Book Title: Anusandhan 2010 03 SrNo 50 2
Author(s): Shilchandrasuri
Publisher: Kalikal Sarvagya Shri Hemchandracharya Navam Janmashatabdi Smruti Sanskar Shikshannidhi Ahmedabad

View full book text
Previous | Next

Page 199
________________ १९२ 31HRI 40(?) norm application, thus safeguarding both generalisability and contextual determinateness, while maintaining a perspective of disengagement with the world and non-specific positive duties. The second main difference between the two types of discourse ethics concerns the moral division of labour presupposed by Jain norms of discourse, which privileges institutionally verified competent speakers or āpta. In contrast to universal pragmatics, Jain discourse ethics is not concerned with questions of human justice, but with the negative freedom of the individual. Footnotes The earliest formulations of this maxim in the Āgamas use the expression musa-vāya veramanam (S. mrsā-vāda viramana), cessation of telling lies. Like SCHUBRING (2000 § 171: 301), BRUHN (2003: 8) notes: “The concept of "truth” is not uniform. But there are several references to the kasāya.s as the root of undesirable speech”. 2 This approach, which informs the following analysys, goes back to Peirce, Royce and Mead, and was further developed by APEL (1973) and HABERMAS (1980). The principal analytical question is not: What does it mean to understand an intention? But: What does it mean to understand a speech act? Universal pragmatics focuses not only on speech acts but on the normative presuppositions of 'linguistically mediated interaction' and on the social function of speech for the coordination of action. Building upon the work of analytical philosophers such as WITTGENSTEIN (1953), AUSTIN (1962), GRICE (1975), SEARLE (1969) and sociolinguists such as GUMPERZ (1964) and HYMES (1972), HABERMAS (1980) distinguishes three universal validity claims presupposed by every communicative action: truth', 'rightness' and 'truthfulness'. 3 Āyāra 2.4.1.4: aha bhikkhu jāņejjā cattāri bhāsā-jāyāim, tam jahă-saccam egam padhamam bhāsa-jāyam, biyam mosam, taiyam saccămosam, jam n'eva saccam n'eva mosam ņ’eva sacca-mosam-asaccănosam ņāma tam cauttham bhāsā-jāyam. CAILLAT (1991: 8 n.4) located the following parallels to the above sūtra in the Śvetâmbara canon: Utt 24.20–23, Thāņa 4.23 (238), Viy 13.7.la (621a-b), Pannavaņā 11 (860866). See also Viy 16.2.2b (701a), 18.7.1 (749a), 19.8 (770b), Samavāya 13.1, and DVS 7.1-3. OHIRA (1994: 14, 155) is of the opinion that the Jain Education International 2010_03 For Private & Personal Use Only www.jainelibrary.org

Loading...

Page Navigation
1 ... 197 198 199 200 201 202 203 204 205 206 207 208 209 210 211 212 213 214 215 216 217 218 219 220 221 222 223 224 225 226 227 228 229 230 231 232 233 234 235 236 237 238 239 240 241 242 243 244 245 246 247 248 249 250 251 252 253 254 255 256 257 258 259 260 261 262 263 264 265 266 267 268 269 270