-trayatmakasya va bhavahetor ekasya vinivartanam pratipaksabhuta-saktitrayatmakam ekam antarena no 'papadyata iti yukta Sutrakarasya trayatmaka-moksa-margopadesana-TSIV, p. 74. Page #193 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 156 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. unaffected by and aloof from it. The school does not attempt at defining the relation between the world process and the purusa. Somehow the purusa appears to have become one with the prakrti and to enjoy it. Everything, good or bad, belongs to the praksti, and the purusa is there only as an indifferent onlooker. The process is conceived as evolving for the interests of the purusa, but there is hardly any serious attempt made at showing how the prakrti establishes its contact with the purusa or, alternatively, how purusa identifies itself with the prakrti. Avidya or nescience is held as the cementing bond between the two. Here again it is left unexplained how avidya, which belongs exclusively to the prakyti, can get the purusa involved in the process. In the ultimate analysis, avidya is an indefinable impetus that creates motion in the prakrti to evolve itself in endless processes for the purpose of the purusa. Neither the purusa knows how his interests are being fulfilled by these processes, nor does the prakyti move with the prevision of a well-defined plan. The world is an ordered unfolding with definite designs. But the order and the design is a work of the prakyti which has neither vision nor any interest of its own. The Sankhya-Yoga fails to account for the ordered movement of prakrti. The purusa does not direct the prakrti and so the order and the design cannot be held to have come from him. It is a wonder how the movements of the prakyti are coordinated with the interests of the purusa. The relation between the purusa and the prakyti is only a make-believe. It is only an appearance. Avidya is conceived as a link between the two which can never be linked a bridge between the two which can never be bridged. It is a principie which keeps the prakyti in motion with the purusa as its witness. The purusa appears as involved without being really so.' It ever remains as it is. It is the prakyti that knows, thinks, and wills under the influence of avidya and it is again the prakrti itself that retires to the state of eternal motionlessness by destroying the seed of avidya. If the Sankhya-Yoga gives any importance to the purusa as a partner in the world drama, it does so only to give a semblance of reality to the universally accepted fact of bondage of the soul. The whole speculation loses its meaning if the fact of bondage is not admitted. But the fundamental hypothesis of the SankhyaYoga system does not warrant the acceptance of bondage for the purusa. And consequently it becomes impossible for the system to account for the constant urge for emancipation and the means prescribed for the fulfilment of that urge. The Yoga prescribes yogic practices and the Sankhya lays stress on the knowledge of the truth. But is not all this in vain in view of the fact that the purusa, in reality, always remains out of the world? Is there any need or justification for 1 Cf. tasman na badhyate na 'pi mucyate na 'pi samsarati kascit samsarati badhyate mucyate ca nanasraya prakstih.SK, 62. Page #194 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ In. x] CRITICISM OF THE SAMKHYA-YOGA AVIDYA 157 earnest striving for the release of the prakrti which is only an unconscious instrument of fulfilment of the interests of the purusa? Moreover, the prakrti remains as it is with reference to other purusas even after it is released with reference to a particular purusa. What then is the meaning of emancipation for the praksti? It is a selfcontradiction to say that the prakrti is emancipated with reference to a particular purusa while it remains in bondage with reference to all others. There is, again, no ground for maintaining that there are as many prakytis as there are purusas. There are of course some adherents of Sankhya who believe in the multiplicity of prakytis, each assigned to each purusa. But though it effects an improvement in the sense that the emancipation of one purusa does not involve the retirement of prakyti from cosmic activity and thus the continuity of the world process is not snapped asunder, yet it leads to unnecessary complexity. In the first place, the postulation of a number of prakrtis is itself a cumbrous hypothesis and the postulation of one prakrti answers the requirements of the law of parsimony. In the second place, the plurality of the prakrtis cannot be supposed to remain unrelated inter se as that would rob the objective world of every claim to independence. The main ground for believing in the objective independence of the material world is that it is public property to which all the purusas have the same or similar relationship. In the third place, if a common objective cosmic principle were posited to comprehend all these microcosmic worlds within its sweep, the objections urged against the unitary prakrti as the cosmic prius would remain unanswered. In the fourth place, the postulation of the plurality of the prakrtis will only be a restatement of the atomic pluralism of the Nyaya-Vaisesika school which the Sankhya system is supposed to transcend by the postulation of a unitary cosmic principle. Though Vijnanabhiksu has sought to reduce one prakrti to a plurality of atoms, it cannot be regarded as the orthodox representation of Sankhya ontology. All the arguments showing the unity of the nature of material, that is, unspiritual things as partaking of threefold character will be reduced to futility. The argument for the repudiation of atomic pluralism that infinite mass cannot be produced out of infinitesimal atoms and that the material cause must be greater than the product in magnitude will lose all meaning if the unitary prakrti were nothing but a congeries of atomic units each independent of and isolated from the other. Fifthly, the explanation of creation as evolution as opposed to conglomeration of units which is the position of the Vaisesika will have no force and cogency if the world could be deduced from a plurality. Lastly, the question would arise whether the infinite praktis are ubiquitous and infinite in magnitude or not. If each prakyti be ubiquitous and all-pervading, it is difficult to conceive how Page #195 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 158 [CH. one prakrti can coexist with other prakrtis without clash and collision. If, on the other hand, they are regarded as atomic in magnitude, then the theory of satkaryavada which affirms the pre-existence of the effect and denies the possibility of the emergence of an unprecedented fact will have no raison d'etre since it will have to be admitted that a big thing can be produced out of small things. The Sankhya has regarded this as an impossibility as the emergence of a bigger magnitude will presuppose the annihilation of smaller magnitude. So the postulation of an infinite plurality of prakrtis apart from the natural objection due to its cumbrousness is incompatible with the basic postulates of the Sankhya metaphysics. PROBLEM OF AVIDYA There are other technical difficulties in the Sankhya-Yoga view. Avidya is regarded as the condition of bondage. Bondage lasts as long as the avidya lasts. Bondage is destroyed when the avidya is destroyed. And the avidya can be destroyed only when the knowledge of the truth dawns. The knowledge of the truth thus is the cause of emancipation. The Sankhya-Yoga holds that this knowledge also is absent after emancipation. But is it logically sound to hold that the condition of emancipation should disappear on the attainment_of emancipation? Driven to desperation the Sankhya-Yoga holds that the disappearance of the final knowledge of the truth is the condition of emancipation. But then another difficulty crops up. If disappearance of the knowledge of the truth is the condition of emancipation, should it not then be admitted that even the knowledge of the truth is not efficient enough to bring about the emancipation? What then is the difference between ignorance (ajnana) and knowledge (jnana) with reference to emancipation? Is not knowledge as much inefficient as ignorance as a means to emancipation? Is not knowledge itself a state of prakrti in bondage? The Sankhya-Yoga cannot logically maintain that ignorance alone is the condition of worldly existence. Ignorance, knowledge, and everything else are all states of the prakrti in bondage. None of them can be regarded as the non-condition of worldly existence. Emancipation, in the ultimate analysis, turns out to be an automatic eternal quiescence of prakyti. And we have stated the difficulties about this quiescence even. The prakrti, somehow related to purusa, is the bondage of existence. Cessation of all relation with the purusa is emancipation. Viewed from the side of the purusa, emancipation consists in purusa existing in its own nature. From the side of prakrti, emancipation consists in prakrti in its state of eternal equilibrium. Prakyti and purusa attain this state when the seed of avidya is completely destroyed. The purusa takes interest in the prakrti so long as there is avidya. Prakrti destroys avidya and becomes enlightened by its own efforts. The Sankhya-Yoga does not define the function of the purusa in the attainment of final enlightenment. Purusa is inactive Page #196 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. x] CRITICISM OF THE SAMKHYA-YOGA AVIDYA 159 consciousness intelligizing the prakrti. Final enlightenment is a state of the prakrti comprehending the truth of the separate identity of purusa from itself. On the comprehension of this truth, the prakyti can no more keep the purusa interested in itself, and consequently stops its processes and retires into the background. The function of the purusa is simply to intelligize and to this extent he is responsible for emancipation. Intelligizing, however, does not mean any effort on the part of the purusa. It is automatically effected by the peculiar relation which the avidya establishes between the purusa and the prakrti. If the purusa is responsible for anything in the drama, it is this element of intelligizing. We can also ascribe the coordination of the movements of the prakyti with the interests of the purusa to this element of intelligizing. But we do not find any clear statement of such a conception in the Sankhya-Yoga system. The principle of purusa hangs very loose on the system. Although this purusa is of the nature of consciousness, the functions of knowing, thinking and willing do not belong to him. The Sankhya-Yoga system intended to preserve the immutable character of the purusa by keeping him free from all functions whatsoever. But it did so at the cost of a number of other difficulties. Acarya Hemacandra has summed up some of the weak points of the Sankhya-Yoga as follows: 'Consciousness does not know the objects, the buddhi is unconscious. Space and the like evolve out of the subtle elements of sound and the like. Bondage and emancipation do not belong to the purusa. And what else selfcontradictory has not been composed by the stupid (Sankhyas).'! Referring to the non-knowing nature of the purusa, Vidyanandi says: 'If purusa is of the nature of non-knowledge, how could Kapila be the instructor (of the truth), even like one in deep sleep. The prakyti also being unconscious, like a jar, cannot do the function of instruction.'2 How can consciousness. (citi) be without knowledge (jnana) and the knowing buddhi without consciousness? How can the purusa enjoy the prakrti if he is absolutely immutable? Haribhadra refers to the following explanation of Vindhyavasin and Asuri the famous exponents of the Sankhya school: 'The purusa, himself remaining immutable, makes the unconscious mind assume its own form because of the proximity, even as a reflection makes a crystal (assume its own form). The enjoyment of the purusa is said to consist in such transformation of the distinct principle of buddhi, just like the appearance of the 1 cid arthasunya sa jada ca buddhih sabdaditanmatrajam ambaradi na bandhamoksau purusasya ce 'ti kiyaj jadair na grathitam virodhi.-AYV, 15. yady ajnana-svabhavah syat Kapilo no 'padesakrt susuptavat pradhanam va 'cetanatvad ghatadivat.-TSIV, p. 18. Page #197 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ [CH. image of the moon in the transparent water'1 and records this criticism: 'In view of the formlessness (of the purusa), even the appearance of his image is not possible. Moreover, if it is conceded that the purusa is imaged in the buddhi, this concession should be extended to the emancipated purusas also. Enjoyment, therefore, is never possible. Nor is it improper to maintain that the emancipated ones should also be imaged, because they have the same nature (as they had before emancipation, since they are immutable). Again, if it were (conceded) that there is difference in their nature, it would necessarily follow that there was change. Moreover, if the purusa is absolutely different from the body, there would nowhere be any occasion for (the sins of) killing and the like. In the absence of (the sins of) killing and the like, there would be no bondage, good or bad, owing to the lack of its cause. In the absence of bondage, there would be no worldly existence or emancipation of the purusa. In the absence of emancipation all (efforts) such as vows and the like would be useless."2 We have thoroughly discussed the problem of reflection of purusa in the buddhi while stating the Yoga conception of avidya" and shall not repeat it again. The serious objection against the doctrine of reflection has been recorded by Haribhadra. How can a formless principle reflect itself? Nor can the Sankhya-Yoga avoid the criticism by saying that the conception of reflection is only for the sake of easy understanding and popular illustration, or in other words, only a metaphorical way of stating the fact. Because in that case the world process will turn out to be a magical show devoid of any essence. Either the purusa must have some concrete relation with the prakrti or the whole evolution of the prakrti should be condemned as an illusory nothing. There must be some difference between the emancipated and the unemancipated. But if the purusa be absolutely immutable and unchanging, there can be no scope for difference of states. If emancipation itself be only an appearance there is absolutely no meaning in spiritual endeavours. The Sankhya-Yoga attempts at explaining away the difficulty of the 160 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA 1 puruso 'vikrtatmai 'va svanirbhasam acetanam manah karoti sannidhyad upadhih sphatikam yatha. vibhaktedrkparinatau buddhau bhogo 'sya kathyate pratibimbodayah svacche yatha candramaso 'mbhasi. -SVS, 221-2 with Svopajna Commentary. 2 pratibimbodayo 'py asya na 'murtatvena yujyate muktair atiprasangac ca na vai bhogah kadacana. na ca purvasvabhavatvat sa muktanam asangatah svabhavantarabhave ca parinamo 'nivaritah. dehat prthaktva eva 'sya na ca himsadayah kvacit tadabhave 'nimittatvat katham bandhah subhasubhah. bandhad rte na samsaro muktir va 'syo 'papadyate yamadi tadabhave ca sarvam eva hy aparthakam.-SVS, 223-6. 3 Vide supra, pp. 85-9. Page #198 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. X] CRITICISM OF THE SAMKHYA-YOGA AVIDYA 'For relation of purusa and prakrti may appear as high and lofty philosophy to those who are fond of metaphysical speculations, but they have little fascination for the Jaina philosopher who is a staunch realist and has a deep conviction about the reality of his own experience. The Jaina philosopher believes in concrete relation between the soul and the body. And Haribhadra is even reluctant to believe that the great sage Kapila could have propounded that bondage and emancipation belong to prakrti and not to the purusa. Haribhadra says: 'The ancient sages have declared emancipation of the purusa in the Tantra."1 Then stating that the Jaina conception of purusa and his relation with karma-prakyti (karmic matter) is not liable to censure, he says: this reason the (Sankhya) doctrine of prakrti also should be accepted as true, and also because it has been propounded by Kapila who was a great sage of godly character."2 Haribhadra means to assert that the original doctrine of Kapila was not different from that of the Jainas. The Sankhya-Yoga conception of the condition of emancipation has been reinterpreted by Vidyanandi. Asamprajnata-samadhi (state of concentration in which self is intuited as it is, free from conceptual constructions) is the ultimate condition of emancipation. The purusa exists in its own state in this samadhi. "This samadhi', says Vidyanandi, 'which consists in the existence of the purusa in its own state and is the condition of the final emancipation is nothing else than the threefold jewels-samyag-jnana (right knowledge) being the nature of the purusa, tattvarthasraddhana (predilection or love for the truth) being the necessary concomitant of it, and the absolute indifference (of the purusa) being the parama-caritra (consummate conduct).' And consequently the nature of Sankhya avidya is also to be interpreted as identical with mithya-darsana (perverted attitude), mithya-jnana (perverted knowledge) and mithya-caritra (perverted conduct). These are in brief the logical difficulties and implications of the Sankhya-Yoga system. Let us now estimate the value of the NyayaVaisesika conception of avidya. 1 purusasyo 'dita muktir iti Tantre cirantanaih.-SVS, 231.. 2evam prakrtivado 'pi vijneyah satya eva hi Kapiloktatvatas cai 'va divyo hi sa mahamunih.-SVS, 237. 3 yad api drastur atmanah svarupe 'vasthanam dhyanam paramamuktinibandhanam tad api na ratnatrayatmakatam vyabhicarati samyag-jnanasya pumrupatvat, tasya tattvartha-sraddhanasahacaritatvat, paramaudasinyasya ca parama-caritratvat-TSIV, p. 18. JP-21 161 Page #199 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 162 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA XI CRITICISM OF THE NYAYA-VAISESIKA CONCEPTION OF AVIDYA The Nyaya-Vaisesika conception of avidya also is vitiated by a number of defects. Knowledge is only a transient quality of the soul, produced by soul-mind contact. Emancipation means permanent destruction of the specific qualities of the soul such as knowledge (buddhi), pleasure (sukha), pain (duhkha), will (iccha) and the like.' Wrong cognition (mithya-jnana) of the twelvefold objects (prameya) is the condition of worldly existence and the right knowledge of them leads to emancipation. In emancipation, however, there is neither wrong cognition nor right knowledge. Right knowledge destroys wrong cognition and disappears itself, being as much a transient quality of the soul as the wrong cognition. The worldly existence lasts so long as there is the delusion of the indentity of the soul with the body, sense-organs and the like, and comes to an end when the true nature of the body, the sense-organs etc. is comprehended and the soul loses attachment to them due to the knowledge of its separate identity from the things of the world. Wrong cognition causes attachment to the world while right knowledge removes it. Wrong cognition degrades the soul to the status of matter, while the right knowledge reinstates it in its own status. But now the difficulty is: How can a passing quality bring about such momentous result? If knowledge is only a transient quality quite separate and distinct from the soul, is it reasonable to maintain that it is the condition of emancipation? Properly speaking, knowledge has very little to do with the nature of the soul. In spite of the fact that the Nyaya-Vaisesika regards the qualities of knowledge, pleasure, pain etc. as exclusively the properties of a soul, it cannot be said that these qualities constitute the nature of the soul. How can what is alienable constitute the nature? What remains if the nature is alienated? Knowledge is not the nature of the soul, because it is alienable from the soul. Wrong cognition and true knowledge qua qualities of the soul have the same status. The latter supersedes the former, and disappears itself when the soul gives up its relation with body and mind and attains emancipation. It is difficult to conceive [CH. 1 Vide supra, p. 112. 2 Cf. atma-sarire-'ndriya-'rtha-buddhi-manah-pravrtti-dosa-pretyabhava-phaladuhkha-'pavargas tu prameyam (NS, I. 1. 9.). Vatsyayana, commenting on this sutra, says: asty anyad api dravya-guna-karma-samanya-visesa-samavayah prameyam tad bhedena ca 'parisankhyeyam. asya tu tattva-jnanad apavargo mithya-jnanat samsara ity ata etad upadistan visesena iti. 3 Vide supra, p. 106. Page #200 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XI] CRITICISM OF THE NYAYA-VAISESIKA AVIDYA 163 If how these qualities can be responsible for change of nature. bondage and emancipation are real facts, it must be conceded that the soul undergoes change of nature. And the qualities of wrong cognition and true knowledge, being not the constituents of nature, cannot be held responsible for the change of nature. If there is real difference between the states of worldly existence and emancipation it must be conceded that the nature of the soul in bondage is different from the nature of the soul which has attained emancipation. But what are the factors that are responsible for this change? The Nyaya-Vaisesika answer is that in the state of worldly existence the soul has the specific qualities of knowledge, pleasure etc. while in the state of emancipation it has none of these qualities. But is it a proper explanation? The qualities, as we have stated above, cannot be regarded as constituting the nature of the soul, and as such it is improper to regard their absence alone as change of nature. The Nyaya-Vaisesika makes capital out of its conception of the relation of inherence (samavaya). The qualities are related to the substance in the relation of inherence. The Nyaya-Vaisesika fights shy of admitting the qualities as forming the nature of the substance, and as a result indulges in the conception of inherence which is obviously only a device to avoid the difficulties and not a solution proper of the problem. The doctrine of inherence involves a number of serious difficulties. If a quality is absolutely different from its substance, it is not logical to say that it belongs to the substance. Inherence cannot be considered as the link between the two, because it is not given in experience. Do we cognize inherence as separate and distinct from the quality and the substance? Supposing that the inherence is given in experience and also supposing that a quality inheres in the substance in the relation of inherence, one would naturally ask: In what relation does this inherence subsist in the substance? If the inherence is regarded as subsisting in the relation of another inherence then there will obviously be regressus ad infinitum and the quality will ever remain unrelated to the substance. It is, again, not logical to maintain that the relation of inherence between the inherence and the substance is only a make-believe and not a real one. Acarya Hemacandra states some of the defects of the doctrine of inherence in the following way: 'There cannot be the relation of dharma (adjunct) and dharmin (substantive) between two things if there is absolute difference between them. Nor can (the relation) subsist by means of inherence because the trio (of dharma, dharmin and inherence) is not perceived. (If on the basis of the experience 'A dharma subsists in a dharmin' it is admitted that there subsists the relation of inherence between them, then this also must be conceded that) there is the experience of 'It is here' even with reference to the inherence. (But the opponent cannot concede this in view of the Page #201 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 164 [CH. inevitable contingency of regressus ad infinitum). Nor can the difference (between one inherence and another) be only a metaphorical one. There is, moreover, contradiction of the popular usages (such as "There are threads in a cloth' and the like which do not recognize inherence).' This doctrine of inherence furthermore leads the NyayaVaisesika to a number of other absurd conceptions. A universal (samanya) cannot inhere in another universal, nor can it inhere in the ultimate particulars (visesas) nor again in an inherence. Accordingly, the Nyaya-Vaisesika holds that existence (satta), being a universal, does not belong to the categories of universal, particulars, and inherence. It exclusively belongs to the other categories of substance (dravya), qualities (guna) and actions (karman). Besides this, it is held that knowledge and pleasure, being as much the qualities inhering in a soul as wrong cognition (ajnana), pain (duhkha) and the like do not belong to the soul on the attainment of emancipation. How can the transient qualities which are quite distinct and separate from the soul belong to it when it is free from all defiling attributes? Knowledge and joy do not arise in the emancipated soul because there is no soulmind contact. Vatsyayana maintains that even as the poisoned sweets are unacceptable, exactly so the joy, invariably being mixed up with pain, is unacceptable. He has to condemn all joy as mixed with pain perhaps in order to explain away the impossibility of the existence of joy in emancipation. Acarya Hemacandra sums up these defects when he says: 'Even of the existents, only some have existence. Consciousness is only adventitious and absolutely different from the soul. Emancipation is not attended with knowledge and bliss. The heretics have composed excellent system indeed!' The main objection of the Jainas is against the absolutistic attitude. Knowledge, joy etc. cannot be absolutely distinct from the soul. They constitute the nature of the J na dharma-dharmitvam ativa bhede vrttya 'sti cen na tritayam cakasti ihe 'dam ity asti matis ca vrttau na gaunabhedo 'pi ca lokabadhah.-AYV, 7. See also Syadvadamanjari on it. For detailed criticism of samavaya see PKM, pp. 609-623; SVR, pp. 965-970. 2 Cf. sad anityam dravyavat karyam karanam samanya-visesavad iti dravyaguna-karmanam avisesah-VS, I. 1. 8. Also cf. VS, I. 2. 7. See also PB, p. 121 dravyadinam trayanam api sattasambandhah. 3 Cf. santah khalv ayam sarva-viprayogah, sarvoparamo 'pavargah. bahu ca krcchram ghoram papakam lupyata iti katham buddhiman sarvaduhkhocchedam sarva-duhkhasamvidam apavargam na rocayed iti. tad yatha, madhuvisasamprktannam anadeyam iti, evam sukham duhkhanusaktam anadeyam iti -Bhasya, NS, I. 1. 2. See also Bhasya, NS, I. 1. 22. 4 satam api syat kvacid eva satta caitanyam aupadhikam atmano 'anyat na samvidanandamayi ca muktih susutram asutritam atvadiyaih-AYV, 8. 1 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA Page #202 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XI] CRITICISM OF THE NYAYA-VAISESIKA AVIDYA 165 soul. The Jainas admit that they are ever changing and renewing in the state of worldly existence. But that does not mean that the soul can remain without them at any time. According to the Jainas, a quality cannot belong to the substance without becoming its nature and being. Change of quality does not mean destruction of nature. An entity preserves its nature through change. The qualities also preserve their identities through their ever changing modes. The relation between the substance and its qualities is one of identity-cum-difference. The element of identity explains the experience of persistence while the element of difference explains the experience of change. The Jainas thus avoid the difficulty of the status of knowledge and wrong cognition in the making up of the nature of the soul. Knowledge constitutes the nature of the soul while wrong cognition is only a transient mode of it. Wrong cognition (ajnana) passes away when right knowledge (samyag-jnana) dawns. But right knowledge does never pass away, being the nature of the soul. Consciousness is the very essence of the self, and is integral to it. Though change is integral and inherent in whatever is existent and as such the self also must be perpetually changing, the change in the emancipated state does not connote absolute diversity in such a way as change from consciousness to un-consciousness. In fact, consciousness is the very stuff and texture of the self and is never liable to lapse. Even in the state of bondage there is not a single moment in which the self ceases to be conscious. Bondage only means, according to the Jainas, the limitation of consciousness to what comes through the channel of the senses. The infinite possibility of the expansion of consciousness is always there. It is only the mind and the body and the senses which shut up the self within a prison, and infinite intuition and knowledge are not allowed to materialize, not because consciousness in bondage is incapable of this consummation but because the embodiment serves to intercept the world of reality from the self. The Jainas accordingly do not believe that knowledge is produced by the good offices of the senses, but that it is innate in it. The senses rather are the handicaps than instruments. Ignorance and delusion are not innate but induced by the karmic forces. But whatever be the magnitude and intensity of these obstructive veils, they never succeed in extinguishing the eternal light of consciousness of the self. In emancipation, the self and its consciousness which are inseparable though not interchangeable, are released from these barriers and therefore can function over the whole range of reality. This is called omniscience. What has been said of the cognitive aspect of the self can be affirmed with equal emphasis of the other aspects and powers such as bliss and energy. The self is possessed of infinite energy and bliss as a matter of inalienable right. It is the karmic obstructions Page #203 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 166 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA (CH. which kept them suppressed. With the disappearance of these external forces, the self recovers its infinite capacity and bliss. The Jaina, however, does not assert that the limitations of bondage are illusory. They are real facts. But they can be overcome and transcended in emancipation. The changes are real changes. The apprehension of the Sankhya that the possibility of change of the self might spell total subversion of consciousness by unconsciousness is regarded by the Jainas as baseless. Change is always limited in scope. Even the Sankhya has to admit that although prakrti is subject to perpetual change it does not change from existence to non-existence because that would be tantamount to denial of change. Change is possible only if there be continuity behind it. So an existent is never found to be so changed as to become a non-existent fiction. Likewise, the self can never change into a totally unconscious entity because consciousness is as inalienable a characteristic of the self as existence is affirmed to be of matter. It is a question of fact as to what is to be regarded as the inalienable essence of an entity, and what is to be regarded as an evanescent character. So the self, though in perpetual change, can never become not-self. Change is integral to it no doubt, but so also are its existence and consciousness and bliss. It may be asked 'Does the self change after emancipation?' The Jaina will answer 'Yes, it does.' But as there is no external interfering agent the change is always homogeneous. It may be regarded as an incessant renewal of its perfected being. But as renewal presupposes continuity, there is no lapse from consciousness, existence, bliss and power. Let us now consider the technical difficulties in the NyayaVaisesika conception of avidya. The Nyaya-Vaisesika, like the Sankhya-Yoga, regards wrong cognition (ajnana) as the cause of bondage. There is emancipation when the wrong cognition is destroyed. But how can the wrong cognition be destroyed in view of the infinitefoldness of the things to be known (jneya)? Vatsyayana himself admits the impossibility of knowing all the objects when he says: "The knowledge of truth (tattva-jnana) does not arise with reference to all the objects severally, inasmuch as the objects are infinite. Nor does it arise with reference to some objects (at random), because then delusion (moha) would still exist with reference to those objects that have not been comprehended (by the knowledge) and so there will be the undesirable consequence of existence of the residuum of delusion; and also because it is not possible that the knowledge (tattua-jnana) with reference to something should remove the delusion with reference to something else. Wrong cognition (mithyajnana) indeed is delusion (moha). It is not simply the absence of the knowledge of truth (tattvajnana). And that object, the wrong cognition about which is the seed of worldly existence, is to Page #204 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XI] CRITICISM OF THE NYAYA-VAISESIKA AVIDYA 167 be known in its true nature.'! The nature of the body, the senseorgans, and the like alone is to be known in order to destroy the attachment to them. Emancipation is attained when the delusion about these things is gone and freedom from the defects (dosa) is achieved.2 Now the difficulty is if wrong cognition (ajnana) is the condition of bondage how is it that the knowledge of a limited number of things is efficient enough to destroy the bondage in spite of the existence of wrong cognition about so many other things? Wrong cognition cannot be totally removed because the objects of cognition are infinite. And how can there be emancipation if there is the least of wrong cognition? Wrong cognition is invariably and necessarily accompanied with bondage, and there cannot be total destruction of wrong cognition unless omniscience is achieved. Omniscience, however, cannot be achieved unless all the objects are known. In other words, if wrong cognition is the invariable, necessary and unconditional cause of bondage, there can never be emancipation because there can never be omniscience, and without omniscience the bondage cannot be destroyed. The Nyaya-Vaisesika believes in wrong cognition as the invariable cause of bondage and at the same time does not regard omniscience as the pre-requisite of emancipation. This is responsible for the difficulty of emancipation. Samantabhadra has put this logical difficulty in an aphoristic and pregnant language as follows: 'If bondage is the necessary concomitant of ignorance (ajnana) there cannot be a being free from bondage because of the infiniteness of the objects (to be known). If the knowledge of a few objects is responsible for freedom (from bondage), the vast amount of ignorance (about other objects) is responsible for the reverse.'3 The Nyaya-Vaisesika position is not consistent enough with its original proposition. If ignorance or wrong cognition is held as the necessary, invariable and unconditional cause of bondage, it is of necessity to be granted that omniscience is achieved before the bondage is destroyed. But the Nyaya-Vaisesika does not admit that omniscience is necessary for emancipation. The Jainas, on the other hand, do not regard wrong cognition (ajnana) alone as the necessary and unconditional cause of bondage. Samantabhadra says: 'Wrong cognition accompanied with delusion (moha) is the cause of bondage. From wrong cognition devoid of delusion, there i na tavad ekaikatra yavadvisayam utpadyate jneyanam anantyat na 'pi kvacid utpadyate, yatra no 'tpadyate tatra 'nivitto moha iti mohasesaprasangah, na ca 'nyavisayena tattvajnanena 'nyavisayo mohah sakyah pratiseddhum iti. mithyajnanam vai khalu moho na tattvajnanasya 'nutpattimatram tac ca mithyajnanam yatra visa ye pravartamanam samsara-bijam bhavati sa visayas tattvato jneya iti-Bhasya, NS, IV. 2. 1. 2 For detailed information vide supra, pp. 106-7. 3 ajnanac cet dhruvo bandho jneyanantyan na kevali jnanastokad vimoksas ced ajnanad bahuto 'nyatha-Aptamimarzsa, 96. Page #205 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 168 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA is not bondage (bandha). There can be emancipation from knowledge about a few objects, provided it is devoid of delusion (moha)." Bondage depends upon delusion. If there is delusion, there is bondage. If there is no delusion, there is no bondage. Here delusion (moha) means the deluding (mohaniya) karman2 and not wrong cognition. On the destruction of this deluding karman, bandha (bondage) is no more possible and omniscience necessarily dawns. The Jainas do not give much importance to knowledge in the attainment of freedom from bondage. The soul is to be purified of the mohaniya (deluding) karman, that is, of the karmans that defile and vitiate the attitude and the conduct of the soul. If this purity is attained, knowledge naturally dawns. Knowledge is the nature of the soul, and as such cannot but dawn when the soul is made absolutely clean of the karmans that obstructed the perfect expression of vision and conduct. We have given a faithful representation of the Jaina's criticism of of its the Naiyayika's conception of emancipation and the means attainment. In fairness to the Naiyayikas, it must be admitted that they have been fully cognizant of the necessity of moral purification and the purgation of all evil dispositions and volitional tendencies which characterize the impure and imperfect life in bondage. The Naiyayikas have, however, laid emphasis upon the supreme efficacy of correct knowledge of reality for the achievement of this objective. They think and assert that with the dawn of the knowledge of the true nature of the self, all our volitional perversities and angularities and moral twists will become automatically straightened and corrected and the cessation of bondage will occur without a hitch. The Jaina here differs from the Naiyayika. He does not deny that true knowledge is an essential condition of salvation, but he asserts that the moral regeneration, which is also recognized by the Naiyayika to be the condition of salvation, cannot be an automatic product of knowledge. It is necessary to cultivate moral perfection by means of various penances and practices of asceticism to get rid of our immoral and volitional dispositions and perversities. The Jainas make moral discipline and subjugation of the will a coordinate condition of salvation along with knowledge. This seems to be an essential divergence of the Jainas from the Naiyayikas. [CH. Another point of divergence about the means is that the Jainas stress the necessity of omniscience as the antidote of ignorance and 1 ajnanan mohino bandho na 'jnanad vitamohatah jnanastokac ca moksah syad amohan mohino 'nyatha-Ibid., 98. 2 Mohaniyakarman mainly consists in mithyatva (perversity) and the kasaya (passions). Vide infra, Chap. IV. Section III, 2nd paragraph. 3 This refers to sthitibandha and anubhaga-bandha which are due to Vide infra, Chap. IV. Section III, 3rd paragraph. kasaya. Page #206 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XII] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA 169 think this to be an essential precondition of final emancipation. We have already given Uddyotakara's defence of the Nyaya position as to how even limited knowledge can be the instrument of salvation. Vatsyayana and Uddyotakara both believe that knowledge of all existent things is not possible of achievement with the limited resources at the disposal of the spiritual aspirant. If omniscience were the prerequisite of salvation, it would mean the impossibility of its achievement, because the number of existents being infinite, the knowledge of the same could be achieved only in infinite time, and to insist on this as the condition of salvation would be tantamount to the repudiation of the possibility of emancipation. It is apparent from the line of argument adopted by these writers that they did not believe in the possibility of infinite knowledge accruing from the practice of yogic discipline. It is certain that acquisition of infinite knowledge is impossible in the course of a human life if the spiritual aspirant is to depend on his senses and understanding. But if supernormal vision of truth on the removal of the barriers of knowledge can be achieved by a course of spiritual exercise, then the difficulties apprehended by Vatsyayana and Uddyotakara will have to be regarded as based upon ignorance of the hidden powers of the soul. In later writings of the Nyaya-Vaisesika school, the infinite knowledge by means of yogic powers is admitted as a possibility. The Jaina criticism of the Nyaya standpoint is confined to the views of the earlier exponents of the school. It may not be entirely amiss to hazard the conjecture that the admission of omniscience as the result of yogic discipline by the later writers of the school may have been necessitated by the criticism of the older position by rival philosophers such as the Jaina and the like who not only believe in the possibility of omniscience but also make it a condition of emancipation. XII CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA CONCEPTION OF AVIDYA We now come to the criticism of the Vedanta conception of avidya. That we are subject to ignorance is admitted by all schools of thought. It is equally admitted that the existing condition of the world and of the selves is not perfect and the individual selves are responsible for this. But whereas ignorance and its concomitants-delusion and allied passions and propensities are usually held to be indirectly and remotely responsible for the objective world order, and are believed to be directly instrumental in the emergence of the imperfect condition of the subjects with their volitional, emotional, and cognitive limitations, the Vedanta has made ignorance the prius of the subjective and the objective order of existence. Ignorance is not only a contributory JP-22 Page #207 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 170 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. condition of the world order but, in association with the eternal Brahman, is the material cause of the world also. Brahman, being limitless existence, consciousness, and bliss with no difference, intrinsic and extrinsic, in its being, is a unity perfect, solid, and simple. The plurality of the phenomenal world, which is experienced by all and sundry, and the existence of which is not liable to be repudiated without blatant self-contradiction, cannot be deduced from the simple homogeneous unity. The Vedantists accordingly postulate an allpervading maya, which is the principle of cosmic illusion, and accord it a timeless status along with Brahman, although it is recognized to be liable to destruction and as such held to be a subordinate adjunct to the Absolute with which it is associated. The Sankhya conception of prakyti is accepted in toto with this essential reservation that it is held to be subordinate to the Absolute, independently of whom it has no existence, and is again held to be quasi-real in character. It is not real like the Absolute though it is unborn like it, because it is subject to annihilation. But it is not an unreal fiction as it has causal efficiency which a fiction cannot have. Thus it is held to be neither ultimately real nor absolutely unreal and thus eludes logical determination. Logic demands that if A is not real it must be unreal. But maya as the basis of the cosmos, subjective and objective, is not capable of being classed under either of these exclusive heads. Its existence is not liable to be repudiated because it is a felt fact. Though logically indeterminable as a real, and not capable of being dismissed as an unreal fiction without contradiction of experience, the actuality of the world appearance and consequently maya as its presupposition has got to be acquiesced in, however offensive it may appear to our logical thought. The Vedantist holds that reality must be rational and logically consistent. Only that is real which possesses existence as an intrinsic and inalienable character. The real is that which exists on its own account and in its own right. It cannot be made real by anything external. The real therefore cannot lapse from its reality, and so cannot change, because change implies the cessation of a previous state and the accrual of a novel condition. But as the sole character of a real is its reality, the cessation of any element in it will mean the lapse of reality and the acquisition of a character which was not real before. This means that a real can cease to exist and an unreal can come into being. There is obvious contradiction in this conception and so the Vedantists affirm that change is not predicable of the ultimate reality. But change is a felt fact, and has to be accounted for. The Vedantist asserts that change and all that it connotes do not belong to reality, but they appear in and upon the Absolute owing to its association with maya which is responsible for the appearance of multiplicity and plurality in spite of the fact that they cannot be real. Reality is again defined to be one Page #208 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XII] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA 171 which is not capable of negation in temporal or spatial reference. This ition is rather the corollary of the basic proposition that a real is possessed of reality on its own account. The logical necessity underlying this conception is the incompatibility of unity with plurality, of reality with change, of the timeless with the temporal. The existence of plurality and of the underlying unity is felt and as they cannot be logically reconciled the plurality is declared to be a false appearance, however unjustifiable its actuality may be from the logical standpoint. The two cannot be real. Either there must be unity or plurality, and as plurality is nothing but plural unities, the concept of unity cannot be got rid of even in the affirmation of plurality. So unity being indispensable is to be asserted as the sole reality when and if we have to clip away one of the pair. In reply to this contention of the monist, the Jaina asserts that the reality of plurality is not capable of being repudiated as false appearance. The assertion of absolute unity and the denial of plurality are both contradicted by the verdict of experience. It is therefore a dogmatic statement and if a mere ipse dixit were to do duty for truth, then the assertion of plurality as the only reality might also lay claim to the rank of truth. It has however been contended by another school of Vedantists viz. that of Bhaskara that the plurality of phenomena is not inconsistent with the unitary Absolute because even one entity can appropriate different attributes, as either the difference of time or space may account for the incidence of different qualities and actions in one and the same entity. Therefore the Absolute also need not come in conflict with the appearance of different qualities and actions happening in it. It is just on a par with the cognition of a multi-coloured object, which though diverse in respect of the multiplicity of colour is still felt as a unitary entity. But the question is whether the multiplicity is real or not. If it be real it has to be decided whether it is possessed of a real genesis. It cannot be asserted that the plurality is destitute of origination because that would make the fact of their occasional and contingent appearance unintelligible. A thing which does not originate is not a contingent occurrence. If however origination is admitted, then it must have a cause. If the Absolute be asserted as the cause, then you will have to admit that there are two things viz. cause and effect. It cannot however be maintained that the effect is not different from the cause and so monism is not affected by the assertion of causality, because this assertion is open to twofold objection. Firstly, the identity of the cause and the effect would make the admission of the same thing qua cause as the same thing qua effect inevitable which 1 Cf...ekam api parabrahma sakala-kriya-karaka-bhedatmakataya na virodham adhyaste tathapratibhasa-vaicitrye 'py ekatvavyaghatac citra-jnanavad ity aparah-Astasahasri, p. 157. Page #209 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 172 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. is absurd. Secondly, the identification of the Absolute with the contingent effect would make the former a contingent fact, a position which is denied by the Vedantist. It may be asserted that the plurality of phenomena derives its genesis from something different from the Absolute. But this would be tantamount to the assertion of dualism, as a cause numerically different from the Absolute is posited. The Vedantist may contend that this cause of the phenomenal world is nothing but an unreal maya and the assertion of such an unreal fact does not militate against real monism. But we cannot accept the defence, because an unreal cause is a contradiction in terms. In fact causal efficiency is the criterion of reality. It may be contended that the effect is also unreal appearance and so there is no logical repugnance in the postulation of an unreal cause. But the question may be seriously posed 'Why should the felt plurality be dismissed as unreal? An unreal fiction is not amenable to experience. It is not found that fone fiction produces another fiction on the basis of which we could imagine that the appearance of plurality is produced from unreal maya. It is not observed that a square circle produces a square triangle.'1 The Vedantist may rejoin 'Well, what about feats of magic? The magic produces a phantasmagoria which nobody accepts as truth on sober reflection. Yet the appearance deceives the spectator so long as it lasts.' But the show of magic, whether it be fire or smoke or anything else, is not entirely unreal. At any rate the experience of it is real. If the experience itself were unreal there would be nothing to determine that there was a magical show at all. Nor can it be maintained that the show is unreal qua an existent fact, because even on the admission of the Vedantist there is no lapse of existence even in false experience.2 There must be an objective basis even for what is called an unreal appearance. This basis is admitted to be true even by the Vedantist himself. This shows that however one may dispute the objectivity of the predicative part of the false judgment, the subject at any rate has got to be admitted as real. We cannot even conceive that an unreal fiction can appear as a content of experience. We have never experienced even in dream a square circle. As regards erroneous perception, neither the subject nor the predicate is absolutely unreal like a square circle. The Vedantist may contend that he does not affirm that the objective world of plurality is an unreal fiction. But it is not real as it is found to be contradicted by a subsequent experience. But the question is 'Does not the denial of unreality involve the admission of reality?' A thing may be either 1 Cf.... katham akincidrupasya karanatvam? karyasya 'py akincidrupatvad adosa iti cet kim idanim kharavisanad asva-visanasya janma 'sti-Ibid. 2. Na 'pi bahihsaddravyadi-rupayor maya-svabhavatva vyabhicaritvabhavat-Ibid., p. 158. Page #210 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ TII. XII] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA 173 real or unreal and there is no tertium quid possible because of the Law of Excluded Middle. The Vedantist has argued that he admits all this. Logically speaking there can be no intermediary stage between two contradictorily opposed terms. Regarded in this light, the content of error cannot be dismissed as an unreal fiction because even appearance is possible only of what is real. But the contradiction of the content of error such as silver is not compatible with its reality as this would result in the obliteration of the cleavage between truth and error. The Vedantist accordingly asserts that the content of error is neither real nor unreal. It is different from both these determinations in spite of its illogicality. Though, logically speaking, nothing but real should appear we have to acquiesce in the proposition that in error at any rate the content cannot be real because it is contradicted and it cannot be absolutely unreal because it appears. It is admitted on all hands, both by the Vedantic idealist and the realist, that an unreal fiction like a square circle has no appearance. The world of plurality is on the same footing with content of error because it appears and is also contradicted by logical thought. TIT The Jaina does not accept this interpretation of error as the only possible explanation. The content of error is not an unreal fiction and that shows that it must be real, whatever be the context. The Jaina philosopher, like the Naiyayika realist, thinks that the predicate of the erroneous judgment 'This is silver' is a real entity really felt. The experience is real and so also its content. It is false because it is contradicted by subsequent experience. But contradiction does not prove the unreality either of the subject or of the predicate. Owing to some defect and aberration the two reals existing in different contexts are felt to be related, though they are not so related in the relevant context. The fact cannot be gainsaid even by the Vedantist that it is exactly analogous to a veridical perception so far as the reality of the terms and also of the relation are taken into account. The relation also is not a fiction, because it is felt, and a fiction cannot be felt. What constitutes the falsity of the judgment then? The answer is that though true in every respect, as the contents including even the relation between them have corresponding objective counterparts, owing to a defect the predicate appears to belong to the subject though in the present context the predicate does not belong to it. The Vedantist has however admitted a third term in between real and unreal, which is neither endorsed by logic nor by experience. The Vedantist has not succeeded in denying that an unreal fiction cannot appear. The logic demands that if the content of error be not unreal, it must be accepted as real. The invention of a quasi-real entity is not only uncalled for but also logically contradictory. The Jaina Page #211 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 174 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. philosopher does not agree with the Vedantist or with the nihilist in his reading of contradiction in the world of experience and of thought. The Vedantist and so also the arch-nihilist Nagarjuna think that causality is an irrational principle. They agree that the cause is not identical with the effect as that would annul the distinction between them, and without this distinction nothing can be regarded as a cause or as an effect. The cause again cannot be different from the effect as in that case there would be no determination possible. If the relation of cause and effect be one of otherness, pure and simple, then it passes one's understanding why should oil be produced from mustard and not from sand though both are equally other than the effect. Similarly with regard to the effect. Why should not another effect be produced from a cause different from the accustomed one when there is nothing to determine either the effect or the cause? No specific relation can be affirmed in the absence of identity and otherness which have been found to be unacceptable. Nor can it be regarded as a combination of both as the objections lying against each would apply together against this hypothesis. It is concluded by the sceptics that causality is a logically indeterminate makeshift. It is a device contrived by the human intellect to lull into slumber our logical curiosity. It is an irrational conception which, however, is unquestioningly accepted by the general mass of mankind owing to nescience which blurs the whole outlook. In conformity with this dialectic the Vedantist, in common with Nagarjuna, thinks that there is irreconcilable antagonism and conflict between plurality and unity. We have seen how the Vedantist conjures away plurality as false appearance and affirms unity as the supreme truth. The nihilist, on the other hand, has declared the whole world as an unmitigated illusion including unity and plurality. The Vedantist argues against Nagarjuna and men of his ilk that existence and consciousness cannot be denied because the denial of existence itself involves the affirmation of the existence of denial, and the denial of consciousness is possible only if there is consciousness of denial. And this involves, according to the Vedantist, a contradiction on the part of the nihilist who denies consciousness and content with equal emphasis. But the Jaina would pose a simple question: Why should the unqualified denial of existence involve contradiction?' The answer must be that existence of denial is felt in the act of denial. Likewise the denial of consciousness is found to be in conflict with the felt consciousness of denial. The contradiction therefore amounts to not a priori self-contradiction as is involved in the assertion of a square circle, but to a conflict based on experience. Existence and consciousness are experienced facts, and the denial of them involves contradiction of experience and its verdict. So the Vedantist virtually Page #212 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 111. XII] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA 175 admits that contradiction is the criterion of truth so long as it does not come in conflict with our indubitable experience and its data. Unity and plurality are equally felt facts, and causality is also a plain deduction from experience. So it is not possible to accept a theory which will contradict the very possibility of the data. As regards the logical difficulty of their relation, the Vedantist also admits that unity and plurality are felt as related though he demurs to accept it as an ultimate truth on account of the logical contradiction. He however is not prepared to dismiss it as a fiction, because he has the courage of his conviction to assert that an unreality cannot have even an appearance of reality. He accordingly gives it the status of a quasireality. But the Jaina avers that this is neither fish, flesh, nor good red herring. The Vedantist should overcome his diffidence and muster courage to declare that it must be real as it is not unreal. As for the logical incompatibility between unity and plurality, and identity and otherness, it is nothing but the figment of abstract logic which runs away from the reality as revealed in experience. It has been seen that the Vedantist entirely relies upon experience when he denies the contention of the nihilist that unity is equally a false appearance as it is never felt in dissociation from plurality. The nihilist also denies the reality of consciousness as he denies the reality of its content, because in his view consciousness without a content and a content without consciousness are never felt, and so they must swim or sink together. From the standpoint of abstract logic, the nihilist's argument seems to be unimpeachable. The Vedantist succeeds in refuting the nihilist's contention only by positing contradiction of experience as the criterion of falsity. The Jaina asks the Vedantist to go a step further and accept the whole experience as true and admonishes him for accepting the dictates of a priori abstract logic in the interpretation and assessment of experience. When unity and plurality are equally felt, and identity and otherness are equally attested by experience, they should both be regarded as true. The Jaina admits, in common with the Vedantist, that the effect is not determinable either as identical with or as different from the cause. He agrees with the Vedantist in his contention that the combination of unity and plurality involves identity and otherness both. He also agrees with the Vedantist that the relation cannot be both identity and non-identity, otherness and non-otherness, difference and non-difference because of the contradiction involved in it. The Vedantist asserts that the world of appearance is accordingly indeterminable in terms of identity and difference, but its felt actuality places it in a different category which is not determinable either as identical with or as different from pure existence. The Jaina accepts this interpretation also. He thinks the world of experience involves both identity and difference. But it transcends and synthesizes them in a Page #213 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 176 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. separate category which is different from both identity and difference, The actual is real, and because the data of experience are neither identifiable with experience, as the Buddhist subjectivist avers in defiance of the plain verdict of experience, nor can they be regarded as unrelated which the assertion of absolute difference involves, the relation is, sui generis which is also admitted by the Vedantist to be the case when he asserts that the data of experience are indeterminable as identical or not-identical. But whereas the Vedantist would assert that the appearance is false, the Jaina would assert that it is true. The contradiction between identity and difference is not denied. But the Jaina does not think that the relation is of either kind. It is different from both, and its reality cannot be repudiated because it is felt to be actual. The denial of causality constitutes a flagrant violation of experience. When the Vedantist asserts that the effect is not produced by itself or by another, and yet cannot blink the actual production of the effect, he fails to render an explanation of it. He thinks that no explanation is possible and the confession of this failure only shows that he only pretends to slip over the problem. Certainly by declaring causality as unreal appearance he proves disloyal to experience. If the nature of reality could be determined by abstract logic, and that again in plain contradiction of experience, then there is no reason why should the Vedantist refuse to chime in with the Buddhist when he declares that there is no self. The Vedantist, as we have shown, cannot find flaw in the Buddhist's argument except by appeal to experience. The Vedantist appeals to dream experience in support of his position that the unitary self-identical Absolute appears as the plurality of phenomena. He asserts that the appearance of plurality is not impossible even when what exists in reality is the undifferenced unitary existence. It is argued that in dream a plurality of facts is experienced though it is one consciousness that only exists and is felt. It is one consciousness that is felt as many. The Jaina does not agree with this interpretation of dream experience. He asserts that if there be inherent opposition between unity and plurality the appearance of one consciousness as plurality even in dream is not possible. As regards the Vedantist's contention that only one consciousness appears as a plurality in dream, the Jaina thinks that it is an assumption unsupported by logic as well as experience. Even in dream as in wakeful experience, the consciousness of action is different from that of the agent. It is admitted even by the Vedantist that dream contents are produced by different memory-impressions and so the contention that there is no plurality of cognitions though there is plurality of contents in dream experience cannot be accepted to be a true estimate. As regards the appearance of plurality, the Jaina does not find any difficulty in it that a self-identical subject should experience Page #214 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XII] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA 177 it. The subject is endowed with an infinite plurality of powers, and by means of these he can experience a plurality of contents both in wakeful and in dream experience. It is found that one identical self is felt to exercise many acts and is felt by another self to be possessed of such manifold activities and attributes. There is no contradiction in it because it is endorsed by valid experience: There is no contradiction in the fact that the potter fashions a jar with his staff and eats his meal with his hand. There is no reason why should these experiences be asserted to be erroneous. The truth is that the difference of act and agent, substance and attribute, is not absolute. They are both different and not-different because this is the logical presupposition of all experience. It has been argued by the Vedantist that our perceptual experiences are false because they are cognizant of difference just as dream experience is. This inference is vitiated by self-contradiction because the factors of inference such as the probans and the example must in any event be regarded as true. If they are true, their difference also is true. And if all these conditions of inference are false and thus cognition of difference be declared to be false, the inference will not prove the thesis, because no true conclusion can follow from false premises.2 The Vedantist might contend that the premises are accepted to be true only on the assertion of the opponent who accepts them to be true, then this would amount to the admission of the truth of the cognition of the opponent as different from the self and thus all cognitions of difference would not be false. It has been contended that consciousness is a unitary principle and its unity is felt by itself. This felt unity contradicts the cognitions of difference and this contradiction proves that the said cognitions are false. Thus the felt plurality is contradicted by the evidence of such false cognitions. This very argument proves the reality of plurality because what contradicts and what is contradicted cannot be identical. Nor can it be contended that the relation between the contradictor and the contradicted is accepted only on the basis of the assertion of others, because that would make contradiction a faked one just like the assertion of the opponent which the Vedantist believes to be false. And if the unity of consciousness be accepted to be true on the ground of experience, there is no reason why should the plurality of contents be rejected as false, as the verdict of experience is found to impartially attest both the facts. As regards the contradiction between plurality and unity the Jaina does not find any one in the situation because he jagrad-dasayam iva svapnadi-dasayam api pumso 'nekasaktyatma. prakrtanumane paksa-hetu-drstanta-bheda-pratibhasasya 'mithyatve tenai 'va hetor vyabhicarat, tanmithyatve tasmad anumanat sadhyaprasiddheh -Ibid. JP-23 1 kasya kriya-karaka-visesa-pratibhasa-vaicitrya-vyavasthiteh-Ibid. 2 Page #215 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 178 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. does not believe that things are related either by way of identity or by way of difference. The relation is distinct from both and must be accepted to be true just like identity and difference. If, however, experience be the ultimate exponent of the nature of reality, it must be admitted that pure identity or pure difference is never experienced and as such cannot be real. They are only figments of abstract logic, and no instance can be adduced which exemplifies either of them. It does not require any logical elaboration to show the absurd consequences that will arise if a person believed in pure monism and consequently denied the reality of society and environment, and the next world and moral and religious laws. There will be no logical justification for the observance of social, moral, and political laws that are prescribed by the scriptures as well as the state. This will mean perfect deadlock and certainly a philosophy which leads to the subversion of all order and tends to destroy the whole fabric of social, moral and religious life and its institutions cannot be safely recommended to mankind. Not only this, there will be no distinction between good and bad action, heaven and earth, truth and error, and even bondage and salvation. The philosophy will defeat its purpose because it cannot induce any enthusiasm and activity for the transcendence of bondage and achievement of salvation which is paradoxically set up as the ultimate objective and goal.' The monist would, however, assert that all these charges are advanced against his philosophy only out of ignorance. Though the Vedantic monist affirms that only the Absolute which is pure existence, consciousness and bliss bereft of all finitude and limitation is the sole reality and plurality is unreal, it does not follow that the plurality does not appear or is not possible. There is not only the plurality of objects but also the plurality of subjects who, under the influence of nescience, believe that they are actually bound by the laws of nature and society and religion. So all these institutions and laws hold good for them, and there is no possibility for lack of moral and religious enthusiasm. The illusion of bondage and belief in the plurality are so much ingrained in mankind that only a philosophical discourse is not enough for their eradication. Unless and until the identity of the individual self with the Absolute is realized there is no chance for getting rid of this illusion. The monist not only believes in the efficacy of rites and ceremonies, of moral and religious discipline, and practice of asceticism, but also asserts that these courses of moral and religious discipline are he condition of the emergence of saving knowledge without which here can be no escape from the meshes of ignorance. 1 Cf. karma-dvaitam phala-dvaitam loka-dvaitam ca no bhavet. vidyavidya-dvayam na syad bandha-moksadvayam tatha. V Aptamimarsa, 25. Page #216 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XII] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA The Jaina would ask the monist: 'Why should you believe in monism and reduce moral and religious life to provisional validity as a makeshift and device for the achievement of the goal? Both the means and end are asserted by you to be destitute of ultimate reality. It is certainly extremely difficult to subscribe to the view that an unreal means can achieve reality, and falsehood can be the means of attaining truth. Why should ethical and religious life, not to speak of the natural world, be declared to be false? What is the logical justification behind this abnormal position which cuts away the very foundation of higher life and culture? The Vedanta philosophy seems to be a dangerous heresy not less than the Buddhist denial of soul.' The Vedantist would assert in reply that all this criticism is inspired by sentimentalism and intellectual cowardice which refuses to face reality because it will upset the prejudices and superstitions fostered by nescience from the beginningless time. We cannot determine the nature of reality without having recourse to logic. If all the organs of valid cognition converge upon a particular position and compel us to accept it as the truth, we have to bow our heads to the inevitable. There may be sentimentalists who will shirk their duty to face truth squarely and will try to multiply their ranks by dissuading vacillating people from pursuit of the enquiry of truth. The doctrine of monism is not a figment of diseased imagination. It is proved by inference and authority alike. The Upanisadic texts are the records of funded experiences of ancient seers and sages who realized the ultimate mysteries of existence by unerring spiritual intuition. They still stand as compelling evidence and as a challenge. These truths have been realized again and again by persons whose name is Legion. They are public property and if an honest enquirer screws up his courage and elects to undergo the preparatory discipline he can realize that truth exactly in the same way as a student of science can verify the truth of the scientific discoveries in a laboratory. But the appeal to scripture and even unquestioning faith in its validity are not of very much avail except as aid and incentive to experiment by future enquirers of truth. Besides, these texts will not carry conviction to those who are fixed in their beliefs and traditions which they have inherited from the community in which they are born. But scripture is not the only resource with the Vedantist. The Vedantist banks upon ratiocination as an equally potent instrument for the realization of truth. The unreality of an independent objective world is deduced from an analysis of even an ordinary empirical judgment. Take for instance the trite experience 'I see the pen.' What is the status of the pen? The pen is felt as an object no doubt. But it is felt as a content of the cognition. It is felt 179 Page #217 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 180 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. inside the cognition just as the character of cognitionhood. The realist may contend that the pen is an external object existing independently and is observed from outside. The act of knowing does not make any difference to it so far as its ontological reality is concerned. The pen existed and will exist even when there was and will be no cognizer to apprehend it. The Vedantist asserts that this attitude bespeaks sheer dogmatism. Certainly there is no ground for postulating the past and future existence of the object, and as regards the present existence of it, it can only be proved by valid cognition. Experience is the only source of knowledge of an existent, internal or external. The realists can affirm that the pen exists only when one is aware of it. Without awareness we have no means of asserting its existence. The contention of the realist that the object of experience stands outside and aloof proceeds from an unreflective attitude which does not care to look into the implications of knowledge. If the object that is cognized is external to cognition just as an uncognized object is, then how can it be determined that a thing is cognized or not cognized. To say that a thing is cognized is to say that it has come into relation with the subject's consciousness. Certainly there can be no relation between two things existing independently and aloof from each other. The relation therefore cannot be one of otherness. It must therefore be the opposite of it. And this means that the object, whether believed to be internal or external, is felt only as an internal content. The externality of the object is rather a guess and nothing more. It may be the case that the guess is universal. But that does not erect it into the rank of an accredited organ of knowledge. The object cannot be a content unless it somehow enters as an element into the cognition. So the logical analysis shows that the seeming brute existent is only an assumption. At the most optimistic estimate it cannot be more than a postulate. It might be contended that the object of cognition is different from the act of cognition irrespective of the fact whether it (object) is external or internal. But when it becomes a content of cognition, it seems to be taken inside and integrated with consciousness. But this integration is only a seeming appearance. But appearance is possible only if there be a veridical analogous fact and this is the ground of one thing being felt as another. When, for instance, the poet asserts the face to be the moon itself nobody is deceived by such assertion of identity. The real basis of this assumed identity is the identity of the moon with itself. Here also the identity of the cognition with the self is the basis of the seeming identity of content and cognition. But the Vedantist would 1 yat pratibhasa-samanadhikaranam tat pratibhasantahpravistam eva, yatha pratibhasa-svarupam-Astasahasri, p. 159. 2 atha pratibhasa-vyatiriktasya pratibhasyasya 'rthasya 'ntar bahir vo 'pacarat pratibhasa-samanadhikaranatvavyavasthiteh pratibhasa-svarupasya mukhya topa patteh-Ibid. Page #218 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. Xu] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA 181 observe that this is only the device of the escapist. There can be no relation at all between a cognition and an object unless the object is integrated with the cognition as its internal content. It has been shown that awareness is not possible if consciousness and object elect to preserve their autonomy which was supposed to be the status quo ante. The Vedantist however does not believe in the independent existence of the cognitum as there can be no proof of it. The Buddhist realist of the Sautrantika school believes in extra-mental reality. But as all existents are fluxional and perish in the immediately succeeding moment, there can be no synchronism between sense-intuition and its object. The object must come into contact with the sense and then intuition will take place. But as the intuition takes place in the second moment, the object cannot be there to be intuited as it has passed out of existence at the time. The Buddhist accordingly affirms that what is intuited is not the external object but its copy which is the content of the cognition. The external object is inferred as the cause of the content just as fire is inferred from smoke. This theory of the Buddhist is ght to be an unwarranted superfluity. There is no ground for believing in the extra-mental reality as a cause of the content and conversely for believing the content to be the effect of it. The external object is bound to remain unperceived in the Buddhist theory. So there is no occasion for observation of concomitance in agreement and difference between a content and the object. Thus how can the relation of causality be established between them? Moreover, the belief that cognition is produced is entirely unwarranted. Consciousness is an eternal fact. To say that it is produced presupposes that there is cognition of concomitance of the cause and effect behind it. So the production or the cessation of cognition can be affirmed only on the admission of another cognition. Cognition as such has got to be admitted as the condition of assertion. There can be no successful denial of consciousness as such, because the denial itself will be a case of consciousness. But it may be contended that though consciousness must be the inevitable condition of all assertion and the denial of it be made impossible by self-contradiction, yet there is no reason to suppose that consciousness is one identical, unitary and eternal reality. The exigency may be satisfied by asserting an uninterrupted stream of consciousness-units one following the other without a gap between them. In fact this is the position of the Buddhist fluxist. But the Vedantist thinks that this theory is absolutely false. What is the ground for distinguishing one cognition from another? A cognition of blue and a cognition of yellow are felt as cognition in spite of the difference of contents. The two acts are believed to be possessed of the common character viz. cognitionhood. So there can be no difference in respect of this cognitional character. The difference is felt only in respect of the contents. But Page #219 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 182 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH the Buddhist himself has had to admit that the content is not different from the cognition as they are felt together as a matter of universal necessity. This shows that the content and the cognition are not numerically different. The felt difference therefore is illusory appearance. Certainly the relation cannot be one of absolute identity as in that case the content and cognition should be felt either as cognition or as content. It cannot also be one of absolute difference because in that case there cannot be relation at all. So the relation is neither one of identity nor of difference but something other than both. But as the Law of Excluded Middle rules out the postulation of an intermediate stage between the two contradictorily opposed terms, the felt relation must be accepted to be false appearance. The content thus being incapable of logical determination in terms of identity or difference must be declared to be equally false. The false difference of false contents cannot therefore be supposed to affect the identity of consciousness. The Buddhist admits the uniformity of consciousness acts but does not believe in their identity. He also believes that there has been no occasion in the past in which consciousness could be non-existent because in that case the present consciousness-unit would not be possible. He will also have to admit that there will be no occasion in future when consciousness can become defunct. The unreality of consciousness at any moment will make each and all the conscious units unreal, because an unreal consciousness cannot have a real consciousness as its condition or as its effect. So continuity and uniformity of consciousness have been admitted by the Buddhist. His denial of identity of consciousness is inspired by his belief in the doctrine of soul-lessness. The Vedantist has asserted that there is no real ground for distinguishing one consciousness from another consciousness, as the only basis of such distinction viz. the plurality of contents has been proved to be unreal appearance. To return to the problem of the relation between cognition and object, the Buddhist theory of the causality of the object and cognition cannot be accepted. The Buddhist would infer the external object from the content of the cognition which he believes to be produced by the former. But as cognition is an eternal entity it cannot be the product of anything. So there will be no ground for inference of the external object. It has been contended by a school of realists that the external object is the basis of cognition and the two must be different. The Vedantist observes that this is a gratuitous assumption. It is under dispute whether our cognitions are directly conversant with an external object or not. To say that the external object is the basis of cognition is to assert the very problem in a different language. How do you know that it is the basis? If you answer that it is felt to be the object and Page #220 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XII] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA so is regarded as the basis, you will be guilty of circular argument. You assert that the external object is the cognitum on the ground of its being the basis of it, and when pressed with the question 'How do you know that it is the basis?' you answer 'Well, it is so because it is the cognitum'. This is clearly a fallacious argument. If one interprets that the cognitum is what is competent to be the objective basis of cognition, then we may answer that the basis is not anything different from the cognition itself. It is admitted by the majority of philosophers that our cognitions cannot exist uncognized and as an external cognizer is found to introduce complication, all cognitions are believed to be self-cognized. So there is no logical necessity for positing an external object as the content of our cognition. The identity of cognition and its content proves that there can be no object external to and numerically different from cognition. It has already been proved that consciousness is one, identical and eternal entity, and the plurality of objects has no existence outside consciousness. This constitutes the proof of the monist's position. It cannot be shown that the argument which proves the identity of consciousness and its content is inconclusive, because there is no fallacy in it. It is a felt fact that the contents are felt as integral determinations of cognitions and this is possible only if there be no hiatus between them. No instance can be adduced which can show that an object is cognized without being a content of the cognition. If you ask 'What is then the subject of the cognition?' we can only answer that it is the Absolute which is consciousness, pure and simple, that acts as the subject. The argument is in perfect agreement with the declaration of the Upanisad that all that exists is the Absolute. The plurality is only a false appearance created by nescience which, we have shown, is a contemporaneous adjunct of the Absolute. 183 As has been observed before, the Vedantist appeals to authority not for the establishment of his position but for additional confirmation of the finding of reflective thought. The monistic position is also independently established by inference. We have shown how the relation of cognition and content serves as a logical ground for establishing the identity of consciousness with the cognitum. But it may be argued that the attempt to establish monism by proving the unreality of difference is bound to fail because in a logical argument the difference 1 1 pratibhasalambanatvat pratibhasyo 'rtho bhavati 'ti cet, kutas tasya pratibhasalambanatvam? pratibhasyatvad iti cet parasparasrayanam-Ibid. 2 pratibhasalambanatva-yogyatvad iti cet tarhi pratibhasa-svarupam eva pratibhasyam. Ibid. 3 pratibhasantar-apravistasya kasyacid api pratibhasa-samanadhikaranatva'yogat-Ibid., p. 160. * na "erayasiddhir api hetoh sankaniya, sarvasya dharminah para-brahmana eva "srayatvat-Ibid. Page #221 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 184 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. of the subject, the probans, and the probandum is the very condition of the conclusion. So you start with the difference of the probans and the probandum as the premise and seek to deduce the unity of them as the conclusion. If you assert that the difference is only an illusion you cannot make it the ground of a true conclusion. Even if it be admitted for the sake of argument that the integration of the cognitum with consciousness proves its unity with the self, yet the difference between the probans and the probandum cannot be repudiated. The argument of the Vedantist was: The cognitum is incorporated within consciousness because it is felt as coincident with the latter (sc. consciousness). Now the act of cognition and the content are asserted to be integrated and incorporated with the self and this is the probandum and the fact of the content being coincident with the cognition is made the probans. Even if the validity of the conclusion be allowed, the numerical difference of the probans and probandum remains unrefuted, and this militates against monism. The Vedantist however asserts in defence that there is no difficulty as the dualism of the probans and the probandum is not presupposed as the condition. The two are identical, and yet they can serve as the probans and probandum just as is the case with existence and momentariness in the Buddhist argument. Things are momentary because they are existent. The probans is existence and the probandum is momentariness. It must be admitted that momentariness and existence are not ontologically different though conceptually they appear to be distinct. Likewise, the Vedantist does not believe in the ontological difference of the probans and probandum though in empirical thought they are conceived to be different owing to the influence of nescience. The Jaina realist avers that the assertion of ontological identity between the probans and the probandum has no justification. The Vedantist seeks to deduce the identity of the content and cognition logically from the felt coincidence of the two. The fact that they are felt as two should have made the Vedantist pause before he drew the conclusion of their absolute identity. If experience be the determinant of the nature of things it cannot be gainsaid that not only the probans and the probandum are felt as identical-cum-different, but also the conclusion viz. the integration of the content should be regarded as a case of identity-in-difference. Even the probans and probandum (sc. existence and momentariness) in the Buddhist argument are not felt as absolutely identical. The fact that one goes with the other necessarily is proof that they are not absolutely distinct and different. But the other fact that one is the probans and the other is the probandum, and as such is felt as distinct from the other should prove that the two are 1 Cf. sabdadau sattvanityatvayor api kathancit tadatmyat sarvatha tadatmyasiddheh, tatsiddhau sadhya-sadhana-bhava-virodhat-Ibid. Page #222 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XII] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA 185 not absolutely identical. From an honest and unbiassed reading of the knowledge situation it must be apparent that the probans and the probandum are identical and different together. The exponent of pure logic may scent incompatibility in it, but as pure logic is not endorsed in its findings by experience, it must be corrected and revised in the light of indubitable findings of experience. Accordingly in fidelity to experience it must be admitted that the relation of the probans and probandum is altogether different from identity and difference, though it contains them as moments. The absolute identity of the probans and the probandum on the contrary would make all inference impossible. The inference of identity of content and consciousness by the Vedantist on the ground of their invariable coincidence must therefore be rejected as ultra vires. With the collapse of inference as the proof of monism, the Vedantist will be deprived of logical proof, and in the last resort will have to fall back upon revelation (Sruti) in support of his position. But the question arises whether revelation recorded in the Upanisadic text is ontologically different from the Absolute or not. If it be absolutely identical with the Absolute Brahman which it seeks to establish, then revelation will be as much an unproved fact as the monistic Absolute which is yet to be established. Certainly the means of proof and the object of proof cannot be absolutely identical as in that case the two will be on the same level so far as they are not established facts. If on the contrary the two are held to be different, this will prove the dualism of revelation and Brahman at any rate. The monistic Absolute thus cannot be established either by inference or by appeal to revelation, and it is nothing but an unfounded assumption like the doctrine of absolute voidity of the Sunyavadin. Let us now examine the argument of the Vedantist. It has been argued that the content must be integral to cognition and incorporated in it, as cognition and content are felt to be coincident. But the felt coincidence, which is made the probans, itself reveals the momentous fact that the two are felt as distinct, and so the content cannot be regarded as absolutely integrated with the cognition. This integration is held by the Vedantist to be the proof of the negation of independent existence of the content. But this is a hasty interpretation. The fact that the content is felt as distinct from the cognition even when they coincide is a pointer to the truth that the content is not absolutely identical with the cognition. The Jaina agrees with the Vedantist when he asserts that the object cannot remain absolutely distinct and different from consciousness when it is cognized. The verbal proposition expressing the knowledge situation is of the form 'The pen is known'. The predicate knownness proves that the pen is not absolutely different from and so unconnected with knowledge. But the negation of absolute difference does not imply that the pen is absolutely made JP-24 Page #223 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 186 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. identical with knowledge. The proposition is entirely on a par with such factual propositions as 'The cloth is white'. In both the propositions e.g. 'The pen is known' and 'The cloth is white', the relation of subject and predicate is one of substance and attribute. The relation cannot be absolute identity as in that case it would be reducible to one of the terms, either the subject or the predicate. The relation is sui generis which may be called identity-in-difference for want of a better and more expressive name. It is undeniable that the terms are different though they are held together by a bond of unity. The Vedantist can at most prove that the content and the cognition are not absolutely different. The Jaina accepts this finding and explains it as a case of identity-cum-difference in which neither identity nor difference is absolute. Jaina holds the relation between the cognition and the object as equally a case of identity-in-difference. And he thinks that his interpretation is more consistent with truth than that of the Vedantist. The coincidence of the content with the cognition is intelligible only if the relation be identity-cum-difference. But what about the judgment 'The cognition per se is known by cognition'? Here the content of the cognition is its own self, and so the Jaina position that the relation of cognition and content is one of identity-cum-difference cannot hold in the present case. It is answered that if we look closely it will be found that the relation is one of identity-cum-difference. The content is not the act of cognition as such but its specific character. Cognition has both specific and generic attributes as constitutive of its nature. For instance, cognition is existent and this shows that it has the attribute of existence in common with all other entities. The attribute of cognitionhood is an uncommon characteristic. In the judgment the content is the specific character of cognition which (sc. the specific character) is not absolutely identical with the cognition. There can be no judgment or proposition possible if the terms are absolutely identical or absolutely different e.g. 'gold is gold' and 'the Himalya is the Vindhya' are not logical propositions. As regards the basic argument of the Vedantist employed to prove the identity of cognition and content, it can be upset by the following argument. Whatever is coincident with cognition is somehow different from the cognition concerned e.g. the nature of cognition itself. All the contents, internal and 1..... pratibhasa-tadvisayabhimatayoh kathancid bhede sati samanadhikaranatvasya pratiteh sarvatha pratibhasantahpravistatva-'sadhanat svavisayasya. na hi suklah pata ityadav api sarvatha guna-dravyayos tadatmye samanadhikaranyam asti-Ibid., p. 160. 2 sarvathabhedavat pratibhasa-svarupam pratibhasata ity atra 'pi na pratibhasa-tatsvarupayor laksya-laksanabhutayoh sarvatha tadatmyam asti pratibhasasya sadharanasadharanadharmadhikaranasya svasvarupad asadharanadharmat kathancid bhedaprasiddher anyatha tatsamanadhikaranyayogat suvarnar suvarnam iti yatha sahya-vindhyavad va--Ibid., pp. 160-161. Page #224 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XII] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA external, such as pleasure and the chair are coincident with cognitions. Therefore they must be somehow different from the cognitions concerned.'1 The same probans is found to prove a different conclusion from that intended by the Vedantist. Nor can monism be established by revelation. The meaning of the proposition 'All that exists is the Absolute' is not unqualified monism. In it the subject is 'all existents' which are revealed to us in knowledge and thus a known factor. The predicate is unknown. In all judgment the subject is a known fact and the predicate must be unknown. If the predicate were equally known with the subject, it would not be a judgment or a proposition.2 So the very form of a proposition implies that the subject and the predicate cannot be identical. The Vedantist therefore cannot establish monism even by appeal to authoritative revelation. It may be contended that the meaning of the predicate is self-identity which is realized by a subject in his own self and this self-identity is asserted of all that appears including self and not-self. The logical implication of the proposition therefore is the negation of the appearance of plurality as real. Thus interpreted the proposition is neither tautologous nor liable to signify dualism. The Jaina would observe that even if the interpretation be accepted to be true, the implication of dualism is inescapable inasmuch as the duality of revelation and the world appearance respectively as the negator and the negated remains uncontradicted.3 If on the other hand revelation were to be regarded as the essence of the Absolute, that also would not prove their identity as essence and possessor of essence must be numerically different. Nor again can selfintuition be regarded as proof of it because the proof must be different from the object of proof. If the Absolute were believed to be selfproved, why not plurality or voidity or the doctrine of universal illusion be accepted as the ultimate truth? The Vedantist has failed to advance any ground in support of his position, and his assertion is only dogmatic. If a dogmatic assertion can pass for truth, any other theory, be it of the nihilist or the materialist might claim allegiance. Suresvara has argued in defence that the Absolute is no other than the self of the individual, yet, owing to delusion, it is regarded as unknown and unperceived. The self is also nothing but the Absolute which is the only reality, yet it appears as a second entity in addition to the Absolute Brahman. The categorical assertion of the Upanisad 'The self is the Absolute' rebuts the illusion of imperceptibility and duality.. 1yat pratibhasa-samanadhikaranam tat pratibhasat kathancid arthantaram pratibhasa-samanadhikaranam sukha-niladi yatha sarvam-Ibid., p. 161. 2 sarvatha prasiddhasya vidhanayogad-Ibid. 3 Cf. kvacid atmavyaktau prasiddhasyai 'katmya-rupasya brahmatvasya katham advaitasiddhih. . .-Ibid, pratibhasa-svarupam, 187 ca Page #225 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 188 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. But the whole assertion is vitiated by ambiguity. What is the nature of the delusion which is asserted to be the outcome of nescience? Is nescience itself an unreal fiction or a real entity? If it be a fiction it cannot be the cause of illusion of imperceptibility or of duality, because a non-entity cannot have any causal efficiency. If on the other hand it is believed to be real, that amounts to the admission of dualism. So whatever be the line of approach or the angle of vision by which the denial of dualism of spirit and matter and the affirmation of the absolute unity of reality may be sought to be established the result becomes nothing but self-contradiction. If the monist is to prove his position by appeal to an accredited organ of knowledge, he unwittingly affirms the reality of two things: the Absolute and the proof of it. The Jaina refuses to agree with the Vedantist that truth can be established by falsehood which is the postulate of the Vedantist when he declares the whole logical and epistemological apparatus to be the figment of illusion. Furthermore, monism can be established only by the negation of dualism. In fact, Sankara, the founder of the school of monistic Vedanta, has called his philosophy the doctrine of non-dualism. The expression 'non-dualism' can convey an intelligible meaning only if dualism be understood. Now 'dualism' is a whole expression and stands for a whole concept. It can be asserted as a universal proposition that the negation of a whole concept presupposes the reality of the concept in some other context. Of course, there are such expressions as 'a square-circle' which do not stand for anything real, and its negation by such a negative expression as 'a non-square-circle' cannot be thought to presuppose the reality of the negatum. But this does no invalidate the universal proposition 'The negatum is always real'. The rule holds only in the case of whole words and whole concepts. A square-circle is only an attempt at combination of square and circle, and it becomes a fiction because the two concepts are mutually repellent. It is for this reason that the rule is propounded to hold good of whole concepts qua negata. Now monism qua negation of dualism is possible only if dualism be a false appearance. But dualism being a whole concept its negation will necessarily presuppose the reality of the negatum (sc. dualism) in some context or other.2 The Vedantist however is not convinced by such linguistic arguments. Even if dualism is regarded as a concept, its negation cannot be made the ground of its ontological reality. The negation of dualism does not in reality belong to the Absolute. The whole 1 mohasya 'vidyarupasya 'kincidrupatve paroksya-hetutvaghatanat sadvitiyatvadarsana-nibandhanatvasambhavat, tasya vastu-rupatve dvaitasiddhiprasaktes tata eva paroksya-sadvitiyatvayor badhanat pumarthe niscitam sastram' ity etasya 'pi dvaita-sadhanatvat... Ibid. 2 See AMi, 27. Page #226 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XII] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA 189 logical apparatus which is the creation of the professional logician is possessed of a provisional value. It is valid until the ultimate truth is realized. Its validity can thus be penultimate at the most optimistic estimate. But what is the necessity of negation of dualism and what again is the reason for the adoption of the logical apparatus for the establishment of monistic position by the Vedantist? The Vedantist answers that the whole order of plurality is an unreal show which has deceived the dualist and the pluralist into the belief of its ultimate reality. When the Vedantist tries to convince the dualist of his error he has to adopt the logical apparatus invented by the logicians of the realistic persuasion. The distinction of self and not-self is equally necessitated by nescience and is not to be mistaken as possessed of ultimate validity. So the charge of self-contradiction urged against the Vedantist is the outcome of misunderstanding. The Vedantist has got to employ these logical weapons not out of belief in their ultimate truth and validity, but as the only possible means of carrying conviction. These logical and epistemological devices hold good only on this side of final realization of the ultimate truth. And the Vedantist also has to offer his allegiance to them so long as he has to deal with the deluded philosophers of rival schools. The whole thing is nescience from beginning to end, and top to bottom. But what is the nature of nescience? This is the question which perplexes the opponent of monism. It is a real difficulty with him because he fails to understand with all the logical resources at his command why this nescience should be associated with the Absolute which is affirmed to be the only reality by the Vedantist. Let us now consider the nature and relation of nescience as expounded by Suresvara in the Bihadiaranyaka-bhasya-varttika. It is possible to conceive that the nescience, if it existed at all, can exist as the content of the Absolute or of the individual or as an independent entity. Now the first alternative is not conceivable. The conception of nescience in the Absolute which is of the nature of cognition and ex hypothesi omniscient involves selfcontradiction. Nor can it be supposed to subsist in the individual because the individual is not different from the Absolute and as such is free from all taint of nescience. How can nescience exist in the individual self which also is of the nature of pure cognition? Nor is the third alternative a tenable hypothesis, because nescience being an independent entity, like the Absolute, cannot be supposed to be annihilated by knowledge and so knowledge of the identity of the self and the Absolute which is prescribed to be the condition of salvation, being the eliminator of nescience, will have no purpose to serve. 1.... na ca sva-para-vibhago 'pi tattvikas tasya 'vidyavilasasryatvatAstasahasri, p. 162. 2 Sambandhavurttika, 175-182 quoted in Astasahasri, pp. 162-3. Page #227 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 190 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA Knowledge of identity is believed to lead to the perfect emancipation of the self, because it is assumed to be destructive of nescience which has induced bondage. But if nescience be an independent entity like the Absolute and be coeval with the Absolute from the beginningless time, it will be as eternal as the Absolute itself. And the bondage also will be an eternal fact. Suresvara answers that the nature of nescience cannot be determined by an organ of knowledge. Nescience is not capable of being determined by logic yet it cannot be denied that it exists. The individual feels that he is ignorant of many things. He is as certain of his ignorance as he is of his own existence. The individual is directly aware that he is a conscious being. So consciousness and existence are inalienable characteristics of the individual self. From the authority of revelation as well as the evidence of logic the self is known to be identical with the Absolute Brahman. And we have seen that nescience is not possible in the Absolute and the individual alike. Suresvara maintains that this is not the correct approach for determining the relation of nescience. To deny the existence of nescience would be contradiction of a felt fact. So, however irrational and illogical the concept of nescience may appear to be, its actual existence has got to be admitted by all. It is true that the conception of nescience as an independent entity is an absurd hypothesis. We find it from our study of the Upanisads that nescience is totally destroyed by knowledge of the reality. This is also the finding of incontestable experience. Our ordinary errors such as the perception of shell for the silver are found to be annihilated when followed by correct knowledge of the reality. This would be impossible and also unaccountable if nescience were an eternal verity. It must be admitted that there is no raison d'etre for error. It is possible only when the conditions of knowledge are given a false twist by something superadded to them. It is absolutely unintelligible why should there be a deviation from the normal standard. Certainly this deviation cannot be the normal law as this would make the emergence of correct knowledge and cancellation of the false knowledge preceding it an impossibility. What holds good of nescience operating in the individual must be true of it in its cosmic aspect also. So nescience cannot be an eternal verity like the Absolute. Nor can it be an independent entity as in that case there will be no ground for positing it. It is felt by us all that we are beset by limitations on all sides and we are not satisfied with our present condition. We always try to transcend it as an undesirable obsession. So nescience cannot have an independent existence outside consciousness. That it is an internal fact always felt in association with consciousness is also the finding even of the realists as we have seen in the course of our examination of the views of the Nyaya-Vaisesika and Sankhya-Yoga schools. It is regarded as a psychical fact and this shows its intimate [CH. Page #228 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XII] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA 191 relation with consciousness. The Vedantist believes that consciousness, absolute and undifferenced, is the only reality and is the very stuff and essence of all that exists and appears. The appearance of plurality according to the Vedantist is erroneous, and as such must have a reason of its own. This reason is found in nescience. And so the nescience is not only subjective but also objective because it is co-pervasive with consciousness in its entire range. Now the individual is not the seat of ignorance according to Suresvara for twofold reason. In the first place the individual is nothing different from absolute consciousness in point of reality. And if the individual be regarded as ontologically different from the Absolute, which is not however the position of any section of the monistic school, then also the individual cannot be regarded as the locus of nescience. The individualization of the self is itself the result of nescience and as such cannot be the determinant of the incidence of nescience which is its very presupposition. Nescience must have a local habitation of its own as the possibility of nescience as a floating entity has been found to be absurd. It must then have pure consciousness as its locus and abode and from the evidence of our own experience we find that nescience is a felt fact. This shows that pure eternal consciousness cannot be opposed to nescience. On the contrary it constitutes the only evidence of its being. Opposition is both a priori and empirical. The opposition of being and non-being is felt a priori. But other types of opposition are empirical and as such can be known only from experience. We have found that there is no opposition between pure consciousness and nescience, Pure consciousness means consciousness which is not determined by any objective reference. It is bereft of subject-object polarization. Pure consciousness thus means unpolarized consciousness. It is not relevant to our purpose to prove that unpolarized consciousness is possible though it is stoutly opposed by Ramanuja and also the realists of the Nyaya-Vaisesika school. The Sankhya-Yoga school and also the Jainas admit the possibility of pure consciousness at least in the final state of emancipation. Granted that there is no opposition between pure consciousness and nescience. But how to account for the opposition of nescience as error with knowledge? It is felt beyond the shadow of a doubt that our erroneous perception of shell as silver is cancelled and corrected by knowledge of the shell in its true character. Our knowledge of shell is attended with the negative judgment 'It is not silver'. This shows that there is opposition between knowledge and error which is nothing but a species of nescience. This has puzzled many a respectable philosopher and it has been seriously asserted that the Vedantist is guilty of self-contradiction. But this is due to their failure to distinguish between knowledge and pure consciousness. Pure conscious Page #229 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. ness is an eternal and transcendental entity. As regards nescience, it is also asserted by the Vedantist to be associated with the absolute consciousness which is pure and transcendental and undetermined by objective reference. There can be no difference in transcendental consciousness. The difference of one consciousness from another is only possible when it is made specific and particularized by objective reference, in other words, when it is possessed of a specific content and is called knowledge. Knowledge is consciousness in its essence, but it is different as a specific determination is from the genus. The opposition of error is with knowledge and not with pure transcendental consciousness which is rather the proof of it. Error is also a cognition with a distinct content and it is cancelled only by a cognition with an opposite content with reference to the same situation. It is the true cognition which cancels the false cognition. The true cognition is here called knowledge, and the false cognition error. The opposition only holds between them. 192 It has been argued by the opponent of the monist that there can be no nescience in the Absolute because of the a priori opposition between consciousness and nescience. But the opposition is not a priori, and so the argument has no validity. The very fact that we are conscious of nescience shows that there is no opposition between them. But though a felt fact and uncaused entity existing concurrently with the Absolute, nescience is not regarded as an eternal verity like the Absolute Brahman, because it is liable to be cancelled and corrected by the unerring realization of the nature of the self as identical with the Absolute. It has been shown that nescience is destroyed by knowledge from the example of common error and its correction. The Vedantist deduces from the fact the conclusion that nescience is not a reality in the true sense of the term. A reality is not capable of death or destruction. Nescience being liable to extinction cannot be regarded as a coordinate reality. But though not a reality, its actual existence is a felt fact and so cannot be denied without self-contradiction. The denial of nescience as well as its assertion is possible only within the limitation of nescience, because they are all judgments and as such have a dualistic reference. Of course, there can be no real relation between the Absolute and nescience. The Absolute is unattached and unrelated to anything within and without. But whatever be the ontological or logical character of the relation of nescience, its actuality cannot be disputed. Even an unreal relation is possible just as an unreal nescience is. A difficulty has been raised that the Absolute has been described as omniscient and certainly nescience is incompatible with omniscience. Anandagiri has anticipated this difficulty and given a solution. It is this. Omniscience does not mean empirical knowledge of all things, Page #230 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XII] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA 193 but the eternal perennial light of consciousness which makes all knowledge possible. So there is no logical repugnance in the unreal association of unreal nescience with it. By logical thought we can understand that this is not impossible, but the actual nature of it can be realized only by perfect knowledge. When nescience is destroyed by knowledge, it becomes identical with the Absolute. Nescience is a fact which refuses to be determined by logical thought. Nescience cannot be said to exist unless the Absolute qua transcendental consciousness is known. In other words, nescience cannot be felt without consciousness. But nescience also cannot be intuited as existent if the true nature of the Absolute as pure consciousness is realized. Moreover, who will be the knower of it-the person who suffers from nescience or who has emancipated himself from it? The determination of the nature of nescience is not possible for the person who is subject to its sway, because this will mean that he is not fettered by nescience. As regards the emancipated self, the logical distinctions of the subject, the object, and the act of knowledge have totally vanished for him for ever, and so such determination is not possible. An organ of knowledge is not competent to gauge unreality. It is only the real that can be determined y it. But nescience is ex hypothesi not a real because it does not stand the scrutiny of accredited cognitive organs. Nescience is called nescience because it is incapable of standing critical examination with success. In fact the criterion of nescience is nothing but this incapacity for standing the trial by accepted instruments of knowledge. But the question may be asked 'Why are we enamoured of such an irrational concept?' You have yourself admitted that it is not capable of being determined by the accredited organs of logic. Why don't you admit that the world is both different and non-different from the Absolute? Both you and myself admit the Absolute and the World, and the relation between them is asserted by us to be identity-cumdifference. The merit of this theory lies in the consideration that it does not entail repudiation of anyone of the felt facts--the world and its cause the Absolute. Why should you postulate an irrational and unreal principle as the cause of the world process? The Vedantist answers that after all his theory is the simplest of all. Secondly, it makes the postulation of a large number of irrational entities uncalled for. Thus the opponent who believes in the reality of the world process has to admit that it is both different and nondifferent from the Absolute. In the second place, he has to posit that bondage, though it is real and also uncaused, is liable to cessation. In the third place, he has to posit that emancipation is the product of 1 avidyaya avidyatve idam eva ca laksanam managhatasahisnutvam asadharanam isyate. -Sambandhavarttika, 181. Astasahasri, p. 163. JP-25 Page #231 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 194 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. religious and moral activity and is yet eternal. The monist only affirms nescience as the sole and sufficient condition of all these results. And though it exists from eternity alongside of and together with the Absolute, yet there is no logical difficulty in the fact that it is liable to annihilation, because it is felt to be unreal and so its disappearance does not entail logical contradiction which would be inevitable if it were real. But it might be argued that simplicity is not by itself a recommendation for a theory. If a multiplicity of things is necessitated by logical thought we cannot reject it for the sake of economy alone. But the Vedantist agrees that simplicity or multiplicity without the sanction of valid cognition is not a compelling consideration in the determination of reality. But if the multiplicity of categories asserted by the opponent is found to be contradicted by accredited sources of knowledge, the postulation of it will be logically indefensible. Now the believer in reality of the world has to assert that the relation between the world and its cause is identity and difference both-a conception which is repugnant to all sources of knowledge. Secondly, he admits that the worldly career is a reality bereft of beginning in time, and to say that it is annihilated by true knowledge is opposed to the universally accepted proposition that a real uncaused and undated. is eternal. Thirdly, it asserts emancipation to be the product of moral activity and yet to be eternal. This is opposed by the proposition universally accepted as true that whatever is caused to happen at a particular time cannot but be liable to extinction. These are the major contradictions in the theory of the opponent, and there may be many more, if minor details are to be taken into account. As regards the Vedantist's theory, it only postulates nescience and this is not also an unwarranted assumption since it is endorsed by experience and scriptural authority alike. The Jaina frankly confesses his inability to appreciate the argument of the Vedantist. In the first place, the postulation of nescience which the Vedantist himself admits to be incapable of any proof strikes him as an unphilosophical position. It is extremely puzzling that a philosopher should subscribe to a position which is not amenable to test by any accredited organ of knowledge. Whatever may be the subject of dispute, call it truth or untruth, science or nescience, the matter can be finally decided by means of the accredited sources of knowledge available to us. The Jaina does not dispute the existence of nescience, but he insists that this is also a matter of proof. When the Vedantist asserts nescience as an actual existent, he is certainly aware of its existence. And this awareness must be true and valid. Otherwise he 1 Cf. tvat-pakse bahu kalpyam syat sarvam manavirodhi ca kalpya 'vidyai 'va matpakse sa ca 'nubhava-samsraya. Sambandha-varttika, 182. Astasahasri, p. 163. Page #232 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. x11] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA 195 will not be in a position to make the assertion. The Vedantist had to admit that nescience is a felt fact. But he chooses to call the awareness of nescience an alogical knowledge. The reason seems to be the opposition of nescience with knowledge which is also a felt fact. That we commit error is not open to dispute. That this error is corrected and cancelled by knowledge of the true character of reality such as of the shell as opposed to silver, is not also liable to be disputed. But the cancellation of error, which consists in the proof that the predicate does not belong to the subject in the context in spite of its reality in another context, need not be construed as evidence of the unreality of error or of its content. That we make error is also capable of being established by a veridical knowledge. This is apparent from the consideration that the Vedantist also cannot deny that we misperceive shell as silver. This misperception is a fact which can be known by an unchallengeable cognition. And this cognition is possible if an organ of cognition operates upon the fact. But the Vedantist may urge 'Well, if error be an object of veridical cognition, it will be a real like true cognition. Not only this, it will also have to be admitted that the knowledge of error will be true knowledge, and this will amount to the assertion that there is no difference between error and truth.' The Jaina does not regard these objections as real difficulties. In the first place, he admits that error is as much a fact and verity as truth. In the second place, he admits that the cognition of error is true cognition. In other words, the Jaina believes that error as a psychical event is a true occurrence, and its cognition is the cognition of a true fact. It has been observed by Akalanka A cognition is true in reference to a fact which is not contradicted by another cognition.' The Vedantist also endorses the factuality of error as a psychical fact, and he also admits that there is awareness of such error. But he refuses to give this awareness the status of a true cognition, and he thinks the content of error, at least the predicative part of it, as neither real nor unreal, but something logically indeterminable. The reason he advances in support of his position is that it is set aside by a true cognition following upon it. Nobody denies this that error is corrected by a subsequent valid experience. But that does not and should not be interpreted as evidence of the unreality of the cognition or of the content. It may be false cognition but nonetheless it is a cognition, and true so far as its occurrence is taken into consideration. It is regarded as error because the external object is not possessed of 1 na ca pramananam avidva-visayatvam ayuktami vidyavad avidyaya api kathancid vastutvat. tatha vidyatvaprasanga iti cen na kincid anistam, 'yatha yatra 'visamvadas tatha tatra pramanata' ity Akalankadevair apy uktatvat Astasahasri, p. 163 Page #233 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 196 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [ch. the predicate judged to belong to it in error. The contradiction only proves that the predicate does not belong to the subject and nothing more. It has been already explained that the contradiction cannot mean that error did not happen. Error is bound to be admitted as historical event, and to be true so far as it is a real happening. The Vedantist has affirmed that the awareness of error is effected by pure consciousness, and as such cannot be assigned any logical value. But this seems to be a distinction without a difference. Granted that error is felt by pure consciousness. But why should this awareness be not valid? If the awareness of error be invalid, there will be no possible means of asserting that it is a psychical occurrence. The question of validity or invalidity of a cognition is not capable of being decided by the intrinsic character of the cognition in question. The validity of a cognition can be decided by external evidence, at least in the initial stage. A cognition is regarded as invalid only when it is found to be contradicted by a subsequent cognition showing that the predicate does not belong to the subject. The awareness of error, no matter whether pure or empirical, is not contradicted by any subsequent cognition. The subsequent cognition does not annul the historicity of error as a cognition. It only shows, as we have observed, that the predicate does not belong to the subject. Thus there does not seem to be any logical warrant for questioning the validity of awareness of error as a fact whether it be classed as empirical or metempirical. As regards the contention of Suresvara that nescience or error (which means the same thing) is not determinable by a valid cognition or an instrument of it, the Jaina does not think that it is based upon truth. It has been observed that a cognition is proved to be false when it is contradicted by a subsequent cognition having the same reference. The contradicting cognition is held to be true by all even including the Vedantist. This shows that error is proved by truth which is based upon a true objective datum. The Jaina accordingly thinks that the Vedantist's interpretation of error as an alogical fact is due to a hasty appraisal of the logical issue. Error as well as truth is always capable of being determined only with reference to reality. When the cognition is found to correspond to the objective situation in all respects it is called truth. When, on the other hand, it fails to conform to reality in any respect it is called false. So nescience as error is always determinable with reference to reality, and that again by means of an accredited organ of knowledge. As for the further contention of Suresvara that nescience is not possible for a person possessed of knowledge, it is observed that nescience is not possible in a person who is possessed of perfect knowledge and as such is omniscient. But there is no evidence to show that it is not possible for a man whose knowledge is limited. The assertion of Suresvara Page #234 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. X11] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA 197 that knowledge is futile in respect of a person free from nescience is also not based upon truth. Freedom from nescience makes perfect knowledge possible, and this knowledge is not futile because everybody will admit that it is covetable for its own sake. So how can knowledge be futile for a person free from nescience? The assertion of Suresvara again that the determination of nescience in a person is possible only so long as he is under the hypnotic spell of nescience is entirely wide of the mark. The differentiation of nescience from truth is possible only when a person discovers the truth. Were a person completely under the spell of nescience such differentiation would not be possible. The truth of the proposition asserted here is borne out by the evidence of dream. The dreaming man cannot distinguish between truth and error, because he is completely enmeshed in nescience in dream. So Suresvara's categorical affirmation that determination of nescience is possible only under the sway of nescience is entirely opposed to fact. It might be contended that if nescience as error be a true cognition, then there will be no reason for its being contradicted by a subsequent cognition ; but the fact that it is so contradicted shows that it is entirely false. But the Jaina asserts that there is no incompatibility in the situation. Error is regarded as a true cognition only in a sectional reference. It is true so far as its reference to the subject is concerned, and also so far as it is felt by the person, that is, with reference to its own being. When the deluded person thinks that he is ignorant or in error, he does not make a false assertion. This shows how a cognition, though true so far as it goes and so far as its particular reference is concerned, can be contradicted by a subsequent experience and thus be false in some particular reference. The dilemma raised by Suresvara that nescience is not intelligible whether the self is known or not known proceeds upon partial appraisal of truth. There is no incompatibility in the fact that a partially illumined person is subject to error and illumination alternately or simultaneously. Nescience is impossible of realization only in the case of perfect knowledge and total ignorance. But the latter alternative is impossible because there is no self which is totally devoid of knowledge, which is the possible outcome of total ignorance. As regards the former alternative the contention is only partially true. A man with perfect knowledge is not subject to nescience. But he realizes and transcends his nescience only with the dawn of such knowledge. na ca 'vidyavam eva sthitva 'sye 'yam avidye 'ti kalpyate, sarvasya vidyavasthayain eva 'vidyetara-vibliaga-niscayat svapnadyavidya-dasayam tadabhavat-Ibid. ? na ca "tmani kathancid avidite 'py avidye 'ti no 'papadyate, badha'virodhat. kathancid vijnate 'pi va 'vidye 'ti nitaram ghatate, viditatmana eva tadbadhakatva-vinisciteh kathancid badhitaya buddher mrsatva-siddhenIbid. Page #235 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 198 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. Again, Suresvara has asserted without compunction and almost with the sang-froid of a bravado that nescience is an irrational principle and the fact that it eludes all the epistemological resources is rather symptomatic of its true character. But the Jaina would pose a simple question 'How do you know that nescience is not amenable to logical proof? Are you sure that it is so? If so, what is the source of your conviction?' If the Vedantist confesses that he has no resource which enables him to make such assertion, then he will be guilty of unabashed dogmatism. If, on the other hand, the Vedantist is sure of the truth of his assertion this will mean that nescience is not altogether incapable of logical determination. At any rate the determination of nescience as alogical principle must be based upon truth and consequently secured by an accredited organ of knowledge. Suresvara has claimed that the postulation of nescience as the prius of the world process makes Vedanta philosophy the simplest of all systems. It may be so. But simplicity by itself is not a compelling consideration for the acceptance of a philosophy. Moreover this simplicity is more apparent than real. The plurality of entities with their infinite diversities is a felt fact. Nescience was posited over and above the absolutely undifferenced transcendental consciousness called the Absolute because it was felt that plurality, even as appearance, cannot be deduced from a simple unity. But if nescience be only another unitary principle, it also will not be competent to produce the appearance of plurality. For this it has been assumed that nescience possesses an infinite plurality of powers. Thus the claim of simplicity is based upon a quibble. It has however been claimed that nescience with its infinite resources and powers is an unreality and so the only reality is pure consciousness. The admission of such an illusory principle does not make reality more than one. But the assertion of unreality of nescience is a puzzle which runs counter to the verdict of experience and logical thought. Why should it be unreal? The Vedantist answers that it is not real because it exhibits selfcontradiction in every stage. The things of the world are subject to constant change and this means the extinction of the old order and emergence of a new one. But if a thing is to be real in its independent capacity and right, it cannot be supposed that it should diminish or increase or cease to be or come into being. Origin and destruction are unpredicable of a real. A real is real always and so must remain constant. The erroneous silver is unreal because it ceases to be when it is contradicted by knowledge of the shell. If a real were capable of origination and cessation like the false silver, there would be no criterion possible for the distinction of real from unreal. It must therefore be admitted, so contends the Vedantist, that constancy and Page #236 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. X11] CRITICISM OF THE VEDANTA AVIDYA 199 continuity and consequently the absence of lapse from uniformity are the true characteristic of a real. But these tests are incapable of being applied to the objects of experience. Things are seen to come into existence and pass out of being and this means that there is neither constancy nor uniformity in them. The conclusion is inevitable that they cannot be real. The Jaina philosopher has not concealed his surprise at this endeavour of the Vedantist to formulate a conception of reality which is entirely opposed to experience. What is the source of the knowledge of this peculiar nature of reality? The ultimate nature of things can be known by experience alone. Well, what is the ground for our belief that consciousness is existent and also is the proof of the existence of other things? The answer must be that it is felt to be so. Consciousness is its own guarantor and proof of its own reality. As regards unconscious matter, its existence is established by means of consciousness. It cannot be asked why consciousness should be selfevidenced and matter be dependent upon consciousness for the proof of its existence. The question is a question of fact, and not of reason. The nature of thing is inalienable and must be accepted to be what it is. Can anybody answer why fire should be hot and water cold, and not vice versa? No, because it is a question of fact. Similarly the nature of reality is to be deduced from the testimony of experience. The existence of things which are experienced is obvious and selfevident. If you call in question their credentials, the fact of existence and consciousness which are posited by the Vedantist to be the ultimate reality will not also be immune from such doubting interrogation. The result will be unrelieved scepticism or universal negation. The Vedantist had the good sense and sanity not to acquiesce in this suicidal estimation. The Jaina would respectfully and earnestly ask the Vedantist to carry his determination of reality consistently to its natural conclusion. He accepts existence to be the ultimate truth solely on the testimony of experience. But as experience records change as the integral character of existence or rather of things felt to be existent, it beats one's understanding why change should be declared as unreal appearance. The Vedantist has contended that change involves lapse of being into non-being and this is a case of self-contradiction. Reality must not be self-contradictory. But as change is fraught with contradiction, it is to be unceremoniously thrown overboard as an unreal and unjustifiable appearance. The Jaina is a frank realist, and is candid in his confession of faith in the verdict of experience. The Vedantist thinks that there is pure being which is incompatible with pure non being. But pure being is an abstraction, and we have no experience of it. So also is the case with pure non-being. What we find in Page #237 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. experience, including the principle of consciousness itself, is concrete being which is a unity of different entities. Thus we never come across a pure substance denuded of all qualities and actions. A substance is always a unity with the multiplicity of attributes. Why should the Vedantist scent contradiction in it? He should take the reality as a whole and the attempt to clip away a part of its character only bespeaks unwarranted zeal for abstract thinking. It is no doubt true that the diversity of reals encountered by experience exhibits existence as their universal trait. But the universality and continuity of this trait and the discontinuity of other traits are facts alike. The former should not be vested with truth and the latter dismissed as appearance. 200 Similarly one should not read contradiction in the combination of identity and difference when they are endorsed by uncontradicted experience. The Vedantist accepts the aspect of identity and rejects the aspect of difference, because he thinks that the nature of reality is absolutely simple. But this is only the outcome of his bias for a priori logical thought in preference to and contradiction of experience. We could accept this assessment of reality if the dictates of a priori logic were found to be confirmed even in a single instance of our experience. The Vedantist is too astute a thinker not to be aware of this weakness in his position. Accordingly he appeals to dreamless experience. He asserts that pure existence is felt in this state. He also appeals to samadhi (ecstasy) in which the spiritual aspirant realizes the reality as a homogeneous simple unity bereft of intrinsic and extrinsic difference. But the state of samadhi is not attainable by all. If a gifted soul experiences it that does not afford any help to men of limited knowledge who are enquirers after truth. So it has no philosophical value. As regards dreamless experience it is not also beyond dispute. So the Vedantist has to rely upon the revealed texts of the Upanisads and upon pure logic. So far as the Upanisadic texts are concerned, the interpretation of the monist is not accepted as the last word. There are other interpretations also. It may not be out of place to remark that the Jaina scriptures also have discussed these texts and have offered their own interpretation which is at variance with that of the monist. As regards pure logic, the Jaina attitude towards it has been elucidated in this work with as much clarity and precision as has been possible for us. The consequential objections of Suresvara regarding bondage and emancipation do not cause much difficulty to the Jaina. The Jaina believes that bondage is a real condition of the self, and though existing from the beginningless time as coeval with the individual yet it is liable to be transcended. Emancipation is nothing but the disentanglement of the self from the karmic matter. The karmic matter is not destroyed but only pulled out. The pure nature of the Page #238 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XIII] CRITICISM OF THE BUDDHIST AVIDYA self with its fourfold infinite characteristics, which is realized in emancipation, is not a new creation in the absolute sense. It was always there. But the karmic matter served to obscure it. The obscuration is ended in the state of emancipation. The Jaina believes in change because it is found to be the universal character of all reals and if it means transition from being to non-being in a sectional reference, the Jaina is not frightened by it. So the objection of Suresvara that emancipation, being a product of a process, will be liable to destruction does not cause any difficulty. It is found that gold in its natural state is associated with the ores from the very emergence of its being, but by a chemical process it is disentangled from them. And this does not involve any logical difficulty. Similar is the case of the self. Though it is associated with karmic matter throughout its past history, its dissociation from the latter cannot be an impossibility. The Vedantic solution that bondage and emancipation are both illusory cannot be regarded as the only satisfactory explanation as it has been made abundantly clear that the denial of plurality, in defiance of experience, cannot escape from fall into the abyss of universal nihilism or scepticism which Nagarjuna and his followers have shown to be the inevitable conclusion of pure logic. Let us now estimate the value of the Buddhist conception of avidya. XIII CRITICISM OF THE BUDDHIST CONCEPTION OF AVIDYA 201 We have seen how avidya heads the chain of pratityasamutpada (dependent origination). We have also stated the Vijnanavadin's conception of vasana under whose influence the consciousness (citta) appears as divided into the perceiver and the perceived, and is responsible for the world illusion.2 The Buddhist conception of 1 Vide supra, pp. 126-7. In this connection cf. also: 'Life in ordinary men is controlled by ignorance (avidya) which is the reverse of prajna, but not its mere absence. It is a separate element which can be and, in every ordinary man really is, present at the same time with his dormant faculty of wisdom. But it is not a constant faculty, it can be suppressed (prahina) and thrown out of the mental stream altogether which then becomes purified or saintly (arya)'-Stcherbatsky: The Conception of Buddhist Nirvana (Leningrad, 1927), p. 9 vide also 'p. 134 (footnote 1) of the same work. 2 Vide supra, pp. 129-30. Also cf. ... The transitional school of the Sautrantikas coalesced in the fifth century A.D. with the idealistic school of the Mahayana and produced India's greatest philosophers Dignaga and Dharmakirti. With regard to Nirvana it assumed the existence of a pure spiritual principle, in which object and subject coalesced, and along with it, a JP-26 Page #239 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 202 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH abhutaparikalpa (constructive ideation or unreal imagination) as found in the Lankavatara and the works of Maitreyanatha and his commentators has also been expounded at some length. Asvaghosa's doctrine of avidya has also been noticed. We have not given separate treatment to the conceptions of the Madhyamikas and others, because the conceptions already treated are sufficient to give an idea of those conceptions. If there is an illusion, there must be a force that creates it. This force is called avidya. The conceptions of this avidya differ according to the conceptions of reality. The criticism of a particular conception of avidya is ultimately the criticism of the conception of reality presupposed by that particular conception. This is also the justification of our treatment of only a few conceptions leaving many others such as the conception of the Sabdadvaitins and the like out of our enquiry. After criticizing the monism of purusa (purusadvaita) of the Vedantins, Vidyanandi says: 'By this criticism the verbal monism (sabdadvaita) has also been refuted ; firstly, because it is also, like the monism of consciousness (vijnanadvaita) and the like, subject to the said defects, there being difference only in procedural methodology ; secondly, because that cannot be established ; thirdly, because there is the common absence of any proof for itself or against the opponent ; fourthly, because it is not self-attested, and fifthly, because there is no other justification possible.'3 These defects are common to all absolutisms. We have also not discussed the other conceptions on similar grounds. This is, of course, irrelevant. Our main task here is to record the Jaina philosopher's estimate of the Buddhist conception of nescience (avidya) or predisposition (vasana) stated above. The Buddhists, like the other absolutists, when they are faced with the difficulty of explaining the universally attested experience, dismiss the experience as only an imagination born of avidya or vasana which is beginningless. The Jaina philosophers remain true to the universally attested experience and formulate their philosophy accordingly. The facts are never distorted to suit the doctrine. Nor the help of nescience (avidya) is sought for the evasion of every new problem that may arise. The Jaina doctrine of non-absolutism has been elaborated and systematized on the basis of experience, and if there appears to be any snag or angularity in it, it is ultimately due to that in the nature of things. force of transcendental illusion (vasana) producing the phenomenal world'.-The Conception of Buddhist Nirvana, p. 61. We have, however, traced these ideas to the Lankavatara, probably the oldest work containing Vijnanavada. i Vide supra, pp. 131-3. 2 Vide supra, pp. 134-7 3 tad etena sabdadvaitam api nirastam, vijnanady-advaitavat tasya 'pi nigadita-dosa-visa yatva-siddheh prakriyamatrabhedat, tadvyavasthanupapatten sva pakse-'tara-sadhaka-badhaka-pramanabhava.'visesat svatah-siddhyayogad gatyantarabhavac ca--Astasahasri, PP. 163-4. Page #240 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XII] CRITICISM OF THE BUDDHIST AVIDYA 203 It is not up to the philosopher to question the nature of things and make them behave in the manner of his own conceptions. The things cannot be expected to follow the likes and dislikes of the philosopher. Nor has the philosopher any right to dismiss as inconsistent and illogical the nature of things revealed to his experience. An absolutistic conception presupposes attachment to a particular aspect of reality and ignorance of or indifference to the other aspects of it. And consequently futile attempts are made at explaining away or dismissing only as imaginary constructions the other aspects that refuse to fit in with the absolutistic conceptions. The Buddhists, like other absolutists, make a capital out of the principle of avidya or vasana which is conceived to be as imaginary and unreal as its products. The Jaina criticism of the Buddhist conception of avidya is substantially the same as that of the Vedantin's conception of it. Of course, the Buddhist's avidya is only a subjective force while the Vedantin's is objective too. But there is essential similarity between the functions of them. We have stated the Jaina's objection against the Vedantin's position. Here we shall state, in brief, his objections against the Buddhist schools. The Jainas believe that all absolutistic conceptions are vitiated by some defect or other and that they all go against the verdicts of experience. The absolutists, however, dismiss the verdicts of experience as untrustworthy and ascribe the various appearances to beginningless avidya. Thus the great Buddhist thinker Dharmakirti, while denying the reality of all distinctions of perceiver and perceived given in the universally attested experience and establishing things as devoid of all definable characteristics, 2 says 'Apprehension of unreal distinction (of perceiver and perceived), emerging under the influence of previous conditions and causes, arises in the people whose consciousness is vitiated by nescience, even as aberrations of vision are conditioned by previous disorders.'3 Belief in the necessity of nescience is almost universal among philosophers. Our errors of judgment and of perception must be due to some condition. It is true that the conditions of normal activity of our intellectual, emotional and volitional constitution cannot be supposed to be responsible for the anomalies and aberrations. It is, for this reason, admitted by philosophers that there must be a tendency and predisposition to give our normal faculties a twist and turn in the opposite direction so that error may be possible. It should be noted 1 Cf. tvan-matamsta-bahyanam sarvathaikantavadinam aptabhimana-dagdhanam svestam dsstena badhyate. --AMi, 7 (Astasahasri, p. 76). 2 See Pramanavarttika, II. 212-216. 3 yathasvam pratyayapeksad avidyopaplutatmanam vijnaptir vitatha kara jayate timiradivat.-Ibid., II. 217. Page #241 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 204 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. that error is not only privative in character but also positive in its results. And for this an adequate condition must be postulated. This condition is called nescience. It not only obscures and hides the nature of reality but also vests it with a false appearance. It is a positive force as has been advocated by the Vedantist, the Buddhist, the exponents of the Yoga school and others. The Jaina also agrees with this view. He thinks that it is the association of destructive karmic matter with the self that is responsible for these abnormal intellectual, emotional and volitional aberrations. This karmic matter is a positive fact and force and it has also twofold function. It not only obscures the innate perfect nature of the soul and hinders the full exercise of the powers, but also makes it a prey to illusions in every plane, intellectual, emotional and volitional. This fundamental agreement with the philosophers of other schools does not however solve the various problems that confront a thinking mind. It is a painful fact that the philosophers are at variance with one another in their estimate of the facts of experience and thought. What is this due to? Each school of philosophers has accused the opposite schools of their failure to grasp the true nature of reality. But the philosophers' differences need not throw a damper upon our enthusiasm for the discovery of truth. After all the Law of Contradiction will help a student of philosophy to reject what is false and to adopt what is true. As we have observed repeatedly, the logic must co-operate with experience in its quest for the Holy Grail, the knowledge of ultimate reality. Whenever there is a tendency of either of these resources available to mankind to dominate and subjugate the other, the result has been a tissue of contradictory findings which cannot be all true. The Jaina's approach to this supreme problem is co-ordination of experience and reason. His differences with the rival philosophers are due to the contradictions of the fundamental postulates and axioms which have claimed unqualified allegiance of all noble minds in their quest of truth.1 Thus belief in the doctrine of karman, which is the natural outcome of the belief in the moral law of causality, is almost universally held by the majority of philosophers in India. Of course the materialists have refused to offer their allegiance to this characteristic doctrine. We do not propose to criticize the materialistic position in the present context. Our concern is now with those schools who believe in the inexorable necessity of the moral law. We shall consider whether their philosophical conclusions are in keeping with this fundamental truth. Let us take up the position of the absolute nihilist. Nagarjuna is the archangel of this school. He believes in the Buddhist doctrine of karman, at least on this side of final realization. So also does the 1 See The Jaina Philosophy of Non-absolutism, Chap. I. Page #242 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XIII] CRITICISM OF THE BUDDHIST AVIDYA 205 Vedantist. Both these absolutistic schools agree that a man is beset with volitional and emotional tendencies and impulses which lead him to perform good and bad actions. They also believe that they have their natural reactions. The good action produces a happy result and the bad act an unhappy one, not only in this life but also in life hereafter. We have already criticized the Vedantic position and now address ourselves to the criticism of nihilism. Now, if there be no reality and truth in the moral law how can the nihilist reconcile his faith in the efficacy of the moral law with the utter negation of it? The nihilist of course has contended that the moral law holds good only provisionally so long as the realization of ultimate truth does not happen. But he believes that performance of righteous actions such, for instance, as the practice of universal love and friendship and the avoidance of infliction of injury are the necessary preparation for ultimate perfection. The denial of the ultimate validity of the moral law presupposes an unbridgeable hiatus and breach of continuity of moral life with spiritual life. Is this supposition of unbridgeable gulf between our empirical life and metempirical destiny unavoidable? The Jaina thinks that it is not. He believes that the self in its onward and upward journey towards consummation surrenders and appropriates its previous acquisitions and present conquests. None of these trophies or defeats is unreal. They have a bearing, essential and natural, upon spiritual progress and advance. The nihilist cannot escape the charge of self-contradiction when he makes moral discipline the scaffolding to the final achievement and denies its efficacy and truth. It is true that the man who has ascended the topmost rung of the ladder has no necessity for the lower rungs. It bespeaks not only ingratitude but also perversity. As regards the Sautrantika fluxist who is not less vocal in his allegiance to the moral law, it will be found on close examination that he too is guilty of selfcontradiction nonetheless. He has argued that a permanent cause is an impossibility. A permanent cause will produce a permanent effect which is absurd. Causal efficiency, according to him, is the criterion of existence. He further argues that efficiency is necessarily concomitant with action, and action can be produced in succession or nonsuccession. But if an entity produces all its actions simultaneously then the question arises whether it persists after the production of effects or not. If it does not persist, it will be momentary. If it persists it will continue to produce all the effects simultaneously. But it is not a fact that all the effects are produced simultaneously. The pen writes. But it is not found that it writes all the letters and words that are written in present, past and future at the present moment. Nor can it be supposed that an entity produces its actions in succession. There is no reason why an entity should defer its, Page #243 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. activity when it is possessed of all the powers. Thus causal efficiency is not possible for the non-momentary. So the non-momentary cannot be a real, being bereft of causal efficiency which is the necessary concomitant of reality. But the momentary also has been found to be incapable of exercising causal efficiency either in succession or in nonsuccession, and as such cannot be real. The Jaina accepts causal efficiency as the criterion of reality which, according to him, presupposes that real should be both permanent and transitory.1 206 The Buddhist has denied a permanent self underlying the course of psychical events which happen in different times. But what exists and is possible is only the present momentary unit. The past is defunct, and the present is lost after its turn. This makes the continuity of personal life impossible, and accordingly the continuity of present life into the future and the necessity of the law of karman that the performer of good or bad act will have to bear the consequences-all these become impossible of explanation. The Buddhist has abolished the permanent soul and replaced it by a series supposed to be governed by the law of causality. The past produces the present and the present produces the future, and in the production the cause communicates its ethico-religious bias into the effect. This seems to be a solvent of the difficulties involved in the breach of continuity. But is causation possible in the absence of a real link between the past and the present? The previous consciousness-unit is dead and defunct when the succeeding unit happens. But how can a defunct and non-existent fact be the cause of anything? Nobody can think that the present occurrence is due to an event which has occurred in the remote past. The reason for this is that the past is not in existence to influence the present event. It might be contended that the immediately precedent event can be the cause of the immediately succeeding one. But how can the effect come into existence in the absence of the cause and yet be due to it? In the Buddhist theory the cause ceases to be when the effect comes into being. How can there be any relation between what is existent and what is non-existent? There can be no distinction between the immediate precedent and the remote precedent when both are equally non-existent at the time of the production of the effect. The determinant of causality is the concomitance in presence and absence of the effect with the cause. But in the Buddhist theory the effect does not happen when the cause is in existence, and it happens only when the supposed cause is non-existent. How can there be concomitance? How can again the Buddhist explain that the effect should happen in immediately succeeding moment and not in remote future or past when the cause has no existence at the time of 1 The Jaina Philosophy of Non-absolutism, pp. 71 et seq. Page #244 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. X111] CRITICISM OF THE BUDDHIST AVIDYA 207 the effect's occurrence? There can be no difference, as we have said, between a remote past and an immediate past, because the absence of the cause is uniform in both cases. The question comes to be 'How can the non-existent be the cause of the existent?' One might equally affirm that an eternally existent entity might produce an occasional effect. If it is urged that there is no concomitance between an eternally existent fact and an occasional event because the existence of the effect is not concomitant with that of the cause, and the cause is present when the effect ceases to be. But this is also the case with the Buddhist when he affirms that the effect comes into being during the absence of the cause at a particular time and place, but not during the whole period of its absence in the uncounted past and in unending future. And this amounts to the denial of the law of causalityl which was the corner-stone of the Buddha's religious and philosophical edifice. Not only this, the self-contradiction obtrudes itself most unabashedly when the Buddhist fluxist makes causal efficiency the criterion of reality and ends in the conclusion that the effect is independent of the cause which is deducible from the proposition that the effect comes into being when the cause is absent. Thus causality is as inexplicable in the theory of flux as it is in the theory of eternally unchanging cause. There is another serious difficulty in the doctrine of flux. It is a matter of universal experience that the continuous indentity of the self as well as of objects is felt by all. This felt identity is asserted to be illusion by the Auxist. But what is the basis of this illusion? Illusion presupposes a previous cognition. A man who has never experienced silver cannot mistake the shell for silver. Identity is inseparable from continuity. But as there is not real continuity anywhere according to the Buddhist, how can there be such illusion possible? The supposed continuity is said to be formed by discrete moments which come into being and pass out of existence. So there is no real continuity anywhere. It is affirmed by the Buddhist himself that the discrete moments when not felt as distinct create the illusion o identity. We have shown that this illusion is impossible. But even admitting for the sake of argument that such an illusion may be possible, the question arises 'How can one continuum be distinguished from another continuum?' Now, it is a felt fact that the chair is different from the table. It is not the discrete momentary chair that is different from the table. But we feel that the table which appears to continue is different from the chair-continuum. There is no difference between the chair and the table so far as the appearance of continuum due to the non-cognition of the difference of the units is concerned. A 1 Astasahasri, p. 183. 2 Ibid., pp. 190 et seq. 3 santanina eva 'paramista-bhedah santana iti svayam abhyu pagamat. Astasahasri, p. 191. Page #245 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 208 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. question arises : How can one continuum be felt as distinct from another continuum ?' Each member of chair-series is distinct from its other members in the same way as the members of the table-series are from those of the chair-series. Yet the chair-series is felt as distinct from the table-series. What is the reason of this? If the unbroken continuity of the emergence of the table-moments be the reason for its distinction from the chair, the same unbroken continuity is found in all the series. It is difficult to understand firstly, how absolutely distinct entities give rise to the appearance of identity ; secondly, how one series can be distinguished from another series when the same absolute difference is found to obtain between them as is found between the members of a particular series. If similarity be held to be an additional reason for this appearance of identity and continuity then why should not the two table-series closely similar be not felt as identical? There is similarity and also unbroken succession between the different units. You may say that one table is felt as distinct from another table and so there is no confusion between them. But the appeal to perception is useless because what is perceived is always the moment and not the series which is an unreal intellectual construction. So again the appeal to recognition cannot be of help, because in the Buddhist theory of flux nothing continues, and there is no identity between the past and the present, which is to be known by recognition. What is felt is always the moment, absolutely distinct and discrete from another moment. So no question of identity of one moment with another moment arises. In fact, a plurality of units without a binding nexus can never account for the unity felt in an entity. If an abiding unity is posited to connect and combine the different units, then recognition and also causality can be explained. This is the position of the Jaina philosopher who asserts that a reality is a permanent unity which runs through the changing moments that appear in it. The criterion of reality is thus continuity and change, that is to say, the flux and influx of states. As regards the subjectivist idealists, the Buddhist subjectivists hold that the only thing that exists is consciousness and external objects are only false appearances like those of dream experience. But this position can be established only by an organ of knowledge. Without the support of an organ of knowledge, the Buddhist cannot prove the falsity of the theories of rival philosophers who believe in extra-mental reality. Not only this, the subjectivist cannot prove the falsity of the differentiation of cognition into an act and a content. The subjectivist 1 na ca parasparam vilaksananam eva ksananam atyantam anvayasattve 'py antar bahir va santatayo 'sankirna eva pratyaksatah pratitah tasyai 'kaksanagocarataya santanavisayatvat-Ibid. 2 Astasahasri, Chap. VII (pp. 240 et seq.). Page #246 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. X111] CRITICISM OF THE BUDDHIST AVIDYA 209 holds that our cognitions are momentary and self-intuited and that there are other subjects. Certainly all these facts cannot be proved by our intuitions. A cognition may be felt by itself, but it is not felt as momentary or as not cognized by another which is the meaning of self-intuition. Moreover, if the cognition has no veridical reference to a real extra-subjective fact, how can the subjectivist believe in the existence of other subjects? The denial of genuine extra-subjective reference must end in solipsism. If the entire logical apparatus including the difference of probans and probandum and the necessary relation between them be a false creation of nescience, then the subjectivist cannot prove anything including his own position. The subjectivist seeks to establish the identity of content with cognition on the ground of the two being felt together. But this very assertion proves that he believes in the duality of cognition and content. Is this not a case of self-contradiction like the vocal statement of a person 'I am an observer of the vow of silence'? It has however been argued in defence by the subjectivist that this line of attack on the part of the opponent is neither fair nor consistent. How can the charge of a fallacy or a self-contradiction be advanced against the subjectivist when the opponent knows that the former does not believe in the reality of anything other than consciousness? It might be said in defence that these adverse criticisms are not unreasonable or illegitimate so long as the subjectivist has not proved his position. The latter also has recourse to the logical apparatus to prove his position to the satisfaction of the opponent. And he is on the same level with the opponent so far as the belief in the validity of logical weapons is concerned. The use of logic will become superfluous after the ultimate truth viz. the reality of consciousness alone is realized. Dignaga and his followers in spite of their ultimate conviction of the truth of pure consciousness alone have elaborated logical weapons and this is not inconsistent with their philosophical convictions. They have frankly avowed that logic has its place and utility only on this side of realization of the ultimate truth and is necessary to combat the prevailing misconceptions of philosophers. So the charge of self-contradiction or inconsistency is nothing better than argumentum ad hominem. The Jaina philosopher observes that his charges could be ineffective if the Buddhist idealist succeeded in proving that his conclusion was established by an unimpeachable logical ground. Dharmakirti asserts that the 'identity' of cognition and content follows from the 'necessity of their being known together' (sahopalambha-niyamat). But what is the meaning of the expression 'the necessity of being known together and of the term 'identity'? The former may possibly be interpreted 1..... sada mauna-vratiko 'ham ity abhilapavat sva-vacanavirodhasyai 'va svikaranat-Astasahasri, p. 242. JP-27 Page #247 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 210 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. as the absence of separate cognition and identity' may be understood to mean absence of numerical difference'. In other words, the negation of separate cognition may be made the ground for the inference of 'negation of numerical difference. But this is not possible because there can be no necessary relation between two negations. As regards such negative inferences as of the absence of smoke' from the absence of fire', of the 'absence of triangle from the absence of figure', they are legitimate only because they derive their cogency from the necessary concomitance between their positive counter-terms. Thus there is necessary concomitance between effect and cause, and so the negation of cause leads to the inference of the negation of effect. Likewise, there is necessary concomitance between 'figure' which is the genus and triangle' which is the species. And so the negation of the former entails the negation of the latter. There is no independent relation possible between two negations. The Buddhist argument could be effective if the positive concomitance between separate cognition and numerical difference were possible. To be explicit, the Buddhist is the last person to assert that a separate cognition of the content from that of the cognition concerned is possible by means of which the numerical difference of the cognition and content can be established ; for the admission of the possibility of the cognition of the content, separate and numerically different from that of the cognition will knock out the Buddhist position of identity of cognition and content. The Buddhist therefore is precluded from asserting a logically necessary relation between their corresponding negations as negations have no independent logical relation apart from that of their opposite positives. The result will not be different even if either of the terms be given a positive interpretation. Thus if the probandum be asserted to be positive identity, it cannot be proved from negative probans, because there can be no relation between a positive and a negative term. Causality and identity of essence are recognized to be the two types of necessary relation. But these two relations are found to obtain between positive entities and not non-entities, nor between an entity and a non-entity. The same difficulty will stand in the way if the probans is supposed to stand for a positive fact. But let us see if the Buddhist can establish his position by making the probans and probandum both positive. Thus it may be interpreted that the necessity of being known together' means identity of the cognition and the probandum is identity of the two'. But this interpretation would make the inference a case of tautology because the probans will not be different from the probandum. What the Buddhist seeks to establish by this argument is that the content and the cognition are not different but identical. So identical cognition' is found to be the probandum and the probans is also Jain Education Intemational Page #248 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. X111] CRITICISM OF THE BUDDHIST AVIDYA 211 nothing but identical cognition'. But the Buddhist may argue that the truth of the identity of cognition is established by means of abolition of the difference between the content and the cognition, because an identical cognition is incompatible with the numerical difference of contents. Thus in every cognition the content is cognized together with the cognition. And the cognition is as much a content of itself as the content is supposed to be. This necessary compresence of the contents in the same cognition is not intelligible without their identity. The felt difference must then be an illusion. The Jaina avers that the necessity of compresence of two or more contents in one cognition proves neither the identity of the contents inter se nor the identity of the contents with the cognition. Thus a substance and its qualities are always perceived together, but this identity of perception does not annul the difference of the contents, nor the difference of the cognition from them. Nor is it our conviction that when many things such as the chair and the table and the other furniture in a room are perceived together, their mutual differences are abolished. But if this association be regarded as accidental, the example of substance and quality will rebut all doubt of falsity of inference. The subjectivist himself admits that the omniscient Buddha cognizes all the different consciousnesscentres (which appear as so many subjects). But he does not conclude that all the different subjective centres are really identical with the Buddha.2 Moreover, we do not find any logical absurdity in the supposition that things may be perceived together and yet be different from one another. Thus, for instance, when any object is seen, it is seen together with light. There can be no visual perception possible for us in darkness. But nobody will conclude from this that light and the jar or the pen are identical. It is quite possible to argue that the relation between cognition and its content is one of illuminer and illumined. And that they are felt together is due to the fact that without the cognition of the one the other cannot be cognized. In other words, the relation may be one of means and end, condition and conditional. The argument of the Buddhist is the prototype of the argument of the Vedantist which we have considered before. The Vedantist has argued from the coincidence of the content and cognition to their necessary identity and integration. We have shown that the Jaina explains this by asserting the relation to be one of identity-indifference. The same conclusion will follow from the Buddhist argument of necessary compresence. Let us now address ourselves to the examination of the nihilist's 1 Cf. dravya paryayau hi Jainanam eka-mati-jnana-grahyau, na ca sarvathai 'katvam pratipadyete-Ibid., p. 243. 2 tatha Yogacarasya 'pi sakala-vijnana-paramanavah Sugatajnanenai 'kena grahyah, na cai 'katvabhajah-Ibid. Page #249 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 212 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. position. The greatest protagonist of negativism as a philosophical doctrine is Nagarjuna. He has subjected to critical examination all the prevailing concepts and theories and has found particular delight in posing their self-contradictory nature. Nagarjuna adopts the attitude of a critic who avows that he has no positive doctrine of his own. The position will be made clear from our study of some concrete problems as dissected by Nagarjuna. Let us take up causality. Nagarjuna asserts that causality is logically indeterminable, yet the constitution of our intellect is such that we cannot jettison it if we are to understand the world order. He asserts that the effect is not produced by itself, that is to say, the effect cannot be its own cause. In other words, the cause and the effect cannot be identical. The cause is the immediate antecedent event. If the effect were self-caused, it would be antecedent to itself. And this means that the effect was existent before. What is then the use of the causal operation which aims at bringing into existence what was not in existence before. It is nonsense to suppose that an existent can be made existent which the advocate of the identity of cause and effect is made to confess on cross-examination. The Sankhya philosopher seeks to explain the causal relation by supposing that the effect is pre-existent in the cause. It is because of pre-existence that causality becomes a relation between two determinates. To the question 'Why should oil be produced from sesamum and not from sand?' the Sankhya answer is 'Because oil is existent in the sesamum and not in the sand'. Nagarjuna observes that the position is untenable because if oil be already existent, what is the necessity of grinding the sesamum seeds in an oil-press. The Sankhya answers that oil is existent only in a latent form and causal operation is necessary to make it patent. But is not patency a novel phenomenon? If it were also existent there is no point in trying to make it patent because this means that the already existing patency is made patent. Is this not a superfluity? To this question the Sankhya seems to turn a deaf ear. The Sankhya has been constrained to say that the effect was existent not in the form which it assumes after the causal operation. But this means that the effect was existent somehow. To be precise, the effect was existent as cause, and the relation of cause and effect is not one of absolute identity but identity-cum-difference. This is the Jaina position. But the Sankhya has not the courage to assert that this is so. Nagarjuna's criticism of the Sankhya theory of causation is unassailable if by identity of the cause and the effect the Sankhya is understood to mean absolute and exclusive identity which is contradictorily opposed to difference. Let us now examine Nagarjuna's criticism of the Nyaya theory of causation. The cause and effect are absolutely different. But Page #250 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. x11] CRITICISM OF THE BUDDHIST AVIDYA 213 Nagarjuna asks 'If the relation be entirely and absolutely one of difference why is it that oil is not produced from sands when both the oil-seeds and the sands are equally different from the effect?' Absolute difference is tantamount to absolute negation of relation. If the effect were entirely unrelated to the cause, it passes one's understanding why should the effect be affiliated to a particular class of facts. The Naiyayika only appeals to experience. He observes that it is a question of fact, and no questioning is relevant or intelligible regarding it. Because oil is found to be produced from oil-seeds and not from sands the former is regarded as the cause and not the latter. This empirical explanation does not satisfy an inquisitive mind. It only puts a gag upon the inconvenient questioner and in this the Naiyayika seems to occupy the position of an autocrat who demands unquestioning acquiescence in his ruling. Nagarjuna naturally rebels against this tyranny of the empiricist. Well, if experience be the final arbiter of all disputes, then philosophy will become a seditious activity. Nagarjuna is not in doubt that oil is actually produced from oil-seeds and not from sands. What he wants to know and understand is the foundation of the ontological necessity of the causal relation. The empiricist quite unjustifiably loses his temper and commands unquestioning allegiance by ruling out all inconvenient questions. This attitude does not seem to be helpful to the understanding of the nature of things and their relation. Nagarjuna therefore has no hesitation in recording his verdict against this explanation. He thinks that the Nyaya theory only restates the problem and asks the opponent to accept this as the explanation of it. He declares that the theory is unphilosophical, to say the least. Nagarjuna now asks if causation can be explained by regarding the relation between the cause and the effect as identity and otherness together. This he thinks to be a contradiction in terms. Identity is diametrically opposed to otherness which means non-identity. So this theory is dismissed by him with scant courtesy. The opponent may ask 'Is this not repudiation of causal relation? Is it your position that the effect is produced without the cause?' Nagarjuna replies 'No, this is not possible. We cannot think that an event can happen without a cause. What is then the nature of the relation between them? Nagarjuna replies that the question is unanswerable because no relation can be discovered by logical thought. We cannot explain why a particular class of events should follow another class of events with clockwork regularity ; for by means of logical thought we cannot discover any factual basis for it. This is in brief the survey of the causal relation and of the findings of Nagarjuna. The Jaina philosopher thinks that the difficulty is the creation of a priori logical thought. In the first place, Nagarjuna Page #251 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 214 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [CH. thinks that there is such a thing as absolute identity. But we have not come across a single instance of any two things being absolutely identical. In the second place, Nagarjuna asserts that there is such a thing as absolute otherness which is also not endorsed by experience at any rate between a cause and an effect. If we are to closely follow our experience without allowing our logical preconceptions to give a twist to its plain meaning we must admit that there is a close affinity between the cause and the effect though they are not absolutely identical because they are two facts. They are thus different no doubt, but the element of close affinity is also undoubtedly a fact. And affinity is intelligible only if there is a common element in both of them. This common element is identity. This identity is not the pure identity of pure logic which is as much a chimera as pure being or pure non-being. So in allegiance to experience we must admit that the relation of cause and effect is such as not to exclude either identity or difference. It is a sui generis relation which is as ultimate as identity and difference are supposed to be. For want of a more expressive term due to the limitation of human language we have to express this relation as identity-in-difference. And there is no incompatibility in it as it is registered by indisputable and unmistakable experience. The Jaina does not arrogate to himself the prerogative of a judge or a law court, who seeks to cut the Gordian knot by threat of the penalty incident to contempt of court. The Jaina's attitude is one of persuasion. He does not stifle the natural curiosity of the human understanding. But he only invites the attention of the opponent to the actual fact and only admonishes him if he shuts his eyes to the truth and seeks to determine it by means of a priori considerations. Well, whatever be the merits of the Jaina estimate of this fundamental problem, it must be admitted that he succeeds in avoiding the anomalies that are inevitable in the position of the Sankhya and the Nyaya philosopher by admitting that there is a relation possible between pure identity and pure difference which wonderfully harmonizes their dispute by a synthesis in a concept which is not a mere summation of the two, as Nagarjuna thinks, but a different category in which the two elements are combined and transcended at the same time. Let us take up another case. Experience shows that things have got a distinctive individuality of their own and this individuality is determinable by means of characteristic attributes. This task of determination by means of characteristics is performed by means of definitions in logic. Nagarjuna calls in question the logical propriety of this procedure. He asks 'Are the characteristics different from the things or identical with them?' If they are different from the things to which they are supposed to belong as much as the characteristics Page #252 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XIV] CRITICISM OF THE SAIVA AVIDYA 215 which belong to other entities, then there will be no meaning in the assertion that the characteristics belong to things. If, on the other hand, they are identical, either the attribute or the substantive will be left over. This seems to be incontestable from the standpoint of pure logic. But as pure logic is not found to be obeyed by the facts which are revealed to our experience which again is the only source of our knowledge of the existence and behaviour of things, the Jaina philosopher who is equally attentive to the claims of logic and experience is not convinced by this flourish of pure logic. He asserts 'Certainly the characteristics are different from the substantives. But because they always go together and are inseparably related, this shows that the relation is not one of absolute difference which obtains between the characteristics of A and B. The characteristics of A are not different from A in the same way as the characteristics of B are. This shows that the relation is also not opposed to identity. This identity is not exclusive of difference. To be precise, the relation is sui generis just like that between cause and effect. You may call it identity-indifference because the two elements are felt in it. But it is not exhausted by both of them or analysable into these two elements. The relation is unanalysable though it is distinguishable in thought as consisting of identity and difference as elements. But, as we have observed, the relation is altogether of a different kind from both because while it synthesizes them it is not exhausted by them. It is a relation which embraces identity and difference in its fold, and also transcends them because it is more than an aggregate of the two. In this way the Jaina solves all the puzzles and cruxes invented by the votary of pure logic. He asserts that the nature of reality is to be determined not by experience alone, nor exclusively by logic. The two must co-operate. And thus the Jaina is not an adherent of uncritical experience, nor is he enamoured of logic alone. Logic is blind without experience and the latter again is a cripple without the criticism offered by logic. One must be tempered by the other. Thus the Jaina is not a blind empiricist but a critical realist who subjects experience to logic and chastens logic by the unmistakable verdict of experience. Let us now estimate the value of the Saiva conception of avidya. XIV CRITICISM OF THE SAIVA CONCEPTION OF AVIDYA The conception of bondage and emancipation is the common property of all Indian systems of thought. It is recognized that the present world and our condition and status are not perfect and there Page #253 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 216 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [ch. must be a way of release from this imperfect state. The soul has got an inherent and inalienable right to perfection, though the conception of perfection is not uniform or identical so far as the positive content of it is understood. But, negatively speaking, it is admitted that there is recovery from unfreedom and the misery of infirmity and limitation of power. The Saiva schools which we have surveyed are also in agreement with others so far as this fundamental standpoint and attitude are taken into account. It is the common presupposition of all schools of thought that the recovery of the innate nature of the self constitutes the extinction of all pain and suffering, which is the corollary of emancipation. This worldly existence is to be transcended. And human resources are equal to this task. This is the fundamental datum and postulate of philosophical and ethical speculations and the goal of religious disciplines. The nature and content of emancipation therefore are bound up with the metaphysical conception of the original nature of self. The Saiva conception of individual self differs from that of other schools and therefore the conception of final emancipation is bound to be different. The Saiva believes that the self is essentially a conscious principle, and joy and bliss and freedom are integral to its nature. The Jaina philosopher would agree on this point. The belief in the innate power of the self for knowledge, will and action will also be endorsed by the Jaina. It would also be conceded that the relation of power and the possessor of it is one of inseparability. But while the Saiva insists on asserting it to be a relation of identity the Jaina would interpret it as identity-in-difference. The Jaina also would agree with the Saiva in regarding the cause of bondage as real and not imaginary or a case of unreal superimposition as the Vedantist maintains. This cause of bondage is designated by the Saiva as mala (contamination or taint) as we have seen. Barring the terminological difference the Jaina would have no objection to the conception of karma-pasa or karma-mala as the fundamental cause of bondage and as for the other contaminations such as anava-mala and mayaya-mala the Jaina would regard them as consequential. The association of karman with the soul is responsible for the limitation of its capacity for knowledge, perversion of will and inhibition of powers of enjoyment and self-expression and also assumption of psycho-physical organism. The difference is rather a matter of elaboration and nomenclature and point of view. Omniscience and omnipotence are regarded as necessarily coexistent in Jainism. Here we meet with a difference from the Saiva point of view. The Saiva philosopher believes in the possibility of the emergence of omniscience on the dawn of suddha-vidya in the soul irrespective of the extent to which the corresponding power of action Page #254 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. XIV] CRITICISM OF THE SAIVA AVIDYA 217 (kriyasakti) may have been evolved. In other words, omniscience and omnipotence are not necessarily coexistent. This may be regarded as a matter of detail, but it indicates a fundamental difference of attitude. The Jaina gives primacy to the correction of will which is invariably and infallibly attended with the perfection of knowledge and power. The Saiva believes in the possibility of the removal of spiritual ignorance without the emergence of spiritual knowledge. But how can this removal of ignorance be possible without the dawn of knowledge ? The Saiva himself recognizes that the removal of intellectual ignorance is possible only on the dawn of intellectual enlightenment, and therefore it is sheer self-contradiction on his part to assert the possibility of the removal of spiritual ignorance without the emergence of spiritual knowledge. The monistic Saiva starts with the assumption that the absolutely perfect Paramasiva, the Supreme and Sole Reality, somehow elects to assume self-limitation and ultimately degrades itself into the status of an imperfect individual self. This process of self-abasement is conditioned by an act of free will and not any extraneous circumstance. This rather smacks of mysticism. The Jaina would not give his approbation to this theory. If the process of self-abasement be an act of free will, the process of discipline that is necessary for the achievement of emancipation should also be effected by a fiat of will. So no amount of individual exertion would succeed and the line of demarcation between good and evil would also be rendered nugatory. Of course, this difficulty cannot be alleged against the dualistic Saiva school of thought which asserts the ontological reality of the plurality of selves like Jainas. The monistic Saiva believes the world order and its evolution to be real. But it presents an insurmountable crux for logical thought. How can real unity of the Absolute be reconciled with real plurality? The Vedantist believes plurality to be an unreal appearance in and over the unitary Absolute, Whatever may be the objections of other schools of philosophers, it cannot be denied that the Vedantic position does not give offence to logical thought whereas the Saiva position of real unity with its concomitant real plurality is logically unthinkable. In the monistic school the relation of the Absolute (Paramasiva) with the world order, which is not illusory like the Vedantic concept of maya, is also not logically intelligible. It is held that the relation is one of identity. The identity of two reals of co-ordinate status is unreachable by logical thought. The Jaina doctrine of non-absolutism would rather be more intelligible. It is held in both schools of Saiva philosophy that the self which is innately perfect suffers the vicissitudes of worldly career with the diminution of its powers. But the question JP_28 Page #255 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 218 PROBLEM OF AVIDYA [ch. arises that if this loss and recovery of perfection be real events in the history of the self, does not the self undergo change of nature? If it does undergo a change, the self will be dynamic principle like the soul of the Jaina. But so far as the monistic school is concerned we do not think it warrantable to suppose that the self is believed to be a changing constant. It is affirmed in one breath that the self merely appears to undergo change and that this appearance is real. It is difficult for the logical understanding to be reconciled with this position. The relation of karman with the individual self is also not intelligible. It is held that the karmans remain embedded and mature in maya in the period of dissolution, and the self experiences their results only from the time of new creation. It appears that karman does not become integrated with the self's nature. But how can the self be subject to the consequences of karman which remains detached from it? This conception seems to be analogous with that of the Sankhya and we have criticized this conception which makes bondage and emancipation vicarious The Saiva makes emancipation of the self dependent upon Divine Grace. But the Jaina cannot accept this position. He makes the individual the architect of his fortune and the maker of his destiny. The individual is alone responsible for his degraded status and it is up to him to work out his salvation by his unaided efforts. He will of course exploit all the advantages from the sastras and the instruction of teachers. But ultimately he must depend upon himself for his success or failure. The credit or blame must be taken by him alone. The descent of the Divine Grace cannot be arbitrary. It presupposes a spiritual preparation of the individual self as a condition. The Jaina would have it that this very condition automatically leads to the succeeding stages of spiritual development. If the descent of Divine Grace is interpreted as a necessary result of previous spiritual preparation, the Jaina philosopher would have no objection to this interpretation in spite of its mystical appearance. XV CONCLUSION We have studied the various conceptions of the nature and function of avidya or nescience in Indian thought. We have also recorded the criticism of those conceptions from the Jaina philosopher's standpoint. We have found that mithyatva or mithya-darsana (perverted attitude) is the Jaina equivalent of avidya qua the fundamental or basic defect responsible for worldly existence. Avidya qua the conditions of worldly existence consists in the threefold elements of Page #256 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III. Xv] CONCLUSION 219 perverted attitude, perverted cognition (mithyajnana) and perverted conduct (mithyacaritra). The Jaina philosopher does not agree with those who regard perverted cognition alone as the condition of worldly existence. He does not also endorse the view which regards perverted cognition as the most fundamental defect responsible for worldly existence. Perverted cognition is only an effect of perverted attitude (mithyatva) which is the most fundamental condition of worldly existence. We shall have occasions in the chapters that follow for further elucidation of the conception of the nature of this 'perverted attitude'. The conception of the nature of avidya depends upon the conception of the nature of reality. It is because of this that we have been led to criticize the various conceptions of reality of the different systems of thought while recording the Jaina philosopher's objections against the different conceptions of avidya. We have shown the Jaina's credence in logical empiricism which regards logic without experience blind and experience without logic a cripple. Page #257 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CHAPTER IV THE JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN INTRODUCTORY Rebirth and karman are the two most important presuppositions of all schools of Indian Philosophy with the solitary exception of the system of Carvaka. This is but consistent with their spiritual outlook. India is the birthplace of a galaxy of spiritual leaders throughout its history and it is no wonder that her heritage is so rich with speculations about rebirth and karman and the pathways leading to emancipation from them. It is not possible to trace the origin of the doctrines in time. The Vedas are the oldest records wherein we can find their rudiments. The outlook of the Vedic people was deeply spiritual and a number of speculations about the origin and destiny of the universe were prevalent. The ideal of sacrifice (yajna) and penance (tapas) asserted itself. Robust life affirmation, philosophical wisdom, and religious intuition were the chief characteristics. The spiritual and the religious inspired the secular. The Jaina and the Buddhist attitudes were exclusively spiritual and religious, and more or less neglected the secular. The disproportionate growth of asceticism in Jainism and Buddhism on the one hand and the balanced growth of the religious and the secular in Brahmanism on the other were responsible for the demarcation between the sramanic and the Brahmanic outlook. The Sankhya-Yoga, the Nyaya-Vaisesika and the Vedanta virtually belong to the same group as the Jaina and the Buddhist, The Mimamsaka belongs to the other group. There were, among the Vedic people, 1 The doctrine of karman seems to have developed against a number of other doctrines about creation. Some regarded time (kala) as the determinant factor of creation. Every event occurs in time and hence is determined by time. Others believed in nature (svabhava) as the determining factor of creation. Things are determined by their own inherent nature. There is nothing, inside or outside, over and above nature, that determines the course of events. This leads to the doctrine of determinism (niyati-vada). There were others who believed in the fortuitous and accidental nature of the occurrences of events. There were other doctrines as well. (Vide SvUP, I. 2. SVS, II. 52-64). The believers in karman or the unseen potency (adrsta), the after-effect of a good or bad action, regarded these theories as inspired by materialistic tendencies and therefore rejected them as untenable. The Jaina philosophers accorded proper place to these doctrines as testified by our experience, while installing karman in the supreme position. Karman is the ultimate determinant of the course of events. Even time, nature and niyati are determined by karman and there is no such thing as fortuitism. These factors, in so far as they are given to experience, are only the expressions of the working of the supreme law of karman. (Cf. STP, III, 53 ; SVS, II. 79-81). of bad earstion karman of the sits well. (Vid Page #258 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV INTRODUCTORY 221 some who were more contemplative, other-worldly and attracted towards life negation than the ordinary. It is these people who helped the growth of asceticism. But before the development of asceticism there was the natural development of the ideas of rebirth and kayman. There was also the development of corresponding metaphysics. If spiritual emancipation is a fact there must be a number of births for its realization. This leads to the doctrine of rebirth. The selfsame of emancipation again presupposes corruption of the spirit in the state of worldly existence. But what is this corruption due to? It is due to beginningless nescience about truth. We have studied nescience in the last chapter. According to the Jaina, nescience presupposes the soul's association with karman which is known as unseen potency (adysta), predisposition (vasana), energy (sakti), trap (pasa) etc. in other systems. Karman is needed to explain variety and unequality. In this chapter we shall record a few determinant characteristics of the doctrine of karman as found in the Jaina system with comparative reference to other systems. In the preceding chapter we studied the nature of the fundamental factor responsible for the relation between spirit and non-spirit, that is, the world order. But here we shall record the modus operandi of the non-spirit upon the spirit or, more accurately, the process whereby an action (karman) produces its reaction (phala). Among the systematic schools, only the Nyaya-Vaisesika admits God as the necessary condition for the fruition of the action (karman) which remains as an unseen potency (adrsta) consisting in merit and demerit in the soul. The Yoga admits God only as an object of worship or meditation and not as an agent in the fruition of the karman. The Sankhya-Yoga, the Jaina and the Buddhist and the Mimamsaka regard the unseen potency itself as competent to produce its fruit in time. Though in the Brahmasutral of Badarayana the agency of God in the dispensation of the fruits of acts, moral and immoral, is advocated with vehemence it however loses metaphysical validity in the system of Sankara who accords a provisional place to Personal God in his monistic Vedanta. Personal God as the creator, sustainer and destroyer of the world order is necessary only so long as maya holds sway. But maya is unreal as a metaphysical entity and as such God's place is only provisional and not more than penultimate. The problem how can the unconscious and inactive potency develop into fruition is explained in various ways. The potency is due to karman (action) and as such is also designated by the term karman. The nature of the predispositions (vasanas) or afflictions (klesas) or passions (kasayas), in one word, the impurity of the spirit determines the character, quantity, duration and intensity of the karman or the 1 phalam ata upapatteh-BS, III, 2. 38. Page #259 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [CH. unseen potency (adrsta). The necessity of the agency of God for the fruition of karman is thus avoided. The Nyaya-Vaisesika also in so far as its early adumbration is taken into account has little necessity for the postulation of God. If we are to believe the Yuktidipika, an early commentary on Isvarakrsna's Sankhyakarika, the introduction of God into the architectonic of the Vaisesika system is due to the influence of the Pasupatas.1 But whatever may be the genesis the conception of an omnipotent God has found place in the system since 'Vatsyayana and Prasastapada. The other systems could well work without Him. The unseen potency or karman, as determined by the conditions and predispositions of the soul, can automatically produce the fruits. We shall study the Jaina conception of the modus operandi of karman in this chapter, stating also, where possible, the corresponding conceptions in other systems. 222 The The relation between the spirit and the non-spirit is responsible for the worldly existence. Apart from the gross body, there is a subtle body which serves as a link between the spiritual and the non-spiritual. This subtle body is the karmic body of the Jainas and the subtle body (linga-sarira) of the Sankhya-Yoga. We shall discuss the problem of the relation between the subtle body and the soul later on. Vedantin regards the non-spiritual as only an appearance, and yet for him the problem how does the false appearance occur and induce individual selves and the world of plurality is as tough as in the other systems. The Nyaya-Vaisesika and the Mimamsaka regard the unseen potency, as a quality of the soul, responsible for the formation of the gross body with the help of the mind (manas). In Buddhism, the predispositions (vasanas) or the afflictions (klesas) relate the conscious (nama) with the material (rupa). According to the Jainas, the vibrations (yoga) and the passions (kasayas) of the soul attract karmic matter and transform it into karmic body. In the Sankhya-Yoga, the subtle body is formed due to the perversions (viparyayas) or afflictions (klesas) of the principle of buddhi which is an evolute of the non-spiritual prakrti. Here we must distinguish between the SankhyaYoga and the Jaina conceptions. With the Sankhya-Yoga, the principle of consciousness (purusa) is ubiquitous and immutable and therefore undergoes no change. It is only the unconscious prakrti and its evolutes the buddhi and the like-that are ever changing. The afflictions (klesas) belong to the buddhi and are responsible for the formation of the subtle body which is nothing but a conglomeration of a number of evolutes of the selfsame prakyti. The position of the Jainas, however, is quite different. The soul, with the Jainas, evam Kanadanam Isvaro 'sti 'ti Pasupato 1 Cf. Yuktidipika (p. 88): 'pajnam etat. Page #260 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. 1] MATERIAL NATURE OF KARMAN 223 undergoes change every moment, although never losing its identity, The soul has a number of potencies, and each moment of its existence is an integration of those potencies. The nature of the karmic body at any moment is determined by this integrated existence of the soul. The soul is pure and perfect in its intrinsic nature. It is due only to its relation with karman that the soul comes to have passions (kasayas). And the relation being beginningless, the problem which of the two-the passions and the karman-comes first does not arise. We shall deal with the problem in due course. The common ground among the different systems is the belief in the intrinsic purity of the self and its capacity to recover its essential nature after a course of moral discipline and philosophical enlightenment. The question why the pure self should come to be invested with the impurity of matter is one of fact as ultimate as its own existence. We find that the soul is not free and perfect which the demands of logic make us accept as the indubitable presupposition. As the soul is immortal and timeless so also is matter--at any rate so far as the first limit is concerned. It is not profitable to question the possibility of a fact. It is there. The question rather is whether this unfreedom and imperfection can be transcended and if so, how. The necessity of the postulation of karmic matter as forming a crust, as it were, on the soul and disturbing its purity is another problem. The complete study of these problems requires also the statement of the various conditions and processes of karman. We shall thus deal with the following four problems in the present chapter: (I) the necessity of postulating the material nature of karman; (II) the relation between soul and karman; (III) the classification of karman; and (IV) the various states and processes of karman. We shall also record, wherever possible and necessary, the corresponding conceptions of the non-Jaina systems. THE MATERIAL NATURE OF KARMAN The Indian philosophers with the exception of the Carvakas are unanimous that the worldly status of the self, as it is, is an evil and must be got rid of. They also agree upon the existence of a fundamental defect that conditions the worldly existence. We have seen this in the last chapter. There are, however, radical differences in the soul-conceptions of the different schools, and consequently there are corresponding differences in the expositions of the various evils making up the worldly existence. The Carvaka does not believe in soul although he believes in empirical consciousness which he regards Page #261 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 224 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [CH. only as a peculiar phenomenon born of the combination of elements. The consciousness has no pre-natal history. Nor has it any post mortem. This materialist view of life is vehemently criticized by the believers in beginningless existence and endless continuance of consciousness reaching its consummation in freedom from worldly bondage (called apavarga or nirvana). Haribhadra, following an old tradition, says that the materialist view indeed was invented by BIhaspati only in order to deceive Indra who, however, could not be deceived in view of its utter lack of logical propriety. Now we pass on to the consideration of the various conceptions of the conscious principle and the defects that vitiate it, stating also the difficulties of these conceptions from the Jaina's point of view. In the end we shall record the Jaina position. The Sankhya-Yoga believes in immutable principles of consciousness, unamenable to any corruption, and yet concedes the reality of the corrupt world existence. The world processes and their conditions belong to the prakrti. In other words, the conscious principle is involved in the evils of the world which does not belong to it. The Jaina philosopher is not prepared to admit the propriety of such position. If the conscious principle is involved in evils, the evils must belong to itself. Moreover, the conception of evil loses all its meaning nd purpose unless the conscious principle is really associated with it. The worldly existence is a state of bondage and as such presupposes a fall of the conscious principle. But the Sankhya-Yoga is not prepared to admit any change in the being of the principle of consciousness which he regards as absolutely immutable. We have discussed the difficulties in this position in the last chapter, and shall not repeat them again. The spiritual and the material do never commingle and yet there is the world order which means the mutual sympathy and co-operation of the two. The spiritual is ever kept aloof from the material, and yet attempts are made to establish relation between them by speculative devices which can satisfy the imagination, but can never appeal to the faculty of reason. The gulf between the spiritual and the material ever remains unreconciled in spite of so many attempts by such exponents as Vacaspati and Vijnanabhiksu. The Vedantin distinguishes between the spiritual and the material. But his distinction is only a make-believe. All plurality, spiritual or material, is false. The world is only empirically true and hence its conditions have also only empirical existence. Karman belongs to the principle of world illusion (maya) and hence is not something belonging to the spirit. And as the maya of the Vedantin is not, to all intents and purposes, different from the prakyti of the Sankhya-Yoga, 1 Indra-prataranaye 'dam cakre kila BIhaspatih ado 'pi yukti-sunyam yan ne 'ttham Indrah prataryate.--SVS, I. III. Page #262 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. 1] MATERIAL NATURE OF KARMAN 225 all the defects of the Sankhya-Yoga conception of karman ought to apply equally well to the Vedantin's conception. The'Nyaya-Vaisesika admits that the conditions of bondage viz. merit and demerit belong to the soul, but keeps them quite distinct and aloof from it. The soul is held to be immutable and ubiquitous, and merit and demerit, jointly called unseen potency, inhere in it as qualities. But how can the qualities of the soul be responsible for the bondage of the soul? And in the absence of the bondage of the soul, it should be admitted that the soul ever remains free from bondage. It may be argued that as the passions of anger, pride etc. condition the bondage of the soul although they are qualities of it, so there should be no difficulty in admitting that the qualities of the soul can be responsible for the bondage of the soul. But the Jaina's reply to such a contention is: Such changes of the soul as the passions of anger and the like are of the nature of bondage; the changes into anger and the like are indeed the bondage itself of the soul, and not the conditions of the bondage. The passions constitute the bondage. And their conditions must necessarily be distinct and different from them. And the passions being the qualities of the soul, it follows that the conditions of the passions are something distinct and separate from the qualities of the soul. And so the conditions of the passions and. the bondage that they constitute must be sought for in what is material Creation is a veritable intermixture of the spiritual and the material, a beginningless inter-influencing of the two. There is no bondage without the inter-relation of spirit and matter, and there is no interrelation of spirit and matter without the bondage. The philosopher of the Nyaya-Vaisesika school also admits the fact. But because of his bias for the absolute immutability of the soul and the absolute separateness of the qualities from its substance, he fails to remain consistent with his realistic position by following the verdicts of uncontradicted and well attested experience. How can the mind relate the body with the soul without itself being really related with both? Even the merit and demerit remain without any real relation with the soul. It is impossible to conceive of any real relation without admitting some kind of identity-cum-difference between the relata--a fact which the Nyaya-Vaisesika is unwilling to accept. According to the Jaina philosopher, the worldly existence is impossible without the admission of the relation of identity-cum-difference between the spiritual and the 1 Cf. nanu ca "tma-gunatvat karmanam katham paudgalikatvam ity anye ; te 'py apariksakah ; tesam atma-gunatve tat-paratantrya-nimittatva-virodhat sarvada "tmano bandhanupapatteh sadaiva mukti-prasangat--PKM, p. 243. 2 Cf. na ca krodhadibhir vyabhicarah; tesam jiva-parinamanam paratantryasvabhavatvat; krodhadi-parinamo hi jivasya paratantryam na punah paratantrya-nimittam-PKM, pp. 243-4. JP-29 Page #263 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 226 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [CH. material, and, therefore, it is maintained that the soul and the matter become somehow identical in the state of worldly existence. The Nyaya-Vaisesika does not admit any sort of identity between spirit and matter, and yet regards merits and demerits as qualities of the soul, born of various activities of the material body and mind. This is certainly ununderstandable. The Buddhist regards nescience as the cover on consciousness (vijnana) and as such the seed of worldly existence. Nescience is as formless (amurta) as the consciousness, for, according to the Buddhist only the formless can affect the formless. The material (rupa) cannot cover the conscious (nama). But the Jaina contention is that if the seed of worldly existence lies within the consciousness itself and is of the same nature and is not dependent upon the material, emancipation will not be possible at any time. If the condition of wild process lies within and is integral to consciousness irrespective of anything external, what reason can there be for emancipation from it? Nature is inalienable from the thing. If fire can forfeit its nature and assume the nature of water, fire will cease to be fire. The Yogacara Buddhist avoids the difficulty by asserting the unreality of the material world itself. But the Jaina as a realist is not prepared to accept the unreality of the worldly career which is as much a fact as the existence of the spirit. The Jaina does not believe in the difficulty of the material (murta) affecting the spiritual (amuita). Consciousness which is spiritual is certainly found to be affected by intoxicating drugs which are material. The worldly existence means concrete association of the spiritual and the material. Impossibility of co-operation between spirit and matter, in the Buddhist terminology between nama (the conscious) and rupa (the material), means impossibility of the world order. Those who do not believe in concrete association or co-operation are finally led to reject the material as illogical and unnecessary. The Jaina philosopher, as a staunch realist, is not prepared to proceed on abstract logic and reject what is so unambiguously given in experience. | The Jaina avoids all these absolutist conceptions of the nature of karman. He avoids the Sankhya-Yoga difficulty of relation between the immutable purusa (principle of consciousness) and the mutable prakrti by admitting real modification of the soul and its concrete association with karmic matter. The soul is ever changing by its own nature and, in the state of worldly existence, this change is determined by the nature of the karmic matter that is associated with it. The nature of the associated karmic matter (karma-pudgala) is determined by the nature of the passions (kasayas) of the soul and the nature of the passions is determined by the nature of the karmic matter. This mutual determination has no beginning in time, and this explains the apparent difficulty of the first beginning of the process. The Jaina Page #264 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. 17 MATERIAL NATURE OF KARMAN 227 does not blink the difficulty by admitting beginninglessness, but only asserts a fact which is admitted by all the other schools. The NyayaVai esika leaves the initiative in the hands of God, and yet he has to admit that God only gives the fruits of the past actions and cannot determine anything of His own accord. The Jaina does not believe in any Divine Power taking interest in the destiny of the universe. This is of course a digression. In contrast with the concrete mutual co-operation of the soul and the karmic matter, the Sarkhya-Yoga envisages only an apparent relation between immutable consciousness and prakyti. The Jaina, as a thoroughgoing realist, smells grounds for refutation of realism itself in the Sankhya-Yoga conception. Once we are unfaithful to our experience and tread the path of absolutist logic, we are sure to enter the pitfall of subjectivism or, worse than that, nihilism. The Jaina philosopher goes so far as to say that, in the state of worldly existence, the soul possesses, in common with the karmic matter with which it is associated, material form (murtatva) which is regarded as only a characteristic of the material things.1 The Buddhist conceives the condition of the world order as lying exclusively in the consciousness. But the Jaina considers this as another untenable extreme exactly like the counter-extreme of the Sankhya-Yoga who regards the condition as lying exclusively in the prakrti. We have already recorded the objections against the position. The Jainas distinguish between the material karman called dravya-karman, and its spiritual counterpart called bhava-karman. The former is also called avarana (cover) and the latter dosa (defects).2 The defects are the passions or privations and perversions of the capacities of the soul while the covers are constituted by karmic matter that brings about those privations and perversions. The material karman and its spiritual counterpart are mutually related as cause and effect, each of the other.4 This is possible only if the worldly existence is accepted to be without beginning. And the Jaina, like all the other schools, finds no difficulty in admitting it." That Hatt' 49 # . . 1 Cf. ahava neganto 'yam samsari savvaha amutto 'tti jam anadi-kamma-santati-parinamavanna-ruvo so. -Dharmasangrahani, gatha 626. 2 Vide Astasahasri on AMi, 4 (pp. 50-51). 3 Gommatasara, however, regards the potency of the material karman as the bhava-karman-Karmakanda, 6. But this view is not very appealing and logical. 4ff. dosavaranayor jiva-pudgala-parinamayor anyonya-karyakarana-bhavahapanarthatvat ... Astasahasri, p. 51. 5 Cf. jivasya bhavasravo ... kasayadin... sa ca karma-bandhanusarato 'neka-prakaro... karma punar nlnam anekaprakaram kasaya-visesad bhavakarmana iti hetu-phala vyavastha. parasparasrayan na tadvyavasthe 'ti cen, na, bijankuravad anaditvat karya-karana-bhavasya, tatra sarvesam sampratipattes ca-TSIV, p. 447. Page #265 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 228 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN (CH. Now, in Jaina terminology, we can say that the Sankhya-Yoga (the Vedantin also included) admits only material karman and not its spiritual counterpart as well while the Buddhist admits only the spiritual counterpart and not the material karman Karman, in the ultimate analysis, is a link between spirit and matter, and lasts as long as the worldly existence lasts. It co-ordinates the mutual changes of the spirit and the matter associated with the spirit. In the Sankhya-Yoga view, karman belongs exclusively to the prakrti and hence it is only the prakrti that is bound or emancipated. In the Buddhist view, the karman belongs exclusively to the consciousness and it is only the consciousness that is bound and emancipated. But the Jaina philosopher is not satisfied with this unilateral view of the worldly existence. Worldly existence means bondage of both spirit and matter, in relation to one another. Emancipation means emancipation of both spirit and. matter. If the various states of passions make up the bondage of the spirit the change of the material atoms into karmic matter makes up the bondage of matter. The freedom of a soul from the passions and their effects means also the freedom of karmic matter from association with the soul. The difficulty in the Nyaya-Vaisesika position has already been stated. So far we have considered the problem only as it crops up at the most developed level of our thought. But it will be profitable to throw a historical glance at the development at this stage of our enquiry. We found that the Sankhya-Yoga (the Vedantin also included), the Nyaya-Vaisesika and the Buddhist keep spirit or consciousness quite aloof from matter, while the Jaina attempts to establish concrete relation between them. It is necessary, if possible, to trace the origin of this difference between the Jaina and the non-Jaina views. For this purpose we are to travel back to hoary past of our thought, and to reconstruct, from the scanty materials that are still available, the structure of the thought of that age. Let us make an attempt. The Vedic thinkers had a clear intuition of the unity of the multifold expressions of the universe. They saw unity 'in diversity, How, why, and when this intuition of unity dawned upon the Vedic mind is a problem too difficult to solve. One unitary principle, Sat or Asat, is regarded as the ground of all creation, conscious and unconscious. The conscious ego is as much an evolute of Sat or Asat as the unconscious elements. Different theories of evolution were developed on the basis of the recognition of this unitary principle which was further called Brahman as well as Prakyti. The conception of Sat, Asat, Brahman, or Prakrti as the ultimate ground of creation was the most important consummation of the Vedic thought. This ultimate ground is ubiquitous, subtle and unamenable to any sense-organ. It is the ground of everything and has no further ground. On the other Page #266 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. 1] MATERIAL NATURE OF KARMAN 229 side, there were thinkers who believed in an infinite number of unchanging material atoms along with an infinite number of souls of variable size as constituting the contents of the universe. The conception of immutability did not appear as yet. It appeared only when the conception of eternal emancipation came in. This we shall see presently. There were yet others who believed in consciousness as only a temporary evolute of the combination of material atoms. They were the materialists. It is not possible to ascertain the chronological priority among these three. We can, of course, imagine a time when all these three flourished side by side. The materialists remained throughout as they were. There was, however, multilateral change in the other two groups which gradually gave rise to a number of others. Let us study, in brief, the history of this change and development. Although it is not possible to ascertain when and how the ideal of eternal spiritual emancipation asserted itself, yet it is without doubt that the ideal necessitated a number of relevant changes in the thoughtstructure of India of prehistoric times. Rebirth and karman had already asserted themselves. The nature of eternal emancipation gradually drew the attention. There was a steady demand for clarification of the issue. The upholders of one unitary principle as the ground of conscious egoes had to adjust their speculations in favour of the admission of an infinite number of ubiquitous, eternal and unchanging conscious principles (purusas) side by side with the everevolving unitary principle of Prakrti which had already been conceived as constituted of the threefold moments of luminosity (sattva), energy (rajas) and inertia (tamas). The other alternative to this adjustment was to reinterpret the unitary ever-evolving principle as a ubiquitous, eternal and immutable conscious principle and to reject its evolutes as false appearance. The first type of orientation gave rise to what is known as the Sankhya-Yoga metaphysics, while the second reinterpretation could easily give rise to such system as the Advaita Vedanta of Sankara. On the other side, the believers in material atoms and variable souls conceived a state of the soul, which is absolutely pure and eternal. Worldly existence is an association of material atoms with the souls, and emancipation is soul in its state of absolute purity and freedom from all association with matter. The soul, being of variable size and amenable to changes, is conceived as changing even in the state of emancipation. But the change in emancipation is uniform and does not mean change into different kinds of states. Such thoughts made up the foundation of the Jaina system. Originally, it seems, the soul was conceived as a quasi-material principle. This is apparent from such synonyms of jiva (soul) as sattva, prana (breath) and bhuta. The names could well be applicable to the above-mentioned conscious egoes as evolved from the Prakyti as well. The affinity of these two Page #267 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 230 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [CH. types of conceptions is quite obvious. There is, however, no doubt that one was developed on the background of Prakrti and the other in consonance with the atomistic conception of the physical world. The Buddha constructed his metaphysics or rather his critique of metaphysics at a period when these various conceptions were fully developed. The conscious (nama) and the material (rupa) were conceived on the pattern of buddhi and tanmatras (subtle elements) of the SankhyaYoga. They were kept as aloof as the soul and matter of the Jainas or rather as purusa (the conscious principle) and prakrti of the SankhyaYoga. There were thinkers who accepted the immutable conscious principle of the Sankhya-Yoga but transferred, perhaps for the sake of logical consistency, the function of knowing, feeling, and willing which belonged to the material evolute buddhi, to the conscious principle as its qualities. They further accepted the atomistic conception with important modifications. The Vaisesika system seems to have originated in the hands of such thinkers. The logical school of Gautama joined the Vaisesika. This, in brief, seems to be the historical evolution of the Indian metaphysical thought. It is certainly nothing but a tentative suggestion. In the absence of indubitable records all our speculations into the genesis of philosophical and religious doctrines in the prehistoric past are bound to remain in the plane of conjectural reconstructions. But history is not so very fundamental to the determination of the plausibility or validity of a philosophical conclusion. It is enough if we can show that the conclusion is not incompatible with the given data of experience and the canons of logical thought. In the absence of the latter all the conclusions and doctrines of a school will be convicted of dogmatism. History is important for the satisfaction of our psychological interest how one thought has given rise to another thought or how one school has influenced another school in its development. But the logical and philosophical validity of a doctrine can be established only by means of logical weapons which are eternal and inevitable laws of thought and as such not subject to historical evolution at any rate in respect of their logical cogency. The evolution consists in the explicit formulation of these laws which, with the growth of logical clarity, come to be expressed with progressively greater precision. But we feel that they are our own modes of thought and not imposed upon us from outside. These laws are so fundamental and so primitive and so spontaneous that they are incapable of being repudiated_although their interpretation has been different in conformity with the different philosophical predilections of thinkers. But this historical speculation may help us to understand the reason why the Sankhya-Yoga (the Vedantin also included), the Nyaya Page #268 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. 11] RELATION BETWEEN SOUL AND KARMAN 231 Vaisesika and the Buddhist had to keep spirit or consciousness quite aloof from matter, while the Jaina could conceive of the inter-influencing of the soul and the karmic matter. The conception of the immutability of soul dominated, in some form or other, the evolved systems, and was responsible for their insistence on the absolute aloofness of spirit from matter. Even the Buddhists who believed in radical momentary change could not escape from the influence of this conception, inasmuch as they do not admit as concrete a relation between the conscious and the material as do the Jainas between soul and karmic matter. The Jainas, on the other hand, were faithful to their thoroughly realistic tradition building up itself on the uncontradicted verdicts of experience. The Jaina conception of the co-operative association of spirit and matter and the postulation of the material counterpart of the spiritual states of passions owe their origin to this faithfulness to the original realistic and empirical attitude. Now we come to the problem of relation between soul and karman, II RELATION BETWEEN SOUL AND KARMAN The problem of relation occupies a very important place in metaphysical thinking. The Jainas, as realists, did not hesitate to accept whatever was given in uncontradicted experience, and moulded their logic in accordance with such experience. Substance and its modes (qualities also included) are given as identical as well as different in experience and as such the relation of identity-cum-difference was posited. Substance without modes or modes without substance can never be experienced. Both their identity and difference are equally given in experience. The dictum of abstract logic viz. 'What are different cannot be identical and what are identical cannot be different' is not accepted as universal and necessary because experience records cases where this dictum does not hold good, for instance, in the case of substance and its modes. The relation of spirit and matter is another problem. We have already referred to it on more than one occasion. The Jaina believes in concrete identity between the soul and the karmic matter in the state of bondage while the non-Jaina schools are reluctant to admit any real relation between spirit and matter and consequently have felt called upon to invent a number of devices to explain the fact of bondage. We have recorded in detail the positions of the various systems of Indian thought and their criticism from the Jaina standpoint. The karmic matter, according to the Jainas, mixes with the soul much in the same way as milk mixes Page #269 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 232 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [CH. with water or fire with iron. In the state of bondage the soul is infected with a kind of susceptibility to establish relation with the nonsoul. This susceptibility finds expression in the passion-states of the soul. In the ultimate analysis, this susceptibility is but a state of the soul in conjunction with matter. We have already sought to explain the problem. Next we turn to the topic of classification of karman. III CLASSIFICATION OF KARMAN The soul in its pure state possesses a number of characteristic attributes which are obscured and distorted in the defiled state of bondage. This obscuration and distortion find expression in the imperfect existence of the soul. In the state of perfection, the soul has infiniteness of knowledge, intuition and bliss as well as freedom from delusion, delimited longevity, embodied existence, difference of status and obstruction of energy. The karmic matter obscures or obstructs these characteristics of the soul and keeps it away from its supreme state of existence. The soul, under the influence of passions (kasayas) and possessed of yoga (that is, the vibrations of body, vocal organ, and mind) attracts karmic matter (karma-pudgala') which then is inseparably mixed up with the soul. The resultant state is bondage (bandha). Even as a lamp by its temperature draws up the oil with its wick and, after drawing up, converts the oil into its body (viz. glow), exactly so does a soul-lamp, with the attributes of attachment and the like, attract the material aggregates by the wick of its activities and after attracting, transforms them into karman.'s The karman, as we have stated above, obscures as well as distorts the attributes of the soul, and is classified into eight main types. The types that obscure knowledge and intuition are respectively called knowledge-covering (jnanavarana) and intuition-covering (darsanavarana). The type of karmic matter that holds up the natural bliss and produces earthly pleasure and suffering is called feeling-producing (vedaniya) karman. The type that effects delusion, theoretical and practical, metaphysical and ethical, is deluding (mohaniya) karman. The type that breaks up the immortal continuity of existence into so many mortal fragments 1 Vide supra, p. 65 for the conception of karma-vargana. 2 TSu, VIII. 2-3. 3usma-gunah san dipah sneham vartya yatha samadatte adaya sarirataya parinamayati ca 'pi tam sneham. tadvad ragadi-gunah svayoga-vartya "tmadipa adatte skandhan adaya tatha parinamayati tams ca karmataya. -TSuBh Tika, Part I, p. 343. Page #270 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. III] CLASSIFICATION OF KARMAN 233 consisting of short or long spans of life is longevity-determining (ayuska) karman. The embodiment of the bodiless is the working of the type called body-making (nama)-karman. What produces difference of racial, social or genealogical status in what are naturally without difference, in other words, what conditions gradations in the ungraded, is called status-determining (gotra) karman. The type that obstructs the infinite energy of the soul and causes handicaps in the enjoyment of wealth and power is called obstructive (antaraya) karman. These are the eight main types of karman. There are numbers of sub-types of each main type. Let us here notice them in brief without going into their details for want of philosophical interest. There are five categories of knowledge and hence there are five sub-types of the knowledge-covering karman that veils them. There are nine sub-types of intuition-covering karmans. Of these, the first four are respectively the covers of eye-intuition (caksurdarsana), noneye-intuition (acaksurdarsana), visual intuition (avadhidarsana) and pure and perfect intuition (kevala-darsana). The effects of the remaining five intuition-covering karmans are felt respectively in sleep with easy awakening (nidra),% sleep with difficult awakening (nidra-nidra), sleep while seated or standing (pracala),5 sleep while walking (pracalapracala) and sleep accompanied by superhuman deeds (styana-gyddhi or styanardhi). The feeling-producing karman has two sub-types viz. (1) what, by its rise, causes pleasant feeling (sadvedya or satavedaniya), and (2) what, by its rise, causes unpleasant feeling (asadvedya or asatavedaniya). The deluding karman is primarily divided into two groups: (I) what deludes the right vision (darsana-mohaniya) and (II) what deludes the right conduct (caritra-mohaniya). The first group has three sub-types viz. (I) what, by its rise, makes the soul lose vision of truth and see a thing as it is not (mithyatva-vedaniya), (2) what is a state of purity of the first sub-type (and is called samyaktva-vedaniya), and (3) what is a mixed state of purity-cumimpurity of the same sub-type. The second group is subdivided into two sub-groups viz. (I) whose rise is accompanied by the reign of passions (kasaya-vedaniya), and (2) whose rise is accompanied by the reign of quasi-passions (no-kasaya-vedaniya). The first sub-group has sixteen sub-types giving rise to the sixteen kinds of passions viz. anger 1 Vide supra, p. 28. 2 TSU, VIII. 7. 3 svapo nidra sukha-pratibodha-laksana-TSuBh Tika, Part II, p. 134. 4 duhkha-pratibodha-laksana nidra-nidra-Ibid., p. 135. 5 urdhva-sayana-laksana pracala-Ibid. 6 cankramanam acaratah sayanam pracala-pracala-Ibid. 7 We have not followed the derivative meaning for which see ibid. See also Kgi, I. 12 with svopajna Tika. 8 Ibid., pp. 137-9. See also Kgr, I. 14-15. JP-30 Page #271 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 234 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [Ch. (krodha), pride (mana), deceit (maya) and greed (lobha)-each again being of four types viz. (1) what obscures the right vision and leads to 'endless' worldly existence (anantanubandhin), (2) what arrests even the aptitude for partial renunciation (apratyakhyanavarana), (3) what arrests only the aptitude for complete renunciation (pratyakhyanavarana), and (4) what afflicts the spiritually advanced soul only occasionally and blocks only the perfect type of conduct (samjualana). The second sub-group has nine sub-types giving rise severally to the nine kinds of quasi-passions viz. laughter, addiction, dissatisfaction, bewailing, fear, disgust, hankering after women, hankering after men and hankering after both the sexes. The quasi-passions are so called because they coexist with the passions and also are inspired by them.2 The longevity-determining karman has four sub-types whose rise severally determines the life-span in hell, plant and animal world, human existence and celestial world. Next we come to the bodymaking (nama)-karman which has a great number of sub-types accounting for various forms of embodied existence. 3 Thus the rise of various gatinaman accounts for the various forms of existence in hell, plant and animal world, human world, as well as celestial region. The jati-naman accounts for the various classes of living organisms one-sensed, twosensed and the like. The rise of sarira-naman accounts for the creation of various bodies such as the gross (audarika), the subtle (vaikriya) and the like. In the same way various functions are allotted to the rise of the organ-building, joint-building, structure-building and such other nama-karmans. We do not enumerate them for lack of relevant interest. The rise of the status-determining karman is responsible for high or low status of an individual. The obstructive karman has five sub-types viz. what obstructs the inclination for making gifts and charities, what obstructs the occasion of gain, what prevents the enjoy PP. 34-5. 1 Ibid., pp. 140-1. See also Kg1, pp. 34-5. The anantanubandhin is the most virulent type of passion. Such anger, pride, deceit and greed are respectively compared to a split in mountain rock, a mountain-column, a bamboo-knot and a lac-stain, which are so difficult to eradicate. The apratyakhyanavarana is a little milder. Such anger etc. are compared respectively to a soil-split, a bone-column, a ram-horn and a mudstain, which can be affected by a little less effort. The pratyakhyanavarana is still milder, and such anger etc. are respectively compared to a sand-split, a wood-column, a go-mutrika (cow's urine), and a safflower-stain. The samjvalana is still more mild and such anger etc. are respectively compared to a watersplit, a straw-column, a carpenter's scratch and a turmeric stain. (Cf. TSuBh, VIII. 10). 2 Cf. kasaya-sahavartitvat kasaya-preranad api hasyadi-navakasyo 'kta no-kasaya-kasayata. --TSuBh Tika, Part II, p. 141, 3 TSubh, VIII. 12. 4 Ibid., VIII. 13 Page #272 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. III] CLASSIFICATION OF KARMAN 235 ment of things that last only for the period of enjoyment, what prevents the enjoyment of things that last for some time and lastly what prevents the free expression of energy. These are, in brief, the types and sub-types of karman. We have stated that karmic matter is attracted and bound due to vibrations (yoga) and passions (kasaya). Here it is necessary to distinguish between the functions of vibrations and passions. The length of duration (sthiti) and intensity of fruition (anubhaga) of the bondage between the soul and the karmic matter attracted depend upon the nature of the passions of the soul. The stronger the passions the lengthier and intenser are the duration and fruition of the bondage This rule, however, applies only to the bondage of inauspicious or sinfyl (asubha or papa) karmans, that is, karmans whose fruition causes suffering. In the case of the bondage of auspicious or virtuous (subha or punya) karmans, although the length of the duration varies directly as the strength of the passions, the intensity of fruition varies inversely as the strength. And this is but logical. The greater the defilement of the soul the less is its purity, and the less the purity the looser is the bondage of the auspicious karmans. And, therefore, the greater the defilement of the soul, the less is the intensity of the fruition of the auspicious karmans. In other words, the intensity of fruition of auspicious karmans varies inversely as the strength of the passions. As regards the relation between the length of duration and the intensity of fruition of karmans, in the case of the inauspicious karmans the intensity of fruition varies directly as the length of duration, while in the case of auspicicus karmanss the intensity of fruition varies inversely as the length of duration. There are interesting speculations about the measure of the maximum and minimum length of duration and intensity of fruition of the various karmans. The maximum lengths of duration are measured in years whose number is beyond 1 Ibid., VIII. 14. 2 It is also called anubhava or rasa. Cf. Kg2, p. 63: anubhago raso 'nubhava iti paryaya). 3 Cf. thii anubhagain kasayao kunai.--Sivasarmasuri's Satakakarmagrantha, gatha 99. See also Kg2, p. 120 (Karmagrantha V, gatha 96). 4 Cf. kasaya-vrddhav anubhago 'subha-prakrtinam eva vardhate subhanain tu parihiyata eva, kasaya-mandataya tu subha-prakstinam eva 'nubhago vardhate 'subha-prakstinam tu hiyata iti na kasayam anuvartate. sthitayas tu subhanam asubhanami ca prakstinan kasaya-vrddhau niyamad vardhante, tada pacaye tv apaciyanta iti-Kg2, p. 51. 5 The three subha-karmans viz. those leading to the plant and animal life, human life and divine life are excepted. In their case the intensity of fruition varies directly as the length of duration. 6 Cf. yatha yatha subha-prakstinam sthitir vardhate tatha tatha subhanubhagas tatsambandhi hiyate.. asubha-prakstinam tu sthitivsddhav asubha-raso 'pi tatsambandhi vardhata eva ..-Kg2, p. 51. Page #273 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 236 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [CH. ordinary conception of number. Thus, for instance, the maximum length of duration of the knowledge-covering, the intuition-covering, the feeling-producing and the obstructive karmans is thirty sagaropamakoti-koti years, of the deluding karman is seventy, of the body-making and the status-determining twenty, and of longevity-determining thirtythree sagaropama years. The minimum lengths are measured in units of forty-eight minutes (muhurtas).2 As regards the measure of the intensity of fruition, the Jainas adopt a special device. The intensity of a karman is the depth of enjoyment or suffering with which the fruition of the karman is accompanied. There is infinite gradation in the depth. The intenser the fruition of an inauspicious karman, the deeper is the suffering. The intenser the fruition of an auspicious karman the deeper is the enjoyment. The infinite gradation of intensity is conceived as falling into four groups called the first degree (eka-sthanika), the second degree (dvi-sthanika), the third degree (tri-sthanika) and the fourth degree (catuh-sthanika) group. The intensity of fruition (anubhaga) is conceived as divisible into infinite number of indivisible parts which cannot be further divided. Each one of such indivisible parts is called 'indivisible unit' (avibhagapaliccheda). Even the single atom of an aggregate of karmic matter (karma-skandha) possessed of the least intensity has an infinite number of such indivisible units. Let us imagine a group (vargana) consisting of such atoms as are possessed of the least intensity. Then there is another group consisting of such atoms as are possessed of one more unit of intensity (rasa-bhaga). Then there is a group consisting of such atoms as are possessed of two more intensity-units, and so on up to the group which is not followed by a group consisting of atoms with the next consecutive number of units. An infinite number of 'consecutive groups' are obtained in this way. The totality of these groups is called the first intensity-class (spardhaka). The first group of the 1 See TSu, VIII. 15-18. About the conception of sagaropama see TSubh, IV. 15. For the conceptions of palyopama and other numbers see Karmagrantha IV, gathas 71-86 with Devendra's Commentary (Kg1, pp. 199-213). 2 See TSu, VIII. 19-21. 3 f. uktah sanklesa-visuddhi-vasad asubha-subha-prakstinam tivro mandas ca 'nubhagah, ayam tveka-dvi-tri-catuh-sthanika-bhedac caturdha bhavati Kg2, p. 64. 4 Cf. kevali-prajnaya chidyamano yah parama-nikrsto 'nubhagamso 'tisuksmataya 'rdham na dadati so 'vibhaga-paliccheda ucyate. uktam ca: buddhii chijjamano anubhagamso na dei jo addham avibhaga-paliccheo so iha anubhaga-bandhammi.-Kg2, p. 63. The term rasabhaga (unit of intensity) is used as the synonym of avibhaga-paliccheda. 6 We have already stated in Chap. II (p. 63) that there is infinite gradetion of infinity, and our statenients in the present context are also to be read with this conception of infinity at their back. Page #274 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. III] CLASSIFICATION OF KARMAN 237 next intensity-class consists of such atoms as are possessed of intensityunits which are infinite times greater in number than the intensityunits of an atom of the last group of the first intensity-class. The totality of another infinite number of consecutive groups, obtained exactly as before, constitutes the second intensity-class. Similarly we get the third intensity-class. And so on. In this way we can obtain an infinite number of intensity-classes consisting of groups possessed of different consecutive numbers of intensity-units. These intensityclasses are conceived as divided into four groups. The first group, called 'first degree group' (eka-sthanika), consists of those intensityclasses (rasa-spardhakas) whose groups are possessed of atoms of infinitely less intensity-units than the atoms of the groups constituting the second group, called 'second degree group' (dvisthanika), of intensity-classes. The second degree group', the 'third degree group' (tri-sthanika) and the fourth degree group' (catuhsthanika) are similarly conceived in relation to one another. As is apparent from our description, each group consists of infinitely graded intensityclasses of varying intensity-units (rasabhagas). The most virulent type of passions (anantanubandhin) leads to the bondage of the fourth degree group' of intensity-classes of all the inauspicious types of karmic matter, the second type of passions (apratyakhyanavarana) leads to the bondage of the third degree group' of intensity-classes and the third type of passions (pratyakhyanavarana) to the second degree group'. The fourth type of passions (sarnjvalana), however, leads to the bondage of the first degree group of only these seventeen types of inauspicious karmic matter: the five obstructive karmans, the first four knowledge-covering karmans, the first three intuition-covering karmans, the karman that generates hankering for the male sex and the four karmans giving rise to the fourth type of passions (sarjvalana).* The reverse is the case with the bondage of the auspicious karmic matter. The third and the fourth types of passions lead to the bondage of the fourth degree group' of intensity-classes of the auspicious types of karmic matter. The second type of passions leads to the bondage of the third degree group' of intensity-classes of the 1 Cf. Kg2, p. 63: tatra cai 'kaika-karma-skandhe yah sarvajaghanya-rasah paramanuh: . yavad anantani rasa-spardhakany uttisthante. 2 Cf. asubhanam nimbopama-viryo ya eka-sthaniko rasas tasmad anantaguna-viryo dvi-sthanikah, tato 'py ananta-guna-viryas tri-sthanikah, tasmad apy ananta-guna-viryas catuhsthanika iti parasparam supratitam eva 'nantaguna-rasatvam iti ... etat sarvam Pancasangrahabhiprayato vyakhyatamKg2, p. 67. 3 We have translated asubha-praksti as inauspicious type of karmic matter. The asubha-prakstis are those karmans whose nature it is to produce painful fruition. * Karmagrantha V, gatha 64 (Kg2, pp. 64-5). Page #275 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 238 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN auspicious karmans. The first type of passions (anantanubandhin) leads to the bondage of the 'second degree group' of the auspicious karmans, there being no bondage of the 'first degree group' of intensityclasses in the case of the bondage of the auspicious karmans.1 The greater the impurity of the soul, the less intense is the bondage of the auspicious karmans. We have elaborated the point beforehand. These details about the bondage of intensity (anubhaga-bandha) are essential for the understanding of the Jaina doctrine of karman. This much do we state about the function of the passions in the bondage of karmic matter. Now let us state something about the function of the activity or vibrations (yoga) of the soul. The space occupied by souls is densely filled up with karmic matter, and there is incessant influx (asrava), from all sides, of it into the souls which are ever involved in activity (yoga). The influx is not stopped for a single moment till the soul is completely freed from all activity. The volume of the karmic matter attracted varies directly as the measure of the activity of the soul. In other words, the more the activity or vibrations of the soul the greater is the influx of matter attracted. The bondage with reference to the volume of matter attracted and the space of the soul occupied by it is called spacebondage (pradesa-bandha). The one function of activity, therefore, is to condition space-bondage. The other function that is attributed to activity is type-bondage (prakrti-bandha), that is, determination of the nature and type of the bondage such as knowledge-covering, intuition-covering and others. Of course, the nature of the activity itself of the soul is determined by the passions and their various effects such as the predispositions created by them, and consequently, in the ultimate analysis, the determination of the nature and type of the bondage depends upon the passions and none else, yet because of the apparent concomitance in agreement and in difference of typebondage exclusively with the activity (yoga), it is held that activity (yoga) is the condition of type-bondage as well. Although the [CH. 1 See Kg2, p. 65. 2 Cf. karma-pudgalanam eva yad grahanam sthiti-rasanirapeksadalika-sankhya-pradhanyenai 'va karoti sa pradesa-bandhah. uktam ca: thii-bandho dalassa thii paesa-bandho paesa-gahanam jam. -(Pancasangraha, gatha 432)-Kg1, PP. 4-5. The term pradesa is explained by Devendrasuri as: prakrstah pudgalastikayadesah pradesah, karma-varganantah-patinah karma-skandhah-(Kg2, p. 121). 3 joga payadi-paesam-Karmagrantha V, gatha 96. Devendrasuri explains this as yogo viryam saktir utsahah parakrama iti paryayah, tasmad yogat prakaranam prakrtih, karmanam jnanavaranadi-svabhavah prakrstah pudgalastikaya-desah pradesah, karmavarganantah-patinah karma-skandhah, prakrtayas ca pradesas ca prakrti-pradesam samaharo dvandvah. tad jivah karoti 'ti sesah, prakrti-pradesa-bandhayor yogo hetur ity arthah-Kg2, p. 121. Page #276 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. III] CLASSIFICATION OF KARMAN 239 totality of perversity (mith yatva), non-renunciation (avirati), passions (kasaya) and activity Tyoga) is generally held to be the condition of bondage, yet even in the absence of the first three, the type-bondage and the space-bondage of the feeling-producing (vedaniya) karman are, found to occur simply due to activity in such stages of spiritual development as are accompanied by complete subsidence of the deluding (mohaniya) karman. In the absence of activity, however, no kind of bondage can take place. And hence it is held that the activity alone is the condition of type-bondage and space-bondage.! Of the eight main types of karman, the four viz. the knowledgecovering, the intuition-covering, the deluding and the obstructive are obscuring (ghatin), and the remaining four are non-obscuring (aghatin). Of the obscuring types, again, some are completely obscuring' (sarva-ghatin) and others are 'partially obscuring' (desa-ghatin). A brief description of the nature of the obscuring and the non-obscuring categories of karman is very essential for the understanding of the states and processes of karman, the topic which we shall take up in the next section. The innate qualities of the soul are crippled and distorted by the obscuring karman. Love of truth (samyaktua) is the innate characteristic of the soul. But it remains fully obscured by the perversitykarman (mithyatva). Omniscience also is natural to a soul. But this also remains completely obscured by the karman that covers the pure and perfect knowledge (kevala-jnana). The full intuition of the truth remains obscured by the karman that covers the pure and perfect intuition (kevala-darsana). The five 'sleeps' also cover the intuition of objects. The first three types of passions (numbering twelve) also obscure their objects completely. These twenty sub-types are 'completely obscuring', that is, they obscure in full their respective objects. But this does not mean that there is absolute non-existence of all love of truth (sraddhana), knowledge (jnana), intuition (darsana) and 'abstention from harmful acts' (virati). If that were the case, the soul would lose its soulness. If the soul were bereft of all these characteristics, there would be nothing left to distinguish the soul from the non-soul. The soul must needs have at least an infinitesimal 1 Cf. yadyapi Sadasitika-sastre mithyatva-'virati-kasaya-yogah samanyena karmano bandha-hetava uktas tathapy adya-karanatrayabhave 'py upasantamohadi-gunasthanakesu kevala yoga-sadbhave vedaniya-laksana prakstis tatpradesas ca badhyante, ayogyavasthayam tu yogabhave na badhyanta ity anvayavyatirekabhyam jnayate prakrti-pradesa-bandhayor yoga eva pradhanam karanam -Kg2, p. 121.. 2 tattva-rucih samyaktvam--TSuBh Tika, II. 3. 3 They are anantanubandhin, apratyakhyanavarana and pratyakhyanavarana types of anger, pride, deceit and greed. Page #277 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 240 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [CH. fragment of the pure and perfect knowledge ever uncovered. Even as a cloud, however dense and dark, cannot completely cover the lustre of the sun or the moon, exactly so the karman covering the pure and perfect knowledge cannot cover the whole knowledge of the soul, because that would mean the conversion of the spirit into matter.2 The remainder knowledge is variously covered by the other four subtypes of knowledge-covering karman. But a ray of knowledge still remains uncovered even in the lowest form of existence called nigodastate where the soul's physical organism is the least developed. The function of the karman covering pure and perfect knowledge is to cover the wholeness or fullness of knowledge while the function of the other four sub-types of the knowledge-covering karman is to effect privation of the remainder knowledge. Pure and perfect knowledge is never possible when the karman covering it is in the rise, while the other types of knowledge are possible even when there is the affecting rise (vipakodaya) of the karmans covering them. It is in view of this fact that the karman covering pure and perfect knowledge is regarded as 'completely obscuring' (sarva-ghatin) while the other sub-types of the knowledge-covering karman are considered only as 'partially obscuring' (desaghatin). Similar is the case of the karman covering pure and perfect intuition and its relation with the other three sub-types of the intuition-covering karman. The five 'sleeps' are also 'completely obscuring' in the sense that they cover the perception of things, and not in the sense that they cover perception itself. There is of course some sort of consciousness even in the state of sound sleep. The example of dark and dense cloud applies equally well in the case 1 Cf. iha kevala-jnanavaranasya svavaryah kevala-jnana-laksano gunah, sa ca yadyapi sarvatmana ''vriyate tathapi sarvajivanam kevala-jnanasya 'nantabhago 'navsta eva 'vatisthate, tadavarane tasya samarthyabhavat. yad ahuh sri-Devardhivacakavarah: savva-jivanam pi ya nam akkharassa anantabhago niccugghanio citthai (Nandisutra)-Kg2, p. 12. 2 Cf. yatha 'tibahale jalada-patale samunnate bahutaraya avstatvat sarva 'pi surya-candramasoh prabha 'nena 'vrte 'ti vacana-racana pravartate, atha ca 'dyapi kacit tatprabha prasarati-'sutthu vi meha-samudae hoi paha sandasuranam' (Nandisutra)-iti vacanad anubhava-siddhatvac ca, tatha 'trapi prabala-kevalajnanavaranavrtasya 'pi kevalajnanasya 'nantabhago 'navsta eva 'ste. yadi punas tam apy avrnuyat tada jivo 'jivatvam eva prapnuyat. yad uktam Nandyadhyayane: jai puna so vi avarijja ta nam jivo ajivattanam pavija---Kg2, p. 12. 3 Cf. so 'pi ca 'vasisto 'nantabhago jaladhara-'navsta-dinakara-kara-prasara iva kata-kutyadibhir mati-sruta-'vadhi-manahparyaya-jnanavaranair avriyate, tathapi kacid nigodavasthayam api jnana-matra 'vatisthate-Kg2, p. 12. 4 The three sub-types are: caksur-darsanavarana, acaksur-darsanavarana and avadhi-darsana varana. Page #278 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IY. III] CLASSIFICATION OF KARMAN .: 241 of 'sleeps' as well. The first three types of passions also completely ob.eure respectively the predilection for truth (samyaktva), the capacity for partial renunciation (desavirati-caritra), and the capacity for full rerunciation (sarvavirati-caritra). But the fact of the abstinence from unwholesome food and the like observed even at the time of the rise of the most virulent type of passions is to be explained on the analogy of the existence of the lustre of the sun and the moon even on the rise of dark and dense clouds.? The predilection for the untruth (mithyatva) completely obscures the love of truth (samyaktva). But stil the love and capacity for the ascertainment of the truth about ordinary things of practical utility remains unobscured, and this also is to be explained on the analogy of clouds. The idea behind the adrnission of the remainder of the fundamental qualities of the soul even in the most undeveloped stage of existence is to bring home the undeniable fact of the existence of the rudiments of love of truth, knowledge of truth, and spiritual striving which when cultivated lead the soul to the ultimate goal. The absolutely non-existent can never come into existence. The soul cannot be imagined to have absolutely lost all these characteristics. It can never lose itself. This has to be accepted by all those who believe in final emancipation. The Jainas insisted on this from the very inception of their thought. This is clear from such statement of the Nandi Sutra as 'The infinitesimal part of the pure and perfect knowledge ever remains, as a rule, uncovered in any form of existence of the soul'' which is, beyond doubt, as old as the Jaina thought. Now we come to the types of 'partially obscuring' (desaghatin) karmans, which are totally twenty-five viz. the remaining four subtypes of the knowledge-covering karman, the three sub-types of intuition-covering karman, the fourth type of the four passions, the nine quasi-passions, and the five sub-types of the obstructive karman. 1 Cf. nidra-pancakam api sarvam vastvavabodham avrnoti 'ti sarva-ghati, yat punah svapavasthayam api kincit cetayati tatra dharadhara-nidarsanam vacyam-Kg2, p. 12. ? Cf. tatha 'nantanubandhino 'pratyakhyanavaranah pratyakhyanavaranas ca pratyekam catvaro yathakramam samyaktvarn desavirati-caritram sarvaviraticaritram ca sarvam eva ghnanti 'ti sarva-ghatino dvadasa 'pi kasayah, yat punas tesam prabalodaye 'py ayogyahara-viramanam upalabhyate tatra varivahadistanto vacyah--Kg2, p. 13. 3 Cf. tatha mithyatvam tu jina-pranita-tattva-sraddhanarupa-samyaktvam sarvam api hanti 'ti sarva-ghati, yat tu tasya prabalodaye 'pi manusya-pasvadivastu-sraddhanam tad api jaladharodaharanad avaseyam-Kg2, p. 13. 4 savva-jivanam pi ya namn akkharassa anantatamo bhago niccugghanio citthai-NSu, 42. 5 They are caksurdarsanivarana, acaksurdarsanavarana and avadhidarsanavarana. JP-31 Page #279 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [/sn. The four sub-types of the knowledge-covering karman are 'partially obscuring' because they obscure only that part of the knowledge which is left uncovered by the karman that covers the pure and perfect knowledge. The three sub-types of the intuition-covering karman also do the same with reference to the part left uncovered by the karman covering pure and perfect intuition. The fourth type of the four passions and the nine quasi-passions obscure only a part of the good conduct already attained, and so are 'partially obscuring'. The five sub-types of the obstructive karman also are 'partially obscuring'. One is not competent to accept and possess all the contents of the universe. One can at best have the contents of a particular small part (desa) of the vast space, and so the obstructive karman whose function is it to obstruct the use and enjoyment of them is 'partially obscuring'.3 The karman obstructing the free expression of energy (viryantaraya) also is 'partially obscuring' inasmuch as it does not obscure the whole energy of the soul. The least developed organisms (nigodas) too have the requisite energy for the processes of metabolism and movement to different births due to the subsidence-cum-destruction (ksayopasama) of the energy-obstructing karman, even though there is the full rise of the karman in their case. In brief, those types of karman whose subsidence-cum-destruction is possible even when they have affecting rise (vipakodaya) are 'partially obscuring'. This characteristic of the types of the 'partially obscuring' karman can be clearly understood from what we have already stated. We do not elaborate the point any further in view of the limited scope of the topic in our enquiry." 242 We now come to the types of the non-obscuring (aghatin) karman, which comprise all the sub-types of the four main types of karman jnana-desam 1 mati-jnanavaranadi-catuskam hanti 'ti desaghati 'dam ucyate-Kg2, p. 13. 2 Cf. tatha samjvalana nava no-kasayas ca labdhasya caritrasya desam eva ghnanti 'ti desaghatinah-Ibid. kevala-jnana varana-'navrtam 3 Cf. danantarayadini panca antarayany api desa-ghatiny eva. tatha hi dana-labha-bhogo-'pabhoganam tavad grahana-dharanayogyany eva dravyani visayah, tani ca samasta-pudgalastikayasya 'nanta-bhaga-rupe desa eva vartante, ato yadudayat tani pudgalastikaya-desa-vartini dravyani yad datum labdhum bhoktum upabhoktum ca na saknoti tani dana-labha-bhogo-'pabhogantarayani tavad desa-ghatiny eva-Ibid. 4 viryantarayam api desaghaty eva, sarvaviryam na ghatayati ''ti krtva Ibid. 5 suksma-nigodasya viryantaraya-karmano 'bhyudaye vartamanasya 'py aharaparinamana-karmadalikagrahana-gatyantaragamanadi- visaya etavan viryantaraya-karma-ksayopasamo vidyate. . -Ibid. * For elaborate discussion of the problem see Yasovijaya's commentary on Karmaprakyti (Bandhana-karana, pp. 13-14). Page #280 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. III] CLASSIFICATION OF KARMAN 243 viz. the feeling-producing, the body-making, the status-determining and the longevity-forming. These types do not obscure any fundamental quality of the soul. They only appear like the obscuring (ghatin) types when enjoyed along with them. The types of karman are also classified as 'virtuous types' and 'sinful types', also known as 'auspicious types' and 'inauspicious types'. We have already noticed this. As we have stated above, those types whose fruition leads to enjoyment of-pleasure are virtuous or auspicious, and those whose fruition leads to suffering are sinful or inauspicious. Now, as the nature of the fruition of the bondage is determined by the nature of the activities of the soul, which may be virtuous as well as sinful, the nature of the karmic types also depends upon the nature of the activities that lead to their bondage. The infinitefold activities of the soul lead to the infinitefold bondage which, for the sake of systematic treatment, is classified in various ways. The classification into 'virtuous' and 'sinful' is only one such way. The Jainas, like others, regard the five moral virtues of non-injury (ahirsa), truth (satya) etc. as the norm for the ascertainment of the nature of the activities. The perfect state, however, is realized on the cessation of all activities. The virtuous and moral activities are as much to be avoided as the sinful ones. Of course, the virtuous and moral activities lead to the bondage of the auspicious types of karman while the sinful ones lead to the bondage of the inauspicious types. But nevertheless they are on the same footing with reference to the summum bonum which is cessation of all activities. The activities are threefold inasmuch as they can belong to the body or the organ of speech or the mind. They are technically known as yoga which is also called asrava (inflow), being the cause of the inflow of karmic matter into the soul.3 In order to complete the enquiry of this section, it is necessary to record some similar speculations on the scheme of classification and other relevant topics as found in the other schools of Indian thought. The Jaina thought was not an isolated movement and as such could not but influence and be influenced by the speculations of the other schools. Of course, it is not possible to accurately apportion the mutual influence. But nevertheless our foregoing study has clearly shown how the different schools influenced each other and helped the 1 Cf. etah prakrtayo 'ghatinyah, na kancana jnanadi-gunam ghatayanti 'ti krtva, kevala sarvadesa-ghatinibhih saha vedyamanas tatsadrsyo 'nubhuyante -Kg2, p. 14. 2 Vide supra, p. 235. 3 TSu, VI. 1-2. See also the sutras that follow for the detailed statements about the conditions of the inflow of sinful and virtuous types of karman. Page #281 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ [CH. JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN development of a superstructure unparallelled perhaps in the whole history of human thought. Let us come to our topic proper. 1 Let us begin with the Yoga school. The term 'accumulated traces of actions' (karmasaya) of this school corresponds to the term karman of the Jainas. The merits and demerits constitute the traces. These traces fructify either into enjoyment or into suffering. The traces fructifying into enjoyment are the merits, and the traces fructifying into suffering are the demerits. The passions of lust, greed, delusion and anger produce those traces." The traces can fructify either in this very life or in the life to come hereafter. The traces of merit which are produced by virtuous deeds without the least hankering for their results generate traces which produce their wholesome effect in this very life. Similarly the sinful deeds of intense cruelty also can generate traces producing their baneful effect in the same life. The virtuous deeds done with absolute non-attachment generate traces ending in emancipation. Deeds done under the influence of attachment and hatred generate traces which fructify in various births into various effects. The accumulated traces of actions (karmasaya) thus are classified into (1) those that are produced by virtuous or moral deeds (punyakarmasaya), and (2) those that are produced by sinful or immoral deeds (papa-karmasaya)-each of which, again, is subdivided into (1) those that produce their effect in this very life (drstajanma-vedaniya) and (2) those that produce their effect in some life to come hereafter (adrstajanma-vedaniya). It can be said that, in the Jaina system, the karmans whose bondage and fruition, on account of the termination of the period of non-fruition (abadhakala), occur in this very life correspond to those which produce their effects in this very life (drstajanma-vedaniya), while those whose period of non-fruition terminates in the future births correspond to those which produce their effects in some life to come hereafter (adrstajanma-vedaniya). The various processes of the karman work jointly and produce manifold effects that determine the nature of the soul during its worldly career. The Yoga and the Jaina systems, as the other Indian systems, are unanimous in this respect. Their metaphysical differences about karman we have already discussed. We shall here state the peculiarity of the Yoga conception as regards the classification of karman and compare it with the Jaina conception. The Yoga classifies karman (accumulated traces) into fourfold categories which are based on the consideration of the nature of the activity that produces it.3 Thus the cruel activities of an individual 244 1 Cf. tatra punyapunya-karmasayah kama-lobha-moha-krodha-prasavahBhasya, YD, II. 12. 2 sa drstajanma-vedaniyas ca 'drstajanma-vedaniyas ca-Ibid. 3 See YD, IV. 7 with Bhasya. Page #282 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. III] CLASSIFICATION OF KARMAN 245 under the sway of passions generate traces which fall in the category called 'dark'.' The cruel-cum-merciful activities generate traces which fall in the category called 'dark-cum-white'. The category called 'white' is constituted by traces generated by such moral activities as penances, study of the scriptures, and meditation. The fourth category called 'neither white nor dark' is constituted by traces generated by such activities as are neither inspired by egoism nor performed with any worldly purpose in view. Only the ascetics who have renounced everything and have removed all their passions are possessed of this category of traces. The first three categories of traces lead to the worldly life which consists in various births (jati) such as the human, the sub-human, and the divine, different spans of life (ayus), and enjoyment and suffering (bhoga). The nature of the accumulated desires (vasanas) awakened are in accordance with the nature of the career of the individual. The accumulated traces work together and determine the nature of the worldly career of an individual. The awakening of the accumulated desires strictly follows the nature of the worldly career. Thus if the accumulated traces led to the human life, the accumulated desires of the human life would be awakened." The fourth category of traces lead to emancipation. The white (sukla) and the dark (krsna) categories can respectively be compared with the moral (punya) and irnmoral (papa) or auspicious (subha) and inauspicious (asubha) categories of the Jainas. The conception ofl 'neither white nor dark' category can be compared with the Jaina conception of the karman of the ascetics who are completely free from passions and desires: This Yoga classification corresponds to the Jaina classification of the inflow (asrava) of karmic matter into auspicious and inauspicious categories. There is yet another mode of classification of karman according to the nature of the fruition. The various traces, informed with passions and accumulated during a lifetime, work together and determine the nature of the next life. This working or fruition of the traces express itself in a number of forms. These forms are given as three: (I) various kinds of births such as the human, the sub-human and the 1. krsna duratmanam-Ibid. 2 sukla-krsna bahih-sadhana-sadhya, tatra para-pidanugraha-dvarena karmasaya pracayah-Ibid. 3 sukla tapah-svadhyaya-dhyanavatam, sa hi kevale manasyayatatvad abahih-sadhanadhina na paran pidayitva bhavati--Ibid. 4 asukla-'krsna samnyasinam ksina-klesanam carama-dehanam iti tatra suklam yogina eva phalasamnyasat, akrsnam ca 'nupadanat, itaresam tu bhutanam purvam eva trividham iti-Ibid. 5 Cf. tatas tadvipakanugunanam eva 'bhivyaktir vasananam-YD, IV. 8. See also Bhasya. Page #283 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 246 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN CH. divine, (2) different spans of life, (3) various enjoyments and sufferings of life. These three roughly correspond to the working or fruition of the gatinamaa-karman (which is a sub-type of the body-making karman), the longevity-determining karman, and the feeling-producing karman of the Jainas. It can be noticed that in this Yoga classification, the workings of the non-obscuring karmans of the Jainas have been enumerated. The nescience (avidya) of the Yoga can be compared with the belief-deluding (darsana-moha) karman of the Jainas, and the other four afflictions of the Yoga can be compared with the character-deluding (caritra-moha) karman of the Jainas. The cover on the faculty of illumination or discrimination of the Yoga can be compared with the knowledge-covering and intuition-covering karmans of the Jainas. The nine obstructions of the Yoga correspond roughly to the energy-obstructing (viryantaraya) karman of the Jainas. The similarities point to the intimate association of the Yoga and the Jaina system in matters of ethical interest. * The Sankhya, the Nyaya-Vaisesika and the Vedanta did not develop separate conceptions on these subjects and so do not need any comparative study. We next come to the Buddhist conceptions. Although there is very little similarity between the Buddhist and the Jaina conceptions of karman, yet we state the Buddhist view in order to complete our survey of the conceptions of karman in the various systems that developed side by side. Moreover, there is much affinity between the Buddhist and the Yoga system, and our study will not be futile if we can show the fact. Before stating the Buddhist classification of the types of karman, it is necessary that we should understand the Buddhist conception of consciousness and its different planes as well as the various planes of life that the consciousness can attain to. We shall therefore at the outset describe in brief the nature of consciousness, the different planes of consciousness, and the various planes of life. And finally we shall state the Buddhist way of classification of karman according to different principles and the points of its similarity with the Yoga conception.. The Buddhists believe in consciousness as a complex of a number of psychic factors which determine the nature of the consciousness and are nothing but forces created by the tendencies of greed (lobha), 1 sati mule tadvipako jaty-ayur-bhogah--YD, II. 13. 2 Vide supra, p. 234. 3 For the enumeration of the five afflictions vide supra, p. 89. 4 prakasavarana or viveka-jnana-varaniya-karman--YD, II, 52 and Bhasya. 5 antarayah--YD, I. 30. 6 The enquiry that follows is based on the Abhidhammatthasamgaha of Anuruddhacarya. I have utilized profusely The Abhidhamma Philosophy by J. Kashyap. I have utilisais based on the Page #284 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. 111] CLASSIFICATION OF KARMAN . 247 hatred (dosa) and delusion (moha) and their opposites viz. selfsacrificingness (alobha), good will adosa) and insight (amoha). The worldly existence is rooted in these tendencies. The consciousness is an integration of the threefold process of knowing (sanna). feeling (vedana) and willing (cetana) and is classified into three categories viz. good (sobhana), bad (akusala) and neutral (avyakata). The good consciousness qua willing is called moral (kusala). The moral consciousness is accompanied by the good tendencies of self-sacrificingness, good will and insight. The good consciousness qua passive states of knowing and feeling and as determined by the past good tendencies is called the resultant (vipaka) consciousness. The consciousness of an arhat, though active, does not produce any resultant and so is called kiriya (barren and inoperative). Thus we can distinguish these three subclasses of the category of good consciousness: (1) moral (kusala), (2) resultant (vipaka), and (3) barren and inoperative (kiriya). Ethically considered, the resultant and the kiriya-consciousness are nonmoral (avyakata) inasmuch as the former, being passive, is devoid of any active willing which is the essential condition of moralness while the latter, though active, yet, being free from the will to live, does not produce any resultant which also is an essential condition of moralness. The bad consciousness is that which is accompanied by any of the three bad tendencies viz. greed, hatred and delusion. Ethically, such consciousness is immoral (akusala). The resultant of the immoral consciousness, however, is not immoral, but non-moral, inasmuch as it is passive and devoid of any willing which is an essential factor of the moral aspect of consciousness. The third, that is, the neutral category of consciousness is that which is not accompanied by any of the good or bad tendencies. It is, therefore, neither moral (kusala) nor immoral (akusala), but is non-moral (avyakata). It is also called conditionless (ahetu ka) being devoid of all the six conditioning tendencies of greed, hatred and delusion and their opposites. All active (javgna) consciousness, that is, consciousness qua willing is determined by condition (sahetuka). But the innocent smile (hasituppada citta) of the arhat is an exception. It is active yet not determined by any condition (ahetuka). The arhat is absolutely free from the will to live, yet he has immense compassion for all and actively wills the well-being of one and all. The immaculate smile is the index of the actively compassionate consciousness. Such consciousness, however, is not moral, but is non-moral (avyakata) being devoid of any end in view. And being incapable of producing resultant, it is kiriya inoperative and barren). A consciousness qua knowing and feeling is the resultant of past actions, good and bad, and is neither moral nor immoral. It is only the consciousness qua willing that is moral or immoral. When such consciousness is accompanied by the Page #285 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 248 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [CH. good tendencies, it is moral, and when it is accompanied by bad tendencies it is immoral. The Buddhists further distinguish three planes of consciousness viz. (1) the plane of weak consciousness (paritta bhumi), (2) the plane of higher grade of consciousness (mahaggata bhumi), (3) the supramundane plane (lokuttara bhumi). The consciousness that is weak and fickle, wavering and unsteady, and roams in the world of desires (kamavacara) belongs to the first plane. Such consciousness cannot realize emancipation (nibbana). Spiritual progress begins only with the training and practice of the mind in exercise of self-mastery and steadfast meditation. Such practice is called yoga and the practitioner is called yogavacara. The practitioner begins by meditating upon a suitable object which is associated with the idea of form. Gradually the consciousness becomes capable of the different stages of ecstasy (jhana) in which it becomes perfectly concentrated on its object. Such consciousness is called the ecstasy-consciousness of the form (rupavacara citta). The practitioner (yogavacara), intending to rise higher, gives up all ideas of forms also, and attains an ecstatic state where he meditates upon such formless objects as infinity of space (anantakasa), infinity of consciousness (ananta-vinnana), nothingness (akincanna) and a state wherein the cognition is so very subtle that it cannot be said whether it is or is not (neva sanna nasanna). Such consciousness is called the ecstasy-consciousness of the formless (arupavacara citta). These two types of ecstasy-consciousness constitute the second plane called the higher grade of consciousness (mahaggata bhumi). The consciousness in this plane, however, is not free from fall in spite of its high steadfastness and power of deep concentration. It can be amenable to the bad tendencies when it returns to the normal state after the ecstasy. One is required to meditate upon the impermanent (anicca), miserable (dukkha), and substanceless (anatta) nature of all existence before one can be capable of the ecstatic meditation upon desirelessness (nibbana). Once the truth of impermanence, misery, and substancelessness is grasped and realized, the consciousness is capable of meditation upon desirelessness (nibbana). It then destroys the first three of the ten fetters1 and attains the first stage of the highest plane of consciousness called the supra-mundane plane (lokuttara bhumi). The consciousness at this stage is called sotapanna, that is, one which has come in the stream leading to emancipation (nibbana). It is now sure to become arhat within the course of seven births. When the consciousness succeeds in weakening the next two 1 The ten fetters are (1) ignorance of identity, (2) doubt, (3) wrong belief that external rituals lead to purity, (4) sensual desire, (5) ill will, (6) attraction for rupa-existence, (7) attraction for arupa-existence, (3) conceit, (9) distraction, and (10) nescience. Page #286 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. 111] CLASSIFICATION OF KARMAN 249 fetters of sensual desire and ill will, it attains to the second stage of the supra-mundane plane and is called saka dagamin (once-returner). After this it is born only once in this world and attains emancipation (nibbana). When the consciousness succeeds in totally uprooting these two fetters, it attains to the third stage of the supra-mundane plane, and is called anagamin or one who is sure to obtain emancipation (nib bana) in that very life. When it destroys the remaining five fetters as well, it becomes an arhat and fully realizes the summum bonum (nibbana). As regards the planes of life, the Buddhists distinguish four such planes viz. (1) the plane of misery (apaya-bhumi), (2) the better plane of the world of desires (kamasugati-bhumi), (3) the plane of the form (rupavacara-bhumi), and (4) the plane of the formless (arupavacarabhumi). There are again various subclasses in each plane. Thus the plane of misery has four subclasses viz. (I) hell, (2) animal kingdom, (3) the world of ghosts, and (4) the host of demons; the better plane of the world of desires has seven subclasses viz. (I) men, (2) the catummaharajika gods, (3) the tavatimsa gods, etc. These eleven subclasses constitute what is called the kamavacara-bhumi or the plane of beings whose consciousness is restless under the influence of diverse worldly desires. The third plane of life, rupavacara-bhumi, has sixteen grades which are distributed among the four stages of ecstatic concentration (jhana) that are possible in the plane. The fourth plane of life, arupavacara-bhumi, has four grades viz. (1) the sphere of the conception of infinite space, (2) the sphere of the conception of infinite consciousness, (3) the sphere of the conception of nothingness, and (4) the sphere of the subtlest consciousness. The consciousness is reborn in the various planes of life in accordance with its resultant state of existence at the time of death. Thus the type of consciousness--which is not rooted in the tendencies (ahetuka), is the resultant of immoral actions (akusalavipaka), is accompanied by indifference (upekkhasahagata), and is an investigating consciousness (santirana)-connects this life, at the time of death, to a life in the plane of misery; the type of consciousness which is not rooted in the tendencies (ahetuka), is the resultant of moral actions (kusalavipaka), is accompanied by indifference (upekkha-sahagata) and is an investigating consciousness connects this life, at the time of death, to the life of one born blind (or dumb or idiot) or to that of a demon living on earth; the eight types of mahavipaka consciousness function as only the condition of birth in the better plane of the world of desires; the resultant consciousness of the first stage of ecstatic concentration conditions birth in the plane of the first stage of concentration i.e. brahmaloka); and so on. The same consciousness that determines birth (patisandhi) in a particular plane of life determines continuation of life (bhavanga) in JP-32 Page #287 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [CH. the same plane as well as the passing away (cuti) from the same after the due period. The consciousness of different planes has different lifeterms. The higher the plane of life, the longer is the life-term. 250 With this background in mind let us study the Buddhist way of classification of karman. The Buddhist substitute for a permanent soul is an everchanging consciousness which, as we have seen, is an integration of a number of psychic factors. The consciousness qua willing is determined by various psychic factors, moral and immoral. The passive consciousness, that is, consciousness qua knowing and feeling is the resultant of past actions, good and bad. It is non-moral. The nature of the resultant consciousness at the time of death determines the plane of life it enters in the next birth. This conception compares favourably with the Yoga conception of all the accumulated traces of past actions working together and determining the nature of the next life. The Buddhists classify these past actions (karman) in four ways based on four different principles. Thus these are the types of karman according to the functions they perform: (1) karman which conditions birth after death (janaka), (2) karman which sustains (upatthambhaka) other karman but does not itself cause rebirth, (3) karman which thwarts (upapilaka) and thus weakens other karman, and (4) karman which overpowers (upaghataka) the other weak karman and produces its own effect. The following are the types of karman according to the priority of the fruition (pakadanapariyayena): (I) karman which is very serious (guruka) such as the killing of one's own mother, (2) karman which is done just before death (asanna), (3) karman which is repeatedly done (acinna), and (4) karman which is of a light kind (katattakamma). Of these types, the succeeding type fructifies only in the absence of the preceding one. The reason is quite obvious. The strength of the karman determines the priority of its fruition. The following classification is according to the time of fruition (1) karman which gives its effects in this very life (ditthadhammavedaniya), (2) karman which gives its effect in the next life (upapajjavedaniya), (3) karman which gives its effect in some life after this (aparapariyavedaniya), and (4) karman which is ineffective (ahosikamma). The following are again the types of karman according to the plane of life of their fruition: (1) immoral (akusala) karman which produces its effect in the plane of misery (apaya-bhumi), (2) moral (kusala) karman which produces its effect in the better plane of the world of desires (kamavacara-bhumi), (3) moral karman which produces its effect in the plane of the form (rupavacara-bhumi), and (4) moral karman which produces its effect in the plane of the formless (arupavacara-bhumi). In these ways of classification, again, we find much affinity with the Yoga conception. The Buddhist conception of the Page #288 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. III] upapilaka and the upaghataka karman can be compared with the Yoga conception of the more powerful karman which absorbs within itself or overpowers the weaker karman.1 The Buddhist conception of the guruka karman can be compared with the Yoga conception of the karman which is produced by the repeated harm done, under intense passion, to those who are afraid, diseased and afflicted and who have placed their confidence, to the virtuous and the honest, and to the ascetics.2 The Buddhist conception of ditthadhammavedaniya is identical with the Yoga conception of drstajanmavedaniya. The two types of upapajjavedaniya and aparapariyavedaniya are included, in the Yoga system, in the one type called adrstajanmavedaniya. The conception of ahosikamma can be compared with the Yoga conception of the karman which lies overpowered for ever by a more powerful karman.3 The Buddhist as well as the Yoga system gave supreme importance to the practice of meditation and ecstasy, and it is no wonder that they developed common ideas of spiritual progress. An individual can pass from the lower to the higher plane of life by means of yogic practices according to both the Buddhist and the Yoga school. Thus the fourth mode of classification of karman according to the plane of life where it produces its effect can be compared with the Yoga conception of the efficacy of yogic practices which enable the practitioner to attain to the higher planes of psychic life, which end in final emancipation of the self (purusa). CLASSIFICATION OF KARMAN This is about the doctrine of karman in the Pali or Southern school of Buddhism. The doctrine of karman in the Vaibhasika school of Buddhism is excellently depicted in the Abhidharmakosa1 of Acarya Vasubandhu. We do not deal with the doctrine for lack of bearing on our topic. One feature of Mahayana Buddhism, however, deserves careful notice in this connection. This is the distinction between the jneyavarana and the klesavarana. The consciousness becomes free from bondage when the klesavarana is destroyed. But still it has not become omniscient. Attainment of omniscience is possible only on the destruction of the jneyavarana. The consciousness is luminous and omniscient by nature. It is jneyavarana that hides the things from it. The Buddhists of the school of Dignaga and Dharmakirti also 251 1 Cf. pradhanakarmany avapagamanam va, niyatavipaka-pradhanakarmana 'bhibhutasya va ciram avasthanam-Bhasya, YD, II. 13. 2 Cf. tatha tivraklesena bhita-vyadhita-krpanesu visvasopagatesu va mahanubhavesu va tapasvisu krtah punah punar apakarah, sa ca 'pi papa-karmasayah sadya eva paripacyate-Ibid., II. 12. 3 Cf. niyatavipaka-pradhana-karmana 'bhibhutasya va ciram avasthanam -Ibid., II. 13. 4 See fourth Nirdesa called Karma-nirdesa. 5 Vide supra, p. 134. Page #289 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 252 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [CH. recognized the luminosity of consciousness, but did not clearly distinguish between the jneyavarana and the klesavarana, though the distinction can be easily derived from their general conception of consciousness. The Mahayana conception of jneyavarana can be compared with the jnanavarana of the Jainas. The klesavarana is not much different from the caritramohaniya of the Tainas. IV THE STATES AND PROCESSES OF KARMAN The karman is related with the soul, as we have seen, on account of its passions and vibrations. We have also differentiated between the respective functions of the passions and the vibrations. There are states of the soul where the passions are totally calmed down or destroyed. But the vibrations or the activity of body, sense-organ of speech, and mind still remain and consequently the influx and bondage of karman as well. This bondage, however, does not last for more than an instant. The influx in this case is technically known as 'non-affecting' (iryapatha), the corresponding bondage also being known by the same term. The influx and bondage due to activity accompanied with passions are both known as 'affecting' (samparayika). The influx and bondage, as a matter of necessity, require some energy on the part of the soul for their origination. This energy is known as virya. The activity (yoga) is nothing but an imperfect expression of this energy. The various states and processes of the karman, which we shall describe in this section, are due to this energy of the soul. The nature of the energy, again, is determined by the nature of the dispositions, actual and potential, of the soul. The soul, at any instant of its worldly existence, is an integrated whole of the dispositions, actual and potential. The infinite energy which is inherent in it finds only an imperfect and partial expression which is responsible for the accretion of the karmic matter on the soul. This imperfect and partial, or rather perverted, expression of the energy is responsible for the various processes of the karmic matter. The perfection of energy is realized when the soul is free from all activity (yoga) and is no more liable to association with any kind of karman, that is, when there is absolute emancipation. Of course, the energy of one who has absolutely dissociated the energy-obstructing karman, but has not absolutely stopped all activities, is also perfect. But this energy is 1 See TSu, VI. 5 with Bhasya and Tika. 2 The Pancasangraha (721) defines yoga as salesyam be clear from what follows. viryam. This will Page #290 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. IV] STATES AND PROCESSES OF KARMAN 253 'accompanied with coloration' (salesya)' and as such is to be distinguished from the former which is absolutely free from such coloration (alesya). There is not any difference of nature between these two energies. The difference is only in respect of the souls that possess them. One is possessed by a soul which has stopped all activities and so is free from coloration and is on the threshold of emancipation or in emancipation itself. The other is possessed by one who is engaged, of course disinterestedly, in activities and therefore is not free from the coloration, although it has absolutely destroyed the energy-obstructing karman. The energy, accordingly, has been classified into two categories: (1) accompanied with coloration (salesya), and (2) not accompanied with coloration (alesya). The second class of energy is possessed, as we have just stated, by those souls that have stopped all activities and are on the threshold of emancipation or by those that are already emancipated. This is the most perfect expression of the energy. The energy accompanied with coloration is possessed by all the other souls that have been classified into three categories: (1) those that are possessed of passions, (2) those that have absolutely calmed down or destroyed their passions, and (3) those that have absolutely destroyed all the obscuring (ghatinkarmans (a fortiori the energyobstructing karinan), and have attained omniscience, but have not till now absolutely stopped all activities. The energy accompanied with coloration, moreover, is either voluntary (abhisandhija), that is, born of self-conscious effort, or involuntary (anabhisandhija), that is, born automatically without any conscious effort. The automatic involuntary physiological processes and the like are the workings of the involuntary (anabhisandhija) energy while the voluntary (abhisandhija) energy finds expression in such self-conscious efforts as the voluntary movements. Before we come to the study of the states and processes of karman, it is essential that we should understand the exact nature of the expression of the energy of the soul and its relation with passions and coloration. Let us elaborate the point. Lesya is a transformation of the soul, dependent upon the activity of the mind. There is lesya so long as there is association of the soul with the mind. The soul has infinitefold transformations due to the infinitefold activities of the mind associated with it. But these transformations are classified, for the sake of convenience, into six main types which are known as klsna-lesya, nila-lesya, kapota-lesya, tejo-lesya, padma-lesya and sukla-lesya. They are thus nothing but the states of the soul brought about by the various conditions of the mind. Cf. lisyanta iti lesyah, manoyogavastambha-janita-parinamah ... anekatve 'pi parinamasya paristhura-katipaya-bheda-kathanam eva sujnanatvat kriyate, na tv asesa-parinama-bhedakhyanam asakyatvat ...-TSuBh, Tika, II. 7. See also DOK, pp. 47-49 with footnotes. 2 For the above classification of virya see Kp, Bandhanakarana, gatha 3 with Commentaries (pp. 19-21). Page #291 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 254 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [CH. The infinite energy of the soul is circumscribed by the energyobstructing karman. It is defiled by the passions. And the coloration (lesya), which forms the colour-index of the embodied existence of the soul, is regarded as defining the energy of the soul in worldly existence inasmuch as it indicates a transformation of the soul in consonance with the transformation of the mind-stuff, which, again, is in consonance with the influence of the passions on the soul. In the ultimate analysis, the passions determine the nature of the coloration. Of course, there is coloration even in the state of the total absence of the passions. But it can be said that the footprints of the bygone passions are still there to give a coloration to the soul. And perhaps it is not without this implication that the Jainas regarded the coloration of the soul free from passions as pure white. The passions darken, as it were, the soul. And the more the soul is free from passions the less dark is the coloration of the soul. The consummation is reached in the pure white coloration (lesya) which also disappears in the state of final emancipation. The disappearance of coloration is attended with the perfect expression of the energy. The energy of the soul in worldly existence is delimited and defiled. This delimited and defiled energy is called activity (yoga). Or, to be more accurate, the energy as defined by coloration (lesya) is yoga. Now let us come to our subject proper. The karmic matter undergoes various processes due to the various conditions of the activities (yoga) which vary infinitely. The infinite variations of the activities are due to the manifold processes of the energy, which have been classified into eight types, technically known as karanas (processes of the energy), viz. (1) bandhana (bondage) 'the condition of the energy responsible for bondage', (2) samkramana (transformation) 'the condition of the energy responsible for transformation', (3) udvartana (increased realization) 'the condition responsible for increased realization', (4) apavartana (decreased realization) 'the condition responsible for decreased realization', (5) udirana (premature realization the condition responsible for premature realization', (6) upasamana (subsidence) 'the condition responsible for calming down or subsidence', (7) nidhatti or the condition that is capable of making the karmans incapable of all the processes (karanas) other than 'increased realization' and 'decreased realization', and (8) nikacana "the condition that is responsible for making the karmans incapable of all the processes'. These processes of the energy (karanas) lead to the corresponding karmic processes known by the same terms. Every change in the soul synchronizes with the corresponding change in the karman and vice versa. This is one of the most fundamental principles 1 Cf. Pancasangraha, 721 where yoga is defined as salesyam viryam. Page #292 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV, IV] STATES AND PROCESSES OF KARMAN 255 of the doctrine of karman. A process of the karman presupposes a process of the energy, and similarly a process of the energy presupposes a process of the karman. Besides these processes of the karman, there are certain states of the karman such as 'endurance of the karman for a certain period of time' (satta), 'endurance without producing the effect (abadha), and 'coming into effect' (udaya). Let us describe, in brief, these states and processes. About bondage we have already spoken in detail. The energy (virya) that is needed to attract the karmic matter for bondage is the process of the energy called 'bondage'. The soul attracts karmic matter at every instant of its worldly career, and assimilates it into so many types of karman, which mature into fruition in due course. There is thus incessant inflow of the karmic matter into the soul, and the consequent bondage leading to various deformations and disabilities of the soul which by itself is so pure and immune from all defilement. This process of bondage is without beginning, but not endless. It stops with the stoppage of the activity (yoga) of the soul. The stoppage of the activity is attended by the release of the undefined infinite energy. Association with the karmic matter delimits the energy, and the delimited energy effects the association with karmic matter. Thus the process goes on. The other details about the process of bondage can be known from what we have already stated. Next comes the process of 'transformation' (sazkramana) which means the transformation of one karman into another. 'Transformation is a process whereby the soul transforms the nature, the duration, the intensity, and the numerical strength of one kind of karmic matter into those of another which it is binding at the time by means of the manifestation of a particular kind of potency.'? The soul is perpetually undergoing metamorphosis leading to the various processes of karman. Transformation is one such process. By it, the soul either deposits a formerly bound karman into one which it is binding at the time and then transforms it into the latter, or of the many kinds of karmic sub-types that it is binding, one karmic sub-type is transformed into another. Thus, for instance, the soul can deposit a previously 1 badhyate jivapradesaih saha 'nyonyanugatikriyate 'staprakaram karma yena virya-visesena tad bandhanam-Kp, Bandhanakarana, p. 19 (I). 2 sankramyante 'nyakarmarupataya vyavasthitah prakrti-sthity-anubhagapradesa anyakarma-rupataya vyavasthapyante yena tat sankramanam--Ibid. Also cf. so samkamo tti vuccai jam bandhana-parinao paogenam pagayantarattha-daliyam parinamai tayanubhave jam. -Kp, Samkramakarana, gatha 1. 3 Cf. badhyamanasu prakstinu madhye abadhyamana-prakrti-dalikam praksipya badhyamana-prakstirupataya yat tasya parinamanam, yac ca va badhyamananam prakstinam dalika-rupasye 'taretara-rupataya parinamanam tat sarvam sankramanam ity ucyate-Ibid., p. I (2). Page #293 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 256 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN bound suffering-producing (asata-vedaniya) karman into the enjoymentproducing (satavedaniya) karman that it is binding at the time and transform it into the latter. Or, it can transform one of the two, say the first and the second sub-type of the knowledge-covering karman, that it is binding at the time into the other. In the case of the three sub-types of the belief-deluding karman, however, transformation is possible even in the absence of bondage. A person of right belief (samyag-drsti) transforms the perversity-producing (mithyatva) karman into the two karmans that produce respectively right-cum-wrong belief (samyag-mithyatva) and right belief (samyaktva), even though the latter two are never bound. Similarly he transforms the karman that produces right-cum-wrong belief into one that produces right belief. It is, however, to be noted that any karman cannot be transformed into any other. There is not mutual transformation between the beliefdeluding (darsana-moha) and the conduct-deluding (caritra-moha) karman as well as between any two among the four sub-types of the longevity-determining karman as also between any two types from among the eight main types of karman.2 In other words the transformation is possible only between any two sub-types of the same main type with the above exceptions. It is also to be noticed that a person of perverted belief (mithya-drsti) cannot transform his perversionkarman (mithyatva) into the karman that produces right-cum-wrong belief or into one that produces right belief; nor can a person of right belief transform his karman producing right belief into one that produces right-cum-wrong belief or wrong belief.3 The reason is obvious. Transformation requires energy, and the nature of this energy is determined by the degree of the purity of the soul. A person of wrong belief is not pure enough to be capable of the energy required to transfer his karmic matter of wrong belief to the karmic matter of [CH. 1 Samyagmithyatva and samyaktva are only the two particular states of purity of the mithyatva-pudgala (i.e. the karmic matter producing perversity). The soul can bind only the karman that produces perversity (mithyatva). It does not bind the karman producing samyagmithyatva or the karman producing samyaktva, but only purifies the mithyatva-karman into samyagmithyatva and samyaktva. Cf. iha mithyatvasyai 'va bandho na samyaktva-samyagmithyatvayoh, yato mithyatva-pudgala eva madanakodrava-sthaniya ausadhi-visesakalpena aupasamika-samyaktvanugatena visodhi-sthanena tridha kriyante, tad yatha suddha ardha-visuddha avisuddhas ca. tatra visuddhah samyaktvam, ardhavisuddhah samyagmithyatvam, avisuddha mithyatvam. tatra visuddhasamyag-drstih samyaktva-samyagmithyatvayor bandham vina 'pi tatra mithyatvam sankramayati, samyagmithyatvam ca samyaktva iti-Ibid., p. 2 (2). 2 mohaduga-'uga-mulapagatina na paropparammi samkamanam. -Ibid., gatha 3a-b. 3 Cf. yasmin darsana-mohaniye yo jantur avatisthate sa tad anyatra na sankramayati, yatha mithyadrstir mithyatvam samyagmithyadrstih samyagmithyatvam, samyagdrstih samyaktvam-Ibid., p. 3 (2). Page #294 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. IV] STATES AND PROCESSES OF KARMAN 257 right-cum-wrong belief or right belief and transform it into them. Similarly, a person of right belief is not impure enough to be capable of the energy required to transfer the karmic matter of right belief to the karmic matter of right-cum-wrong belief or wrong belief, and transform it into them. Similar is the case of the soul possessed of the karmic matter of right-cum-wrong belief. Next we come to increased realization' (udvartana) and 'decreased realization' (apavartana) which are nothing but the transformation (samkramana) of the length of duration (sthiti) and intensity of fruition (anubhaga) of a karman. The energy whereby the soul increases the length of duration and the intensity of fruition of a karman is the process called 'increased realization' (udvartana-karana). And the energy whereby the soul decreases them is decreased realization'.? The processes of the karman due to these energies are also known by the same terms. These processes, like others, are very complicated ones and there is every possibility of losing sight of the very essence of the processes if we once enter the labyrinth of description as found in the Jaina works on karman. We, therefore, rest satisfied with the statement of the central ideas of the processes. The doctrine of karman attempts at explaining the various states of the soul by postulating the corresponding processes of karmic matter. This interplay of spirit and matter is described in its numerous aspects, and the complicated doctrine of karman is formulated. There is, however, very little of philosophical interest in the description of the various processes. Now we come to the process called 'premature realization' (udirana). The karman does not yield fruit as soon as it is bound. It remains inactive for some time before producing its result. This period of inactivity is called 'the period of non-production' (abadhakala). The karman comes into rise (udaya) in order to give its fruit after this period of non-production is over. This rise continues uninterrupted till the end of the fruition. At any instant of rise (udaya) the order of the groups of karmic aggregates (karma-dalika) that are to rise into fruition in the following instants making up one avalikas is arranged beforehand. The avalika referred to in this context is called udayavalika. By the process of 'premature realization' the soul attracts back the group of karmic aggregates that were to rise into fruition after the passing away of the udayavalika in question, and places them into the udayavalika so that they may fructify earlier. The special kind of 1 Cf. . . . . . sankramanam. tadbhedav evo 'dvartanapavartane, te ca karmanam sthityanubhagasraye-Kp, Bandhanakarana, p. 19 (2). 2 tatro 'dvartyete prabhutikriyete sthityanubhagau yaya viryaparinatya sa udvartana. apavartyete hrasvikriyete tau yaya sa 'pavartana-Kp, Bandhanakarana, p. 19 (2). 3 An avalika is a very small measure of time. JP--33 Page #295 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 258 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [CH. energy that is requisite for the process is called the process of premature realization (udirana-karana). In brief, 'premature realization' is the process by which a karman is made capable of premature fruition." The process necessarily involves 'decreased realization'. Next we come to the process called 'subsidence' (upasamana). The 'subsidence' is a process which holds up the processes of 'rise' (udaya), 'premature fruition', nidhatti and nikacana? of the karmic matter. The manifestation of the requisite energy is called the process of subsidence (upasamana-karana). We have stated on more than one occasion that the world process is considered to be without beginning. It is also admitted that everyone is striving in his own way for the realization of the ultimate state of emancipation. The striving becomes a self-conscious effort only when a measure of purity has been achieved by the soul. The processes of the deluding karman play a very important part in the making up of the worldly existence, and it is only the holding up (upasamana) of this karman that gives the soul a glimpse of the truth of reality. The soul develops its inherent love of truth into a definitive self-conscious predilection which illumines the spiritual journey leading to the ultimate goal. The process of 'subsidence' thus occupies a very important place in the spiritual speculations of the Jainas. We shall have occasion in the next chapter to describe the process in some detail. The subsidence (upasamana) is only a temporary holding up of the deluding karman. The antithesis of it is total dissociation (ksaya) which means total disintegration of the karmic matter from the soul. Then there is the process of dissociationcum-subsidence (ksayopasama) wherein some portion of karmic matter is held up, some portion is exhausted by fruition, while some is in rise (udaya). Thus, for instance, at the time of perceptual cognition (matijnana), which is a state of dissociation-cum-subsidence of the relevant sub-type of the knowledge-covering karman, some 'partially obscuring intensity-classes' (desaghati-spardhakas) of the said karman are held up, some such are exhausted by fruition, while others are in rise. Dissociation (ksaya) and dissociation-cum-subsidence (ksayopasama) are not treated separately from subsidence (upasama) in view of their lack of any peculiarity of nature. Dissociation is the state of absence of the karman and as such needs no description. Dissociation-cumsubsidence is a complex of dissociation (ksaya), subsidence (upasama), and rise (udaya) and so can be understood if the latter three are 1 Cf. udiryate 'nudaya-praptam karma-dalikam udayavalikayam pravesyate yaya sa udirana-Kp, Bandhanakarana, p. 19 (2). 2 Nidhatti and nikacana will be defined immediately after the description of the process in question. 3 karma-pudgalanam udayodirana-nidhatti-nikacana-karanayogyatvena vyavasthapanam upasamana--Kp, Bandhanakarana, p. 19 (1). Page #296 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV. IV] STATES AND PROCESSES OF KARMAN 259 understood, and so needs no separate explanation. Next we come to nidhatti and nikacana. Nidhatti is a process whereby a karman is made incapable of all processes (karanas) except the two viz. 'increased realization' and 'decreased realization'. The manifestation of energy responsible for such process is nidhatti-karana. Under particular dispositions, the soul binds karman in such a way that the latter is so irrefrangibly pasted with the soul that it becomes incapable of all possible changes except the two. In nikacana, however, even these two are impossible. This is the difference between nidhaiti and nikacana. It follows, therefore, that the manifestation of energy which is responsible for such bondage with the karman as has its nature, duration, intensity and numerical strength unalterably fixed from before, in other words, whose course of fruition is predetermined from the very time of bondage, is nikacana-karana.? As regards the states of 'existence' (satta), 'period of non-production' (abadha), and 'rise' (udaya) of a karman, it is perhaps not necessary to explain their meanings which follow from the etymological meaning of the terms themselves. A karman is regarded to be in existence unless and until its last particle has fallen off from the soul. This whole existence of the karman is called satta. 'Period of nonproduction' and 'rise' we have already explained. We can here distinguish between affecting rise (vipakodaya) and non-affecting rise (pradesodaya). The affecting rise of a karman is attended with the effect of the karman on the soul while the non-affecting rise is fruition without any effect on the soul. The soul can, by manifestation of requisite energy, lessen the intensity of fruition, and when the lessening is so great that the karman almost loses all its effect on the soul, the fruition of that karman is non-affecting. Let us now record some comparative remarks on these processes and states of karman. It is of course not possible to find exact parallels of these states and processes in the non-Jaina systems. It is, however, possible to interpret some ideas of the Yoga school in terms of the Jaina conceptions. And this has been done by the great Jaina scholar of modern times Upadhyaya Yasovijaya. He has suggested such comparisons in his brief Commentary on Patanjali's Yogadarsana. Thus, in his 1 nidhiyate udvartanapavartana-'nya-sesa-karanayogyatvena vyavasthapyate yaya sa nidhattih-Ibid., p. 19 (2). 2 nikacyate sakala-karanayogyatvena 'vasyavedyataya vyavasthapyate karma jivena yaya sa nikacana-Ibid. 3 This Commentary has been edited by the great savant Pt. Sukhlalji. The reader is requested to go through the learned introductory portion of the edition which was published by Shri Atmanand Jain Pustak Pracharak Mandal, Roshan Muhalla, Agra, (1922). Page #297 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 260 JAINA DOCTRINE OF KARMAN [CH. Commentary on Yogadarsana II. 4, Yasovijaya says that the five afflictions of nescience, egohood, attachment, repulsion and will to live are the particular states of rise (udaya) of the deludingkarman. He interprets the dormant prasupta) state of these afflictions as the period of non-production (abadhakala) of the Jainas. The incipient (tanu) state is interpreted as the state of subsidence (upasama) or dissociationcum-subsidence (ksayopasama) of the Jainas. The interrupted (vicchinna) state is interpreted as the interruption of a particular karman on account of the rise of a karman of the opposite nature. The operative (udara) state is interpreted as the state of rise (udaya) of the Jainas.1 The Yoga school recognizes some traces of karman whose fruition is not certain (aniyata-vipaka) inasmuch as such traces may perish before the time of their fruition, or may merge into a more powerful karman, or they may remain ineffective for ever being overpowered by the more powerful karman. This Yoga conception can be roughly compared with the Jaina conception of the process of transformation (samkramana). The karman with unfailing fruition (niyatavipaka) of the Yoga can be compared with the nikacita karman of the Jainas. The Taina conception of the karmans in the period of nonproduction (abadhakala) compares with the conception of stored (sancita) karmans, and the conception of the karmans in rise (udaya) corresponds to the conception of fructifying (prarabdha karmans. The conception of the karman that is being done (kriyamana) can be compared with the Jaina conception of the karman that is being bound (badhyamana). Cf. atra 'vidyadayo mohaniyakarmana audayika-bhava-visesah. tesam prasuptatvam tajjanakakarmano 'badhakalapariksayena karma-nisekabhavah. tanutvam upasamah ksayopasamo va. vicchinnatvam pratipaksa-prakrtyudayadina 'ntaritatvam. udaratvam co 'dayavalika-praptatvam ity avaseyamYasovijaya's Commentary on YD, II. 4. 2 yo hyadrstajanmavedaniyo 'niyata vipakas tasya trayi gatih-kstasya 'vipakvasya nasah, pradhanakarmany avapagamanam va, niyata vipaka-pradhanakarmana 'bhibhutasya va ciram avasthanam-Bhasya on YD, II. 13. Page #298 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CHAPTER V JAINA YOGA INTRODUCTORY In the first chapter we studied the fundamental nature of the Jaina attitude. We found that the Jaina is a thoroughgoing realist who would not let a single element given in experience be rejected as false on the verdict of abstract logic. In the second chapter we studied the Agamic conception of the nature of experience which the Jainas consider as the ultimate organ of the determination of the nature of reality. The experience of one who is not omniscient is imperfect and vitiated. In the third chapter we studied the nature of the fundamental defect that vitiates the experience of imperfect souls and is the ultimate condition of worldly existence. In this connection we studied also the various conceptions of the basic defect in the other systems of Indian thought and also recorded their criticism from the Jaina standpoint. We were then naturally led to the consideration of the Jaina doctrine of karman which attempts at explaining the various expressions of the worldly existence conditioned by the basic defect. The Indian systems of philosophy are not mere speculations on the nature of things but, with all sincerity and earnestness at their command, dive deep into the mysteries of the universe in order to find the way out of the limitations of the worldly existence vitiated by perversities and crippled by various privations and disabilities. The perfect unfolding of the potentialities of the self is the object aimed at. The pursuit of truth must culminate in the realization of the truth. And the pathway or the process leading to the discovery of truth must be made a public property so that anyone who would care to tread upon or practise the same might discover and realize the truth. The systems of Indian philosophy therefore have chalked out their respective paths of spiritual realization. The ordinary sources of knowledge are found to be inadequate to the discovery of the ultimate truth, being subject to the limitations imposed by the senses. The intellect, though possessed of a superior status in that it organizes the data of experience into a system, is also not immune from the limitations of the senses and has been found to record varying and conflicting conceptions which cannot all be true. Kant has proved the erratic tendencies of intellectual understanding when it is allowed to wander in the unchartered regions which are beyond the jurisdiction of senses. Our reason is a valued instrument but its services are bound to be negative. It can enable us to determine that the ultimate reality cannot be of this or that sort. Page #299 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 262 JAINA YOGA [CH. But it is undependable so far as the positive nature of it is concerned. For this we must fall back upon another organ and this organ is meditation free from the visitations of the extraneous influences. Self-meditation is common to all, and is a process of supreme importance to all the Indian systems. Meditation on the nature of self is the only means of realizing the truth. * One cannot grasp the truth unless one meditates upon it, and one cannot realize it unless one grasps it. The aspirant should pin his faith on whatever system he might have been initiated into and should see for himself at the end of the process whether he started with a right postulate. A sceptic has no place in the path of realization. How can one realize the truth unless one exerts oneself for it? And why should one exert oneself for the truth unless one has implicit faith in it and the possibility of its realization? One must have either unflinching faith in the authority of one's preceptor (guru), or else one must have a direct glimpse of the truth itself before one can proceed in the path of realization. Implicit faith in the truth, whether born with the help of the preceptor or fostered by a spontaneous intuition of the truth, is the starting point of the path of spiritual realization. There are various processes of leading oneself from this stage of implicit faith in the truth to the stage of final realization of the truth. The processes have a common term for them, and that term is yoga. In Jainism the term caritra (conduct) is the exact equivalent of the general term yoga. But we have selected the term for the headline in order only to suggest the unanimity of Indian 1 The term yoga has a chequered history. 'The word 'yoga' occurs in the earliest sacred literature of the Hindus in the Rgveda (about 3000 B.C.) with the meaning of effecting a connection. Later on, in about 700 or 800 B.C. the same word is used in the sense of yoking a horse. In still later literature (about 500 or 600 B.C.) it is found with the meaning of controlling the senses, and the senses themselves are compared with uncontrolled spirited horses. The word probably represents a very old original of the Aryan stock, which can be traced also in the German joch, OE. geoc, Latin jugum, Greek zugon.' Dasgupta: Philosophical Essays, Calcutta University, 1941, p. 179. In Panini's time the word yoga had attained its technical meaning, and he distinguished the root yuj samadhau (w/yuj in the sense of concentration) from yujir yoge w yujir in the sense of connecting).'-HIP, Vol. I, p. 226. It is, so far as my knowledge goes, only Haribhadra who defined the term yoga in the sense of 'what leads one to emancipation for the first time in the history of Jaina thought. (Cf. mukkhena joyanao jogo savvo vi dhamma-vavaro Haribhadra's Yogavimsika, karika 1). This meaning of the term is unanimously accepted in the post-Haribhadra Jaina literature. Of course, the term yoga was used in the general sense of subduing the senses and the mind and the processes of concentration and ecstasy even in the earlier stages of the Jaina thought as well as in the early Buddhist thought. But the terms jhana (dhyana) and samadhi were more in vogue than the term yoga. It is only in the Yogasutra of Patanjali that we find the proper location of dhyana in the whole process called yoga for the first time. Page #300 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ V] INTRODUCTORY 263 systems regarding the processes leading to self-realization. If there is any difference it is only one of emphasis and not of essence. This will be apparent from the study. Before we come to the central theme we must have some understanding of the general scheme of the Jaina doctrine of conduct (caritra). In the last chapter we have spoken about the inflow of karmic matter and bondage. Here we shall enquire about the means of stoppage (samvara) of the inflow of new karmic matter and also the means of dispersion or dissociation (nirjara) of the accumulated karmic matter from the soul. We have seen in the last chapter that the inflow and bondage of the karmic matter are due to the activities and passions of the soul, and so it naturally follows that the eradication of the activities and passions is the means of the stoppage of the inflow and fixation or bondage of new karmic matter. The inflow of karmic matter is due to the threefold activities of the mind, the sense-organ of speech and the body, and hence the first condition of the stoppage of inflow is the control (gupti) of thought, speech and physical movements. There are other conditions needed for the consummation. They are: (1) the fivefold regulation (samiti) of the five main activities for the maintenance of life;2 (2) the tenfold moral virtues (dharma) of consummate forbearance, modesty, straightforwardness, contentment, truth, self-restraint, austerity, renunciation, non-attachment and celibacy;3 (3) contemplation (anupreksa) of these twelvefold objects viz. the fleeting nature of things, the helplessness of one involved in the worldly existence, the nature of the world itself as fraught with misery and suffering, the loneliness of the worldly sojourn, the transcendental nature of the self as distinct and separate from the body, the impure character of the body, the conditions of the inflow of karmic matter and the consequent misery and suffering, the nature of the condition of the stoppage of karmic inflow, the nature of the condition of the dissociation of karmic matter from the soul, the nature of the constituents of the universe, the difficulty of the attainment of enlightenment, and the rightness of the path of righteousness one has selected to tread upon;" (4) the patient endurance of the twenty-two afflictions (parisahas) and their conquest for the sake of steady persistence in the path of righteousness as well as for the dissociation of karmic matter;6 and 1 samyag-yoga-nigraho guptih-TSu, IX. 4. 2 Cf. irya-bhasai-'sana-''dananiksepo-'tsargah samitayah-TSu, IX. 5. 3 uttamaksa ma-mardava-'rjava-sauca-satya-samyama-tapastyaga - "kincanyabrahmacaryani dharmah-Ibid., IX. 6. 4 anitya-'sarana-samsaraikatva-'nyatva-'sucitva-'srava-samvara-nirjara - lokabodhidurlabha-dharmasvakhyatatva-'nucintanam anupreksah-TSu, IX. 7. 5 For enumeration See TSu, IX. 9. 6 margacyavana-nirjarartham parisodhavyah parisahah-TSu, IX. 8. Page #301 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 264 JAINA YOGA [CH. (5) the fivefold conduct (caritra) viz. desisting from all harmful activities (samayika), re-initiation (chedopasthapana) after the rectification of the activities due to carelessness (pramada), austerity which is possible only for one who has attained special purity and has thorough knowledge of the rules of conduct as well as the energy to observe them in life (pariharavisuddhi), conduct which is attended by the rise of only the subtlest type of passions (suksmasamparaya), and lastly the conduct which is perfect (yathakhyata). The above six viz. (1) self-control (gupti), (2) self-regulation (samiti), (3) moral virtues (dharma), (4) contemplation (anupreksa), (5) conquest of afflictions (parisahajaya) and (6) conduct (caritra) constitute the means to the stoppage (samvara) of inflow of new karmic matter. Apart from these six, the Jainas admit austerity (tapas), both physical and mental or external and internal, which effects stoppage (sarvara) of the inflow as well as the dissociation (nirjara) of the accumulated karmic matter. Each of the external and the internal types of austerity has six subclasses. Thus fasting, decreased diet, fixing the type of diet by the exclusion of all other types, giving up of strong and delicious diet, selection of a lonely and peaceful habitat, and various types of physical postures that enhance the strength of endurance are the six subclasses of the external austerity. These forms of external austerity, when rightly followed, result in non-attachment, lightness of body, conquest of the senses, protection of self-control, and lastly the dissociation of karmic matter. The following six are the subclasses of internal austerity: 5 (I) ninefold expiation (prayascitta) such as confession of a sin, repentance and the like ; (2) fourfold humility (vinaya) such as one observed in the presence of a person who is superior in the purity of attitude or knowledge or conduct and the like ; (3) respectful service (vaiyavrttya) of these ten viz. the supreme preceptor (acarya), the preceptor (upadhyaya), an ascetic (tapasvin), an ascetic student (saiksa), an ailing ascetic (glana), the descendant group (gana) of lisciples of a sthavira, the descendant group (kula) of disciples of a famous acarya, the fourfold community (sangha) of monks, nuns. laymen and laywomen, ascetics (sadhu) and the associates (samanojna); (4) the fivefold 'study' (svadhyaya) of the scriptures viz. teaching, enquiry, contemplation, correct reading and preaching of their contents; 1 TSu, IX, 18. 2 sa gupti-samiti-dharma-'nupreksa-parisahajaya-caritraih-Ibid., IX. 2. 3 anasana-'vamaudarya-vittiparisankhyana - rasa parityaga - viviktasayyasanakayaklesa bahyam tapah--TSu, IX. 19. 4 Cf. samyak-prayuktani bahyam tapah. asmat sadvidhad api bahyat tapasah sangatyaga-sariralaghave-'ndriyavijaya-sariyamaraksana-karmanirjara bhavanti--Bhasya, TSu, IX. 19. 5 prayascitta-vinaya-vaiyavsttya-svadhyaya-vyutsarga-dhyanany uttaramTSu, IX. 20. Page #302 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTORY 265 (5) the renunciation (vyutsarga) of the not-self such as the external possession as well as the quasi-self such as the body, the mind, the sense-organs and the passions ; and (6) lastly concentration (dhyana) which we propose to deal with in detail in view of its supreme importance in the scheme of the processes leading to emancipation. This long prescription of the rules of conduct, objects of contemplation and varieties of austerity is symptomatic of the supreme importance hat Jainism gives to the moral life of a spiritual aspirant. Of course, this is true of all the branches of Indian culture. But Jainism lays special stress on mortification of the flesh for the regeneration of the spirit. This is also apparent from the fact that Jainism gives so much importance to the difficult vow (vrata) of non-violence (ahirsa). The whole Jaina code of moral and spiritual virtues is inspired by the one great principle of non-violence. The other four vows of truthfulness, non-stealing, celibacy and non-possession of property are nothing but the accessories which help the fulfilment of the vow of non-violence. A number of minor vows known as sila and classified under the two categories of gunavrata and siksa-vrataare also prescribed for the householders in order to enable them to observe the five primary vows. But we do not enumerate them in order to avoid unnecessary elaboration. We also desist from stating the classification of various activities which lead to the transgression (aticara) of these vows for the same reason. It is however to be noticed that the selfsame five vows, which, when undertaken to be observed completely as is done by the Jaina ascetics (sadhus), are called mahavratas (great vows), are known as anuvratas (small vows) when they are undertaken only to be partially observed, as is done by the Jaina laity. The Jainas prescrib number of ways and means for the preservation of these vows.3 They are called bhavanas (literally contemplations). Thus, for instance, regulation of movement (iryasamiti), control of thought (manogupti) and the like are prescribed for the preservation of the vow of nonviolence; avoidance of indignation and greed, courage, and the like are prescribed for the preservation of the vow of truthfulness; and so on. Furthermore, one must always be conscious of the bad effects, both spiritual and secular, of the acts of violence, falsehood, stealing, intemperance and accumulation of property. It should also be understood that everything that helps the perpetuation of worldly existence is ultimately a condition of suffering and pain. What is, however, of supreme importance is the preservation of equanimity, consciousness of the evil nature of worldly existence, and uttermost indifference to 1 See TSu, VII. 16 with Bhasya and Tika. 2 TSu, VII. 19-31. 3 TSu, VII. 3 with Bhasya. 4 Cf. himsadisv iha 'mutra ca 'payadarsanam-TSu, VII. 4. 5 Cf. duhkham eva va-Ibid., VII. 5. JP-34 Page #303 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 266 JAINA YOGA [CH the things of the world. For the preservation of equanimity one should cultivate friendship (maitri) with all creatures, appreciation (pramoda) for the superior, compassion and sympathy (karunya) for the afflicted, and indifference (madhyasthya) for the unruly.' Contemplation of the nature of the world and the body generates fear (samvega) and indifference (vairagya) for the worldly existence and therefore is to be earnestly pursued. These are in brief the main features of the Jaina doctrine of conduct. Let us now study the essential characteristics of the Jaina conception of the pathway to emancipation, in other words, Jaina yoga. The trio of right attitude, right knowledge and right conduct constitutes, according to the Jainas, the pathway to final emancipation." We have studied the nature and mutual relation of these three in the third chapter. Right attitude or samyag-darsana is the predilection or love for truth. Every soul has such predilection in some measure. But unless and until it develops into a self-conscious pursuit of truth, it does not help spiritual progress. It is only at the stage of self-conscious effort for spiritual advancement that this love of truth is called samyag-darsana. The soul is conceived as groping in darkness before it acquires this love of truth in an appreciable measure. And it has to undergo a number of processes before the acquisition of this characteristic. After the acquisition of this characteristic the soul passes through a number of stages of spiritual development, technically known as gunasthanas. This is a very important doctrine of the Jainas. Once the soul succeeds in acquiring the samyag-darsana, it is bound to attain emancipation sooner or later. The nature of this samyagdarsana and its condition viz. the purity of the soul we have already described on more than one occasion and shall have again an occasion to do so while dealing with the doctrine of gunasthana. The attainment of right attitude (samyag-darsana) is followed by the attainment of right knowledge (samyag-jnana) and right conduct (samyakcaritra). The soul acquires more and more power for self-concentration I maitri-pramoda-karunya-madhyasthyani sattva-gunadhika-klisya mana-'vincyesu-Ibid., VII. 6. 2 jagat-kayasvabhavau.ca sarvega-vairagyartham--TSu, VII. 7. 3 samyagdarsana-jnana-caritrani moksamargah-TSu, I. 1. 4 Vide supra, pp. 146-151. 5 There are souls who do never acquire this characteristic and, therefore, are never released from worldly bondage. These souls are called abhavya (incapable of release). The Jainas do not give any ultimate reason for this endless bondage. We find similar conception in Buddhism as well. Cf. varsaty api hi parjanye nai 'va 'bijam prarohati samutpade 'pi buddhanam na 'bhavyo bhadram asnute. -Abhisamayalankara, VIII. 10, quoted in Bu-Ston (Part II, P. 138 footnote). Page #304 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ v] INTRODUCTORY 267 (dhyana) along with the increase of its purity and consequent attainment of the corresponding stages of spiritual development. We shall describe the nature of this concentration after we have discussed the doctrine of gunasthana. It is generally believed that the Jainas, from the very outset, put their whole stress on physical austerity and more or less neglected the aspect of meditation and self-concentration. But this belief is not true. Physical austerity is only an index of tual detachment.' The identification of the soul with the body is the root evil to be got rid of. And this is possible only if one practises detachment from the body. The natural consequence of this practice of detachment is indifference towards it. The practice of detachment is incompatible with the care for its well-being. The works of Acarya Kundakunda, Pujyapada and Jinabhadra contain elaborate instructions in self-meditation and concentration of mind. The works of Haribhadra record a number of different doctrines of yoga and their comparative evaluation. The Jnanarnava of Subhacandra and the Yogasastra of Hemacandra are valuable works on yoga. Upadhyaya Yasovijaya revived the study of Haribhadra's works on yoga. The Jaina mind was always conscious of the efficacy of meditation for the achievement of final emancipation. But it abhorred the acquisition of supernormal powers by means of the yogic processes. Self-realization was the only aim to be fulfilled by yoga. It is unanimously believed by Indian mystics that the yogic practices are attended by supernormal powers which bring about the fall of the practitioner if utilized for selfish purposes. The Jaina ascetics devoted themselves absolutely to the purification of the soul and acquisition of the power of detachment, and the result was that they were indifferent to everything else, even to their bodies. But with the ebb of spiritual fervour and earnestness in the late mediaeval and modern times, the Jaina ascetics exhausted all their energy in the observance of external austerity. The original tradition of mortification of the flesh for the regeneration of the spirit was lost in the labyrinth of formal austerities signifying nothing but spiritual bankruptcy. We have proposed to deal with the Jaina doctrine of dhyana in detail in order to bring to light the almost absolutely forgotten tradition of self-meditation that had a very important place in the scheme of Jaina yoga. We shall also record the Jaina conception of Godhead while dealing with the problem of the first attainment of samyag-darsana (right attitude) in the life history of a soul. Thus our enquiry will fall under these three heads: (I) the 1 Cf. bahyamn tapah parama-duscaram acarams tvam adhyatmikasya tapasah paribomhanartham dhyanam nirasya kalusadvayam uttarasmin dhyanadvaye vavitise 'tisayopapanne. -Samantabhadra's Byhatsvayambhustotra. 83. Page #305 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 268 JAINA YOGA (CH. doctrine of gunasthana including the conception of Godhead and the first attainment of samyag-darsana, (II) the doctrine of dhyana as contained in the Agamas and the works of Umasvati, Kundakunda, Pujyapada, Jinabhadra, Haribhadra, Subhacandra and Hemacandra, and (III) Haribhadra's comparative study and evaluation of various yoga-doctrines. I THE DOCTRINE OF GUNASTHANA The soul has inherent capacity for emancipation. But this capacity remains dormant and inactive unless and until it gets an opportunity for expression. The soul is roused to active spiritual exertion when it is reminded of the great mission that it has to fulfil. The reminder sometimes comes from the instructions of those who have realized the truth and revealed it to the public. Sometimes the soul gets hold of he truth automatically without any outside help. The Jainas do not believe either in the eternal revelation of the truth like the Mimamsakas and the Vedantins, or in its revelation by a Supreme Divinity like the Yoga and the Nyaya-Vaisesika systems. But they believe in the inherent capacity of the soul to realize the truth even in the absence of any revelation. The capacity to reveal and effectively preach the truth, however, does not belong to all the enlightened and omniscient souls. It is only those rare souls, who have acquired the potency of revealing the truth and establishing a religious community (tirthakrttva) by their moral and virtuous activities of the past life, that are capable of revealing the truth and preaching it to the world at large on their attainment of omniscience (kevalajnana). Such souls become the tirthankaras, founders of religion, who are the embodiment of the best and the highest virtues that the human mind can conceive of, the fullest expression of the potentialities of embodied existence. This is the Jaina! conception of Godhead. God, according to the Jainas, is the symbol of all that is good and great, moral and virtuous. But he is not the creator or the preserver or the destroyer. He is not in any sense responsible for the destiny of the universe or the individual. Nor is he capable of granting grace to any individual. Nor is he himself eternally free, but has worked out his own freedom exactly in the same way as the others do. The difference between the ordinary omniscient 1 For enumeration of such activities see TSu, VI. 23: darsanavisuddhir vinayasampannata silavratesv anaticaro 'bhiksnami jnanopayoga-samvegau saktitas tyagatapasi sangha-sadhu-samadhi-vaiyavsttyakaranam arhadacarya-bahusruta-pravacanabhaktiravasya kaparihanir marga prabhavana pravacanavatsalatvam iti tirthakTttvasya. Page #306 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ v. 1] DOCTRINE OF GUNASTHANA 269 and a tirthankara is this that the latter can reveal and preach the truth and found a religious community while the former cannot. The worldly career of a soul destined to be a tirthankara is purer and much more spiritually elevated than that of an ordinary soul destined to be emancipated. The tirthankara is a spiritual leader and an inspirer and a founder or reviver of a religion which is destined to last for an appreciable period of time. The worldly existence is beginningless and there has been an infinite number of cycles of creation, and it is held that the first founder of culture and civilization of each cycle is the first tirthankara of that cycle. It is only the tirthankara who can reveal the truth and inspire the masses. This is the Jaina conception of Godhead. After this brief digression to the idea of Godhead in Jainism, let us revert to our original problem of the first awakening of the predilection for truth (samyagdarsana). There is always a tendency in the soul to run away from the circle of world existence. But this centrifugal tendency is thwarted by a centripetal force that keeps the soul tracing the circumference of the world process. The centripetal force consists in the passions of attraction (raga) and repulsion (duesa) or rather their root viz. perverted attitude (mithyatva) towards truth. The centrifugal tendency is that part of the characteristic potency of the soul which still remains unhindered or unobstructed. This remain-1 ing part of the potency we have referred to in the last chapter. It is this centrifugal tendency that ultimately leads the soul to the right path. The problem 'Why should this tendency develop into a patent force in one soul, and remain only a dormant virtue in another' is not regarded as needing solution. It is a fact of common experience that different individuals have different degrees of power manifest in them. And this is an ultimate fact of experience incapable of being accounted for by further ultimate facts. The soul, during the course of its eternal wanderings in various forms of existence, sometimes is possessed of an indistinct vision of its goal and feels an impulse from within to realize it. This impulse is the work of the eternal centrifugal tendency already mentioned. The impulse is a kind of manifestation of energy, technically known as yathapraurtta karana. It is not always effective, and 1 Vide supra, p. 241. 2 How the soul happens to develop this tendency is illustrated in a number of ways on the analogy of the experience of common facts. For these illustrations see ViBh, 1204-1217. 3 Sometimes the eternal tendency itself is stated as the yathapravsttakarana. Cf. anadikalat karmaksa panapravitto 'dhyavasayaviseso yathapravittakaranam ityarthah-Byhadurtti, Vibh, 1202. But generally and almost unanimously the yathapravsttakarana is identified with the temporary impulse lasting for less than a muhurta (forty-eight minutes) wherein the soul achieves such purification as causes it to feel uneasiness with the worldly existence. This yathapravrttakarana * Page #307 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 270 JAINA YOGA But so does not always invariably lead to spiritual advancement. sometimes it is so strong and irresistible that it goads the soul to come to grips with the centripetal force and to weaken it to an appreciable extent in the struggle that ensues. Here the soul is face to face with what is known as granthi or the Gordian knot of intense attachment and repulsion.1 If the impulse is strong enough to cut the knot, the adhA prakRtikANa athAha pravRtikaraNa is known as athapravrttakarana or adhahpravrttakarana in the Digambara works (TRa, p. 317 Labdhisara, 35). The original common Prakrit term was adhapavatta (PS: Upa, 5; Kp: Upa, 8; Labdhisara, 35) which was equated to a number of Sanskrit terms expressing different meanings. The Labdhisara distinguishes four stages of the achievement (labdhi) of purification before the soul reaches the adhahpravrttakarana. They are: (1) a certain measure of dissociation-cum-subsidence (ksayopasama) of the karmic matter, (2) the consequent purification (visuddhi), (3) the opportunity of getting the instructions (desana) of the enlightened sages, and (4) prayogya or the reduction of the duration of all the types of karman except the ayuh-karman to less than kotakoti years as well as the reduction of the intensity of the inauspicious karmans. The fifth labdhi comprises the three karanas of which the first is adhahpravrttakarana.-Labdhisara, 3-7- The Karmaprakrti also recognizes these labdhis. (See Kp: Upa, 3 with Curni. The second labdhi is not mentioned explicitly, but it is indubiously implied). As regards the state of the physical organism of the soul when it is competent to undergo such processes it is said that the organism must be five-sensed and possessed of mind as well as fully developed. Furthermore, at the time of such processes the soul is possessed of determinate knowledge and anyone of the threefold activities of body, the sense-organ of speech and mind.. The soul enjoys purification even from before the actual setting in of the processes. And on account of the purification, during the antarmuhurta (a period of time less than forty-eight minutes) preceding the process of yathapravrttakarana, the soul binds only such duration as is less than a kotakoti sagaropama years, and binds only the second degree of intensity of inauspicious karmans while it binds the fourth degree of intensity of the auspicious karmans. Similarly the soul reduces the duration of the already existing karmans to less than one kotakoti sagaropama years and the fourth degree of intensity of the inauspicious karmans to the second degree while increasing the second degree of intensity of the auspicious karmans to the fourth. It, however, cannot bind the ayuhkarman being too pure to do so. 'Nor can the soul effect reduction of the duration of the already bound ayuhkarman, because such reduction is an impossibility. This is, as we have said above, called prayogya labdhi. Then follow the three processes during the next three antarmuhurtas. And during the fourth antarmuhurta that follows these three, the soul enjoys absolute subsidence of the vision-deluding karman. This period is called upasantadhvan, the period of the absolute subsidence of the vision-deluding (mithyatva) karman. For other details see Kp: Upa, 3-8. [CH. 1 Cf. gamthi 'tti sudubbheo kakkhada-ghana-rudha-gudha-gamthi vva jivassa kammajanio ghana-raga-dosa-parinamo.-ViBh, 1195. The soul is confronted with this knot when the remaining duration of each of the eight types of karman except the ayuhkarman is one sagaropama kotakoti years minus a fraction of a palyopama number of years. Cf. antima-kodakodie savvakammanam auvajjanam paliyasamkhijjaime bhage khine bhavai gamthi. -ViBh, 1194; see also Brhadvrtti. Page #308 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ v. 1] DOCTRINE OF GUNASTHANA 271 soul is successful in the struggle and is now bound to be emancipated sooner or later within a limited time. The struggle consists in the twofold processes known as apurvakarana' and anivrtti karana (also known as anivartikarana). Let us study, in brief, their nature. By the pathapravrttakarana the soul is confronted with the concentrated force of the passions, and the other two karanas enable the soul to overpower and transcend the force. The force of the passions was there from all eternity. But it is only on some occasions that the soul is feelingly conscious of this force. Such consciousness means coming face to face with the knot (granthi). This consciousness is the work of the process called yathapraurtta karana. During this process the soul undergoes progressive purification every instant, and binds the karmic matter of appreciably less duration. Furthermore, there is increase in the intensity of the bondage of auspicious karmans accompanied with the decrease in the intensity of the bondage of inauspicious karmans. And as a result the soul gets an indistinct vision of the goal of its tiresome journey. This, we think, is the implication of the conception of granthi and the soul's coming face to face with it. Originally the soul lies in a state of spiritual slumber. Gradually it awakens and becomes self-conscious. Moral and spiritual consciousness dawns only when it is sufficiently conscious of and confronted with the force that has eternally been keeping it ensnared and entrapped. But this consciousness alone is not sufficient to enable the soul to overcome the force. A more powerful manifestation of energy is necessary for the purpose. And the souls that lack in this requisite energy fail to fulfil their mission and withdraw before the force. It is only the souls having the requisite energy who can overcome the force. Such souls manifest the requisite energy by way of the two processes of apurvakarana and anivetlikarana at the end of which the soul develops such spiritual strength as is destined to gradually develop and lead it to the final emancipation. In the process of apurvakarana which, like the yathapravrttakarana, lasts only for less than forty-eight minutes (antarmuhurta), the soul passes through such states as it never experienced before (apurva). The soul had considerably reduced the duration and intensity of the karmans in the process of yathapravrttakarana, and reduces them still further in the apurvakarana. The karanas are spiritual impulses that push the soul to fulfil its mission and realize the goal. And this is possible only if the soul can reduce the duration and intensity and also the mass of the karmic matter associated with it. What the soul did automatically without any moral or spiritual effort until now, it now does consciously with spiritual exertion. During the process of apurvakarana the soul undergoes such 1 It is called nivsttikarana in PS: U pa, 5. Page #309 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 272 JAINA YOGA [CH. purification as has colossal effect on the duration and intensity of the bondage of new karmans as well as the accumulated ones. This is made possible by the following four sub-processes which begin simultaneously from the very first instant of the main process : (I) destruction of duration (sthitighata), (2) destruction of intensity (rasaghata), (3) the construction of a complex series (gunasreni) of the groups of karmic atoms, arranged in geometrical progression with an incalculable common ratio, transplanted from the mass of karmic matter that would have come to rise after an antarmuhurta? for the sake of their premature exhaustion by fruition, and (4) an unprecedented type of bondage of small duration (apurva-sthitibandha) whose length is much smaller than that of the duration hitherto bound.3 The soul undergoes yet another (5) sub-process known as transference of karmic matter (gunasamkrama). By this process a portion of the karmic matter of the inauspicious types of karman is transferred to some other types of karman. The mass of karmic matter thus transferred increases every moment until the end of the apurvakarana process. There are thus five characteristic sub-processes in the process of apurvakarana. At the end of this process the knot (granthi) is cut never to appear again. The first process of yathapravytta karana leads one face to face with the knot, and the second process of apurvakarana enables one to cross it, while the third process of anivytti karana leads the soul to the verge of the dawn of the first enlightenment that comes like a flash on account of the absolute subsidence of the karmic matter of the vision-deluding (mithyatvamohaniya) karman. The nature of this enlightenment we shall describe later on. The soul undergoes the same five sub-processes, described above, in the process of anivrttikarana also. But here there occurs a new process called antarakarana whereby the soul divides into two parts the karmic matter of the vision-deluding karman that was to come into rise after the anivyttikarana. The first of the two parts the soul forces into rise during the last few instants of aniurttikarana while the rise of the second part is postponed for an antarmuhurta during which no karmic matter of the vision-deluding karman is allowed to rise and produce its effect on the soul. Thus at the end of the process of anivyttikarana the vision deluding karman has no effect on the soul for an antarmuhurta. This antarmuhurta is the period when the soul 1 See Kp: Upa, 12. 2 This is equivalent, as already stated, to a period which is less than forty-eight minutes. 3 For a detailed description see Kg2, pp. 125-6. 4 Kg2, p. 126. 5 ja gamthi ta padhamam gamthi samaicchao apuvvam tu aniyattikaranam puna sammatta-purakkhade jive.-Vibh, 1203. Also Cf. anadikalad arabhya yavad granthisthanam tavat prathamar yathapravsttakaranam bhavati....... tata eva visuddhatamadhyavasaya. rupad anantarar samyaktvalabhat-Byhadvytti on the above gatha. Page #310 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ v. 1] DOCTRINE OF GUNASTHANA 273 enjoys the first dawn of enlightenment or the spiritual vision (samyaktva or samyag-darsana). It is necessary in this connection to state in brief the nature of this enlightenment or spiritual vision that now brings about a colossal change in the career of the soul. As we have stated above, there is absolute subsidence of the visiondeluding karmic matter for one antarmuhurta at the end of the process of aniurttikarana. The function of the vision deluding karman is to delude the soul's right attitude towards or predilection for truth. But now as there is no effect of this karman on the soul, the vision of truth dawns upon it. This is enlightenment. The soul realizes its own nature during the vision, and it does no more fall into the darkness that it was in until now. Of course, the vision does not last long. But it leaves such indelible impress on the soul as does ever keep it above the previous depth of darkness. The soul may again fall in the darkness. But the darkness is never so deep as before, and that even the soul is sure to get rid of in due course. It is said that on the attainment of the vision the soul attains an insight which it had never attained before. Even as a person born blind can see the world as it is on the sudden acquisition of the eyesight so can a soul having experienced the vision can see the truth as it is. Even as a person suffering from long-drawn disease experiences extreme delight on the sudden disappearance of the disease so does a soul eternally bound to the wheel of worldly existence feel spiritual joy and bliss on the sudden dawn of the enlightenment. This elightenment is called aupasamika samyaktva because it is due to the upasama (subsidence) of the karman that deludes the samyaktva (right vision). The vision-deluding karman, as we have seen in the third chapter, is nothing but what is known as avidya in the other systems. We can therefore say that the enlightenment dawns on the subsidence of avidya. And this is a very simple truth. The enlightenment is only temporary and the soul attains such enlightenment on more than one occasion during its spiritual career leading to the final eternal enlightenment. Let us come back to the main problem and see what happens after the enlightenment. We have stated that the vision-deluding karmic matter is divided into two parts by the process of antara karana. The first part has already come into rise in the last part of the aniurttikarana. The second part, the rise whereof was postponed for the duration of enlightenment, is now to come into rise. The content of this part is placed into three heaps according to the difference of intensity during 1 Cf. jatyandhasya yatha pumsas caksurlabhe subhodaye saddarsanam tathai 'va 'sya samyaktve sati jayate. anando jayate 'tyantam tattviko 'sya mahatmanah sadvyadhyapagame yad va vyadhitasya sadausadhat. - Quoted in Malayagiri's sika on Kp: Upa, 18. JP-35 Page #311 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 274 JAINA YOGA [CH the last instant of the anivrttikarana, that is, the instant just preceding the enlightenment. Of these three heaps, one is pure (that is, does not obscure samyaktva 'right vision' by its rise), the second is semi-pure (that is, obscures the right vision only partially), and the third is impure (that is, obscures the right vision completely). Then from the very first instant of the period of enlightenment the soul begins, by the process called guna-sainkrama, transforming the content of the impure heap into pure as well as semi-pure matter and depositing them into the corresponding heaps. The quantity of matter thus transformed increases every moment, the quantity transformed into semi-pure matter being always greater than the quantity transformed into pure matter.? Now in this way at the end of the period of enlightenment the soul is confronted with three qualitatively different heaps of vision deluding karman which was originally homogeneous before the enlightenment. Anyone of these three can come into rise after the period of enlightenment. If it is the pure heap that comes into rise on account of the persistent purity of the soul, then the soul attains purity of character also and attains to a higher stage of spiritual development. But if it is the semi-pure heap that comes into rise then the soul feels rebuff and gradually falls back to the lowest stage. And if it is the impure heap that comes into rise the soul at once finds itself in the lowest stage. We have now seen how the soul attains the first spiritual vision on account of the subsidence of the karmic matter responsible for the basic defect called perversity of attitude (mithyatva). This spiritual vision, however, is only temporary and disappears within a very short time. The soul now attempts in a number of ways to recapture the vision, and make it a permanent possession. The processes that the soul has to undergo for the purpose are quite analogous to the processes already described with slight variation in their details which are not very important. Moreover, the processes follow quite easily from an analysis of the conditions of bondage. There are five conditions of bondage viz. perversity of attitude (mithyatva), non-abstinence (avirati), spiritual inertia (pramada), passions (kasaya), and the threefold activities (yoga) of the body, the sense-organ of speech, and the mind.3 The passions are four viz. anger, pride, deceit, and greed each of which again can be of four types viz. 'lifelong' (anantanubandhin), that which obscures the energy for even partial abstinence (apratyakhyanavarana), that which obscures only the energy for complete abstinence (pratyukhyanavarana), and that which is very fickle and meagre and is effective only occasionally (sarnjualana). We have stated these types in the last chapter also. We shall refer to these four types respectively 1 kp: Upa, 19 with Tika. 2 Ibid., 20 with Tika. 3 mithyadarsana-'virati-pramada-kasaya-yoga bandhahetavah--TSu, VIII. I. Page #312 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ V. 1] DOCTRINE OF GUNASTHANA 275 as the first, the second, the third, and the fourth type in the following enquiry as we did in the last chapter too. For the final consummation the soul has to remove all these five conditions. The soul has weakened the hold of the perversity of attitude but has not practised abstinence from evil and immoral deeds. This it has to do by increasing its purity and augmenting its energy for right willing and right conduct. Then the soul has to secure immunity from the spiritual inertia (pramada). But all this is only preliminary activity. The most important activity for spiritual progress, however, is the subduing of the passions. And this is possible only by the repetition of the threefold processes of yathapravrttakarana, apurvakarana, and anivytti karana. There are now two ways open for the soul. It may climb up the spiritual ladder by suppressing the passions or it may climb it up by totally annihilating them. The former mode of spiritual progress is known as upasamasreni (ladder of subsidence) and the latter as ksapakasreni (ladder of annihilation). The fifth condition of bondage viz. the threefold activities lasts up to the final stage of spiritual ascent, and its absolute elimination is immediately followed by the disembodied emancipation of the soul. It will be helpful for the understanding of the stages of spiritual development (gunasthana) if we give a brief description of the twofold ladders at this stage of our enquiry. While climbing up the ladder of subsidence, the soul suppresses, by undergoing the three processes of yathapravrttakarana etc., the four 'lifelong' passions at the outset and then the three vision-deluding karmans. The soul then attains such purification as enables it to rise up from spiritual inertia. But the progress is not steady. The soul repeatedly gets up to the stage of spiritual vigour and falls back to the stage of spiritual inertia. It fluctuates between the state of spiritual vigour and the state of spiritual inertia a hundred times before it reaches the state of steady progress through the repetition of the three processes and begins the gradual suppression of the following sub-types of the conduct-deluding (caritramohaniya) karman: the nine quasipassions?; the second, the third, and the fourth types of anger; the same three types of pride ; the same three types of deceit ; and the second and third types of greed. Then the soul suppresses the fourth type of greed and attains a state where all the twenty-eight sub-types of the deluding karman are completely suppressed. The soul's minimum stay at this stage of absolute suppression of the deluding karman is for one instant and the maximum for an antarmuhurta. After this stay the soul invariably falls down to the lower stages on the rise of the suppressed passions. The stronger the rise of the passions, the lower is the fall. A soul can climb up this ladder of subsidence only twice in the same life. But the soul which has climbed up the i Vide supra, p. 234. 2 See Kgi, p. 73. Page #313 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 276 JAINA YOGA [CH. ladder twice cannot climb up the ladder of annihilation in that life and so cannot attain emancipation in the same life. The soul which has climbed up the ladder of subsidence only once has the chance of climbing up the ladder of annihilation and thus attaining final emancipation in that very life. The ladder of annihilation also is climbed up in almost the same way. Only the souls encased in a strong body can climb up this ladder. By the three processes the soul annihilates at the outset the four 'lifelong' passions. Then the three sub-types of the visiondeluding karman are annihilated. If the individual dies at this stage after the annihilation of the above seven sub-types of karman, it has to experience three or four more births before it attains emancipation.1 Otherwise, the soul proceeds further for the gradual annihilation, by means of the threefold processes, of the second and third types of passions, the nine quasi-passions, and the fourth type of anger, pride and deceit. Then last of all the soul annihilates the fourth type of greed and attains a state where all the sub-types of the deluding karman have been annihilated.2 This is the summit of the ladder of annihilation. The soul is now free from passions and immediately attains omniscience and reaches a stage which is known as the state of embodied freedom (jivanmukti). With this background in mind, let us study the conception of the stages of spiritual development (gunasthana).3 The soul passes through an infinite number of states while reaching from the lowest to the highest stage of spiritual development. These states have been classified into fourteen stages of spiritual development called gunasthanas. The lowest stage is the state of perversity of attitude towards truth (mithyadrsti-gunasthana). The soul has the minimum possible degree of right vision at this stage. It has only a very indistinct enlightenment, the minimum that the soul can have, and we have stated on more than one occasion why the soul cannot be absolutely bereft of the enlightenment. Even those souls which have cut the knot (granthi) and experienced the spiritual vision on account of the absolute suppression and subsidence (upasama) of the visiondeluding karman can fall down to this stage on the rise of the relevant karman. But such souls do not sink down to the depth where the souls which have not cut the knot exist. Next we come to the second stage called sasvadana-samyagdrsti. The soul does not pass on to the second stage from the first, but only halts at it while falling down from some higher stage of spiritual development. Thus if at the end katitame bhave 1 Cf. athocyeta-ksinasaptako gatyantaram sankraman moksam upayati? ucyate-trtiye caturthe va bhave-Malayagiri's Tika on Kp: Upa, 32. 2 See Kg1, p. 74. 3 This study is based on Kg1, pp. 67-77 Page #314 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ V. 1] DOCTRINE OF GUNASTHANA 277 of the period of the dawn of the first enlightenment there is the rise of the 'lifelong' passions, the soul falls down from that enlightenment to this stage of sasvadana-samyagdrsti. Sometimes the soul climbing up the ladder of subsidence also falls down to this stage. And the souls falling down to this stage necessarily fall back to the first stage. Then we come to the third stage of right-cum-wrong attitude (samyagmithya-dysti). If after the end of the period of the dawn of the first enlightenment there is the rise of the semi-pure heap of the visiondeluding karman, the soul sinks down to this stage for an antarmuhurta, and afterwards either falls back to the first stage or rises up to a higher stage of right vision. The fourth stage of spiritual development is called right vision without abstinence (avirata-samyagdrsti). The soul has acquired right vision, but is lacking in spiritual strength, and so, in spite of the knowledge and the will it cannot abstain from the wrong path. It has steady vision, but is lacking in the capacity for spiritual self-control in conformity with the vision. The right vision at this stage may be the vision due to the absolute subsidence of the vision-deluding karman (aupasamika) or it may be the vision due to the subsidence-cum-dissociation of the relevant karman (ksayopasamika) which occurs on the rise of the pure heap of the vision deluding karman, or it may be the vision due to the annihilation of the four lifelong' passions and the three sub-types of the vision-deluding karman (ksayika-samyagdysti). For spiritual development the soul must develop the strength of all these three-vision, knowledge, and selfcontrol. At this stage the soul lacks in self-control. It has the requisite vision and knowledge and wisdom. It has the right will. But the energy for self-control is wanting. The soul can rise to the next stages only if it can fulfil this want. Next we come to the fifth stage of right vision with capacity for partial abstinence (desavirata-samyagdysti). At this stage the soul is not capable of complete abstinence from immoral deeds on account of the rise of the third type of passions which obscure the capacity for total abstinence. There is only a partial expression of the energy for self-control at this stage. The soul overcomes this weakness in the next stage. But even there the energy of the soul is not fully expressed. The spiritual inertia (pramada) is still there. This is the stage of selfcontrol with spiritual inertia (pramatta-samyata). The spiritual inertia is overcome in the next, the seventh, stage of self-control with freedom from spiritual inertia (apramatta-sarnyata). Next we come to the eighth stage called apurvakarana (or nivytti). Here the soul attains special purification and is capable of reducing the duration and intensity of the previously bound karmans and binds 1 The Prakrit equivalent is niyatti.-See Kg1, p. 67 (gatha 2). Page #315 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 278 JAINA YOGA [CH. new karmans of reduced duration and intensity. At this stage the soul does the processes of sthitighata (destruction of duration), rasaghata (destruction of intensity), gunasreni (arrangement of series), gunasarnkrama (transformation of karmic matter), and apurvasthitibandha (bondage of an unprecedented kind of duration)--already describedmore vigorously and increases its purity more rapidly. The stage is so called because the soul performs these processes with a vigour and rapidity unprecedented (apurva) in its history. The soul's maximum stay at this stage is for one antarmuhurta. The soul performs the process of apurvakarana, while climbing up either of the two ladders, at this stage. The soul climbing up the ladder of subsidence remains in the minimum one instant and in the maximum an antarmuhurta at this stage, while the soul climbing up the other ladder remains there, as a rule, for an antarmukurta. The next, the ninth, stage of development is anivrtti-badara-samparaya. The soul performs the process of aniurttikarana at this stage while climbing up either of the ladders. There is still the possibility of the attack of even the gross passions (badara-samparaya) and hence the name of the stage. The tenth stage is called suksma-samparaya because in it only the subtle (suksma) greed of the fourth type can disturb the soul now and then. At this stage the soul is free from the influence of all the passions except very subtle greed. This subtle greed can be interpreted as the subconscious attachment to the body even in the souls which have achieved great spiritual advancement. The soul which has advanced by only suppressing the sub-types of the deluding karman, that is, the soul which has climbed up the ladder of subsidence goes up to the eleventh stage of suppressed passions (upasanta-kasaya). The subtle greed that was active in the previous stage is also suppressed in this stage and the soul is free from the rise of all types of passions. The soul even at this stage has not freed itself from the enveloping influence (chadman) of the karinans other than the deluding karman and hence is 'enveloped (chadmastha). It has suppressed attachment and hence is known as free from attachment (vitaraga) at this stage. The full designation of this stage therefore is upasantakasaya-vitaragachadmastha. The soul stays at this stage for one instant in the minimum and for an antarmuhurta in the maximum, after which it invariably falls down to some lower stage on the rise of the suppressed passions. The soul which, however, has advanced by gradually annihilating the sub-types of the deluding karman, that is, the soul which has climbed up the ladder of annihilation goes up from the tenth to the twelfth stage of annihilated passions (ksinakasaya). The other characteristics of the twelfth stage are identical with those of the eleventh stage. This stage is the summit of the ladder of annihilation as the former is the summit of the ladder of subsidence. The soul Page #316 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ V. 1] DOCTRINE OF GUNASTHANA 279 remains for one antarmuhurta in this stage. In the last instant of this stage all the sub-types of the knowledge-covering, intuition-covering and the obstructive (antaraya) karman are annihilated, and the soul is now absolutely free from all the four types of obscuring (ghatin) karman. The soul now is in the thirteenth stage of spiritual development. This stage is the equivalent of what is known as the jivanmukta stage in other Indian systems. The Jaina name for this stage is sayogakevali-gunasthana. Of the five conditions of bondage viz. perversity, non-abstinence, spiritual inertia, passions, and activity, the first four are now totally annihilated. The last one however still remains, and hence it is sayoga (with activity). The soul is now omniscient (kevalin). It has now attained full and perfect intuition. There is now perfect expression of spiritual energy. There is however still the rise and existence of the four non-obscuring types of karman viz. feelingproducing (vedaniya), longevity-determining (ayus), body-building (naman), and the status-determining (gotra). The soul is not freed from the embodied existence until it reaches the end of the life term already determined by the ayuhkarman. There is also the threefold activity of the body, the sense-organ of speech and the mind. But there is no new bondage leading to worldly life. A soul remains in this stage for one antarmuhurta in the minimum and for somewhat less than a purvakoti in the maximum. Before entening into the last and the final, the fourteenth, stage of absolute motionlessness which lasts only for a very short time and is immediately followed by final emancipation, the soul prepares for the stoppage of all activity, gross and subtle. The stoppage of an activity requires another activity as the instrument. And so the soul first stops the gross activities of the sense-organ of speech and the mind by the gross activity of the body. Then it stops the gross activity of the body as well as the subtle activities of the sense-organ of speech and the mind by the subtle activity of the body. The soul then enters the third stage of sukla-dhyanal which is 'accompanied with subtle vibration' (suksmakriya) and steady (anivartin), and stops the subtle bodily activity by means of the activity itself for there is none other than itself. Due to the above dhyana the soul contracts and fills the cavities created in embodied state. It is now reduced. Then it enters the fourth stage of the sukla-dhyana which is bereft of all vibration (samucchinnakriya) and infallible (apratipatin). It is now as motionless as a mountain rock (sailesa). Here all the remaining karmans are annihilated. This state of absolute motionlessness is the fourteenth stage of ayoga-kevalin. The state lasts only for the period of time required to pronounce five short syllables at the ordinary speed. At the end of this period the soul attains unembodied emancipation. 1 Vide infru, p. 292. Page #317 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 280 JAINA YOGA [CH. It is to be noticed in this connection that the length of the ayuhkarman of a soul attaining emancipation cannot be reduced or increased. And in case the length of any of the other three karmans is greater than that of the ayuh karman, the soul reduces the former length in order to make it equal to the latter. This equalization is possible by a certain process called samudghata. It is a rule that the omniscient must enjoy in full the fruits of the four karmans viz. vedaniya, naman, gotra and ayus. It is again usual that the length of the vedaniya karman of an omniscient is greater than the length of his ayuhkarman. The lengths of the said three karmans are to be equalized by the process of samudghata. This process lasts only for eight instants, and is an indispensable means of the premature fruition and the consequent exhaustion of the karmans of longer durations." The karmic matter is forced to fructify earlier than the scheduled time by this process. There is a number of types of samudghata. We are, however, concerned with the process of the samudghata of a kevalin (omniscient). The soul in the thirteenth stage performs this process just an antarmuhurta before its final emancipation. In the first instant of the process the soul stretches itself vertically both ways and touches the zenith as well as the nadir of the inhabited universe (loka), the thickness of this vertical column being the same as that of the body. In the second instant the soul expands itself in the forward and the backward directions up to the end of the loka. In the third i the soul expands sidewise both ways up to the end of the same. The soul now has divided the loka into four parts. In the fourth instant the soul expands in the remaining gaps and thus fills up the whole loka. Then in the next four instants the soul retraces the steps and returns to its original condition in the eighth instant. Now the soul has equalized the length of the other karmans with that of the ayuhkarman. It now prepares for the fourteenth stage of absolute motionlessness in the way described above. 1 See Kgi, p. 159. 2 Cf. samudghatagato jivah prasahya karmapudgalan kalantaranubhavarhan api ksapayati drutam. --Lokaprakasa, Dravya, III. 13. 3 Even as a wet cloth dries up sooner when it is fully stretched out, so is the intensity (rasa) and consequently the duration (sthiti) dried up by the utmost expansion of the soul in the process of samudghata. Cf. ardrambara-'susosavad atma-visarana-visuska-samakarma. -Tika on TSubh, IX. 41 (p. 276). Page #318 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ . II] V. DOCTRINE OF DHYANA II THE DOCTRINE OF DHYANA Jainism, like the other systems of Indian thought, attaches supreme importance to dhyana (concentration of mind) as a means to spiritual realization. Along with its purification, the soul develops the capacity for self-concentration.1 Before coming to the topic of dhyana proper it is necessary to understand the fundamental motive that inspired the whole Jaina outlook towards dhyana. The Jainas, like others in the field, put stress on self-realization. The materialist view of the self as identical with the body is the first thing that one is to get rid of in order to tread the path of spiritual realization. For this purpose one" is required to turn inward and concentrate upon the self as distinct and separate from the body. When one is fully convinced of the distinction between self and not-self, one is required to rise still higher and concentrate upon and realize the transcendental self. which is free from all the limitations of the empirical self. Acarya Kundakunda and, following him, Pujyapada and Yogindudeva have very thoroughly discussed this method of self-realization in their respective works viz. Moksaprabhrta, Samadhitantra and Paramatmaprakasa. They distinguish three states of the self viz. the exterior self (bahiratman), the interior self (antaratman), and the transcendental self (paramatman). The self with the deluded belief that it is none other than the body is the exterior self. The self that clearly discriminates itself from the body and the sense-organs is the interior self. The pure and perfect self free from all limitations is the transcendental self. The exterior self becomes the transcendental self by means of the interior self. Or, in other words, the transcendental self is the self-realization of the exterior self through the intermediary stage of the interior self. The self or the soul is intrinsically pure and perfect. Its limitations are due to its association with karmic matter. Considered from the point of view of gunasthana, the soul before it cuts the knot (granthi) and experiences the first dawn of the spiritual vision is the exterior self, 281 1 We leave out of account the habit of the self to concentrate upon a particular object or a theme out of attachment or hatred, love or fear, anger or greed. The Jainas classify such concentration into two types viz. (1) artadhyana (mournful concentration) of mind which occurs when one experiences or apprehends the loss of one's beloved object, or when one is suffering from anguish, or when one contemplates upon one's unsatisfied desires; (2) raudradhyana (cruel concentration) which occurs when one contemplates to attack one's enemy, to do an act of injustice, to misappropriate someone's property or to protect one's own. These dhyanas are the features of animal life and therefore are left out of account. For further information one may refer to SthSu, IV. I. 247 TSu, IX. 31-36 with Bhasya and Tika; Jinabhadra's Dhyanasataka, 6-27. JP-36 Page #319 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 282 JAINA YOGA and the soul after the vision and before the attainment of omniscience is the interior self. On the attainment of omniscience the self becomes the transcendental self. One is to eradicate the interior as much as the exterior self in order to realize the transcendental self. This process of eradication is yoga. Self-concentration leads to self-realization. But such concentration is too abstract and as such too difficult to achieve for the beginner. And so a number of yogic practices is prescribed for the purpose. These practices are more of the nature of contemplation than of the nature of concentration. One is required to ever remain conscious of the nature of the world and its sufferings. And for this purpose one must initiate oneself into a certain system of thought. One must start with firm belief in the rightness of the system and should earnestly try to realize the truth advocated by it. The practices prescribed fall into two categories called dharma-dhyana and sukla-dhyana. They lead to final emancipation. Let us see the nature of these dhyanas as found in the Jaina literature-the Agamas as well as the later works. The Jainas define dhyana as 'the concentration of the thought on a particular object'." Our thought and its instrument, the mind, are ever restless. The regulation and concentration of these on a particular object is dhyana. The mind is capable of the threefold functions of concentration (bhavana), contemplation (anupreksa) and thought (cinta). Dhyana consists in the concentration of the mind on a particular object for a certain length of time which in no case can be greater than a muhurta or forty-eight minutes." The mind does not become motionless in concentration. But it is regulated and canalized. It thinks in a particular way on a particular object. Dhyana is con [CH.. 1 Cf. evam tyaktva bahirvacam tyajed antar asesatah esa yogah samasena pradipah paramatmanah.-Samadhitantra, 17. ekagra-cinta-nirodho dhyanam-TS, IX. 27. 2 3 Cf. jam thiram ajjhavasanam tam jhanam jam calam tayam cittam tam hojja bhavana va anupeha va ahava cinta. antomuhuttamettam cittavatthanam egavatthummi chaumatthanam jhanam joganiroho jinanam tu.-Dhyanasataka, 2-3The Jainas believe that the mind cannot remain concentrated on a particular object for more than a muhurta (forty-eight minutes). Of course, it can re-concentrate upon the same object after the period. This is true in the case of the imperfect beings (chadmastha). But in the case of those who have achieved omniscience, the problem of concentration of mind does not arise at all. The omniscient need not apply his mind and think. It is therefore held that in the case of the omniscient, the function of dhyana is to stop his physical activity, both gross and subtle, during the last few moments of his worldly existence which are immediately followed by final emancipation. Total stoppage of activity leads to the total stoppage of the inflow of new karmic matter and the soul, on the total dissociation, during the few moments, of all karmic matter bound in the past attains final emancipation. Page #320 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ V. II] DOCTRINE OF DHYANA: DHARMADHYANA 283 centration of thought, and not of perception. Now, as one can canalize one's thought for an evil as well as a good purpose, the dhyana is broadly classified into two categories viz. inauspicious or evil (aprasasta) and auspicious or good (prasasta). What leads to the inflow and bondage of bad karmic matter is inauspicious concentration, and what leads to the dissociation or destruction of karmic matter is auspicious concentration.' We shall leave out of account the first category of dhyana in view of its lack of bearing on our topic.2 The second category of dhyana is divided into two types viz. dharmadhyana and sukla-dhyana. Each of these types are again considered in a number of ways. Let us begin with the dharma-dhyana which is the primary condition of spiritual development. (a) Dharma-dhyana The Sthanangasutra expounds dharma-dhyana in these fourfold aspects viz. (1) its objects, (2) the signs (laksana) of a soul possessed of this dhyana, (3) its conditions (alambana), and (4) its afterthoughts.* The immaculate and infallible nature of the revelation (ajna), the fact of universal suffering (apaya) and its conditions, the nature of the fruition (vipaka) of various karmans, and the structure (samsthana) of the universe are the four objects of the dharma-dhyana. The concentration of thought on account of the meditation (vicaya) on these objects is called dharma-dhyana. The characteristic sign of a soul capable of this type of concentration is its natural love for and faith in the path it has selected to tread upon and the system of thought which it has been initiated in. Exposition (vacana), critical enquiry (pratipracchana), repeated study (parivartana), and reflection (anupreksa) are the conditions that lead to such concentration of mind. The mind muses upon the following subjects when it retires to the normal state after the concentration: the loneliness of the self in its wanderings, the fleeting nature of the worldly things, the absence of spiritual wellbeing in the world of mortality, and the nature of the world as an 1 See SSi on TS, IX. 28. Subhacandra distinguishes three categories of dhyana: (1) prasasta, (2) asat, and (3) suddha.-Jnanarnava, pp. 66-7 (verses 29-31). 2 Vide supra, footnote I, p. 281. The Prakrit term is dhamma... dharmya. 4 SthSu, IV. I. 247. 5 The SthSu mentions these four characteristic signs: (1) predilection for the revelation (ajnaruci), (2) natural predilection for truth (nisarga-ruci), (3) predilection for the scriptures (sutraruci) and (4) predilection for the deep study of the scriptures (avagadha-ruci).-SthSu, IV. 1. 247. Some commentators have rendered it as Page #321 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 284 J AINA YOGA [CH. endless motion (samsara). Jinabhadra expounds this dhyana from a few other standpoints as well. Thus, for instance, he states the four prerequisite practices -(1) the regular study (jnana) for the achievement of steadiness and purification of the mind, (2) the purification of the attitude (darsana) for the sake of removing the delusion (moha), (3) the right conduct (caritra) for the purpose of stopping the inflow of new karmic matter and the destruction of the accumulated one, and (4) non-attachment (vairagya) for acquiring steadfastness--for qualifying oneself for dharma-dhyana.2 For the beginner it is necessary that he should select a lonely place for his concentration. For those who have achieved control over themselves by the practice of the above four factors, there is no necessity of selection of place. As regards the proper time one may select any according to convenience. One may select any posture (asana) according to one's convenience." One can attain the highest state of concentration in any place at any time and in any posture. From the viewpoint of the stage of spiritual development (gunasthana), the dharma-dhyana is possible only in the seventh stage where there is absolute absence of spiritual inertia (pramada) and the full expression of self-control, or in the still higher stages up to the twelfth.6 Umasvati defines dharma-dhyana as the collection of scattered thought (smrti-samanvahara, literally collection of the memory) for the sake of meditation upon the revelation, suffering, karmic fruition, and the structure of the universe. Akalanka, following Pujyapada, holds quite a different view from the one given above regarding the stages of spiritual development wherein the dharma'-dhyana is possible. 10 According to him this dhyana is possible from the fourth up to the seventh stage. The ground given is that when the soul has attained right vision (samyaktua) in the fourth stage there is no reason why it should not be capable of this dhyana. This dhyana is not possible in the eighth and the higher stages because it is held that it is not possible in either of the two ladders (srenis). It is not possible to give any independent judgment on this controversy in view of the peculiar character of the problem which can be solved only by reference to scriptural texts. But as the texts of the one party are not acceptable to the other, it is not possible to solve the problem 1 Dhyanasataka, 28-29. 2 Ibid., 30-34 3 Ibid., 35-36. 4 Ibid., 38. 5 Ibid., 39. 6 Ibid., 63 ; TSu, IX. 37-8. 7 Pujyapada interprets it as (well regulated) thought stream (cinta prabandha). SSI, TSu, IX. 30. 8 TSu, IX. 37. 9 The term used in SSi, TRa and TSIV is dharmya. 10 SSI, IX. 36; TRa, IX. 36. 14-15; TSIV, IX, 36. Page #322 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ V. II] DOCTRINE OF DHYANA: DHARMADHYANA 285 beyond doubt. Next we come to Siddhasenaganin the commentator of Umasvati's Bhasya on the Tattvarthasutra. Siddhasenaganin seems to have summarized the contents of the Dhyanasataka already referred to. 1 He further quotes a number of verses which excellently reveal the function of the dharma-dhyana in leading the soul to higher spiritual stages. When an individual strives to rise higher than the seventh stage, he collects his thought and concentrates it on the self and withdraws his senses and the mind from the worldly things. He aims at final emancipation, and begins to practise the dharma-dhyana in order to destroy the deluding karmans. He has the requisite mental strength on account of his robust physical structure. He meditates upon the four objects and rises up. Next we come to the Jnanarnava of Subhacandra and the Yogasastra of Hemacandra. Subhacandra prescribes the practice of fourfold virtues of maitri (friendship with all creatures), pramoda (appreciation of the merits of others), karuna (compassion and sympathy), and madhyasthya (indifference for the unruly) as the prerequisite condition of dharmaahyana. The slumber of delusion disappears and the quiescence of ecstasy (yoga) sets in, and finally the truth reveals itself, when one has perfectly practised these virtues.* As regards the selection of a proper place, it is held that one should be very careful about it, and avoid the bad places. Concentration of mind should be practised in the holy places that have been purified by great saints. Or one may select a beautiful place that is peaceful and soothing. A number of postures (asana) is also prescribed. One should select such posture as is the most suitable one for one's concentration. The most important condition of success in concentration however is the robust structure of the body, and the requisite purification of the soul. One can attain the highest state of concentration in any posture provided 1 See Tika on TSuBh, IX. 38 (pp. 271-2). 2 tasmad atha 'pramatta-sthanat sa visodhim uttamam prapya 6 jneyam akhilam vividisann adhitisthasams ca moksavidhim akhilam sandhaya smrtim atmani kincid upavartya drstim svam. visayebhya indriyani pratyavahrtya ca manas tatha tebhyah dharayati manah svatmani yogam pranidhaya moksaya. dhyanam tatah sa dharmyam bhiksur vicinoti moha-nasaya uttama-samhanana-balah ksapaka-srenim upayiyasan.-Ibid., pp. 272-3. 3 Jnanarnava, XXVII, 4-15. 4 yoganidra sthitim dhatte mohanidra 'pasarpati asu samyak pranitasu syan munes tattva-niscayah.-Ibid., XXVII. 18. 5 Ibid., XXVII. 22-34. 6 Ibid., XXVIII. 1-11. Page #323 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 286 JAINA YOGA [CH. one has the requisite strength, physical, moral, and spiritual.' There is no special time prescribed for concentration. One can practise it at any time provided one's mind is cool and collected. According to Subhacandra, only one who is in the seventh stage of spiritual development is properly qualified for such concentration. One in the sixth stage is only secondarily qualified for it. The person fully qualified for such concentration must be free from spiritual inertia (apramatta), should possess well-proportioned body (susamsthana), and must have strong physical structure (vajrakaya). He must have full control over the senses and steadfastness. He should be wellversed in the scriptures, self-controlled, and perfectly patient.* Subhacandra says that the scriptures recognize the capability for this dharma-dhyana even in those who are deficient in scriptural knowledge and belong to the lower stages. He also mentions the view that all the stages beginning from the fourth upto the seventh are suitable for this dhyana.. Subhacandra seems to compromise this difference of views by accepting gradation among the persons qualified for such dhyana. We have noticed above the two mutually opposed views regarding the persons qualified for the dharnia-dhyana. Subhacandra also is conscious of this opposition and attempts at a happy compromise which is very much appealing. As regards the yogic postures, Subhacandra says that the conquest of posture (asanajaya) helps the practitioner in keeping steadfast even in the face of adventitious obstacles. He draws a very beautiful picture of a yogin engrossed in self-concentration. The yogin in self-concentration dives deep into the ocean of sympathy and love for all creatures and is absolutely free from attachment to the world. He keeps his body straight and erect and becomes as motionless as a painted figure. His mind is purified by the waves of the ocean of enlightenment. Subhacandra admits the necessity of the various processes of breath-control (pranayama) as well for the development of the power of concentra I Cf. vajrakaya mahasattva niskampah susthirasanah sarvavasthasv alam dhyatva gatah prag yoginah sivam. --Ibid., XXVIII. 13. ? Cf. mukhyopacarabhedena dvau muni svaminau matau apramattapramattakhyau dharmasyai 'tau yathayatham. -Ibid., XXVIII. 25. 3 This is possible only in the seventh stage of spiritual development. 4 CJ. a pramattah susamsthano vajrakayo vasi sthirah purvavit sarnvrto dhiro dhyata sampurna-laksanah.-Ibid., XXVIII. 26. 5 Ibid., verse 27. lbid., verse 28. ? ketasana-jayo yogi khedito 'pi na khidyate. Ibid., XXVIII. 32. 8 Ibid., XXVIII. 34-40. Page #324 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ v. II] DOCTRINE OF DHYANA: DHARMADHYANA 287 tion.1 He also prescribes the withdrawal (pratyahara) of the mind along with the sense-organs from the external objects, and its concentration (dharana) on some place of the body, for instance, the forehead (lalata). Such process is held to be more useful than the regulation of breath which sometimes leads to unnecessary pain and uneasiness. Moreover the processes of breath-control lead to the acquisition of various supernormal powers which are detrimental to the spiritual well-being." The most important factor that inspires one for self-concentration and self-realization is the consciousness that the difference between the empirical self and the transcendental self is only one of non-manifestation and manifestation, both being intrinsically possessed of the same attributes which are unmanifest or less manifest in the empirical self, and fully manifest in the transcendental spirit. One must be conscious of one's latent powers before one can develop them. And when one has been sufficiently conscious of them one must be determined to realize them and exert to the utmost of one's capacity. When one becomes conscious of the eternal nescience that has stifled one's soul one must exert to overcome it and attain enlightenment, now and here. Only those who have such determination can practise the dharma-dhyana. Matter and spirit with the threefold nature consisting in continuity, origination and disappearance as well as the pure and perfect emancipated spirit, both embodied and disembodied, are held to be objects of this dhyana. The consummation is reached when the formless self, pure and perfect, is concentrated upon. yogin loses his identity and becomes one with the pure self when such concentration is achieved. This is the state of equality (samarasibhava) and unification (ekikarana) where the self merges into the transcendental self and becomes non-different from it." Subhacandra distinguishes three states of the soul viz. the exterior self, the interior self, and the transcendental self in the same way as we have already noticed. One should run away from the exterior self and concentrate upon the The 1 Ibid., XXIX (whole). 2 Subhacandra has enumerated ten such places.-Ibid., XXX. 13. 3 Cf. vayoh sancara-caturyam animadyangasadhanam prayah pratyuhabijam syan muner muktim abhipsatah. -Ibid., XXX. 6. 4 Cf. mama saktya gunagramo vyaktya ca paramesthinah etavan avayor bhedah sakti-vyakti-svabhavatah. -Ibid., XXXI. 10. 5Cf. maya 'dyai 'va vinisceyam svasvarupam hi vastutah chitva 'py anadi-sambhutam avidya-vairi-vaguram.-Ibid., XXXI. 15. 6 Cf. so 'yam samarasibhavas tadekikaranam smrtam aprthaktvena yatra 'tma liyate paramatmani.-Ibid., XXXI, 38. Page #325 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 288 JAINA YOGA [CH. transcendental self by means of the interior self. One can achieve the concentration on the transcendental self by the constant practice in the awareness of the truth of one's identity with it.? Such practices are, according to Subhacandra, common to both the dharma and the sukla-dhyana, there being difference only in the measure of their perfection. The concentration of thought on the revelation (ajna), suffering (apaya), karmic fruition (vipaka), and the structure (samsthana) of the universe is also accepted as dharma-dhyana. Subhacandra records furthermore the four types of dhyana viz. pindastha, padastha, rupastha and rupatita," which it has not been possible for me to trace anywhere in the Jaina works earlier than the Jnanarnava. Of course, we find these types elaborately treated in the Yogasastra of Hemacandra. But scholars think that the Yogasastra has borrowed these ideas from the Jnanarnava which is held to be decidedly an earlier work. In the pindastha, one is required to concentrate upon five imaginary objects in the following way. (1) One should imagine a vast ocean as big as the world inhabited by animal life (tiryagloka) with a thousand-petalled golden lotus as big as the Jambudvipa. He should then imagine himself comfortably seated on a white throne situated on the lotus. Then he should imagine himself as getting ready to destroy all the karmans. This is called parthivi dharana,6 (2) Then follows the agneyi dharana wherein he is required to imagine fire rising up from the mantric syllables in a lotus situated in the navel and burning the eight-petalled lotus situated in the heart, representing the eight karmans. Then he should imagine fire situated outside and burning the external body as well as the lotus situated in the navel. When all these are burnt to ashes the fire is automatically extinguished. (3) After this has taken place one is to imagine a devastating whirlwind which carries away all the ashes left by the fire. This is svasana dharana. (4) Then follows the varuni dharana wherein one is to imagine heavy rainfall which is to wash away all the remaining ashes of the consumed body. (5) Then follows the fifth dharana called tattvarupavati wherein the yogin imagines himself as devoid i Cf. apasya bahiratmanam susthirena 'ntaratmana dhyayed visuddham atyantam paramatmanam avyayam. -Ibid., XXXII. 10, 2 Cf. sa eva 'ham sa eva 'ham ity abhyasyann anaratam vasanam dradhayann eva prapnoty atmany avasthitim. -Ibid., XXXII. 42. 3 Cf. iti sadharanam dhyeyam dhyanayor dharma-suklayoh visuddhi-svami-bhedena bhedah sutre nirupitah.-Ibid., XXXII. 104. 4. Ibid., XXXIII- XXXVI. 5 Ibid., XXXVII-XL. 6 We give only a rough sketch in order to give some idea of these conceptions. Page #326 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ V. II] DOCTRINE OF DHYANA: DHARMA-DHYANA 289 of the seven elements, as possessed of a lustre as pure as the full moon, and as great as the omniscient.1 This is the nature of the pindastha dhyana. In the padastha, one is required to practise concentration with the help of mantric syllables.2 Subhacandra mentions a number of processes of such concentration with the help of mantras (incantation) and refers to many supernormal powers achieved by the practice of such processes. But we shall not deal with these in view of their lack of relevant interest. In the rupastha one is required to concentrate his mind on the omniscient arhats with all their glory and extraordinary powers, and thus seek inspiration for spiritual endeavour. In the rupatita one is to meditate upon the self as full of consciousness and bliss, pure and formless, supreme and infallible." Now we come to Acarya Hemacandra. Let us begin with Hemacandra's conception of yoga. Yoga, according to him, is the cause of final emancipation and consists in the threefold jewels of right knowledge, right attitude and right conduct. Hemacandra has discussed in detail the nature of right conduct.5 But then what is the ultimate nature of right knowledge, right attitude, and right conduct? Hemacandra says that it is the self of the ascetic that is right knowledge, right attitude and right conduct. They are nothing but the comprehension of the self in the self by the self on account of the disappearance of the eternal delusion. Emancipation is nothing but the conquest of the passions and the senses. One cannot conquer the passions unless one conquers the senses. And the conquest of senses is dependent upon the purification of mind. One should conquer the tendencies of attachment and hatred for the purification of the mind. And these tendencies can be conquered by equanimity (samatva). Equanimity however is possible only if one has completely given up the sense of mineness. And one should take resort to the 1 saptadhatu-vinirmuktam purnacandramalatvisam sarvajnakalpam atmanam tatah smarati samyami.-Ibid., XXXVII. 28. 2 Cf. padany alambya punyani yogibhir yad vidhiyate tat padastham matam dhyanam vicitra-naya-paragaih. -Ibid., XXXVIII. 1. 3 cidananda-mayam suddham amurtam paramaksaram smared yatra 'tmana "tmanam tad rupatitam isyate.-Ibid., XL. 16. 4 Cf. caturvarge 'granir mokso yogas tasya ca karanam jnana-sraddhana-caritra-rupari ratna-trayam ca sah. 5 Ibid., I-III. atmai 'va darsana-jnana-caritrany athava yateh.-Ibid., IV. I. 7 Cf. atmanam atmana vetti mohatyagad ya atmani tad eva tasya caritram taj jnanam tac ca darsanam.-Ibid., IV. 2. manahsuddhyai ca kartavyo raga-dvesa-vinirjayah.-Ibid., IV. 45. JP-37 -Yogasastra, I. 15. Page #327 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 290 JAINA YOGA [CH. twelvefold contemplation in order to conquer the sense of mineness.? One should practise dhyana after one has attained equanimity, because without equanimity one would try in vain to achieve concentration of mind (dhyana). Concentration of mind leads one to the knowledge of the self, and the knowledge of the self leads to the destruction of the karmans, which means emancipation. Hemacandra then classifies dhyana as dharmya and sukla. The four virtues of friendship (maitri), appreciation (pramoda), sympathy (karunya) and indifference (madhyasthya) are recognized as the sustainers of dharmya dhyana. Hemacandra also deals with the questions of the selection of proper place, postures, regulation of breath (pranayama),6 withdrawal (pratyahara) of the mind with the senses, and fixing (dharana)" of the mind on different places. In these matters he closely follows Subhacandra, and therefore we do not state his views because that would be only repetition of what we have already stated. Hemacandra also recognizes the types of pindastha, padastha, rupastha, and rupatita dhyana. The other particulars about the dharma-dhyana are as they are usually found elsewhere. Hemacandra states some facts about dhyana on the basis of his own experience. He distinguishes four kinds of mental states viz. scattered (viksipta), scattered-cum-collected (yatayata), collected (slista), and merged (sulina).' The scattered mind is ever restless. The scattered-cum-collected can sometimes concentrate itself and experience spiritual joy. The third kind is capable of greater concentration and spiritual joy. The mind reaches the fourth state when it becomes perfectly steady and enjoys supreme bliss. Hemacandra also recognizes three distinct selves viz. the exterior, the interior, and the transcendental, and prescribes the rejection of the exterior, and concentration upon the transcendental by the interior. 10 He insists upon the help and guidance of a competent guru (preceptor) for the revelation of truth. 11 He also insists upon the supreme importance of the practice of detachment and indifference. He discourages forcible withdrawal of the mind and the senses, but asks to control them by I Vide supra, p. 263. samyam syan nirmamatvena tatkrte bhavanah srayet.-Ibid., IV. 55. The bhavanas are also known as anupreksas (contemplations). 3 samatvam avalambya 'tha dhyanam yogi samasrayet vina samatvam arabdhe dhyane svatma vidambyate.-Ibid., IV. 112. 4 Cf. moksah karmaksayad eva sa ca 'tma-jnanato Whavet dhyanasadhyam matam tac ca tad dhyanam hitam atmanah. --Ibid., IV. 113. 5 Ibid., IV. 123-33. 6 lbid., V. 1-273. 7 Ibid., VI. 6-8. * Ibid., VII-X. Hemacandra uses the word sarirastha for pindastha, 9 Ibid., XII. 4. 10 Ibid., XII. 6. 11 Ibid., XII. 13-17. Page #328 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ V. 11] DOCTRINE OF DHYANA: SUKLA-DHYANA 291 means of the practice of indifference. When the soul ceases to impel the mind, the mind has no reason to impel the senses. And the senses being inactive, the worldly things lose all charm and fascination. Gradually the mind ceases to exist. With the cessation of the mind the truth reveals itself to the soul. (b) sukla-dhyana Forbearance, humility, straightforwardness, and freedom from greed are the conditions of the sukla-dhyana. In the dharmadhyana, the mind concentrates upon the general features of worldly existence. But in the sukla-dhyana, the mind gradually shortens its field of concentration. The mind now concentrates upon atom and becomes steady and motionless. And on the attainment of omniscience, the functions of mind are completely annihilated. Even as the poison that has spread all over the body is first brought back and collected at the point of bite by a mantra incantation) and then totally removed by a more powerful mantra, exactly so is the mind wandering all over the universe first concentrated on an atom by means of yoga, and finally its functions are destroyed by the omniscient soul.' The sukla-dhyana has four types. The function of the first two types is to collect and concentrate the mind on the minutest possible entity. When one has achieved perfection in this and has lost all attraction for the worldly things, one attains pure and perfect enlightenment. The functions of the mind are now no more there. There is now no more conceptual thinking. The function of dhyana at this stage is not the concentration of thought because there is now no thought. The soul is now omniscient. The dhyana is now utilized for the purpose of stopping the activities of the sense-organ of speech and the body. This is done by the last two types of the sukla-dhyana. The last type of sukla-dhyana is immediately followed by final emancipation. Let us now see the nature of the four types of sukla-dhyana. Conceptual thinking based on scriptural knowledge, technically called vitarka,' is the background of the first two types of sukla-dhyana. Accordingly both these types are savitarka.. In the first type, the mind concentrates upon the thought of the various modes such as origina 1 Cf. aha khamti-maddava-jjava-muttio jinamaya pahanao alambanaim jehim sukka-jjhanam samaruhai.--Dhyanasataka, 69; vide also SthSu, IV. 1. 247. 2 Dhyanasataka. 70. 3 Ibid., 71-72. 4 Ibid., 76. . Cf. Tsa, IX. 45 with Bhasya. 6 Cf. TSu, IX. 44. Page #329 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 292 JAINA YOGA [ch. tion, continuity and disappearance of a particular entity from a number of standpoints. In other words, the mind concentrates upon the aspect of difference (prthaktva) of the objects of conceptual thinking (vitarka). Moreover, in this type there is vicara, that is, movement from one aspect of the entity to another, from one verbal symbol to another as well as from one kind of activity to another. Accordingly this type is known as prthaktva-vitar ka-savicara.In the second type there is no vicara (movement). Nor does the mind concentrate upon the various aspects of an entity. The mind, in this type, concentrates upon a single mode (ekatva) of an entity. And hence this is known as ekatua-vitarka-' vicara. The third type of sukla-dhyana is known as suksma-kriya'nivartin* (accompanied with subtle physical movement and infallible). This dhyana, as we have already stated, is resorted to by the omniscient a few minutes before his final emancipation. In this dhyana all the activities, gross and subtle, of the mind and the senseorgan of speech as also the gross activities of the body are absolutely stopped. There are, however, present the subtle activities of the body such as the physiological processes. Moreover, this dhyana is infallible (anivartin) because one does not return to the previous state when this dhyana is over, but rises up to the last type which is immediately followed by emancipation. And hence this type of sukladhyana is known by the above term. In the last type of sukladhyana even the remaining subtle activities are stopped (vyavacchinna). And moreover there is no fall (pratipata) from it because it is immediately followed by final emancipation. Accordingly it is known as vyavacchinnakriya-'pratipatin.? In this dhyana the self becomes as motionless as a rock being devoid of all movements of mind, the sense organ of speech, and the body. This is the consummation of sukladhyana. The knowledge of the scriptures is an essential qualification of the first two types of sukladhyana. One must have, moreover, a good physical structure (samhanana) and be at least in the seventh stage of spiritual development. The first two types are possible only upto the twelfth stage of spiritual development. In the thirteenth and the 1 TSu, IX. 46. Cf. also sankrantir arthad artham yad vyanjanad vyanjanam tatha yogac ca yogam ity esa vicara iti va matah.---Tika on TSuBh, IX. 43. 2 Dhyanasataka, 77-78; SthSu, IV. J. 247. 3 Dhyanasataka, 79-80. 4 It is also called suksmakriya- pratipatin. See TSu, IX. 42. 5 Vide supra, p. 279. 6 Dhyanasataka, 81. ? It is also known as vyuparata kriya-'nivartin.-TSu, IX. 42. 8 Dhyanasataka, 82. Page #330 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ V. III] HARIBHADRA'S STUDIES IN YOGA 293 fourteenth stages, only the last two types are possible. The time when the omniscient soul takes resort to these dhyanas, and their purpose and necessity, we have already stated. The first two types of sukladhyana are followed by the contemplation (anupreksa) of these four objects: (1) suffering and its conditions, (2) the evil nature of worldly existence, (3) the endless continuity of the world, and (4) the impermanence of all things.2 Freedom from fear, freedom from delusion, discrimination, and absolute renunciation and detachment are the characteristic signs of the sukladhyana. Akalanka's Tattvartha-rajavarttika, Vidyanandi's Tattvarthaslokavarttika, Subhacandra's Jnanarnava" and Acarya Hemacandra's Yogasastra give elaborate description of sukladhyana. But there is no essential deviation from the old scheme, and so we do not advert to these works as this will involve reduplication. III HARIBHADRA'S COMPARATIVE STUDIES IN YOGA Haribhadra made a very valuable contribution to the comparative study of yoga. He composed a number of works on the subject. His Yogabindu and Yogadrstisamuccaya are very valuable works. The Yogavimsika and the Sodasakas also deserve notice. We are dealing with these works in a separate section in view of their supreme importance and unique character in the Jaina literature on yoga. We have already stated that Upadhyaya Yasovijaya revived the studies of Haribhadra. We shall therefore advert to his works as well for the sake of better understanding of Haribhadra's works. We shall begin with the Yogavimsika and the Sodasakas, and then come to the Yogabindu and the Yogadystisamuccaya. We shall refer, where necessary, to the other works of Haribhadra as well. All spiritual and religious activities that lead towards final emancipation are considered by Haribhadra as yoga. But special importance should be attached, he says in his Yogavimsika, to these five kinds of activities: (1) practice of proper posture (sthana), (2) correct utterance of sound (urna), (3) proper understanding of the meaning (artha), (4) concentration on the image of a tirthankara in his full glory (alambana), and (5) concentration on his abstract attributes (analambana). Of these five, the first two constitute external spiritual 1 Ibid., 64 ; TSu, IX. 40-41. 2 Dhyanasataka, 88. See also SthSu, IV. I. 247. 3 Dhyanasataka, 90-92. See also SthSa, IV. I. 247. 4 Prakarana, XLII. 5 Prakasa, XI. Page #331 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 294 JAINA YOGA (CH. activity (karmayoga) and the last three internal spiritual activity (jnanayoga). These activities can be properly practised only by those individuals who have attained to the fifth or a still higher stage of spiritual development (gunasthana). One reaches the consummation of these activities in the following order. At the outset one develops an interest in these activities, and comes to have a will (iccha) for practising them. Then he takes an active part in them, and begins actual practice (pravrtti). Gradually he becomes steadfast in them and achieves stability (sthairya). Finally he gains mastery (siddhi) over the activities. Each of the five activities is mastered in this order. First of all one is to master the posture (sthana), then correct utterance (urna), then the meaning (artha). After that one should practise concentration upon an image (alambana), and finally one should attempt at mastery over the concentration upon the abstract attributes of an emancipated soul. This is a full course of yogic practice. One may practise these spiritual activities either out of love (priti), or reverence (bhakti), or as an obligatory duty prescribed by scriptures (agama or vacana), or without any consideration (asanga).3 When a spiritual activity is done out of love or reverence it leads to worldly and other-worldly prosperity (abhyudaya). And when it is done as a duty or without any consideration whatsoever it leads to final emancipation. Of the fivefold activities mentioned above, the last two viz. concentration of the mind upon the image of a tirthankara, or upon the abstract attributes of him are the most important. We shall therefore deal with them in some detail. When one has practised posture (sthana), correct utterance (urna), and the correct understanding of the meaning, one is qualified for concentration (dhyana). The beginner is to practise concentration on an image of a tirthankara in his full glory and splendour. When one has perfected this practice and has achieved steadfastness, one begins the practice of concentration on the abstract attributes of a tirthankara. This concentration is known as analambana inasmuch as its object is not a concrete entity perceptible by a sense-organ." The soul at this stage concentrates upon the abstract attributes which are not the objects of empirical perception. By this time the soul has reached the seventh stage of spiritual development (gunasthana). The concentration is however only in its primary stage even in the seventh gunasthana. 1 YV, 1-2 ; SP, XII. 4 ; for salambana and niralambana yoga see $P, XIV. I. 2 YV, 4. 3YV, 18; SP, X. 1. 4 SP, X. 9. 5 The word analambana does not mean 'devoid of any alambana (object)'. but only 'devoid of a concrete alambana'. The prefix a(n) here means 'abstract' or 'subtle' (suksma). Cf. suksmo 'tindriyavisayatvad analambano nama yogah. -Yasovijaya's Tika on YV, 19; also of. $P, XIV. 1. Page #332 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ V. III HARIBHADRA'S STUDIES IN YOGA 295 The soul develops an irresistible urge for the realization of the transcendental self and reaches the eighth stage of spiritual development on the ladder of annihilation (ksapakasreni). The concentration becomes more steadfast at this stage. The soul has now achieved full detachment from the world, and earnestly proceeds onwards to the realization of the truth. It now does not rest until it has reached the consummation. The soul is then in the ninth gunasthana and is pressing forward to the twelfth on the ladder of annihilation. It has now revealed its full capacity (samarthyayoga)' for spiritual development and is bound to reach the twelfth stage and attain the knowledge of the transcendental self. In this state the soul attains concentration on the abstract attributes. Of course, it has not realized those attributes. But it has an ardent spiritual urge for the realization of them. This is analambana yoga. The soul is detached from the world and is on the verge of realizing the self. It has not yet realized the self, but is only striving for it. And so it is not concentrated on any object whatsoever at this stage. This is the reason why the concentration is without any object." The soul is here compared with an archer, the ladder of annihilation with bow, the realization of the self with the target and the concentration with the arrow. The analambana yoga lasts until the arrow is shot. The arrow is sure to pierce the target. The soul immediately attains realization of the self as the consummation of the concentration. The soul, as we have stated, concentrates upon the abstract formless (arupin) attributes of the transcendental self in the analambana dhyana. The distinction therefore between the salambana and the analambana yoga is this that in the former one concentrates upon an object having form (rupin) while in the latter on a formless object (arupin)." Yasovijaya, following Haribhadra, says that this analambana yoga is known as samprajnata samadhi in another (that is, Patanjali's) system. The consummation of this analambana concentration is omniscience which, according to Yasovijaya, is the state of asamprajnata samadhi of Patanjali's system. The functions of the mind and the sense-organs cease when omniscience is achieved, and so there is annihilation of all the transformations of the mind It is a technical term for the meaning whereof vide infra, p. 300. 2 Cf. samarthyayogato ya tatra didrkse 'ty asangasaktyadhya. sa 'nalambanayogah proktas taddarsanam yavat.-SP, XV. 8. 3 Cf. tatrapratisthito 'yam yatah pravsttas ca tattvatas tatra ............... tena 'nalambano gitah.-$P, XV. 9. 4 Cf. drag asmat taddarsanam isupata-jnata-matrato jneyam etac ca kevalam taj jnanam yat tat param jyotih. ---SP, XV. 10. - Cf. rupi-dravyavisayam dhyanam salambanam arupivisayam ca niralambanam iti-Yasovijaya's Tika on YV, 19. 6 esa eva samprajnatah samadhis tirthantariyair giyate--Ibid., YV, 20. Page #333 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 296 JAINA YOGA [CH. (asesavyttinirodha). And so it is not improper to compare the state of omniscience with the asamprajnata samadhi of the Sankhya-Yoga.1 There is however another higher stage of this samadhi. The soul attains that stage in the fourteenth gunasthanao where, as we have already stated, all the activities, gross and subtle, are totally stopped. The soul is now devoid of all vibrations caused by its association with matter. It has now annihilated all the residual karmans and immediately attains final emancipation. This stage of concentration, says Yasovijaya, corresponds to the dharmamegha of Patanjali's system, to amytatman of yet another system, to bhavasatru of a third system, to sivodaya of yet another, to sattvananda of yet others, and to para of a still another school." The above study is mainly based on the Yogavirsika. Now we come to the Sodasakas. There are some primary defects of the mind which are to be removed before practising the yogic processes. The minds of the common people (pythagjanacitta) are vitiated by these defects. Haribhadra enumerates them as eight viz. inertia (kheda), anxiety (udvega), unsteadiness (ksepa), distraction (utthana), lapse of memory (bhranti), attraction for something else (anyamud), mental disturbance (ruk), and attachment (asanga).* The mind of a yogin should always be free from these defects. It should be calm and quiet (santa), noble and great (udatta). It should be free from all impurities and intent on the well-being of others (pararthaniyata)." Such minds are capable of concentration of the highest order, and are known as pravsttacakra (engaged in yogic practices day and night). Gradually by practising the concentration of mind the soul realizes itself. This self-realization is known as 'supreme bliss' (paramananda) and freedom from nescience in the Vedanta) ; it is known as freedom from the specific qualities in the Nyaya-Vaisesika system); it is the extinguished lamp (vidhmaladipa) of the Buddhists; it is extinction of animality (pasutvavigama), end of suffering (duhkhanta), and detachment from the elements (bhutavigama).? Haribhadra thus tries to show the unanimity of the conceptions of final self-realization of all the systems of thought. He then asks the enquirers to keep their 1 Cf. kevalajnane 'sesavrttyadi-nirodhal labchatma-svabhavasya manasavijnana-vaikalyad asamprajnatatvasiddhih-Ibid. 2 ayam ca 'samprajnata-samadhir dvidha---sayogikevalibhavi ayogikevalibhavi ca. adyo manovittinan vikalpajnanarupanam atyantocchedat sampadyate, antyas ca parispandarupanam-Ibid. 3 ayam ca dharmamegha iti Patanjalair giyate, amatatme 'ty anyair bhavasatrur ity aparaih, sivodaya ity anyaih, sattvananda ity ekaih, paras ce 'ty aparaih-Ibid. See YBi, 422. 4 SP, XIV. 2-3. 5 SP, XIV. 12. 6 For the technical meaning of the term see YDS, 210. ? SP, XVI. 1-4. Page #334 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ V. III] minds open and investigate the truth with perfect detachment and freedom from prejudices. For this purpose he enumerates eight virtues which are necessary for the pursuit of truth. They are: freedom from prejudice (advesa), inquisitiveness (jijnasa), love for listening (susrusa), attentive hearing (sravana), comprehension (bodha), critical evaluation (mimamsa), clear conviction (parisuddha pratipatti), and earnest practice (pravrtti) for self-realization.1 of Now we come to the Yogabindu. The object and purpose yoga is the realization of truth. And as there is no controversy about this object and purpose of yoga there should be none regarding the nature of yoga as well. The worldly existence is a fact accepted by all. And freedom from it is the summum bonum of every spiritual system. The problem before us is only the means to that end. Haribhadra says that the same principle is expressed by different terms in different systems. Thus the selfsame principle of consciousness is known as purusa in the Vedanta as well as the Jaina system, as ksetravit in the Sankhya system, as jnana in the Buddhist school. Similarly the fundamental ground of worldly existence is known as avidya in the Vedanta and the Buddhist system, prakrti in the Sankhya school, and karman in the Jaina system. Moreover, the relation between matter and spirit is known as bhranti in the Vedanta and the Buddhist system, pravrtti in the Sankhya school, and bandha in the Jaina system. There is thus fundamental unity among all the apparently conflicting systems of thought. There ought to be no real controversy among them about the fundamental things. Truth is truth. It is our different ways of looking at it that is responsible for the building up of different systems. Haribhadra does not attempt at cheap and superfluous compromise, but only tries to show the fundamental unity of all thought. Every earnest student of philosophy has his own way of looking at the truth. And the result is the origination of different systems. Haribhadra asks us to see unity in difference. At least for a spiritual aspirant it is necessary to avoid controversy and strive for self-realization. About the path of selfrealization there is absolutely no controversy among the otherwise mutually conflicting systems. Haribhadra lays down these five steps as a complete course of yoga: adhyatma or contemplation of truth accompanied by moral conduct, bhavana or repeated practice in the contemplation accompanied by the steadfastness of the mind, dhyana or concentration of the mind, samata or equanimity, and vrttisamksaya or the annihilation of all the traces of karman.4 But one is not capable 1 SP, XVI. 14. 2 Cf. moksahetur yato yogo bhidyate na tatah kvacit sadhyabhedat tathabhave tu 'ktibhedo na karanam.-YBi, 3. 3 YBi, 17-18 with Svopajnavrtti. 4 YBi, 31. JP-38 HARIBHADRA'S STUDIES IN YOGA 297 Page #335 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 298 JAINA YOGA [CH. of this yoga until and unless one has worked out the requisite purification of the self. The soul, as we have already stated, naturally moves towards emancipation. It is because of this inherent capacity that the soul comes face to face with the knot and cuts it asunder. We have stated the process of cutting the knot. The worldly existence of a soul falls into two periods viz. dark (krsna), and white (sukla). The soul in the period preceding the cutting of the knot is known as belonging to the dark period (krsnapaksika), and it is known as belonging to the white period (suklapaksika) when it has cut asunder the knot. The duration of the white period is much shorter in comparison with that of the dark period. Only a soul belonging to the white period and following the moral conduct is capable of the first stage called adhyatma.? From the viewpoint of the stages of spiritual development, only the souls in the fifth or some higher stage are capable of it. But the problem is why should a soul cross into the white period at all? Or, why should not all the souls do so? Haribhadra says that it is all due to the inherent nature of things. He also refers to the view of an exponent of the Sankhya system, named Gopendra, which holds that the purusa, the principle of consciousness, does not even enquire about the path of realization unless and until the prakrti has turned her face from him. It is the nature of the spirit to get disentangled from matter. But this disentanglement is possible only when its conditions are fulfilled. However pious and virtuous and spiritually advanced one may appear to be, one is not capable of yoga unless one has cut the knot and attained the requisite purification of the soul. After such state has been achieved the soul is fit for the preliminary preparation (purvaseva) for yoga. This preliminary preparation consists in the worship of the preceptor and the like, good conduct, austerity, and absence of hatred for the final emancipation." The soul now attains right attitude and becomes a bodhisattva. All the characteristics of a bodhisattva are present in such soul. Thus the soul henceforth does no more fall to the depth wherein heretofore it had been. A bodhisattva does not commit an evil act from the depth of his heart, but if he does so at all he does only physically. There is no more spiritual degeneration. The soul which has cut the 1 The length of the white period is only less than even one pudgalaparavarta while the length of the dark period covers an infinite number of such pudgalaparavartas. A pudgalaparavarta is the time required by a soul to absorb as karman at least once all the atoms of the universe and release them after they have come to fruition. 2 Y Bi, 72. 3 Cf. YBi, 77 4 Ibid., 100-IOI. 5 purvaseva tu tantrajnair gurudevadipujanam sadacaras tapo muktyadvesas ce 'ha prakirtita.---Y Bi, 109. 6 Y Bi, 270. 7 Cf. ibid., 271, Page #336 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ v. 111) HARIBHADRA'S STUDIES IN YOGA 299 knot fulfils this characteristic. It now takes interest exclusively in the well-being of others, acquires wisdom, treads upon the right path, becomes noble, and appreciates merits. It has now attained enlightenment (bodhi). But if the conception of a bodhisaitva is narrowed down and made to include only those rare souls who are destined to redeem the world from sin and suffering, Haribhadra says that the Jaina conception of a tirthaikara fulfils that ideal. There are some souls who are naturally inclined towards universal well-being and are destined to be tirthankaras (founders of religion). Such souls are bodhisattvas in the true sense of the term. In this connection Haribhadra distinguishes three categories of souls destined to be emancipated. The first category comprises such souls who, as soon as they experience the first dawn of enlightenment on the annihilation of the knot, make determination to redeem the world from its suffering by means of the enlightenment and work strenuously in accordance with the determination. These souls are destined to become tirthankaras. The second category comprises those souls who are intent upon the well-being of only a limited circle of relatives by means of the enlightenment. These souls become ganadharas (literally the possessors of the gana 'group' of virtues of transcendent intuition, knowledge and the like), that is, the chief disciples of the tirthankaras.* The third category comprises those souls who strive for the well-being of themselves with little care for others. These souls are destined to become ordinary (munda) kevalins. Let us revert to the topic of preliminary preparation for yoga. After this preparation the soul becomes fit for the first stage of yoga called adhyatma. The soul now observes the five vows and meditates upon the truth. It now cultivates universal friendship, appreciates merits of others, develops sympathy for the suffering, and remains indifferent to the wicked. By these practices the soul overcomes the karmans, reveals its spiritual energy, improves its power of self-concentration, and becomes wise. It then becomes fit for the second stage called bhavana. This stage is the consummation of the first. The soul now maintains steady progress. Its power of concentration increases. It now desists from bad habits and develops good ones. The third stage is dhyana. We have already described it. Then we come to the fourth stage of equanimity (samata). Here the soul makes correct estimate of the nature and value of things, and consequently loses attachment for them. The soul is now disillusioned and does iCf. ibid., 272. 4 Ibid., 289. 7 lbid., 360-1. 2 Ibid., 274. * Ibid., 290. 3 Ibid., 284-8. 6 Ibid., 358-59. Page #337 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 300 JAINA YOGA [CH. not attach any importance to the supernormal powers that it might have acquired by means of the yoga. Then it reaches the fifth stage called annihilation of the residual karmans (urttisamksaya). It now gradually destroys the accumulated karmans once for ever. On the annihilation of the obscuring (ghatin) karmans, the soul attains omniscience. Then in due time it attains final emancipation. This is in brief the plan of the Yogabindu.? Next we come to Haribhadra's famous work Yogaarstisamuccaya. The author here distinguishes eight stages of yogic development. The work records a quite novel plan of classification of yogic stages. The most important feature of spiritual development is acquisition of samyagdrsti (love of truth). The soul undergoes gradual purification and along with the purification its drsti (love of truth) becomes progressively steady and reaches consummation in the realization of the truth. This gradual development of the drsti has been classified into eight stages viz. mitra, tara, bala dipra, sthira, kanta, prabha, and para. Before coming to the description of these drstis we shall refer in brief to the threefold yoga with the description of which the Yogadystisamuccaya opens. A qualified yogic practitioner passes through a number of stages before he reaches the consummation of the practice. Sometimes even in spite of his knowledge and will he falters in his practice on account of spiritual inertia (pramada). This faltering practice is call icchayoga. The practice of one who has revealed spiritual energy and does never falter in his yogic practices, strictly follows the scriptural injunctions, and has developed penetrating insight is called sasirayoga." The practice of one who has fully mastered the scriptural injunctions and has developed the power to transcend them is called smarthyayoga.6 This latter yoga, again, is of two kinds viz. (I) that which is accompanied by the dissociation of all the acquired virtues (dharmasarnyasa), and (2) that which effects the stoppage of all activity (yogasarnyasa). The first kind occurs at the time when the soul undergoes the process of apurvakarana for the second time in the ninth stage of spiritual development while the second occurs in the last stage of spiritual development immediately after which the soul attains final emancipation. These viz. icchayoga, sastrayoga, and samarthyayoga are the three broad divisions of all the possible stages of yoga. The 1 lbid., 364-5. 2 Ibid., 366-7 3 Upadhyaya Yasovijaya has followed this plan in his Duatrirsikas No. 12 to 18 as contained in the Ovatrivsad-dvatrimsika published by Sri JainaDharma-prasaraka Sabha, Bhawnagar. 4 YDS, 3 5 Ibid., 4 6 Ibid., 5 7 Ibid., 9. 8 Ibid., 10. Page #338 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ V. III] HARIBHADRA'S STUDIES IN YOGA 301 eight drstis which we shall now describe are only the elaboration of these three.' Drsti means attitude towards truth. This attitude is wrong and perverse so long as the soul has not cut the knot and attained purification. The perverse attitude is known, as we have stated on more than one occasion, as darsanamoha or mithyatva or avidya. The attitude of the soul which has not cut the knot is known as oghadrsti (literally commonplace attitude). The opposite of this is yogadysti or the attitude of the spiritually advanced soul. It is also known as saddrsti, that is, right attitude. The oghadrsti is held to be responsible for the origination of the mutualiy conflicting systems of thought. The eight dystis that we have enumerated above are yogadrstis and not oghadrstis. Of course, of these eight the first four belong to those who have not cut the knot. But even then they are not oghadystis in view of the fact that they are destined to lead to the yogadystis. It is only those souls who are destined to cut the knot and attain final emancipation that are capable of these dystis. The eight dystis have respectively been compared to the sparks of straw-fire (trnagni), cow-dung fire, wood fire, the light of a lamp, the lustre of a gem, the light of a star, the light of the sun, and the light of the moon. The first four drstis are unsteady and fallible. . The last four are steady and infallible. The eight drstis respectively correspond to the eight famous stages of yoga viz. vows (yama), self-control (niyama), posture (asana), regulation of breath (pranayama), withdrawal of the senses (pratyahara), fixing of the mind (dharana), concentration (dhyana), and samadhi (ecstasy), as found in the system of Patanjali. They are respectively free from inertia (kheda), anxiety (udvega), unsteadiness (ksepa), distraction (utthana), lapse of memory (bhranti), attraction for something else (anyamud), mental disturbance (ruk), and attachment (asanga). They are respectively accompanied with freedom from prejudice (advesa), inquisitiveness (jijnasa), love for listening (susrusa), attentive hearing (sravana), comprehension (bodha), critical evaluation (mimarsa), clear conviction (parisuddha pratipatti), and earnest practice (pravrtti)." This is about the general features of the drstis. Now let us state in brief the specific characteristics of them one by one, In the first dysti called mitra the soul achieves very faint and indistinct enlightenment. It here accumulates the seeds of yoga 1 Ibid., 12. 2 Ibid., 14 with Svopajnavrtti: .... etannibandhano 'yam darsanabheda ici yogacaryah, 3 Ibid., 15. 4 Ibid., 19. 5 Ibid., 16 with Svopajnavrtti. Haribhadra here refers to the concensus of opinion of a number of authors regarding the stages of yoga. Page #339 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 302 JAINA YOGA [CH. (yogabija) which eventually fructify into emancipation. The soul is now attracted towards the founders of religion and worships them with reverence. It now earnestly and sincerely does the service of his preceptors and other sincere ascetics. The soul now develops fear for worldly existence. It now performs great and noble deeds. It develops sympathy for the suffering multitude. The soul is now free from the envy of the meritorious. It now gets good opportunities for spiritual development. The soul is now just in front of the knot (granthi) and is undergoing the process of yathapraurtta karana.? Now we come to the second drsti known as tara. The enlightenment becomes a bit distinct here, and the soul is capable of some sort of self-restraint as well. It now attains some sort of steadiness in spiritual activity, and becomes inquisitive about truth. It now develops steady love for the discussions in yoga and has respect for the yogins. The soul is now not so much desperate and does not indulge in evil activities so frequently. It now aspires for spiritual progress and is conscious of its shortcomings. The soul is now earnestly anxious to get rid of the worldly existence. Next we come to the drsti called bala. Here the enlightenment becomes more distinct. There is now strong desire for hearing the truth. The evil desire automatically disappears at this stage and the soul gains control over posture. In the fourth dysti called dipra one gets control over breath and is free from the lapse of yoga. One has now heard about the truth but has not developed the power of understanding its subtlety. The individual at this stage regards his religion dearer than his life and is always ready to give up his life in order to save his religion." Real spiritual progress however has not yet set in. The truth has not dawned as yet. The soul is only trying to capture the image of the truth instead of the truth itself. The knowable has not yet been known. The above four drstis thus are 'not attended with the knowledge of the truth' (avedyasamvedyapada). It is only the next four drstis that are attended with the knowledge of the truth' (vedyasamvedyapada). The avedyasarvedyapada is to be transcended by means of the companionship of the virtuous and the study of the scriptures. One makes various conjectures about truth until one sees it face to face. This leads to a number of speculative systems based on fallacious logic (kutarka). Haribhadra, in conformity with our ancient tradition, asks us to realize the truth by means of all these three organs viz. the scripture, the logical argument, and the practice of yoga. One must utilize the store of knowledge inherited Ibid., 22. 2 Ibid., 22-40. 3 Ibid., 41-48. 4 lbid., 49-50. 5 Ibid., 57-58. ' Ibid., 67. ? Thid., 85. & Cf. ibid., 90-98. Page #340 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ V. III] HARIBHADRA'S STUDIES IN YOGA 303 from one's ancestors, one's own logical understanding, and the vision gained by spiritual discipline and culture for the ascertainment of truth.' The truth is one. It cannot be many. There is only the difference of terminology. The state of final realization is known as sadasiva in one system, as parabrahman in another, as siddhatman in the third, and as tathata in yet another system. There can be no controversy when the truth has been realized.4 If it is a fact that those who have revealed the truth had realized it, then there is no reason why there should be controversy among them. The various revelations therefore are to be understood in their relevant contexts. They can in no way be considered as false assertions. The enlightened souls have revealed the truth in accordance with the needs of the spiritual aspirants. The selfsame revelation appears as different to different persons. It is necessary to understand a revelation in its proper context. One should cultivate faith in spiritual revelations. This is most necessary for spiritual progress. This faith is wanting in all the four drstis described above. It is only when the soul has properly cultivated this faith that it cuts the knot (granthi) and comes to possess the fifth arsti known as sthira. The soul has now cut the knot. The enlightenment has now dawned. It is now infallible (nitya). The soul is now capable of subtle thinking and sinless conduct. It now looks upon the worldly things as the toys made of sand. The world now appears to be a worthless show.? Next we come to the sixth drsti known as kanta. Here the individual develops personality and attracts others. He is now engrossed in spiritual contemplation and has his mind firmly concentrated on the virtues. The world now loses all attraction for him.8 The seventh drsti is known as prabha. The soul has now developed the capacity for self-concentration and is free from all mental disturbances. It has now achieved peace of mind (sama). The soul has now fully developed the power of discrimination.' It now practises spiritual discipline without any ulterior motive (asanganusthana). It is now in the seventh stage of spiritual development and is preparing to rise up to the eighth stage on the ladder of annihilation. The soul is now marching on the great path (mahapathaprayana) which leads to the place from which one does never return (anagamipadavaha). Haribhadra remarks that this dysti is known as prasantavahita in the Sankhya system, as visabhaga-pariksaya in the Buddhist school, as sivavartman in the Saiva system, and as dhruvadhvan according to the Mahavratikas, 10 1 Ibid., 101. 2 Ibid., 127. 3 Ibid., 128. 4 Ibid., 130. * Ibid., 132-3 6 Ibid., 134. 7 Ibid., 152-4. 8 Ibid., 160-2. 9 Ibid., 168-9. 10 Ibid., 173-4. Page #341 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ JAINA YOGA [CH. We now come to the eighth drsti called para. The soul is now completely free from all attachment to the world. It now achieves ecstasy (samadhi), the consummation of dhyana. The activities of the soul in this stage are free from all transgressions of the vows, and as such are pure and perfect. The soul now dissociates itself from all the acquired virtues and has its purpose fulfilled.' This occurs in the ninth stage of spiritual development. The soul then gradually attains omniscience on the annihilation of all the obscuring karmans. Now the final emancipation is attained by means of the last yoga known as ayoga.2 304 Haribhadra distinguishes four types of yogins viz. gotrayogin, kulayogin, pravrttacakrayogin, and nispannayogin. The yogins of the first type are not capable of emancipation. The yogins of the fourth type have already achieved their objective and so do not need any instruction in yoga. It is only the yogins of the second and the third type that need instruction." 1 Ibid., 179. 2 Ibid., 184. supra, pp. 279-280. 3 Ibid., 206-7 with Svopajnavrtti. ibid., 208-210. Here ayoga refers to ayogakevali-gunasthana for which vide About the definitions of these types see Page #342 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Abhayadeva, 45, 46, 770, 79. Akalanka (Bhatta), 29, 33, 34, 36, 39, 43, 55, 59, 60, 62n, 67, 67, 68, 74, 78, 195, 284, 293. Asuri, 159. INDEX I AUTHORS MENTIONED1 Asvaghosa, 134, 134, 135, 136, 137, 202. Badarayana, 221. Bergson (H.), gn. Bhadrabahu, 30, 32, 35. Bhaskara, 171. Bhavaganesa, 95n. Bhutabali, 62n. Brahmadeva, 73. Buddhaghosa, 128n. Dasgupta (Dr S. N.), 127, 134, 137, 2620. Devendrasuri, 236, 238n. Dharmakirti, 201n, 203, 209, 251. Dignaga, 201n, 209, 251. Dutt (Dr N.), gn. Gaudapada (Sankhya), 93, 95. Gaudapada (Vedantin), 113, his conception of maya and avidya, 115121, 125. Gautama, 230. Gopendra, 298. Haribhadra, 22n, 49n, 5on, 78, 79, 790, 146n, 159, 160, 161, 224, 2620, 267, 268, his comparative studies in yoga 293-304. Hastimalla (Muni), 49n, 50n. Hemacandra (Acarya), 36, 39, 40, 44, criticism of Sankhya-Yoga 159, criticism of inherence 163, 164. 267, 268, 285, 288, conception of yoga 289-90, 293. Isvarakrsna, his view about mind 31, 90, 92, 93, threefold creation 93n, description of perfect knowledge and emancipation 100, 222. Jinabhadra, 27, 28, 29, 30, 35, 36, 37, 38, 39, defines iha 40, distinguishes samsaya from iha 41, 42, defines dharana 43: 44, 45, gives the psychology of solution of problems 47, defends the possibility of potential verbal knowledge even in one-sensed organisms 51, 53, 54, 540, 56, 57, 58, 66, 66n, 67, 67n, 68, supports the alternate occurrence of jnana and darsana of a kevalin 78, 79, 79n, 80, 148, 150, 267, 268, 281n, 284. Jinadasagani-Mahattara, 79. Kapila, 159, 161. Kashyap (Rev. Bhikkhu J.), 246n. Keith (A. B.), 4n. Kundakunda (Acarya), 34n, 48n, 72, 74, his view of simultaneous occur JP-39 rence of jnana and darsana of kevalin 75, 144, 145, 267, 268, 281. 52n, Maitreyanatha, his idea of the functions of avidya, samskara etc. 127, his argument for non-existence of artha and vijnana 130n, his conception of abhutaparikalpa 131-2. Malayagiri, defines instinct 52, distinguishes upayoga from pasyatta 71, 71, 72, 74, 79, 79n, 273n, 2760. Mallavadin, 79. Mathara, 92, 93, defines viparyaya 93n, 95. Monier Williams, 13n. Nagarjuna, origin of his dialectic 115, 116, function of avidya 127, 127, 137, on causality 174, 201, as nihilist 204, criticizes causality 212, criticizes empiricism 213, criticizes otherness 214. Nemicandra, 73. Pancasikha, 89, 97. Patanjali, xviii, xxii, 90, 92, implication of his definition of avidya 97-8, 259, 262n, 295, 296, 301. Prabhakara, his theory of error 98-100. Prasastapada, II, III, 222. Pujyapada Devanandi, 33, 36, defines avagraha 37, 39, defines iha 40, defines dharana 43, 55, twofold purpose of sruta 58-9, defines manahparyaya, 66-7, 68, 68n, 74, 75, twofold mithyadarsana 145, 149, 267, 268, 281, 284, 284n. Puspadanta, 72. Radhakrishnan (Sir S.), 6n. Ramanuja, 191. Rhys Davids (Mrs.), 126n. Samantabhadra, 74, 78, criticizes the view that ignorance alone is the cause of bondage 167, on mutual relation of physical austerity and spiritual detachment 2670. Sankara, vide Sankaracarya. Sankaracarya, his interpretation of Sat 4, includes mind under senseorgans 31, 113, his analysis of adhyasa, avidya and maya 121-6, 188, accords provisional place to Personal God 221. Siddhasena Divakara, 29, identity of mati and sruta 56, 60, 61, 61n, 69, identity of kevala-jnana and kevala-darsana 75-80, meaning of darsana 148-9. Siddhasenaganin, distinguishes three categories of matijnana 33, 36, 39, 1 The numbers indicate pages and n refers to footnote. Page #343 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 306 distinction between iha and samsaya 41, 66n, 75, 75n, 145, 148, 149, function of dharma-dhyana 285. Sivasarmasuri, 2350. Stcherbatsky, 201n. Sthiramati, explains abhutaparikalpa 131. INDEX II Subhacandra, 267, 268, distinguishes three categories of dhyana 283n, 285, 286, distinguishes three states of soul 287, 287n, records four types of dhyana 288-9, 290. Sukhlalji (Pandit), 79, 259n. Suresvara, on Absolute 187, nature of nescience 189-91, 196, 197, 198, 200, 201. Suzuki, 134. Tarkavagisa (MM. Phanibhusana), 153n. Uddyotakara, on nature of delusion 106, 169. Umasvati (Vacaka), 30, defines matijnana 32-3, 34, synonyms of avagraha 35, 36, synonyms of tha 40, synonyms of apaya 42, defines srutajnana 48, relation between mati and sruta 55, distinguishes two varieties of manahparyaya 66, 66n, 67, 68, 70, 75, two categories of mithyadarsana 145, mutual relation of right attitude, right knowledge and right conduct 147-8, 268, defines dharmadhyana 284, 285. Utpalacarya, xix. Vacaspati, 87, 89, 93, 94, 95, 97, 99, 36, 39. defines 224. Vadi-Devasuri, dharana 43. Varsaganya, 94. Vasubandhu, illustrates three charac fines vinnana Ion. Abhidharmakosa, 251. Abhisamayalankara, Abhidhamma Philosophy, 246n. Abhidhammatthasamgaha, 246n. Abhidhammatthavibhavini-tika, WORKS de conception of abhavya 266n. Acaranga Sutra, 18n, 19n, 200, 210, 50, 70, 70n. Agamas, 1, 71, 74, 75. Agamasastra, 113, 115, 116, 1170, 118, 119, 120n, 125, 125, 128, 1340. Anguttaranikaya, 70, 160. Anuyogadvara Sutra, 280, 29, 29n, 30, 48n. Anyayogavyavacchedika, Sankhya criticized 159n, Nyaya-Vaisesika criticized 1641. teristics of things 128-9, on origin of afflictions 131, 251. Vatsyayana, 31, explains moha IOI, defines delusion 103, 106, 1620, refutes possibility of unalloyed joy 164, impossibility of omniscience 166 & 169, 222. Vidyanandi, gives additional synonyms of mati 34, 36, regards avagraha as determinate 39, 43, 44, 68, 74, supports simultaneous occurrence of jnana and darsana 78, criticizes the position of the upholders of knowledge alone as the cause of emancipation 151-5, criticizes Sankhya 159, reinterprets Sankhya-Yoga 161, common defects of all absolutisms 202, 293. Vijnanabhiksu, 87, gives origin of knowledge 88, 93, differentiates between Yoga and Sankhya theories of error 95, 98, 100, has reduced one prakyti to plurality of atoms 157, 224. INDEX II Vindhyavasin, 159. Virasena (Acarya), jnana from darsana 72. Wenzel 127n. William Law, 18n. on Yasovijaya (Upadhyaya), 29, 36, on vyanjanavagraha 37, 39, vasana 44, 56, defends identity of mati and sruta 60-1, 77n, 79, 83n, 242n, compares Yoga conception of karman with the Jaina conception 259-60, 260n, 267, 293, 2940, compares analambana dhyana with samprajnata samadhi 295, pares fourteenth gunasthana with dharmamegha etc. 296, 300n. Yogindudeva, 281. com differentiates QUOTED Aptamimamsa, 78, 78n, criticizes the view that ignorance alone is the condition of bondage 167n, asserts moha as the condition of bondage 168n, criticizes absolutism 1780, 188n, 2030. Astasahasri, 78n, 171, 1720, 1770, 180n, 183, 184n, 186n, 1871, 188n, 1890, 1930, 194n, 1950, 2030, 2070, 208n, 1970, 2020, 2090, 2110, 227n. Astasati, 780. Avasyakaniryukti, 35, 35n, 40, 40n, 41, 42, 45, 45n, 46, 46n, 47, 47, 48, 48n, 49, 490, 53, 63n, 64, 64n, 65, 65, 66n, 68, 68n, 69, 7on, 74, 74, 75, 149, 15on. Avasyakatika, 52, 52n. Awakening of Faith, 1340, 13bn. Page #344 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ WORKS QUOTED 307 Basic Conception of Buddhism (The), 8n, Ion, 14n, 126n. Bhagavadgita, 31, 316, 92, 92n. Bhagavati Sutra, 22n, 239, 270, 29n, 51, 52n, 7on, 74n. Bhatta parinnaya, 145n. Bodhicaryavatarapanjika, 127, 128n, 134n. Bodhisattvabhumi, 8n. Brahmajala Sutta, 9. Brahmasutra, 153, 153n, 221, 221n. Brhadaranyaka-Bhasya-Varttika, 189, 189n, 193n, 194n. Byhadavanyaka Upanisad, 3, 40, 6, 6n, 113, 113, 116, 116, 117, 118n. Byhadvytti (Sisyahita, a commentary on ViBh), 35n, 38n, 44, 440, 46n, 5on, 5in, 52, 52n, 54n, 570, 650, 66, 66, 69n, 7on, 1490, 269n, 27on, 272n. Byhatsvayambhustotra, 267n. Bu-Ston, 266n. Carakasarhita, 31, 3in. Chandogya Upanisad, 3n, 114, 114n. Conception of Buddhist Nirvana (The), 2010, 202n. Creative Evolution, gn, 15n. Dasavaikalika-Niryukti, 30, 3on, Dhammapada, 17n. Dharmasavgrahani, 22n, 146, 227n. Dhavala, 72, 72n. Dhyanasataka, 281, 282n, 284n, 285, 291, 292n, 293n, Digha Nikaya, 141, 2in, 25n. Doctrine of Karman in Jaina Philo sophy (The). 253n. Dravyasamgraha, 73.-Vitti, 73, 73n. 74n. Dvatrirsad-dvatrinsika, 3oon. Early Monastic Buddhism, gn. Gautama the Buddha, 6n. Gominatasara, 227n. History of Indian Philosophy (A), 1 27n, 134n, 136n, 137n.. Indian Philosophy, 5n, 115, 12n. Isa Upanisad, 6, 113, 113, 114n. Tsvara pratyabhijna-karika, xix. Itivuttaka, 126n. Jaina Philosophy of Non-absolutism, 204n, 206n. Jaina-tarka-bhasa, 36, 371, 39, 39n, 44n. Tnanabindu paricaya (Introduction to JBP written in Hindi by Pandit Sukhlalii), 79. Jnanabinduprakarana, 46, 5on, 60, 6on. 68, 69, 77n, 79, 79n, son. Inanapravada, 27. Inanarnava28an, 285, 285, 286n, 2877, 288, 288n, 289n, 293. Jnanasarasamuccaya, 7n. Karmagrantha, First 530, Fourth 145 & 145n. Karmagrantha (Vol. I), 233n, 234n, 236n, 275n, 276, 2770, 28on, Karmagrantha (Vol. II), 235n, 236n, 237n, 238n, 239n, 240n, 2410, 242n, 243, 272n. Karmaprakyti, 253n, 255n, 256n, 257n, 258n, 259n, 27on, 272n. --Yasovijaya's Commentary, 242n. -Curni, 270n.-sika, 2733, 274n, 276n. Karma pravada, 27. Katha Upanisad, 6n, 113, 114, 114n. Kathavatthu, Atthakatha, 128n. Kena Upanisad, 4n. Labd hisara, 270n. Laghiyastraya, 34, 340, 39n, 43n, 59n.-Viurti 34n, 39, 43, 590. Lankavatana Sutra, I27n, I28n, I29n, 130, 13on, 131, 133, 133n, 134, 134, 137, 202, 202n. Loka prakasa, 28on. Madhyamakakarika, ton, 128n. - Vitti, 127n. Madhyantavibhagasutra, 127, 128n, 13on, 13in, 132n.-Bhasya, 127n. 13in. -Tika, 127, 131, 132n. Mahabandha, 62n. Mahabharata, 31, 91, 92. --santi parva, 3in, 9in, 92n, 93n. Mahavagga, 17n. Mahayanavimsika, 127n. Majjhima Nikaya, 8, 9, 14n. Matharavytti, 92n, 93n, 94n. Mili1zdapvaSna, 8n. . Moksaprabhyta, 281. Mundaka Upanisad, xxii, 6n, 114, 114n. Nandi Sutra, 28n, 30, 32, 35, 350, 36, 36, 37, 40, 4on, 42, 42n, 44, 45, 45n, 46, 49, 49, 5on, 51, 53, 53n, 55, 55n, 6in, 62n, 63, 64, 641, 68, 68n, 79, 147, 2410. --Curni, 79n. -Tika, 52n. -Vitti, 49, 5on, 52n, 79n. Niscavadvatrinsika, 56, 56n, 6on, 69n. Niyamasara, 72n, 75n. Nvaya kandali 112n. Nyayakumudacandra, 34n. Ny@yaparicaya, 153n. Nyaya Sutra, 31, 31, 32, IOI, Ion, 102, 104n, 106, 107, 107n, 162n. -Bhasya, 310, 32n. Ion, 102, 103, 106, 107n, 153n, 162n, 164n, 167n. --Vytti, IOIN. Padarthadharmasangraha, IIO. Pancasangraha, 252n, 2540, 2711. Pancastikayasara, 34n, 48n. Paramatmaprakasa, 281. Philosophical Essays, 262n. Pitakas, I. PrajabanSutra, 5in, 52n, 71, 7In, 72. 74, 740.---Tika, 710. Pramanamimarsa, 400, 44n. Pramananavatattvalokalankara, 4on. Pramanavarttika, 203n. Page #345 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 308 INDEX II Prameyakamalamartanda, 1640, 225n. Prasastapadabhasya, 110, 11on, III, 1120, 1640. Pratyabhijnahrdaya, 1410, 1420, 1430. Purvasruta, 27, 270. Rayapasenaiya Sutta, 27, 27n. Religion and Philosophy of the Veda and Upanisads (The), 4n. Rgveda, In, 2n, 4, 4n, 5, 5, 115. Salistambasutra, 127. Samadhitantra, 281, 282n. Samayaprabhrta, 144n. Samayasara, 145. Samosaranajjhayana, 24. Samyutta Nikaya, 131, 12bn. Sankara Bhasya, on BS, 31, 121, 121, 122, 124n, 125n, 126p.-on ChUp, 3n.-on TUp, 3n. Sankhyakarika, 31, 31n, 90, 92, 93, 93, 94, 94, 95, 97n, 101, 156n, 222. Sankhyapravacanabhasya, 85n, 96n. Sankhyasutra, 96, 99. Sanmatitarkaprakarana, 750, 76n, 77n, 78n, 79, 790, 148n, 220n. Sanskrit English Dictionary, 13n. Sarvarthasiddhi, 33, 330, 37, 37, 4on, 41, 41n, 43n, 58n, 59, 67n, 68n, 75, 145n, 149n, 283n, 284n. Sastravartasamuccaya, 1600, 161n, ion, lin, 120, 2200, 224. Satakakarmagrantha, 2351. Sataratnasangraha, 138n, 139n, 140p, 1410. Satkhandagama, 72, 72n. Siksasamuccaya, 127n. Sivadrsti, xix. Sodasaka-prakarana, 293, 2940, 295n, 296, 2960, 297n. Sraddhotpadasastra, 1341. Sthananga Sutra, 28n, 291, 44, 44n, 45, 45, 46, 48n, 62n, 66, 66n, 69n, 145, 283, 283n, 292n, 293n. Suhyllekha, 1270. Sutrakrtanga, 21n, 24, 24, 25, 25, 50, 1450. Svetasvatara Upanisad, 115, 1150, 220n. Syadvadamanjari, 164n. Syadvadaratnakara, 43n, 44, 164n. Taittiriya Upanisad, 3n, bn, 117. Tantraloka, 143, 144n. Tatparyatika (a commentary NBhV), 99. Tattvakaumudi, 93n, 94n. Tattvaprakasa, 138n, 1390. Tattvartharajavarttika, 340, 55n, 56n, 62, 63n, 67, 68n, 270, 284n, 293. Tattvarthaslokavarttika, 34, 34n, 39, 430, 83n, 1470, 152, 153, 1540, 155, 1590, 1611, 2270, 284n, 293. on Tattvarthasutra, 28n, 3on, 31n, 32. 320, 330, 35n, 38n, 44n, 48n, 62n, 630, 69n, 7on, 1470, 232, 2330. 236n, 2430, 2520, 263n, 2640, 2650, 266n, 268n, 2740, 2820, 284n, 292n. -Bhasya, 300, 33, 330, 35, 36, 36n, 39, 40, 41n, 42, 42n, 44n, 48n, 55n, 64, 66, 68, 69, 7on, 75n, 145, 147, 148n, 2340, 2350, 2360, 2520, 264n, 281, 285, 291n. -Tika. 330, 36n, 41n, 430, 69n, 74, 75, 145n, 2320, 2330, 234n, 2390, 2520, 2530, 2650, 28on, 281n, 2850, 2920. Tattvavaisaradi, 94n. Trimsika, 129, 1340. Tripurarahasya, xviii. Trisvabhavanirdesa, 129n. Upaskara, 109n. Uttaradhyayanasutra, 2711, 148, 149, 149n. Vaisesika Sutra, 31, 31, 32, 108, 108n, 109, 109n, 11on, III, III, 1640. Visesanavati, 78, 78n, 790. Visesavasyakabhasya, 270, 28, 30, 320, 35, 36n, 37, 37n, 38, 390, 4on, 41, 42, 43, 44, 45, 46n, 47, 48n, 51n, 52n, 53, 53, 54, 55, 56, 57, 58n, 59n, 62n, 63n, 64, 65, 66n, 69n, 7on, 78, 78n, 1470, 1480, 1500, 269n, 2700, 2720. Visnupurana, 94n. Visuddhimagga, 25n, 127, 128n. Vyomavati, 112. Yogabhasya, see Bhasya under Yoga darsana. Yogabindu, 293, 296n, 297 298n, 299n, 300, 300n. Svopajnavrtti, 2970. Yogadarsana, 31, 31n, 84, 85, 86n, 87n, 89n, 90, 92, 95, 97, 98, 98n, 152n, 246n, 262n. -Bhasya, 8n. 31, 31n, 84n, 85n, 86, 86n, 87n, 89, 89n, 90, 9on, 93, 93, 94, 95, 97, 97n, 98, 152n, 244n, 245n, 246n, 251n, 260n. -Dipika, 95n. Varttika, 94, 95n. Yasovijaya's commentary, 259, 260, 260n. Yogadrstisamuccaya, 293, 2960, 300, 300n, 302n, 303n. Svopajnavrtti, 83n, 301n, 304n. Yogasastra, 285, 288, 289n, 290n, 293. Yogasutra, see Yogadarsana. Yogavarttika, see Varttika under Yogadarsana. --- Yogavimsika, 262n, 293, 294n. Yasovijaya's Tika, 294n, 295n. 296n. Yuktidipika, 93, 93n, 222, 2220. Page #346 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ GENERAL SUBJECTS 309 INDEX III GENERAL SUBJECTS Absolute, 4, 6, doctrine of non-ori gination of 116, 119, 120, of Saivism 141, 170, 171, 172, 176, 178, 183, 185, 187, nature of the Absolute according to Suresvara 187, 188, 189, 190, 191, 192, 193, 194, 198, 217. Absolutism, 116, defects common to all absolutisms 202. Action, origin of good and bad 109, presupposes identification of self and not-self 123. Actionism, 24. Afflictions, 221, 222. Agnosticism, 14, 25 Agnostics, 24, 25, 145. Appearance, explanation of 120, meaning of 123. Art, purpose of 81. Asceticism, 7, 168, 221. Attitude, Brahmana 1, Buddhist 7, Jaina 17, non-absolutistic 29, perverted and right 80, right 146. function of the perversity of 147. purification of the 147, mutual relation of right attitude, right knowledge and right conduct 14751wrong 155, perverted 161, perverted 218-9, Jaina and Bud dhist 220. Becoming, its relation to being 24. Beginninglessness, of the world pro cess 82, of mithyatva 146, a fact universally admitted 227, 269. Being, 3, its relation to becoming 24. pure being is an abstraction 199, 201, impossibility of pure being 214 Bhisma, 91, 92. Birth, meaning of 102, is only an illusion 116, 126. Body-making karman, 233, sub-types of 234, maximum and minimum durations of 236. Bondage, 18, 20, 99, objects become a source of bondage when they are invested with false values 104. conditions of 151, nature of 151, Jaina conception of the threefoldi cause of 155, conditions of 239. Buddha, rationalistic attitude of 7. his attitude towards metaphysics 14. ethical attitude of 15, his teaching 17, his hesitation to preach the Law 17, neither a sceptic nor an agnostic nor a materialist 25, avyakyta attitude of 26, 230. Buddhism, 222, Pali or Southern 251. Carvaka, 220, 223. Causality, the doctrine of 115, 120, an irrational principle 174, denial of causality constitutes a flagrant violation of experience 176, law of 206, determinant of 206, is as inexplicable in the theory of flux as it is in the theory of eternally unchanging cause 207. Nagarjuna's criticism of 212. Cause, problem of its relation with effect 174, problem of mutual relation of effect and cause 175, permanent cause is an impossibility 205. Change, 15, according to Mahayira 18, 165, 166, 170, 201. Cognition, sensuous 30, direct 32, sensuous cognition defined and classified 33, intuitional 39, subjective and objective cognitions according to Vacaspati and Vijnanabhiksu 88, Vaisesika classification of 110, perceptual and inferential 110, perverted 153 original perverted 154, wrong 155 wrong 166-7, question of validity or invalidity of 196, perverted 219. Cognitional activity, varieties of 50. Compassion 17. Concentration, doctrine of 281 et seq. Conduct, right 25, right 146, perverse 147, mutual relation of right attitude, right knowledge and right conduct 147-51, constituents of right 150, wrong 155, consummate 161, perverted 161, perverted 219, general scheme of the Jaina doctrine of 263 et seq., fivefold 264, main features of the Jaina doctrine of 266. Consciousness, 7. resultant IO, CO efficients of II & 14 & 16, stirring of 35, dormant and active 55-6, 73, consciousness alone is real 129 et seq., why it projects the universe 131, in Saivism 141, 143, 151, 159, 164, 165, 166, why it cannot be denied 174, 175, 176, 177, 190, nature of pure III, 208, 224, 226, 277, 288, a temporary evolute of material combination 229, 231, Buddhist conception of 246-7. planes of 248, nature of 251, dawn of moral and spiritual 271. Contact-awareness, 35, 36, 37, 38, 40, 44, 45. Contemplation, twelvefold 290. Craving, 16, 126. Creation, speculations about 2, ulti mate source of 3, old doctrines regarding 24, psychical 93, subtle physical, psychical and gross phy Page #347 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 310 INDEX III sical 93n, religious potency lies at the root of 109, is false according to Gaudapada 116, Upanisadic statements about 117, 118, nature and root of 130, pure and impure orders of 137, as evolution 157, doctrines about 220n, 225, Asat as the ground of 228. Death, meaning of 102, 126. Definitions, function of 214. Deluding karman, 232, two groups of 233, maxiinum and minimum durations of 236. Delusion, 16, 73, 102, 103, the fountain-head of worldly career 103-4, companion of the soul from beginningless time 104, nature of 106, 107, source of 113, 127, 128, 141, 145, 146, 162, 165, 166, 167, 168, 187, 188, theoretical and practical 232, eternal 289. Determinism, 2200. Difference, 165, is not absolute 177. pure difference is never experienced 178, 184, 185, absolute difference is tantamount to absolute negation of relation 213. Different attitudes, doctrine of 29. Discontent, divine 103. Disputation, 107. Divine Freedom, xix. Divine Grace xxi, xxii, xxiii, 139, descent of 140, 218. Divine Will, 138. Doubt, differentiated from speculation 41, 73, 110. Dream Experience, interpretation of 176. Dualism, 172, 187, 188. Duality, origin of the notion of 120, reason why it appears 124, origin of 131, 132, 133, 188. Ecstasy, 200, supreme importance of 251. Effect, problem of its relation with cause 174, problem of the mutual relation of cause and 175. Ego, 90, 122, 228. Egoism, 89, 90, nature of 103, contents of ego-consciousness 103, egoconsciousness is the supreme evil 104. nature Emancipation, 6, 13, nature of 15, 25, requisites of 91, cause of 108, nature of 112, pathway to 147, 150, pathway to 151. J 52. of 158, 159, Nyava-Vaisesika conception of 162, 163, 164, 165, 167, 168, 190, 193, 194, 200, 201, 215, 220, 221, 226, meaning of 228, ideal of eternal spiritual 229, Jaina pathway to final 266, nature of 289, meaning of 290. Empiricism, Jaina's credence in logical 219. Energy, 151, 165, 254. Enjoyment, meaning of 84. Enlightenment, 17, in Tathata philosophy 135, nature of final 159, intellectual 217, first dawn of 273. Error, 73, anyathakhyati doctrine of 95, nature of 96, Yoga and Sankhya had a common theory of 97, Sankhya theory of error distinguished from that of Prabhakara 98, misinterpretation of the Sankhya theory of 99, universal condition of 99, Yoga theory of error is not anyathakhyati 100, universal condition of 100, Sankhya and Yoga theory of 100, instances of perceptual and inferential III, transcendental error defined IZI, universal nature of 123, nature of erroneous perception 172-3, predicate of erroneous judgment 173. 190, opposition between knowledge and 191-2, 195, Vedantist's interpretation of 196, 203, 204. Eternalism, 9, 10, II, 14, origin of 15, 22, origin of 23. Evil, cause of 18, objects by themselves are not 104. Evolution, purpose of 89, beginning and purpose of 90, purpose of 97. origin of evolution in Saivism 138. Excluded Middle, law of 173, 182. Existence, not an evil 18, 73, ulti mate foundation of existence in the Tathata philosophy 135, threefold conditions of worldly 154, 164, why it cannot be denied 174, 184, 190, 199, causal efficiency is the criterion of 205, fundamental defect conditioning worldly 223, meaning of worldly 228, meaning of worldly 229, roots of worldly 247. Experience, Sankara's examination of 121, adhyasa is the very texture of our experience according to Sankara 123, its relation to reasoning 146, 175, 177, 180, 184, 185, 199. logic must co-operate with experience 204, 213, only source of knowledge 215, 219, 261. Expiation. ninefold 264. Faith, right 25, 54. Falsity, contradiction of experience as the criterion of 175. Feeling-producing karman. 232, two sub-types of 233, maximum and minimum durations of 236. Fetters, ten 248n. Freedom, Divine xix, meaning of 18, individual 21, in Saivism 141, 143, 150. Gautama, 230. God, 221, 222, 227, 268. Godhead, Jaina conception of 268, 269. Page #348 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ GENERAL SUBJECTS 311 Happiness, balance of 102, impossi bility of unalloyed 103 Heretics, four types of 24, 137. Holy Grail, 204. Idealists, subjectivist 208. Identification, nature of mutual iden tification of self and not-self 123. Identity, meaning of 124, 165, pure identity is never experienced 178, 185, origin of the illusion of 207, nature of 214, concrete 231. Identity-cum-difference (=identity-in difference), 193, 225. Identity-in-difference, 186, 211, 214, why so called 215, 216, necessity of the admission of 231. Ignorance, 10, 16, 25, the original capital of worldly existence 104, original sin of 105, 106, 126, 127, 130, nature of ignorance in Tathata philosophy 135, function of 136, 158, 165, 167, as the prius of the subjective and the objective order of existence 169, 178, 191, spiritual 217, intellectual 217. Ignorance (spiritual and intellectual), xxiii, 143, 144, 217. Illusion, transcendent 99, origin of the appearance of 130, necessity and nature of 132, maya as the principle of cosmic 170, 224. Impulse, possessive 102. Inertia, spiritual 147. Inference 60, 61, 67, 67n. Infinity, Jaina conception of 63, 65n. Inherence, 163, 164. Instant, 63. Instincts, varieties and meaning of 52, 54, 54n. Intellect, four kinds of intellect de fined and illustrated 44-8, common feature of all the four kinds of 48, eight qualities of 49, 150. Intuition, instinctive incipient 33 super-sensuous 34, 37, supernormal spiritual 110, 151. Intuition-covering karman, 232, nine sub-types of 233, maximum and minimum durations of 236. Judgment, origin of objective and subjective judgments according to Vacaspati and Vijnanabhiksu 88, nature of false 96, nature of its subject and predicate 187. Karmic matter, function of 204. Kesi-Kumara, 27. Knowledge, right 25, Jaina theory of 27, criterion of its wrongness 28, pure and perfect 28, criterion of directness and indirectness 28, empirically direct and immediate 28, perceptual, inferential, analogical and scriptural 30, non-sensuous 33. transcendental direct, and empirical direct 34, scriptural 34. vital source of the Jaina theory of 62, 80, nature and origin of it according to Yoga 86, according to Sankhya-Yoga 88, possibility of complete 105, transcendental III, right 146, source of the perversity of 147, mutual relation of right attitude, right knowledge and right conduct 147-51, 151, 158, right 161, perverted 161, Nyaya-Vaisesika conception of 162, 165, 168, opposition between error and 191-2, spiritual 217. Knowledge (spiritual and intellec tual), xxiii, 217. Knowledge-covering karman, 232, five sub-types of 233, maximum and minimum duration of 236. Language, relation of thought with I, shortcomings of 15, articulate 52, 56. Law, 10, 15, 17, 20. Law of Contradiction, 204. Liberation, its meaning 20. Life, presupposes action 123, Bud dhist conception of various planes of 246, four planes of 249. Logic, abstract 9, meaning, purpose and value of 81, its relation to spiritual vision 82, abstract logic runs away from the reality as revealed in experience 175, 185, must Co-operate with experience 204, its place and utility 209, 214, pure logic obeyed by facts 215, 219, abstract 226. Longevity-determining karman, 233, four sub-types of 234, maximum and minimum durations of 236. Love, 17. Madhyamika, 120, 129, 137, 202. Mahavira, his attitude towards life 17, 18, neither a sceptic nor an agnostic nor a materialist 25, non absolutistic attitude of 26. Mahavratikas, 303. Mahayana, 20in, 25. Mahesvara, 137 Material form, II, 25. .Materialism, II, nature of 15. Materialist, 187, 204, 229. Matter, 63, pure and impure 137, 223, 287. Meditation, 20, supreme importance of 251, 262. Memory, 34. Mental states, four kinds of 290. Metaphysics, defects of 8, Buddha's attitude towards 14. Middle Course, IO, II. Middle Path, doctrine of the to. Mimamsa, 108. Mimamsaka, 220, 221, 222. Mind, problem of its status of sense organ 31, 32, 33, 35, nature of 53n, stuff making up the 65, undergoes change while thinking 66, 67, Page #349 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 312 INDEX III 69, initial motion of 108, complete annihilation of the functions of 291. Misperception, 195. Modes, 63, 64, 70, 165, their rela tion with qualities 231. Momentariness, 184. Monism, 7, 116, 172, 178, 179, 185, it cannot be established by revela tion 187, 188, 189. Monotheism, 7. Morality, standard of 5, doctrines regarding 24, 25. Moral Law, necessity of the 204, 205. Moralness, essential conditions of 247-8. Naiyayika, 87, 152, 173, 213. Negativism, 212. Nescience, 81, function of 83, defined 84, 85, nature of it according to Yoga 89, its relation to the other klesas 89, 90, 107, 108, III, 112. 120, 145, 152, 155, 156, 174, 178, 179, 188, 189, 190, 191, 192, 193, 194, 195, 196, differentiation of nescience from truth 197, 198, 203, 204, 209, 218, 221, 226, 248n, 287, 296. Nihilism, 9, 10, 11, 14, identified with materialism 15, origin of 23, 201, 205, 227. Nihilist, 174, 187, 204. Non-absolutism, origin of 22, 202, doctrine of 217. Non-abstinence, 147. Non-actionism, 24. Non-being, 2, 3, pure non-being is an abstraction 199, 200, impossibi lity of pure 214. Non-dualism, 188. Non-dualists, 117. Non-duality, 116. Non-enlightenment, in the Tathata philosophy 135. Non-existence, I, 9. Non-injury, 18, 21. Non-obscuring karman, types of 239. Non-violence, 265 Nyaya, 100, 109, theory of causation 212, 214. Nyaya-Vaisesika, 153, 157, 190, 191, 220, 221, 222, 225, 226, 227, 228, 230-I, 296. Objectivity, its relation with subject ivity 142. Object-perception, 35, 36, 37, 38, 41, 44, 45 Obscuration, ultimate cause of 138. Obscuring karman, types of 239. Obstructive karman, 233, five sub types of 234, maximum and mini mur durations of 236. Omnipotence, 138, 143, 216, 217. Omniscience, question of the possi bility of krama in xviii-xix, 64, 70, 77, 78, 138, 142, 143, 165, 167, 168, 169, 216, 217, natural to soul 239, 251. Omniscient, 61, 63, 72, 74, 77, 150n. Opposition, it is both a priori and empirical 191. Organisms, even the one-sensed are capable of potential verbal thinking 52, having two or more sense organs 54. Otherness, absolute 214. Paramusiva, nature of 137, the Abso lute of monistic Saivism 141, as both transcendent and immanent 142, Supreme and Sole Reality 217. Parsva, 27. Particular, 72, 164. Passions, 147, 168n, 221, 223, 225, 226, 227, 238, sixteen kinds of 2334. Quasi-passions, nine kinds of 234 Pasupatas, 222. Pasupati. 137. Path, eight-fold 16. Penance, 21, 150, 168, 220. Perception, 11, 14, 16. Perception, empirical 30, transcen dental, 32, sensuous and quasisensuous 34, synonyms of 34, 44, 47. auditory 57, critical estimate of the Yoga theory of 87, representative and presentative theories of 87. Perceptual judgment, 36, 37, 38, 39, defined 41, Synonyms of 42, 44, 56, 148. Permanence, absolute 18. Personality, 86. Perversion, emotional and volitional 106, 127, 128, 222, 227. Perversity, 51, 145, 168, 168n. Plurality, origin of the perception of 113, cannot come out of the Absolute 120, 171, 172, 173, antagonism and conflict between unity and 174, 175, 177, 189, 191. Polytheism, 7. Prabhakara, his theory of error 98-9, 100. Preceptor, 262. Predispositions, 221, 222. Probans, 77. Problems, unexplainable 8, psycho logy of the solutions of 47. Property, effects of the love of 102. Quality, 163, 164, 165. 211, its rela tion with substance 231. Quasi-passions, see under passions. Quasi-sense, 31, 32 Questions, four kinds of 8. Ramayana, 50. Realism, 227. Reality. nature of ultimate 7, 18, universal-cum-particular 72, internal 73, 77, according to Upanisads 113, as beyond reach of mind and intellect 175, ultimate reality accor Page #350 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ GENERAL SUBJECTS 313 ing to the cessation of 16, aggre. gate of 16. Soul, 4, 10, 16, believer in 18, nature of the liberated 20, relation with body 23, old doctrines regarding 24, Jaina belief in 25, absence of knowledge unnatural to 28, belief in its capacity to know 61, 69, 70, 71, 73, 78, 80, specific qualities of TOT, uncommon characteristics that prove the existence of coin, inherent dissatisfaction of 103, means of purification of 107, in Tathata philosophy 135, the innate nature of soul in Saivism 137, potential nature of 138, 145, 150, enumeration of the capacities of 151, 152, 163, 164, 165, its right to perfection 216, 222, 223, 227, infinite number of 229, intrinsic attributes of 232, three states of 287, naturally moves towards emancipation 298. ding to Gauda pada 116, 119, 126, nature of Supreme Reality in Saivism 141, Vedantist's conception of 170, causal efficiency is the criterion of 172, must not be selfcontradictory 199, causal efficiency is the criterion of 206, continuity and change as the criterion of 208, how determined 215. Reason, 261-2. Reasoning, its relation to experience 146. Rebirth, 4, theory of 5, 7, 15, funda mental condition of 83, presupposition of all Indian schools 220, origin of the doctrine of 221, 229. Recognition, 34, 60. Recollection, 54, 60, 61, IIO. Relation, of body and soul 1o, as objective link 70, not intelligible in terms of absolute difference or abso lute identity 123, 176, 186. Religion, it has value only in the phenomenal plane 116. Retention, 38, 41, defined 42, synonyms of 42, defined 43, 44, 148. Revelation, 185, 187, 190, 303. Sabdadvaitins, 202. Sacrifice, 220. Saiva, 303 Saivism, dualistic 137-41, monistic 141-4 Sanjaya Velatthiputta, 25, 26. Sankhya, 121, 152, 166, 170, 212, 214, 218, 297, 303. Sankhya-Yoga, 87, 101, 153, 166, 190, 191, 220, 221, 222, 224, 225, 226, 227, 228, 229, 230. Sautrantika, 181, 2010, 205. Scepticism, 121, 199, 201. Sceptics, 24, 25, 174, 262. Scriptural or Verbal Knowledge, ori ginal meaning and varieties of 48, 150. Self, 73, its fear of death 103, nature of 116, 117, 119, 122, only reality ex hypothesi 123, 152, 165, 166, 176, 201, Buddhist denial of permanent self 206, intrinsic purity of 223, three states of the self, viz. exterior, interior and transcendental 281, difference between the empirical and the transcendental 287. Sensuous Cognition, 30, synonyms of 32, defined 33, classified 34, three hundred and thirty-six types of 44. Sevenfold Predication, doctrine of 29. Sin, besetting sin of worldly career * 102, Original 104. Siva, nature of 137, 138, 140. Solipsism, 121, 209. Sorrow, universal fact 15, causa! chain of, cessation of, path lead JP-40 Soullessness, the doctrine of 182. Sound, 35. Space, 63, 64, 159. Space-point, 63. 64. Speculation, 38, 39, 40, differentiat ed from doubt 41, 44, 47, 56, 57. 59. Spiritual Development, doctrine of the stages of 268-80. Spiritualism, 21, 83. Standpoint, empirical, transcendental 72, empirical, analytic 80. Staticity, meaning of 23-4. Status-determining karman, 233, two sub-types of 234, maximum and minimum durations of 236. Subjectivism, 121, 227. Subjectivist, 208, 211. Subjectivity, origin of the appear. ance of 136, its relation with objec tivity 142. Substance, 12, a creation of the staticizing tendency 16, that helps motion 64, that helps rest 64, its relation with a quality in the Nyaya-Vaisesika system 163, 164, 165, 177, 200, 211, its relation with modes 231. Substancelessness, 12. Suchness, 135 Suffering, an evil 18. Suicide,' a misnomer for voluntary death 20. Sunyavadin, 185. Superimposition, nature of 122, nature of mutual superimposition of self and not-self 123, presupposes mutual identification 123, 216. Syllogisin, problem of the number of members of 30. Sympathetic joy, 17. Tathagata, 13, 14, 135, 136. 50. Page #351 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 314 INDEX IV Tathata Philosophy, 134-7. Teleology, 84, Nyaya school does not believe in 101. Tendencies, 10. Thatness, 134, 135. Thought, relation of language with 1, shortcomings of 15, is relative 22, discursive 34, discursive 56, main inspiration of Indian 81. Time, 63, 64, 119, 220n. Time-point, 63, 64. Transmigration, 4. Truth, what is 82, 114, why it is misunderstood 136, predilection for the 148, predilection or love for the 161, 173, contradiction is the criterion of 175. Truths, four noble 16. Unity, 171, antagonism and conflict between plurality and 174, 175, 177, 184, of the multifold expressions 228. Universal, 72, 164. Universe, speculation on the ultimate source of I, the inhabited 63. speculations about the origin and destiny of the 220, contents of the 229. Vaibhasika, 251. Vaisesika, 95, 96, 152, 157, 222, 230. abadha (endurance without effect), 255, defined 259. kala (period of non-fruition) 244, 256, 260. abhava (non-perception), 34. abhavya, 266n. abhigrahika (obstinate) mithya darsana, defined 145: abhigrhita (firmly held) mithyadarsana, defined 145. abhinibodha (perceptual cognition), 32, 34. abhinibodhika-jnana (perceptual cognition), 30, 30n, 32, total number of types of 44, 55, 148. abhinivesa (desire for life), 89, defined go, 93, 94. abhinivesa (irrational predilection), 120. abhinivesika (irrational) mithyadarsana, defined 145. abhisandhija (voluntary) energy, 253. abhoganata (leaning towards), 40. abhutabhinevesa (the bias and predilection for the unreal), 121. abhutaparikalpa (the conjuring up of imaginary unreal; constructive ideation or unreal imagination), nature of 131, different meanings of 131, 132, 133, 134, 202. Vedanta, 220, 221, Advaita 229, 296, 297. Vedantin, 152, 203, 222, 224, 225, 228, 230. Vedantist, 100, 204, 211, 216, 217. Vedas, 50. Vedic people, outlook of the 220. Vijnanavada, 137 Vijnanavadin, 128, 130, 131, 134. Vision, prolonged 71, clear 71, of one's self 73, 151. Visual Intuition, 28. Vivarana School of Sankara Vedanta, 87. Will, autonomous will of Paramasiva 142. evil 149, 150, 168, correction of 217. INDEX IV SANSKRIT, PRAKRIT AND PALI WORDS Words, articulated 57, physical gestures are also 59.. World, problem of finiteness and infiniteness 23, external 73. Purusa (Absolute) as the source of 114, is an illusion 121, nature of the objective 130, genesis of the world process 136, nature of 156. Wrangling, 107. Yoga, 91, 92, 95, 152, 204, 221. Yogacara, 120, 129, 226. Yudhisthira, 91, 92. acaksurdarsana (intuition by the mind as well as the sense-organs other than the eye), 71, 77. 233. -avarana, 240, 241. acarya (supreme preceptor), 264. acinna (repeatedly done), type of karman 250. adarsana (non-intuition), 127. adhahpravrttakarana, 270n. adhapavatta, 270n. adharma (substance that helps rest; medium of rest), 64. adharma (opposite of dharma; religious demerit), 93, 100n, 101, 102, its different senses qua cause and effect 109, 110, 111, 112, 139, 144, 152, 154. adhyasa (superimposition), 121, 122, 123, 124. adhyatma (a stage of yoga), 297, 298, 299. adosa (absence of aversion), 16, 247. adrsta (unseen religious potency). 108, its different senses qua cause and effect 109, 111, 154, 220, 221, 222. adrstajanmavedaniya, 244, 251. advaita (non-dual), 118. advaya (without a second), 119. Page #352 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ SANSKRIT, PRAKRIT AND PALI WORDS 315 . 65. advesa (freedom from prejudice), 297, 301. agama (scriptural knowledge), 30. agamika (opposite of gamika), 53. aghati-(non-obscuring)-karman, XX, 239, 242. agneyi dharana, described 288. ahankara (ego; egoism), 94, 103, ahanta (subjectivity), 142. aharaka, 65 ahetuka (conditionless; not rooted in tendencies), 247, 249. ahimsa (non-injury ; non-violence), 18, 21, 243, 265. ahosikain ma, 250, 251. aisvarya (supernormal powers), 93, roon. aja (unborn), 118. ajata (unborn), 118. ajiva (non-soul), 144. ajna (revelation), 283. ajnana (wrong knowledge; ignorance; nescience; wrong cognition), 28, 41, 5in, 83, 93, 1oon, 130, 145, 147, 152, 155, 158, 164, 165, 166, 167, mithyadarsana defined 145, paurusa and bauddha 143. ajnanin (agnostic), 145. akalpaka (pure), 119. akincanna (nothingness), 248. akiriyam (non-actionism), 24. akrivavadin (non-believer in moral and spiritual action), 145. aksara (alphabet), 48, 49n. aksara (the immutable), 115. aksarasyuta, 49. akusala (bad ; immoral), 247. --vipaka, 249, 250. alambana (conditions), 283. alambana (concentration on the image of a tirthankara in full glory), 293, 294. alayavijnana (all-conserving mind), 135, 136. alesya (free from coloration), 253. alobha (absence of greed), 16, 247 alocana (intuition), 35. alocana (intuitional cognition), 38. amagga (wrong path), 144. amnaya (scripture), 108, 109. amoha (absence of delusion), 16, 247, amytatman, 296. amurta (formless), 226. amutta (unemancipated), 145. anabhigrahika (indiscriminate) in thyadarsana, defined 1915. anabhigyhita (lightly held) mithya darsana, defined 145. anabhisandhija (involuntary) energy, anabhoga (involuntary) mithyadar sana, defined 145. anadhyavasaya indecision), IIO. anadika (having no beginning), 51. ana gamin, 249. anagamipadavaha, 303. anaisvarya (opposite of aisvarya), 93, roon. anakara (indeterminate), 70, 71. anaksara (opposite of aksara)49, 49n. anaksara (bereft of words), 58. analambana, 293, defined 294-5. anantakasa (infinity of space), 248. anuntanubandhin (what leads to 'endless' worldly existence; "lifelong'), 234, illustrated 234n, 237, 238, 239, 274. ananta-vinnana (infinity of conscious ness), 248. ana pana (respiration), 65. --vargana, anatta (not-self), II, substanceless 248. anava-mala, xix, xxii, definition of 138, origin, nature and function of 142, origin of the twofold 143, 216. andhatamisra, 93, eighteenfold 94. anekanta (non-absolutism), 22. angabahya (other than the original scripture), 48, 53. anga pravista (included in the original scripture), 48, 53. anicca (impermanent), II, 248. anindriya (quasi-sense), 31, 33n. anivartikarana, 271. anivetti-badara-samparaya (ninth gunasthana), described 278. anivettikarana, 271, function of 272, 273, 274, 275. aniyata-vipaka (with uncertain frui tion), 260. annanam (agnosticism). 25. annaniya (agnostics), 24. antah karana (mind), 122. antara karana, 272, 273. antaratman (inside self; interior self). 114, 281. antaraya (obstructive) karman, 69, 150, 233, 279. antarmuhurta (period of time which is less than forty-eight minutes). 271. antarmukha (introvert). 73. anu (atomic). 138. anubhaga (intensity of fruition), 235, 236. 257 anubhaga-bandha (bondage of inten sity), 1687, 238. anubhava, 235n. anugraha-sakti (Grace), xxii, 140. anumana (inferential knowledge). 30, 34, 67 anu preksa (contemplation; reflection), twelvefold 263, 264, 282, 283, 290n, 293 anuvrata (small vow), 265. anyamud, 296, 301. anyathakhyati, the doctrine of 95, Vijnanabhiksu's distinction between the Yoga and the Vaisesika anyathakhyati 95, Yoga and Vaise 253 Page #353 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 316 sika anyathakhyati 96, 97, the doctrine of 98, 100. apagama (determinate judgment), 42. apagata (determinate judgment), 42. apanoda (determinate judgment), 42. apanutta (determinate judgment), 42. aparapariyavedaniya, type of kar man 250, 251. INDEX IV aparyavasita (having no end), 51. apavarga (final release or emancipation), 84, conditions of its attainment 107, III, 153, 224. apavartana (process of decreased realization), 254, defined 257apaviddha (determinate judgment), 42. apavyadha (determinate judgment), 42. apaya (perceptual judgment), 36, 37, 38, 39, defined 41, synonyms of 42, 43, 44, 46, 56, 60, 148. apaya (universal suffering), 283. apayabhumi (plane of misery), 249. 250. apeta (determinate judgment), 42. apoha (exclusion), 32. apramatta (free from passions), 68, 286. apramatta-samyata (seventh guna sthana), described 277. apratyakhyanavarana, 234, illustrated 2340, 237, 239n, 274. aptakamatva (self-contained com placency), 139. apunna (bad act), 128. apurnammanyata (sense of incompleteness and imperfection), 142. apurvakarana, nature and function of 271-2, 275, 278, 300. Eighth gunasthana, described 277. apurva-sthitibandha, 272, 278. arhat (literally 'the adorable'; the omniscient), 77, 289. arhat (of Buddhism), his conscious ness 247, 248, 249. ariya-saccani (noble truths), 16. arsa-jnana (supernormal spiritual in tuition), 110. artadhyana, 28gn. artha (material prosperity), 47. artha (object), argument to prove the non-existence of 130n. artha (proper understanding of the meaning), 293, 294. arthapatti (presupposition), 34. arthavagraha (object-perception), 35, 36, 37, 38, 41, 44, 45arupa, 248n. arupavacara, defined 248. -bhumi, 249, 250. arya (saintly), 2010. asadvedya (what causes unpleasant feeling), 233, 256. asahu (sinner), 145. asakti (mental disability), 93. asamjna (absence of samjna), 53. asamjnin (opposite of samjnin), 49, explained 50, 54. asamjni-sruta, 50, 53asamkhyeya (countless), 35, 42. asamprajnata samadhi, 161, 295, 296. asana (posture), 284, 301. asanajaya (conquest of posture), 286. asanga (without any consideration), 294. asanga (attachment), 296, 301. asanganusthana, 303. asanna, type of karman 250. asat, 228. asatavedaniya, see asadvedya. asava (bondage), 20. asaya (past actions), 112. asmita (egoism), 89, 90, 93, 94. asramas (stages of life), 109. asrava (influx, inflow), 238, 243. 245. asrutanisrita (not backed by scriptural learning), 44, 45, 46, 48. asubha (inauspicious or sinful) karman, 235, 245. prakyti, defined 2370. asukla-'krsna, 245n. athapravrttakarana, 270n. aticara (transgression of vows), 265. atindriya-pratyaksa (super-sensuous intuition), 34. atiprasanga (unwarranted extension), 60. atman, 4, 12, 16, 62n, its identity with knowledge and intuition 72, 117, 118, 122, 124, 125, 126, 137. atta, meaning of 12. atthangiko maggo (eightfold path), 16. audarika (gross), 65, 69, 234. aupamya (analogical knowledge), 30. aupasamika, 273, 277. autpattiki buddhi (instantaneous comprehension), 45, defined 46, illustrated 47. avabodha (cognition), 42. avadharana (holding), 35. avadharana (memory), 42. avadhi, see avadhi-jnana. avadhi-ajnana, 71, 147. avadhi-darsana, 63n, 71, 77, 233-avarana, 24on, 241. avadhi-jnana (visual intuition), 28, 29, 30, 61, a birthright of the denizens of heaven and hell 62. scope of 63, 63n, 64, 66, 68, 69, 71, 75, 147. avadhyajnana, see avadhi-ajnana. avagama (retention), 42. avagraha (perception), synonyms of 34, two kinds of 35. definition of 35, defined by Umasvati 36, defined by Pujyapada Devanandi 37. 38, defined by Akalanka 39, defined by Hemacandra 40, 44, 45, 46, 47, 57, 58, 60, 61, 77, 148. Page #354 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ SANSKRIT, PRAKRIT AND PALI WORDS 317 avagraha (receiving), 35. avagrahanata (receiving), 34. avairagya, 1oon. avalambanata (grasping), 35. avalika (a small measure of time). 257, 257n. avarana (obscuration), xx. avarana (veil ; cover), 134, 227. avartanata (limited determination), 42. avasthana (retention), 42. avaya, see apaya. . avaya (determination), 42. aved ya-sarvedya-pada, 302. avibhaga-paliccheda (indivisible unit), 236, 236n. avicyuti (absence of lapse), 43. avidya (nescience, wrong cognition, ignorance), xx, 16, 25, 80, 81, 83, Yoga definition of 84, qua sasana and qua wrong cognition 85n, its nature and relation to other klesas 89, 90, Sankhya conception of 93, 94, 95, 97, 98, 100, in the Nyaya school IOT, as defined in the Vaisesika school 108, 109, IIO, Iron, 112, in the Vedanta school 113, 114, 115, 120, 121, 122, 124, 126, in the Buddhist school 126, 127, nature of 128, 129, 135, 137. Saiva conception of 137, 138, 140, 143, in the Jaina school 144, criticism of the Sankhya-Yoga conception of 155 et seq., criticism of the Nyaya-Vaisesika conception of 162 et seq., criticism of the Vedanta conception of 169 et seq., criticism of the Buddhist conception of 201 et seq., 2010, 202, 203, criticism of the Saiva conception of 215 et seq., 218, 219, 246, 273, 297. avidya-lesa, xx. avijja, 10, 126. avikalpa-jnana (non-constructive in tuition), 129. aviraga (opposite of viraga), 93. avirata-samyagdysti (fourth guna sthana), described 277. avirati (intense attachment; non abstinence; non-renunciation). 145, 147, 153, 239, 274. aviveka, the doctrine of 95, 97, the doctrine of 98, 99, 100. avivekakhyati, 98, 99, 100. avyakata (unexplainable), 8, 13, 14. av yakata (neutral), 247. aya-vai (believer in soul), 18. ayoga, see ayogakevalin. ayogakevalin (fourteenth gunastha na), described 279, 304n. ayuhkarman, 270n. ayus (longevity), 90, category of karman leading to 245, 279. ayuska (longevity-determining) kar man, 233 badara-samparaya (gross passions), 278. badhyamana (being bound), 260. bahiratman (exterior self), 281. bahirmukha (extrovert), 73. bala (third dysti), 300, described 302. bandha (bondage), 132, 133, 232, 297 bandhana (process of bondage), 254. bhakti (reverence), 294. bhasa (speech), 65. bhau tikasarga (gross physical crea tion), 93n. bhava (psychical factor), 93, eight Ioon. bhava (coming to be), 126, 127. bhava (worldly existence), 153, 154. bhava-karman, 227, 227n. bhao ama (contemplation), 265, 282, 2gon. bhavana (a stage of yoga), 297, 299. bhavanga (continuation of life), 249. bhava-pratyaya (due to birth), 62. bhavasarga (psychical creation), 93n. bhavasatru, 296. bhavasruta, 52, 53, 58. bhavendriya, 52n. bhavyata, xxi. bhoga (enjoyment), meaning of 84, go, 153, category of karman lead ing to 245. bhranti (illusion), 132, 297. bhranti (lapse of memory), 296, 301. bhranti-vijnana (illusory conscious ness), 132. bhuta, 229. bhutatathata (thatness), 134, 135. bhutavigama, 296. bindu (pure matter), 137. bodha (comprehension), 297, 301. bodhi (enlightenment), 17. 299. bodhicitta, xxii. bodhisattva, 298, 299. Brahmaloka (the region of the Brahman or truth), 114. Brahman (Absolute), 3, 6, 7, 116, 117, 120, 170, 185, 187, 190, 192, Brahman (Creator), 24, 112. buddhi (vivid determination), 42. buddhi (intellect), 33, 34, four kinds of 44-8. buddhi (of Sankhya-Yoga), 84, 85, 86, 87, 89, 93, 97, 98, 159, 222, 230. buddhi (knowledge), 162. cakkhu-samphassa (eye-contact), 12. cakkhu vinnana (eye-consciousness). 12. caksurdarsana (eye-intuition), 71, 77, 233. -avarana, 240n, 241n. caranu (conduct), 149, 150. carana-guna (rectitude of will), 149. caritra (conduct), 147, 149, 150, 152, 153, 262, 263, fivefold 264. 228. Page #355 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 318 INDEX IV caritramoha (character-deluding) kar. man, 246, 256. caritramohaniya (what deludes the right conduct) karman, 233, 252, 275. See also caritramoha-karman. catuhsthanika, 236, defined 237. catummaharajika, 249. cetana (willing), 247 chadmastha (a being involved in the world), 54, 74, 740, 75, 282n. chedopastha pana (re-initiation), 264. cinta (thought), 32. cinta (discursive thought), 34, 40. cinta prabandha (thought stream). 284n. citi (consciousness), 159. citta (consciousness), 201. citta-caitasika (pure consciousness and its concomitant associates), I31. cuti (passing away), 250. darsana (intuition), 37, 69, problem of the relation of jnana and 70-80, it is introvert 73, problem of its relation with pasyatta 74, 148, 239. darsana (attitude ; predilection for truth; vision), 147, meaning of 148, 149, 151, 153. darsanamoha (delusion of attitude or vision), 83. 144. darsanamoha (attitude-deluding or belief-deluding) karman, 149, 233, 246, 256. darsanamohaniya, see darsanamoha. darsanavarana (intuition-covering) karman, 71, 76, 78, 144, 150, 232. desaghatin (partially obscuring) karman, 239, 240, 241. --spardhaka, 258. desana (instruction)., 270n. desavirata-samyagdrsti (fifth guna sthana), 277. desavirati-caritra (capacity for par tial renunciation), 241. dhomma. TO. 15, 17, 20, 127. dharana (holding). 42. dharana (concentration), 287, 290, 301. dharana (retention). 38, 41, Syno nyms and definition of 42. meaning of 43, various definitions of 43, 44, 46, 148. dharma (religion ; what leads to pros perity and emancipation; religious merit; moral virtues), 47, 93, 100, roon, TOI, as defined in the Vaisesika school 108. its different senses qua cause and effect 109, III, II2, pravartaka (creative) and nivartaka (emancipative) 112n, 139, 144, 152, tenfold 263 264. dharma (thing : element of existence), 133, 134, 136. dharma (adjunct). 163. dharma (substance that helps motion; medium of motion), 64. dharmadhatu (totality of all things ; unity of all), 134, 135. dharma-dhyana, defined and describ ed 283-91. dharmakaya, 135. dharmamegha, 296. dharma-nairatmya (unsubstantiality of things), 134. dharma-samnyasa, 300. dharmin (substantive), 163. dharmya, 2831, 284n, 290. dhruvadhvan, 303 dhyana (concentration), 265, 267, doctrine of 281-93, 281n, defined 282, function of dhyana in the case of the omniscient 282n, categories of 283, 283n, Subhacandra's classification of 288, different functions of 291, a stage of yoga 297, 299, 301 diksa (initiation), xxiii, 140, sadhi karana and niradhikarana 141, function of 141, 143. dipra (fourth dysti), 300, described 302. dirghakaliki (lasting for a long time), 50, 53. ditthadhammavedaniya, type of kar. man 250, 251. dosa (aversion , hatred), 16, 247. dosa (defect), TOI, 102, 107, 154, 167, 227. drasta (witness), 84. dravya (substance), 164. drav ya-karman, 227. dravya-mati, 58. dravya-sruta, 52, 58. dravyendriya, 52n. dostajanma-vedaniya, 244, 251. dysti (faith), 54. dysti (love of truth), 300, meaning of 301, eight drstis described 301 dystivada-sarjna, 55. See dystivado padesiki. dustivadopadesiki (backed by scrip tural knowledge), 50, defined 54. drsya (objective world; external object), 84, 129. duhkha (suffering or pain), 102, 107. 154, 162, 164. duhkhanta (cessation of pain), 296. dukkha (sorrow), II, 16, 248. dukkhanirodha (cessation of sorrow), 16. dukkha-nirodha-gamini patipada (path leading to the cessation of sorrow). 16. dukkha-samudaya (causal chain of sorrow). 16. dvaita (dual ; duality), 118, 119. dvesa (aversion), 89, 90, 93, 94, TOI, 269. dvi-sthanika, 236, defined 237. Page #356 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ SANSKRIT, PRAKRIT AND PALI WORDS 319 ekamsa-vyakaraniya (answerable cate gorically), 8. ekanta (absolutistic) mithyadarsana defined, 145. eka-sthanika, 236, defined 237. ekatva-vitarka-'vicara, described 292. ckikarana, 287. gamika (containing repetitions), 48, 53. gana (descendant group), 264. ganadhara, meaning of 299. ganipitaka, 50. gantha (bondage), 18. garbhaja (born of womb), 53. gatinaman, 234, 246. gavesana (gavesana, fathoming), 32. gavesanata (fathoming), 40. ghati(obscuring)-karman, xx, 239, 243, 279. glana (ailing ascetic), 264. gotra (status-determining) karmian, 233, 279. gotrayogin, 304. graha (receiving), 35. grahana (receiving), 35. granthi (knot of intense attachment and repulsion)nature of 270-I, cutting of 271, 302. granthibheda, xxi, xxii guna (sensuous objects), 18. guna (elements or energies), 85, 90. guna (quality), 164. gunanimitta (due to merit), 63. gurapratyaya (due to merit), 62. gunasamkrama, 272, 274, 278. gunasreni, 272, 278. gunasthana (stages of spiritual deve lopment), xxi, xxii, 266, 267, 268, the doctrine of 268-80. gunavrata, 265. gupli (self-control), 263, 264. guru (preceptor), 47, 140, 141, 262, 290. guruka (serious). type of karman 250, 251. hasituppuda citta innocent smile), 247. hetu, 29n. hetupadesiki (discriminating), 50, 54. hetuvada-sarjna, see hetupadesiki. hetuvada-samjnin, defined 54. iccha (will), 162, 294. iccha yoga, defined 300. idanta (objectivity), 142. iha (speculation), 32, 38, 39, syno nyms given by Nandi Sutra and Umasvati and the different definitions 40, differentiated from sansaya 41, 43, 44, 45, 46, 47, 56, 57, 58, 59, 61, 148. indriyanindriya-pratyaksa (sensuous and quasi-sensuous perception), 34. indriya-pratyaksa (sensuous direct cognition), 30, 34. tryapatha (non-affecting), 252. iryasamiti (regulation of movement), 265 Tsvara, 24, 127. isvara, xx, xxi, defined 140, 142. janai, 63n, 71. janaka, type of karman 250. janma (birth), 102, 107, 154. jaramarana (decay-and-death), 10, 126, 127. jati (birth), 90, 126, 127, category of karman leading to 245. jatinaman, 234. javana (active), 247. Ghana (ecstasy), 248. haya (meditation), 262n. jijnasa (enquiry or inquisitiveness), 40, 297, 301. jina (literally the victor'; one who has attained omniscience), 76. jiva (soul ; individual self), 10, 117, 125, 144, 229. javanmukta (embodied beings free from bondage), 152, 279. jivanmukti (emancipation during life; state of embodied freedom), xx, 143, 144, 276. jnana, 69, problem of the relation between darsana and 70-80, it is extrovert 73, 147, 148, 149, 150, 153, 158, 159, 239. jnana (discriminating knowledge), 93, Toon, pursuit of 107. jnana (consciousness), 297. jnanasakti (power of knowledge). 140. jnanavarana (knowledge-obscuring or knowledge-covering) karman, 61, karman, 61, 70, 71, 76, 78, 144, 150, 232, 252. jnanavaraniya, see jnanavarana. jnanauytti (knowledge-modification), 87. jnanayoga (internal spiritual acti vity), 294. jneya (thing to be known), 166. ineyavurana, nature of 134, 251, kaivalya (self-isolation), 85, roo, IOI. kala (limited power of action), genesis of 143 kala (time), xviii, genesis of 143. 22on. kaliki, 54. See dirghakaliki. kalpita (imagined), 128. kama (sensual pleasure), 47. kamasugati-bhumi, 249. kamavacara (roaming in the world of desires), 248. -bhumi, 249, 250. kamma (action), 18. kamma-vai (believer in karman), 18. kanta (sixth dysti) 300, described 252. 303 karana (process of energy), 254. karana, xxii, meaning of 271. karma (incomprehensible activity of life), 135 Page #357 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 320 INDEX IV karmabhumi (lands where tirthankaras are born), 68. karmadalika (karmic aggregates), 257. karmaja buddhi (intellect developed by practical experience), 45, 46, also called karmiki or karma samuttha 47. defined 47. harma-mala, 142, origin, nature and function of 143, 216. karman, doctrine of 4, law of 5, 7, 15, believer in 18, doctrine of 27, 65, obstructive 75, fruits of karman in Yoga 90, nature and process of karman in Saivism 139, 140, 141, 144, evil will induced by 149, 151, operative 151, 153, doctrine of 204, law of 206, 216, 218, 220, necessity of 221, 224, 226, general function of 228, classification of 232 et seq., intensity of karman defined 236, conditions of the inflow of sinful and virtuous types 243n, Buddhist classification of 250, states and processes of 252, 297. karman (sacrifice), 114. karman (action), 164. karma-pasa, xxi, 138, nature and function of 139, 216. karmaprakrti (karmic matter), 161. karmapudgala (karmic matter), 226, 232. karma-samya, xx. karmasaya (accumulated traces of actions), 244. karmaskandha (karmic matter), 236. karma-vargana, 65, 232n. karma-vijnana (activity conscious ness-the subjective mind), 135. karma-yoga (external spiritual acti vity), 294. karmendriya (motor organs), 143. karuna, 17, 285. karunya (sympathy), 266, 290. kasaya (passions), 147, 153, 168, 221, 222, 223, 226, 235, 39, 274. kasaya-vedaniya, 233. katattakamma, type of karman 250. kayavyuha (plurality of bodies), 152. kevala, see kevala-jnana. kevala-darsana (perfect intuition).. 29, 71, 76, 77, 78, 233, 239. kevala-jnana (pure and perfect knowledge), xviii, xx, 28, 29, 30, 61, 69, 70, 71, 75, 76, 78, 100, 239, 268. kevalin (omniscient), 55, 61, 74, 75, 76, 77. khandha, IO. kheda (inertia), 296, 301. kiriya (barren and inoperative), 247. kiriyam (actionism), 24. kiriya-vai (believer in action), 18. klesa (afflictions), 89, 90, 93, 221, 222. klesavarana, nature of 134, 251, 252. kostha (firmly grasping), 42. kotakoti (a big number), 2700. Also spelled kotikoti. krama (sequence), question of its possibility in omniscience xviii-xix. kriya (will; spiritual discipline), 150. kriyamana (being done), 260. kriyasakti (power of action), xxiii, 140, 217. kriyavadin (believer in moral and spiritual action), 145. kriyayoga, xxii.. krodha (anger), 234. krsna (dark), a category of karman, 245. kysnapaksika, 298. ksapakasreni (ladder of annihilation), described 275-6, 295. ksaya (total dissociation), 258. ksayika-samyagdrsti, 277. ksayopasama (subsidence-cum-destruction), 242, 258, 260, 270n. ksayopasamika, 277. ksepa (unsteadiness), 296, 301. ksetravit, 297. ksinakasaya (twelfth described 278. kula, 264. kulayogin, 304. kundalini, xxii. kusala (moral), 247. -vipaka, 249, 250. labdhi, 55, meaning of 55n, defined 56. labdhi (stages of the achievement of purification), 270n. labdhyaksara, 49. laingika (inferential), 110, 11on. laksana (characteristic), 128. lesya (coloration), defined and classified 253n, 254linga (probans), 77. gunasthana), linga-sarga (subtle physical creation), 930. linga-sarira (subtle body), 222. lobha (greed), 16, 234, 246. loga-vai (believer in world), 18. loka (inhabited universe), 23, meaning of 23n, 63, 280. loka (worldly life), 102. lokuttara bhumi plane), 248. madhuvidya, 117. madhyasthya (supra-mundane (indifference), 285, 290. magga (right path), 144. maggana (margana, searching), 32. mahaggata bhumi (higher grade of consciousness), 248. 137, mahamaya (pure matter), nature of 139, 1390. mahamoha, 93, tenfold 94. mahapathaprayana, 303. mahat, 93, 94. 266, Page #358 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ SANSKRIT, PRAKRIT AND PALI WORDS 321 mahavrata (great vows), 265. Mahesvara (Great Lord), 115. Mahesvara, nature of 137. mai (mati, sensuous cognition). 32. maitri (friendship), 17, 266, 285, 290. mala (taint or contamination), xix, nature of 138, 139, 140, 141, 142, 143, 216. mala-pasa, nature of 138, 140. mana (pride), 234 inanah paryava, 65n. manah paryaya, seemanah paryaya. jnana. manahparyaya-jnana, 65, 65n. manah paryaya-jnana (intuition of mental modes), 28, 29, 30, 61, 65, 66, 66, 67, 670, 68, 69, 69, 71, 75, 77. mana pajjavanana, 65. manas (mind), 31, 32, 35, 62n, 65, 67, 119, 222. manodravya (matter constituting mind), 69. manogupli (control of thought), 265. mano-samphassa (mind-contact), 12. mano-vargana, 65. marganata (searching), 40. mati, see matijnana. mati-ajnana, 71, 147, 149. matijnana (sensuous knowledge), 28, 29, 30, 3on, 32, defined and classified 33, subdivisions of 34, total number of types of 44, 45, 48, 50, 510, 53, 55, its relation with Srutajnana 55-6, 57, 58, 59, 60, 61, 62, 66, 69, 70, 71, 75, 76, 77, 147, 148, 149, 258. matyajnana, see mati-ajnana. matyupayoga, 55. maya, 113, 115, 116, 117, 118, 119, 120, 121, 124, 125, 126, 130, 170, 172, 217, 221, 224. maya (impure matter), 137, nature of 139, 140, 218. -kancukas, xx, xxiii. maya (deceit), 234. mayahastin (elephant called up by illusion), 130. mayapasa, xxi, nature of 139. mayavat, 115. mayin, 115 mayaya-mala, 142, origin, nature and function of 143, 216. medha (retentiveness), 34. medha (gradual awareness), 35. mimarisa (critical evaluation), 297, 301. mithya (vitiated; perverted), 147, 151. mithyabhinivesa (perverted predilec tion), 155. . mithya-caritra (perverse conduct), 147, 151, 153, 155, 161, 219. mithya-darsana (perverse attitude), JP-41 144, categories of 145, 147, 151, 155, 161, 218. mithyadesti (a person of perverted attitude; wrong view), 28, 51, 54, 144, 256. mithyadysti (first gunasthana), des cribed 276. mithya-jnana (perverted knowledge; wrong assessment of values; delusion; nescience; wrong cognition), 83, IOI, 102, defined 103, 107, 121, 147, 151, 153, 155, 161, 162, 166, 219. mithya-Syuta, 50. mithya-sruta (false scripture), 51. mithyatva (wrongness), 50. mithyatva (perverted attitude; per versity; predilection for the untruth), 80, 83. 144, 145, 146, 168n, 218, 219, 239, 241, 256n, 269, 274. mithyatva (vision-deluding) karman, 145, 146, 239, 256, 270n. mithyatvamohaniya karman, 272. mithyatva-pudgala, 256n. mithyatva-vedaniya, 233. mitra (first dysti), 300, described 301-2. moha (delusion ; false belief), 16, 18, 83, 93, eightfold 94, IOI, 103, 127, 128, 144, 145, 166, 167, 168, 247. mohaniya (deluding) karman, 69, 150, 168, 168n, 232, 239. moksa (emancipation), 6, 85, III, 133. mudita, 17. muhurta (forty-eight minutes), 40, 4on, 69, 236. mukhya-pratyaksa (transcendental direct knowledge), 34. mukti (emancipation), 133. mundakevalin, 299. mutta (emancipated), 145. naisargika (inborn) mithyadarsana, defined 145. nama (consciousness; mind), 25, 126, 127, 222, 224, 230. nama (name), 125, 126. nama(body-making)-karman, 233, sub types of 234, 279. nauya (neologician), 61. naya (different attitudes), 29. neva sanna nasanna, 248. nibbana (emancipation), 248, 49. nidhatti, defined 254, 258, 258n, de fined 259. nidra (sleep with easy awakening), nidra-nidra (sleep with difficult awakening), 233 nigodu, xxi, 240. nikacana, defined 254, 258, 258n, defined 259. nikacita (unalterable on account of the process of nikacana), 260. niraksara, 58. 233.. Page #359 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 322 INDEX IV niralambana, 294n. niravarana, 75nirjara (dissociation), 263, 264. nirvana (emancipation), xxii, 13, nature of 15, 131, 132, 136, 149, 152, 2010, 224. niscaya (continued cognition), 42. nispanna (true or real), 128. nispannayogin, 304. nivytti (eighth gunasthana), 277. nivrttikarana, 271n. niyama (self-control), 301. niyatavipaka (with unfailing fruition), 260. niyati (spatial limitation), genesis of 143. niyativada (doctrine of determinism), 2200. niyatti, 2771. no-indriya (quasi-sense), 31. no-indriya-pratyaksa direct knowledge), 30. no-kasaya (quasi-passion), 234, 234n. no-kasaya-vedaniya, 233. oghadrsti (commonplace attitude), 301. (non-sensuous defined to ogha-samjna (instinct), 54. padastha, 288, described 289, 290. pakadanapariyayena (according priority of fruition), 250. palyopama, 236n, 270n. panna (wisdom), 17. panna (wisdom), 32. papa (sinful) karman, 235. 245. karmasaya, 244. para, 296. para (eighth drsti), 300, described 304. parabrahman, 303. paramacaritra (consummate conduct). 161. paramananda (supreme bliss), 296. paramarsa (expression of power), 141. paramartha (absolute reality), 132. paramasiva, nature of 137. Paramasiva (Absolute), nature of 141, at once transcendent and immanent 142, 217. paramatman (transcendental self), 281. parartha (objective and public), 60. paratantra (dependent; causally determined), 128, nature of 129, 131. pariharavisuddhi, 264. parikalpana (imagination), 130. barikalpita (imagined), 128, nature of 129. pariksa (investigation), 40. parinamiki buddhi (mature intellect), 45, 46, defined 48. parinis panna (real nature of 129. parisaha (afflictions), twenty-two 263. jaya, 264. or true), 128, parissava (cause of release), 20. parisuddha pratipatti (clear convic tion), 297, 301. paritta bhumi (plane of weak consciousness), 248. parivartana (repeated study), 283. paroksajnana (indirect knowledge). 28, 30, 34. parthivi dharana, described 288. paryaya (modes or states), 67, 70. pasa (trap), 138, forms of 1390, 140, 221. pasai, 63n, 71. pasanaya, 71. See pasyatta. pasu (animal), 138. pasupati, nature of 137. pasutva (animality), 138, 141. pasutva-vigama, 296. Pasyanti Vak, xix. pasyatta, 71, meaning of 72, problem of its relation with darsana 74. patisandhi (birth), 249. pindastha, described 29on. 288-9, 200, pity (manes), 112. prabha (seventh drsti), 300, described 303. prabhasvara (luminous), 134. pracala (sleep while seated or standing), 233. pracala-pracala (sleep while walking), 233. pradesa (space-point), 63, defined 238n. pradesabandha (space-bondage), defined 238. pradesodaya (non-affecting rise), 259. pradhana, 24. prahina (suppressed), 2010. prajapati, 112. prajna (reasoning), 34. prajna (wisdom), 135, 201n. prakrti (nature), 127. prakrti (principle of matter), 83, 84, 85, 90, 93, 93, 94, 97, 99, 100, 121, 156, multiplicity of prakrtis 157, 158, 159, 161, 166, 170, 222, 224, 226, 227, 228, 297. prakyti, qua maya 115, 126. Prakyti (Absolute), 228, 229, 230. prakrti-bandha (type-bondage), defined 238. pralayakala, defined 140, 142. pramada (unmindfulness; spiritual inertia; carelessness), 18, 147, 264. 274, 275. pramana, 27, samyag-jnana 28, 29, classification of 34, 58, 80. pramata (subject of knowledge), 124. pramatta-samyata (sixth gunasthana), described 277. prameya (objects), 162. pramoda (appreciation), 266, 285, 290. Page #360 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ SANSKRIT, PRAKRIT AND PALI WORDS 323 prana (breath), 229. pranayama (breath-control). 286, 290, 301. prarabdha (in course of fruition; fructifying) karman, 152, 153, 260. prasarkhyana, xxii. prasantavahita, 303, prasupta (dormant). 260. Pratibha, nature of xviii-xix. pratibha (grasp), 33, 34. pratipatti (continued cognition), 42. prati pracchana (critical enquiry), 283 pratipyccha-vyakaraniya (to be ex plained by putting another ques tion), 8. pratistha (fixing), 42. pratit yasamutpada (dependent ori. gination), 126, 201. pratitya-samutpanna (causally deter mined), 130. pratyahara (withdrawal), 287, 290, 301. pratyakhyanavarana, 234, illustra ted 234n, 237, 239n, 274. pratyaksa (perceptual cognition), 110, Tion. pratyaksa-jnana (direct knowledge), 28, 30, 32, proper 62, 67. pratyavartanata (repeated determi nation), 42. pratyaya-sarga (psychical creation), 93, 93n. pravyttacakra, 296. pravrttacakra yogin, 304. pravytti (volitional activity; merits and demerits born of volitional activity), TOI, 102, 107. pravytti, 297. pravytti (practice), 294, 297, 301. prayascitta (expiation), ninefold 264. prayogya, meaning of 270n. preksana (prolonged vision), 71. preta (devils), 112. preyas (covetable), 6. priti (love), 294 prthagiana, xxii. -citta, 296. pythaktva-vitarka-savicara, described monistic Saivism 143, 154, 155, 269. rajas, 90, 92, 93, 229. rasa, 235n. rasabhaga (unit of intensity), 236, 236n, 237. rasaghata, 272, 278. vaudyadhyana, 281n. yddhi (extraordinary powers), 68. rjumati, 66, 68. rjusutra (analytic standpoint), 8o. rodha-takti (power of obscuration), 139n, 140. Rta, conception of 5. ruci (predilection), ajna , nisarga sutra-, and avagadha- 283n. ruk (mental disturbance), 296, 301. rupa (material form; body), II, 13, 25, 126, 127, 222, 226, 230. ruba (form), 25, 26, 248n.. rupa (coloured shape), 35. rupastha, 288, described 289, 290. rupatita, 288, described 289, 290. rupavacara, defined 248. --bhumi, 249, 250. sabdadvaita (verbal monism), 202. sabda-jnana (verbal cognition), 60. sadasat-khyati, 99. sadasiva, defined 140, 142, 303. sadayatana (the six sense-organs), 126, 127. saddysti, 301. sadhu (ascetic), 264, 265. sadika (having beginning), 48, 51. sadvedya (what causes pleasant feel ing), 233, 256. sagaro pama, 236, 236, 270n. sahaja (natural). 141. sahetuka (determined by conditions), 247 sahopalambhaniyama (necessity of being known together) 209. sahu (saint), 145. sai (smyti, memory), 32. saiksa (ascetic student). 264. sakada gamin (once-returner), 249. sakala, defined 140, 142. sa kara (determinate), 70, 71. saksara, 58. Sakti (energy: power), 126, 141, 221. sakti-daridra (devoid of powers), 143. salambana, 294n. salesya (accompanied with colora tion), 253 samadhi (meditation ; ecstasy), xxii, 17, 106, 107, III, 152, 153, 161, 200, 262n, 296, 301. --yoga, xxii. samadhi-prayatnoparjita (acquired through effort), 141. samanojna (associate), 264. samanya (general feature ; universal), 38, 164. samarasibhava, 287. samarthyayoga, defined 300. samata (absolute sameness), 134. samata (a stage of yoga), 297, 299. 292. pudgala-nairatmya (the unreality of the individual ego), 134 pudgala paravarta, defined 298n. punya (virtuous) karman, 235, 245. punya-karmasaya, 244. Purusa (Absolute), 114, 297. purusa (self), 83, 84, 84, 85, 86, 87, 88, 89, 97, TOO, 152, 155, 156, 157, 158, 159, 160, 161, 222, 226, 229, 230, 251, 297. Purusadvaita (monism of Purusa), 202. purvakoti (a big number), 279. purvaseva, 298. raga (attachment), 89, 90, 94, IOI. genesis of the principle of raga in Page #361 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 324 samatva (equanimity), 289. samavaya (inherence), 163. samaya (time-point), 63. samayika (desisting from harmful activities), 264. sambhava (probability), 34. 50, samhanana (physical structure), 292. sumiti (regulation of activities; selfregulation), fivefold 263, 264. sumina (cognitional activity), nature and types of, 53-5. samjnaksara, 49. samjnin (discursive or cognitive or scriptural), 48. samjni-sruta, three ways of the consideration of 50, 53. samjualana (effective only occasionally), 234, illustrated 234n, 237, 274. samkhyeya (countable), 42. samkramana (process of transformation), 254, 255, 256, 260. samma-ajiva (proper means of livelihood), 16. samma-ditthi (right view), 16. samma-kammanta (proper action), samma-samadhi (proper meditation), samma-samkappa (right resolution), 16. summa-sati (mindfulness in the right way), 16. samma-vaca (proper words), 16. samma-vayama (proper exertion), 16. sammurchanaja (gross-bodied beings born without sex relation), 54samparayika (affecting), 252. samprajnata samadhi, 295. samsara (worldly life; metempsychosis), 102, 103, III, 128, 135, 136, 154. samsaya (doubt), differentiated from iha 41, 110, 11on, mithyadarsana, defined 145. samsayika (sceptic) mithyadarsana, defined 145. 16. 16. INDEX IV samskara (trace), 43, 44, IOI. samskara (coefficients of consciousness; predispositions), 11, 16, 126, 127, 128. samsrsta (related), 123. samudghata, 280, 280n. samvara (spiritual discipline), 150. samvara (stoppage of karmic inflow), 263, 264. sumvega (fear), 266. samurti, function of 128. samurti satya (empirical truth), 128. samuyavahara-pratyaksa (empirically direct and immediate), 28, 30, 34. samyagdarsana (right attitude; predilection for truth; enlightenment; spiritual vision), xxii, 146, 147, meaning of 148, nature of 149, 151, 155, 266, 267, 268, first awakening of 269-73. samyagdrsti, 54, 256, 300. samyag-jnana (right knowledge), 27, 146, 147, 148, 149, 151, 161, 165, 266. samyag-mithya-drsti (third gunasthana), described 277. samyag-mithyatva (right-cum-wrong belief), 256, explained 256n. samyak (right), 48, 147, 149, 151. samyakcaritra (right conduct), 146, 147, 149, 151, 153, 166. samyak-sruta (right scripture), 50. samyktua, 50, 80, 144, 146, distinguished from sruta 148, love of truth 239, 241, 256, explained 256n, first dawn of 273. samyaktva-vedaniya, 233. samyama (restraint and discipline). 150. sancita (stored), 260. sangha (community), fourfold 264. sanghata (conglomeration), 117. sangraha (synthetic standpoint), 80. sanjna (perception), II, 16, 128. (Also spelled samjna). sanjna (recognition), 34sankhara, 10, II, 14. See samskaru (coefficients of consciousness). sanklesa (afflictions) 131, 132, 133. sanmatradarsanam (intuitional cog nition of pure existence), 39. sanna (recognition), 32. sanna (instincts), 52. See samjna. sanna (perception; knowing), 11, 14, 247. See sanjna (perception). Santa (quiet), 296. santirana (investigating ness), 249. conscious saparyavasita (having end), 48, 51. saptabhangi (sevenfold predication), 29. sarga (creation), 93, nine types of 930. sarira-naman, 234. sarirastha, 290n. sarva-ghatin (completely obscuring) karman, 239, 240. sarvakartrtva (omnipotence), 138. sarvavirati-caritra (capacity for full renunciation), 241. sasana (teaching), 17. sassatavada, 9. Sastra (scriptures), 218. sastrayoga, defined 300. sasvadana-samyagdrsti (second guna sthana), described 276-7. sasvatavada (eternalism), 10, 22. sat, 4, 228. satavedaniya, see sadvedya. satkaryavada (theory which affirms. the pre-existence of the effect in the cause), 158. satta (existence), 73, 164. Page #362 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ SANSKRIT, PRAKRIT AND PALI WORDS satta (endurance of a karman), 255, defined 259. sattva, 90, 92, 229. sattvananda, 296. sattvika, 93. satya (truth), 243. sauca (purification), 92. savitarka, 291. sayoga-kevalin sthana), described 279. siddhatman, 303. Siddhi, xx, xxi. siddhi (consummation of knowledge), 94. (thirteenth siksavrata, 265. sila (good conduct), 17. sila, 265. Siva, nature of 137, 138, 140. siva, 141, 142. sivatva (perfection; divine nature), 138, 140, 141, 142. guna siva-vartman, 303. sivodaya, 296. siyavaya, 22. slista (collected), 290. smrti (recollection), 32, 34, 43, 110. smrti (past experiences of many previous lives; creative instinctive incipient memory), 134, 135, 136. sobhana (good), 247. sota panna, defined 248. spardhaka (intensity-class), 236, 237. sparsa (contact), 126, 127. sraddhana, meaning of 148, 239. sravana (attentive hearing), 297, 301. sravanata (hearing), 34. sreni (ladder), 284. sreyas (good), 6. sruta, see sruta-jnana. sruta-ajnana, 71, 147, 149. srutajnana, see sruta-ajnana. sruta-jnana (scriptural or verbal knowledge), 28, 29, 30, 34, original meaning and varieties of 48, conditions of 49, 50, 51n, development of the conception of 53, 53n, 55. its relation with mati-jnana 55-6, 57, 58, 59, 60, 61, 62, 69. 70, 71, 75, 77, 147, distinguished from samyaktva 148, 149. srutanisrita (backed by scriptural learning), 44, 45, 46. sruti (revelation), 185. srutopayoga (verbal knowledge) 55. 60. sthairya (stability), 294. sthana (proper posture), 293, 294. sthapana (placing), 42. sthapaniya (to be set aside), 8. sthavira (elderly), 264. sthira (fifth drsti), 300, described 303. sthiti (duration), 235, 256. sthitibandha (bondage of duration), 168n. sthitighata, 272, 278. 325 styanagrddhi (sleep accompanied with superhuman deeds), 233. styanardhi, see styanagrddhi." subha (auspicious) karman, 235, 245. suddhadhvan, 142. suddha vidya, 140, 216. suddhi (purification), 133. sukha (pleasure), 162. sukla (white), a category of karman, 245. sukladhyana, 150, 153, 279, described 291-3, characteristic signs of 293. sukla-krsna, 245n. suklapaksika, 298. suksmakriya-nivartin, described 292. suksmasamparaya, 264, tenth gunasthana described 278. sulina (merged), 290. sunna (voidity or substancelessness), 12. sunya (devoid of intrinsic reality), 129, 132. sunyata (negation of duality), 131. susamsthana (possessed of well-proportioned body), 286. susrusa (love for listening), 297, 301. svabhava (nature), 220n. svadhyaya (study), fivefold 264. sva-gopana (self-concealment), 141. svapna (dream-cognition), 110, IIon. svartha (subjective and private), 59. svasana dharana, described 288. sva-sankoca (self-limitation), 141. svayambhu (the self-subsistent prin ciple who has all the conditions of self-existence in himself), 114. syadvada, 22. taijasa (luminous), 65. tamas, 90, 92, 93, eightfold 94, 229. tamasa, 93. tamisra, 93, eighteenfold 94. tanmatra or tanmatra (subtle elements), 94, 230. tantra (dependent), 128. tanu (incipient), 260. tapas (austerity, penance), 92, 114, 150, 220, 264. tapasvin (ascetic), 264. tara (second drsti), 300, described 302. tarka (reasoning), 40. tathagata, 13, 14, 135. -garbha, 135. tathata, 134, 135, 303. tattvajnana (knowledge of the truth), 152, 153, 166. tattvaruci (predilection for the truth), 148. tattvarupavati dharana, 288. tavatimsa, 249. tirodhana-Sakti (obscuring power), 140. tirthakrttva (potency of revealing the truth and establishing religious community), 268. Page #363 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 326 INDEX IV sire; will to desires). 43 2021, 203 tirthankara, xx, xxi, 68, 76, nature of 268-9, 299. tiryagloka (animal world'; mid region), 288. tri-sthanika, 236, defined 237. trsna (craving), 16, 126, 127, 128. turya (the transcendental state of the self called the fourth state), 125. tusti (idle complaisance), 93. ucchedavada, 9, 10, 22. udara (operative), 260. udatta (noble). 296. udaya (coming into effect; rise) 255, 258, defined 259, 260. udayavalika, defined 257. udirana (process of premature reali zation), 254, 256, 258. udvartana (process of increased rea lization), 254, defined 257. udvega (anxiety), 296, 301. uha (reasoning), 40. uha (instinct), 54. upadana (clinging), 126, 127. upadharanata (holding), 34. upadhyaya (preceptor), 264. upaghataka (overpowering), type of karman 250, 251. 2 palabdhi (perception), 34. upamana (analogy) 34. upamiti (analogy), 34. upapajjavedaniya, 250, 251. upa pilaka (what thwarts), type of karman, 250, 251. upasama (subsidence), 258, 260. upasamana (process of subsidence), 254, defined 258. upasamasreni (ladder of subsidence), described 275-6. upasantadhvan, 270n. upasanta-kasaya-vitaraga-chadmustha (eleventh gunasthana) described 278. upatthambhaka (what sustains), type of karman 250. upayoga, 55, meaning of 55n, defined 56, 70, 71, 72, 74. upekkha-sahagata (accompanied by indifference), 249 upeksa (indifference), 17. urna (correct utterance of sound), 293, 294. utthana (distraction), 296, 301. vacana (exposition), 283. vaikriya (subtle), 65, 69, 234. vainayika (credulous person), 145, mithyadarsana defined 145 vainayiki buddhi (intellect born of faithful service), 45, 46, defined 47. vairagya (indifference), toon, 266. vaiyarthya (redundancy), 60. vaiyavyttya (respectful service). 264. vajrakaya (having strong physical structure), 286. vargana (group), 65, 69, 236. varuni dharana, described 288. vasana (mental trace ; deep-rooted desire; will to live; predispositions; accumulated desires), 43, 44, 85n, 103, 127, 130, 201, 202, 202n, 203, 221, 222, 245 vedana (feeling), 11, 14, 16, 126, 127, 128, 247. vedaniya (feeling-producing) karman, 232, 239, 279. vedyasarvedya pada, 302. venaiya (upholders of non-discrimi nation), 25 vibhajjavaya (conditional expressions), 21, 22. vibhajyavada, 21. vibhajya-vyakaraniya (to be ex plained by making a division), 8, 21. vibhanga, 71, 147. vicarana (thinking), 40. vicaya (meditation), 283. vicchinna (interrupted), 260. vidhmatadipa, 296. vidya (right cognition), IIO. vidya (suddha), defined 140. vidya (asuddha), genesis of 143. vidya pramata, 141, 142. vijnana (consciousness, seed-consciousness), II, 16, 126, 127, 128, 226. See vinnana. vijnana (cognition of object), argu ment to prove the non-existence of Izon. vijnana (waves of mentality), 135. vijnana (determinate cognition), 42. vijnanadvaita (monism of conscious. ness), 202. vijnanakala, defined 140, 141. vijnanavada, 202n. viksepa (projection), xx. viksipta (scattered), 290. vimamsa (vimarsa, enquiry), 32. vimarsa (enquiry), 40. vinaya (non-discrimination), 25. vinaya (humility), fourfold 264. vinnana, 10, II, 14. See vijnana. vipaka (resultant), 247. vipaka (fruition), 283. vipakodaya (affecting rise), 240, 242, 259. viparita mithyadarsana, defined 145 viparyasa (perversion), 128. viparyaya (perversion; perverted cog nition), 83, 93, Mathara's definition of 93n, sub-categories of 94, Vijnanabhiksu's differentiation between the Yoga and the Sankhya conceptions of 95 et seq., 100, ITO, III, 153, 154, 155. 222. vipulamati, 66, 68. viraga (non-attachment), 93. virati (abstention from harinful acts), 239. virya (energy), 252, types of 253, 255 viryantaraya (energy-obstructing kar man, 242, 246. Page #364 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ SANSKRIT, PRAKRIT AND PALI WORDS 327 visabhagapariksaya, 303. visesa (particular), 164. visuddhi (purification), 270n. visvatmaka (immanent), 142. visvottirna (transcendent), 142. vitarka, defined 291. viveka (discrimination), 97 vivekaja-jnana, xviii, xxi. vivekakhyati, 98. vivekakhyati (realization of differ ence), 99. vytti (modification or function), 87. vyttisamksaya (a stage of yoga), 297, 300. vyanjana, defined 36. vyanjanaksara, 49. vyanjanavagraha (contact-awareness). 35, 36, 37, 38, 40, 44, 45, 45n, vyavacchinnakriya pratipatin, describ ed 292. vyavadana (freedom from afflictions), 132, 133 vyavahara-naya (empirical stand point), 80. vyutsarga (renunciation), 265. yajna (sacrifice), 220. vama (vows), 301. vatayata (scattered-cum-collected), 290. yathakhyata (perfect), 264. yathapravittakarana, xxi, nature and function of 269-72, 275, 302. yoga (self-concentration), III, 144, 153, 248, general meaning 262, evolution of its meaning 262n, function of 282, Hemacandra's conception of 289, object and pur pose of 297 yoga (activity; vibration), 147, 153, 222, 232, 235, 238, 239, 243, 252, defined 252n, 254, defined 254n, 255, 266, 267, 274. yagabija, 302. yogadysti, 301. yogaja-pratyaksa (transcendental per ception), 32. yoga-sarnyasa, 300. yogavacara (practitioner in vogu), 248. yogin, described 286. yogi-pratyaksa, Iton. 46. Page #365 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Page #366 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________