Book Title: Essence Of Jaina Scriptures
Author(s): Jagdish Prasad Jain
Publisher: Kaveri Books
Catalog link: https://jainqq.org/explore/022313/1

JAIN EDUCATION INTERNATIONAL FOR PRIVATE AND PERSONAL USE ONLY
Page #1 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Essence of Jaina Scriptures Pravachanasara of Kundakunda with Tattvadipika Commentary by Amrtachandra Suri Edited with an Introduction by Jagdish Prasad Jain Page #2 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Pravachanasara by Kundakunda contains the Essence of Divine Discourses or the Jaina Scriptures, which contain the teachings of Lord Mahavira - the last of the 24 Tirthankaras. This volume discusses the fundamental concepts of Jainism, including the definition of dharma, the nature of the self, equanimity, the pure (shuddha), good (shubha) and evil (ashuba) conscious attentiveness, morality and spirituality, the issue of compassion, the concepts of svaymabhu and omniscience, the relation between soul and knowledge, the principle of knowledge and the principle of the knowable, including jiva, internal and external aspects of conduct, the dual role of moral virtues, non-violence, nonpossessiveness, the mechanism of bondage, and the path to attain liberation. The extensive introduction presents and clarifies these concepts in their proper perspective and dispels misperceptions and misrepresentations of both Indian and foreign scholars, including Kanjipanthi and W.J. Johnson as well as Amrtachandra and Jayasena — the two Sanskrit commentators of Pravachanasara. The book will be useful to scholars and students of Indian philosophy and religion, particularly Jainism. Page #3 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Essence of Jaina Scriptures Pravachanasara of Kundakunda Page #4 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BY THE SAME AUTHOR FUNDAMENTALS OF JAINISM SALVATION THROUGH SELF-DISCIPLINE: NIYAMSARA OF KUNDAKUNDA THE ART AND SCIENCE OF SELF-REALIZATION: PRUSHARTHA-SIDDHYUPAYA OF AMRTACHANDRA SURI THE ENLIGHTENED VISION OF THE SELF: SVARUPA SAMBODHANA OF AKALANKA DEVA (EDITOR) SPIRITUAL ENGLIGHTENMENT: PARAMATMA PRAKASH OF YOGINU DEVA (EDITOR) SPIRITUAL INSIGHTS: ISHTOPADESH AND SAMADHI SHATAK OF PUJYAPADA (EDITOR) Page #5 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Essence of Jaina Scriptures Pravachanasara of Kundakunda with Tattvadipika Commentary by Amrtachandra Suri Edited with an Introduction by Jagdish Prasad Jain 2014 Kaveri Books New Delhi - 110002 Page #6 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reprodced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photucopy, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of the Author. First Published in 2014 © Jagdish Prasad Jain ISBN: 978-81-7479-163-4 Published by Kaveri Books 4832/24, Ansari Road New Delhi-110002 (India) Tel: 011-23288140, 23245799 E-mail : kaveribooks@vsnl.com kaveribooks@gmail.com Website: www.kaveribooks.com Typeset in AGarment Font at Delta Book World, New Delhi - 110 002. PRINTED IN INDIA Page #7 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Dedicated to Shrimati Shakuntala Devi Jain and Late Shri Madan Lal Jain Jain Familiy Trust Page #8 --------------------------------------------------------------------------  Page #9 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Contents Abbreviations Preface 1 Introduction by Jagdish Prasad Jain Kundakunda and His Works 1/Two Recensions of Pravachanasara 2/ Additional Verses in Jayasena's Recension 3/Problems in Translation of Old Scriptures 9/Significant Concepts in Pravachanasara: An Appraisal 10/The Concept of Equanamity (Samya) 11/Transcendental Nature of the Soul 151 Characteristics of Equanamity 16/Definition of Dharma 18/Nature of Dharista 19/Nature of the Self or Soul 20/ Parinamika Bhava 22/ Jiva Nikaya 24/ Bhava and Dravya-pranas 26/Pure Nature of the Soul 29/Jayasena's Faulty Explanation of Pure 31/Upayoga 351 Chetana and Upayoga are not the Same 37/Three Kinds of Upayoga 39/ Evolvent Nature of the Soul 44/Importance of Upayoga compared with Mindfulness in Buddhism 46/The Issue of Shuddha, Shubha and Ashubha Upayoga 47/Mistaken View of Kanjipanthi in Equating Shubha and Ashubha 48/ Shubha is preferable to Ashubha 54 /Shuddha and Shubha Upayoga 62/ Shuddha, Shubha and Ashubha in Other Works of Kundakunda 64/ Shubha and Ashuba in Panchastikayasara 691 Shubha and Ashuba in Other Jain Texts 71/Dual Role of Shubha 80/ Mokshamarg Prakashak 81/Morality and Spirituality 851 Overall Appraisal of Shubha 86/Dual Role of Shubha 88/Misperceptions and Distortions of Kanjipanthi regarding Shubha Punya 90 /The Page #10 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ VIII THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Characteristics of Infatuation (Moha) and Issue of Compassion PS (85) 97/Different Works and Scholars on Compassion 97/Compassion and Infaturation are Different 103/Compassion and Non-violence 104/Amrtachandra's Comment on Compassion 107/Circumstances in which Compassion could be Deluding 108/Jayasena's Commentary on Compassion 113/Distorted Views of Kanjipanthi on Compassion 113/Concept of Svayambhu (Self-Sufficient) 116/Concept of Omniscience (Sarvajnata) 116/The Exposition of Knowledge 117/Relation between the Soul and Knowledge 118/Misplaced Criticisms of Kundakunda by I.C. Shastri 119/Jaina Concept of Soul and its Relation to Knowledge 124/ The Exposition of Joy 126/The Exposition of knowlable (Jneya) 127/Definition of Substance 129/Misperceptions of Kanjipanthi concerning Substance and Mode 133/The Mechanism of Bondage 135/ Nishchaya and Vyavahara Points of View 138/Material Karman and Psychic States 141/Psychophysical Parallelism 145/Internal and External Aspects 146/The Concept of Non-violence (ahimsa) in Pravachanasara 148/Greater Emphasis on Psychic Dispositions 149/ Tattvartha Sutra on Non-violence 151/ Dual Role of Moral Virtues 153/Conduct in Pravachanasara 156/Exposition of Good Psychic-attention (Shubha Upayoga) 161/Meaning of Samana 163/Faulty Criticism of Johnson of Kundakunda's Views on Conduct 164/ Nishchaya and Vyavahara Charitra (Conduct) 166/The Path of Liberation 169/Distortion of the Path of Liberation by Kanjipanthi 174/Faulty View of Bronkhorst regarding Liberation 175/Mistaken Concept of Non-doership or Inactive Self of Kanjipanthi 177/Samvara and Nirjara are Essential for Liberation 184/Kanji's Distortion of Pure Psychic-attention 186/Active and Evolvent Aspect of the Self 189/Notes 191 201 Translator's Preface Introductory Remarks by E.W. Thomas 2. Summary of Significant Concepts by A. N. Upadhye 203 208 Page #11 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CONTENTS 267 Book I: The Principle of Knowledge Benedictory Verses (Verses 1-5) 217 Self and its States-of-Evolution (Verses 6-12) 219 Pure, Psychic-attention (Verses 13-20) 222 Exposition of Knowledge (Verses 21-52) 226 Exposition of Joy (Verses 53-68) 244 Good (Shubha) Psychic-attention (Verses 69-92) 253 Book II: The Principle of the Knowable Substance in General (Verses 93-126) 268 Substance in Particular (Verses 127-144) 304 Distinctive Feature of Jiva Substance (Verses 145-200) 318 Book III: The Conduct Conduct including Negligence (Verses 201-231) 346 The Path of Liberation (Verses 232-244) 365 Good (Shubha) Psychic-attention (Verses 245-270) 375 The Five Jewels (Verses 271-275) 385 Gathas given only in Tatparya-vrtti of Jayasena Appendix: Concerning 47 Points of View regarding the Self Notes Prakrit Text 345 388 392 401 419 Glossary Name Index Title Index Word Index Subject Index 445 454 457 459 478 Page #12 --------------------------------------------------------------------------  Page #13 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ List of Abbreviations AC AM BA DS JS KK MMP NN NS Outl. Pk. PKS PP PS Kalash PSU RKS SAS Amrtachandra Apta Mimansa of Samantabhadra Baras Anuvekkha of Kundakunda Dravya Sangraha of Nemichandra Jayasena Kundakunda Moksha Marg Prakashak of Pandit Todarmal Nishchaya Naya Niyamsara of Kundakunda Outlines of Jainism by Jagmander Lal Jaini (J.L.Jaini) Prakrit Panchastikayasara of Kundakunda Pramatma Prakash of Yogindu Deva Pravachanasara Kalash of Amrtachandra Purusharthasiddhyupaya of Amrtachandra Ratna Karanda Shravakachara of Samantabhadra Savarthasiddhi Commentary on Tattvartha Sutra (TS) of Pujyapada Sanskrit Samayasara of Kundakunda Tattvarta Rajvarttika Commentary on Tattvartha Sutra (TS) of Akalanka Tattvarta Sutra of Umasvami or Umasvati Tattvarta Sholka Varttika of Vidyananda Vyavahara Naya Sk. SS TRV TS TSV VN Page #14 --------------------------------------------------------------------------  Page #15 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Preface Acharya Kundakunda, the author of Pravachanasara, is one of the greatest philosophers and foremost spiritual thinkers of the world. Being a multifaceted personality, he was an outstanding thinker, reformer, organizer, philosopher, teacher, poet, saint as well as a living legend. His importance within both Jainism and the Jaina philosophical tradition is incomparable. In fact, in the Digambara sect of Jains, he is revered next only to Lord Mahavira and his apostle Gautam Ganadhara. As the leader of Mula Sangha (basic ascetics), he was indeed the most prominent. The origin of almost all the lineages of the Digambara monks is therefore traced to Kundakunda. Though Kundakunda occupies a very prominent place in Jainism and commands the highest respect, the literature on his life continues to be both scant and controversial. The existing literature contains numerous legends and is replete with incredible miracles, exaggerations, contradictions and inconsistencies. For instance, the Epigraphic Carnatica states that due to his excellent religious conduct, Kundakunda possessed miraculous power to move in the air four fingers above the ground. There is also a controversy about Kundakunda's air travel to Videh where he is said to have directly heard the divine discourses of the omniscient Lord (Tirthankara) Simandhara Swami. Different views are also prevalent regarding the dates of his life, which range from 108 BC to 5th-6th century A.D. A. N. Upadhye however maintains that Kundakunda flourished in the beginning of the Christian era. The real name of Kundakunda is said to be Padmanandi. According to Shrutasagar's commentary on Bodh Prabhrat, Kundakunda was also known as Vakragreeve, Elacharya and Graddhapichha. Kundakunda Page #16 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ XIV THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES is said to have had a number of preceptors (gurus). These include shruta kevali Bhadrabahu (see Bodh Prabhrat, verses 61-62), Kumarnandi Siddhantadeva (see Jayasena's observation in Panchastikayasara), or Jinbhadra (see Nandisangha's Pattavali). All these descriptions, beliefs or opinions about the life of Kundakunda are based on pattavalis, rock inscriptions or eulogies in books written in the 10th century or thereafter. These books are not historical biographies in the modern sense of the term. In fact, till today we do not have absolutely reliable materials from which it is possible to reconstruct the life or writings of Kundakunda with any degree of certainty. Five of his works, viz. Panchastikayasara (PKS), Samayasara (SS), Pravachanasara (PS), Niyamasara (NS), and Baras Anuvekkha (BA) (Twelve Reflections or Affirmations may be safely ascribed to him. Of these five treatises, the first three have been commented upon in Sanskrit by Amrtachandra in the tenth century and by Jayasena in the thirteenth century, which contains a number of interpolations (in Jayasena's recension)? However, Kundakunda's authorship of Ashta Pahuda, Rayanasara, Kurah etc. is disputed. All of Kundakunda's works have been written in Shaurseni Prakrit. The treatise Pravachanasara (Pavayanasara in Prakrit the name of treatise mentioned in PS 275) has been written by Acharya Kundakunda. The word “pravachan” consists of pra+vachan in which“ pra” means "prakrisht”, i.e. the best, the excellent and immaculate, while “vachan" means description, exposition or instruction. And sara means the essence. In reality, such pravachan can only be delivered by those who are pure and perfect, and by those who have conquered all their shortcomings, limitations and impurities of deluded view, attachment, aversion, etc. They can be delivered only by those who know the reality of things since they are imbued with a desire to foster the well-being of all living beings. The Tirthankaras are the promulgators of dharma-tirtha (the path of dharma), i.e. the rules and guidelines for the well-being and the moral and spiritual upliftment of living beings through their discourses (pravachana or sermons) which are the source of scriptures (Jinvani or Jain Agama). These scriptures provided invaluable insights into the reality of things and provide guidance to all living beings even when Tirthankaras or Jinas are not available. Pravachanasara, thus, contains the “Essence of Divine Discourses”, Page #17 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PREFACE XV i.e. the essence of the sermons or the teachings of Lord Mahavira — the last of the 24 Tirthankaras. These teachings are said to have been organized subject-wise, in a systematic manner by his apostle Gautam and have been preserved for generations through being memorized by the learned people of both the Digambara and Shvetambara sects of Jains. These teachings were later enshrined/encoded in the canons/ scriptures of the two sects. Kundakunda inherited these teachings and his work Pravachanasara, therefore, contains the Essence of Divine Discourses, i.e. sermons or the Essence of the Jain Scriptures. The treatise is based on the solid foundation of the scriptures or Jain texts and the principles contained therein. Kundakunda was not only well-versed in Jain scriptures, but was imbued with a mission to communicate the spiritual knowledge of the Tirthankaras to his readers. He was also well versed in other systems of philosophy as well as psychology, ethics, spiritualism and social aspects that facilitate a better understanding of human life in all its ramifications. All of Kundakunda's works have been written in Prakrit. They are full of enlightening wisdom and contain deep insights of the inner recesses of human nature. Being an excellent poet, he had the creative ability (pratibha) or the intellectual capacity of expressing new ideas and interpreting things in his own inimitable style. One may encounter certain 'difficulties in understanding Kundakunda's works, especially if the reader proceeds from a purely analytical, descriptive and objective perspective. Things that were quite clear to him may not seem so to the lay reader. The reader must therefore have the intellectual ability to understand the inner meaning to see the hidden insights and to experience the enlightening wisdom himself. Kundakunda never wanted to impose his views, ideas or concepts on readers on the authority of the Revealed Word (the scriptures) of the Lord. He also did not ask people to accept his description of the reality because it is based on his own experience. He wanted people to read, listen, think, critically examine, and never to suspend their own judgment because one should accept them only after verification by one's own experience (SS 5). This is similar to what Buddha said: “Don't take my word for it; find out for yourself.” Pravachanasara discusses important concepts such as the definition of dharma (PS 6), the nature of the self (PS 7 and 192), equanimity (PS 7 and 24), jnayaka bhava (something that is essentially of knowing Page #18 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ XVI THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES nature) (PS 200 and 35), the pure and good or auspicious conscious attentiveness, and the bad effects of evil or inauspicious psychic disposition (PS 11-14, 45, 69-79, 85, 92, 208-221, 236-240, 245270). It also discusses the concepts of omniscience (PS 15-20), svayambhu (self-evolved enlightenment) (PS 16), knowledge (PS 2158), the exposition of joy (PS 53-68), including sensorial pleasure, and of the knowable substance, including jiva, both in general (PS 93126) and particular aspects (127-144), the mechanism of bondage (PS 169-189), and the path of liberation (PS 232-244), good conscious attentiveness (PS 245-270), the concepts of ahimsa (non-violence), aparigraha (non-possessiveness) and the conduct of samana (noble, selfrestrained person), etc. My appraisal of the significant concepts contained in Pravachanasara is given in the extensive Introduction, in which I have sought to present these concepts in their proper perspective in order to dispel misperceptions that readers may have. The detailed Introduction is extremely useful in dispelling various misrepresentations/distortions of Kundakunda's ideas by scholars of other religions, who lack a proper understanding of Jain principles and Jain scholars. These include some biased Shvetambara and Kanjipanthi scholars of the Digambara sect, who tend to take a one-sided, distorted view of Kundakunda's basic concepts. Among these, we may include many other well-meaning scholars of the Digambara sect, who have translated and commented in different languages and have given different interpretations. It also includes several foreign scholars like W.J. Johnson, who has created considerable confusion about Kundakunda's works, especially Samayasara and Pravachanasara. The subject matter of Pravachanasara is serious, subtle, and profound requiring thoughtful investigation. In order to properly comprehend it, it is necessary for one to be a dedicated reader and one need not necessarily be an ascetic as is sometimes mistakenly believed. Repetitions are inevitable in a work of this nature especially as one seeks to clarify the issues and remove the misperceptions pertaining to the essential concepts dealt with in this superb treatise. In fact, repetitions are said to be characteristics of all Indian spiritual and philosophical treatises. The critical reader may not appreciate them, but the assiduous sadhaka (spiritual seeker) will value them immensely. Page #19 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PREFACE XVII Pravachanasara is composed in Prakrit, which was once the common language of the people However, it is almost a dead language now. This poses serious problems. Even the first commentary thereon by Amrtachandra in Sanskrit (which again is understood by few people and is not understood by lay men) was written after nine centuries when Prakrit was neither spoken nor written. One cannot say with any certainty how proficient Amrtachandra was in Prakrit. It is very likely that he wrote his commentary on the basis of the Sanskrit rendering of Prakrit gathas (verses). It is therefore not surprising that the word “mayacharo” (PS 44), which in Prakrit means “conduct” that is natural to maya, i.e. mata or mother, has been mistakenly equated with the Sanskrit word “maya" (deceitfulness), even by Amrtachandra, which is considered a characteristic natural to women. Accordingly, the sitting, standing, teaching of moral rules, etc. activities of arihant (Enlightened Lord, worthy of worship) are compared not to the natural conduct of the mother (Samantabhadra has compared the Enlightened Lord to mother), but with the aptitude of deceitfulness considered natural to women (PS 44 AC and JS). This not only denigrates the image of the Worthy Lord, but tarnishes the image of women as well. That Prakrit and Sanskrit words have several meanings often pose another serious problem. This has given rise to gross misperceptions regarding the nature of the self. For instance, the word “suddham" (in Prakrit or “shuddha" in Sanskrit) in both languages means not only pure in the sense of impurity/purity, faultless, sinless, blameless, but also unique, unmixed, pure and simple in the sense of nothing else, only (kevala). This has created a very serious problem in a proper understanding of the inherent nature of the self in Kundakunda's works, especially Pravachanasara and Samayasara. In his commentary on Pravachanasara 192, Amrtachandra has interpreted the nature of the self as pure (atmanah shuddhatvam) in the sense that it is distinguishable, different, and discriminated from other substance(s) (para-dravya vibhagena) and indistinguishable or not to be discriminated from its own properties or traits (sva-dharma aribhagena) with which it maintains an indivisible unity (ekatvam cha). In his commentary on Samayasara verse 6 also, Amrtachandra states that the self is said to be “shuddha" (pure), in the sense that the jiva (soul or conscious entity) can never become non-soul, or non-living (ajiva) Page #20 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ XVIII THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES material entity, and ajiva can never become jiva. These two substances, viz. life and non-life or the spirit and matter, are not liable to lose or interchange their inherent nature. Jiva can never assume or have the characteristic attributes of touch, taste, smell, etc. of non-living material entity or its modes/states of evolution (evashesha dravyantara bhinnatvena upasyanman shuddha iti abhilipyate) (SS 6 AC). Jayasena, on the other hand, has deliberately translated and interpreted the word "suddham" as being devoid of all distortions or impurities of attachment, etc. (ragadi samasta vibhava rahitam) (PS 192 JS). In his Samayasara verse 6 commentary, he interprets it as "pure soul" or "pure consciousness" (shuddhatma) even though he had access to Amrtachandra's commentary. Jayasena's interpretation in this regard is inappropriate since it does not differentiate the nature of the self from the Advaita Vedanta and the Sankhya system of philosophy. It also fails to distinguish the embodied souls in the empirical existence from the liberated souls, who alone are devoid of all impurities and all kinds of karmas. T: None of the Hindi and English translations of the Prakrit verses of Kundakunda in either Samayasara or even Pravachanasara, or the Sanskrit commentaries of Amrtachandra and Jayasena including those in Hindi can be said to be immaculate. This creates a serious problem for those not knowing Prakrit and Sanskrit. The problem of translating and interpreting Kundakunda's concepts of the complex subject of spirituality in English, a foreign language, is all the more difficult. Prakrit and Sanskrit are not understood by the common folk as well as most scholars. Jainism is considered to be a universal religion. The propagation of such a religion far and wide (dharma prabhavana) is held to be one of the necessry prerequisites of an enlightened person. Since English is the lingua franca of the world, it is imperative that Jain scriptures are increasingly translated in the English language as well as other languages. A proper translation is as necesssary as a proper interpretation of the ideas contained in the Jain scriptures. As Jaina concepts are often very subtle and rich in meaning, it is usually difficult to explain them in English. In fact, an English translation poses a large number of problems compared to those of Hindi translation. The terminology constitutes one of the most important and difficult part of any translation from one language into another one. The Hindi Page #21 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PREFACE XIX translators could use the same Jaina technical terms as in the original. However, this facility is not available in English. A number of early scholars like J.L. Jaini, A. Chakravarti, and A.N. Upadhye have translated many scriptures, including those authored by Kundakunda. I have been benefited by these translations as well as by the translations of terminology such as J.L. Jaini's Jaina Gem Dictionary, N.L. Jain's Glossary of Jain Terms, and Ramesh Chand Jain's Sudha Sagar: HindiEnglish Jaina Dictionary. However, quite often these translations including those of Pravachanasara, whether in English or Hindi, have been found wanting in one respect or other in properly explaining the true purport or meaning of the subtle concepts. I have, therefore, tried to elaborate the technical terms as far as possible so that the reader may grasp the actual meaning of the term. I have also retained many original terms like jiva, karma, etc. as these are quite common nowadays. Other problems encountered in the English translation of the scriptures pertain to the paucity of scholars proficient in the English language and the subject matter or the lack of financial and/or literary encouragement. Moreover, the task of a proper understanding of Kundakunda's concepts and ideas is further complicated by the preferences of some biased Shvetambara scholars and the one-sided interpretations of Kundakunda's concepts by the Kanjipanthi writers. Even some Digambara scholars and writers seek to give a certain twist to Kundakunda's ideas in favour of asceticism and external austerities, etc. The proper understanding of this scripture (The Essence of Jaina Scriptures) and the reality of things, Amrtachandra states, requires the right mental perspective and the purified enlightenment, which is free from any bias, preference or prejudice, which is obtained by the practice of conduct and the power of knowledge of the doctrine of syadavada (PS 275 AC and PS Kalash, 20-22). In my detailed introduction, I have tried to highlight the significant points covered in Pravachanasara giving my own translation wherever necessary in order to present a correct and balanced view of the various issues to the best of my ability without any bias or preference. To that end, I have made full use of existing translations and commentaries in Sanskrit, Hindi and English. I have also drawn heavily on Kundakunda's other works, especially Samayasarā (The Essence of Spirituality, Consciousness and the Transcental Self) together with various Page #22 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ XX THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES translations and commentaries thereon in different languages. I have benefitted greatly from dozens of other books and articles on the subject, written by numerous Indian and foreign scholars. The present translation of the treatise Pravachanasara is based on the English translation by Professor Barend Faddegon, a Dutch Indologist, of the Prakrit gathas (verses) of Pravachanasara of Kundakunda together with the Sanskrit commentary, Tattva-dipika, by Amrtachandra. To that end, Faddegaon has indeed rendered a great service to the Jains since it is probably the only significant Digambara text authored by Kundakunda, which has been translated by a European scholar. Faddegon deserves credit for undertaking the painstaking task of translating the complicated Sanskrit sentences of Amrtachandra, which, as F.W. Thomas observes, “renders the work of interpretation and translation extremely difficult”. He undertook this laborious task at the “behest” of Prof. Thomas, even when he was not feeling well due to a constitutional nervous disease-for “the joy of a deeper and better understanding” of the Jain religion. Faddegon has translated not only the text of Pravachanasra but also the Tattvadipika commentary of Amrtachandra thereon honestly and sincerely with an open and critical mind, which is reflected in his notes. At some places, the notes give a comparative perspective of various systems of philosophy including Jainism, Buddhism and Vaisheshika on certain issues. It is indeed a matter of deep concern and regret that no Jaina or non-Jaina scholar, Indian or foreign, has so far deemed it necessary to translate the other two commentaries by Amrtachandra of Kundakunda's two other outstanding works, viz. Panchastikayasara and Samayasara. A.N. Upadhye has translated only Kundakunda’s verses of Pravachanasara text, but not Amrtachandra's commentary thereon. Faddegon's translation of both Kundakunda's text and Amrtachandra's commentary thereon, A.N. Upadhye says, reached his hands very late, when all the forms of his translation and Introduction had already been printed. Faddegon's mastery of Sanskrit is evident from the fact that he taught the Mimansa and Nyaya systems of philosophy and Vyakaran (Sanskrit Grammar) to Ludo Rocher and wrote on Panini and the Vaisheshika system. Even Upadhye, who has called his own translation of Pravachanasara text of "tentative character”, states that he is "benefitted by some of the ideas of the late B. Faddegon who has so Page #23 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PREFACE XXI carefully translated into English the Pravachanasara along with the Sanskrit commentary of Amrtachandra”. Since Faddegon was not exclusively devoted to Jaina philosophy and religion, he was not very well conversant with the intricacies of all the Jaina concepts and technical terms, such as “sarvagata," "samyak,” "para-samaya,” “dravyatva”, etc. Therefore, his translation of Kundakunda's verses and even Amrtachandra's commentary thereon in a number of places does not seem to be proper. For instance, following the Vedanta tradition, Faddegon has translated the word “sarvavyapi ekchid-rupa” (PS Kalash 1) as “pure intelligence pervading everything,” which I have corrected as atman being “one principle or reality of consciousness-as-such that permeates all its attributes and modes”. The literal translation of “achaľ as “immobile” (in PS 192) and of “rupa” in “yathajata rupam” as “colour” (in PS 204 and 207) are also not correct. I have therefore translated “achaľ as “stable” and “rupa” as “form" or "character,” which in my opinion are more appropriate translations in conveying the sense and purport of the author. Since Faddegon was not very familiar with Indian conditions, he could not understand that sahakara fruit (in PS 104 AC) means mango fruit, which evolves by itself from the green state into the yellowish state, not a "white” state as he has translated the term “pandu”. The word "pandu,” like many other terms, has more than one meaning. When it is used in the context of silver, it means “white” but when it is used with respect to mango fruit "yellowish” is more appropriate. The translation of “samyak” as "absolute” in Amrtachandra's commentary on Pravachanasara 241, and of “samyak-darshan” as “perfect faith” in Amrtachandra's commentary on Pravachanasara 242 is not proper. Similarly, translation of vyavahara and nishchaya nayas as “view of common acceptance” and “view of strict verity” respectively (see PS 191) or “theoretical point of view” and “practical point of view” respectively in Amrtachandra commentary (see PS 242) do not seem to be appropriate. In my view, a better translation of the word “samyak” is “enlightened”, of nishchaya naya as “internal, self-referential point of view” and of vyavahara naya as “external, other-referential point of view”. Since most Indian scholars have also not translated these terms properly, Faddegon alone should not to be blamed. I have sought to revise, correct and modify Faddegon's translation of Kundakunda's Prakrit verses wherever considered ncecessary. I have Page #24 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ XXII THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES also used Upadhye's translation of Pravachanasara in this regard. Faddegon's translation of Amrtachandra's commentary has also been modified and revised at a number of places. I have also removed a few question marks noticed in his translation. In his translation of Amrtachandra's commentary on Pravachanasara in verse 207 concerning pratikramanl pratyakhyana, Faddegon has left out one long sentence pertaining to the fourth avashyaka (essential daily duties), which has been translated and inserted in the proper place by the present editor of this volume. As a result, Faddegon only mentioned five of the six essential daily duties. This possibly occured because the copy of Pravachanasara available to him did not contain that sentence in Sanskrit. This sentence in Amrtachandra's Sanskrit commentary is missing even in the Pravachanasara book, edited and published by A.N. Upadhye. Moreover, while Faddegon had a good command over Sanskrit, he apparently did not have much knowledge of Prakrit. Like most other translations, his translation of the Prakrit text of Kundakunda is based on the Sanskrit rendering (Sanskrit chhaya) of Prakrit verses. As a result, when he translates the two Prakrit verses quoted by Amrtachandra which do not have a Sanskrit rendering in his Appendix on 47 points of view, his translation has been found to be incorrect and even perverse. The Sanskrit rendering and English translation of these two Prakrit verses by J. L. Jaini available in Gommatsara Karmakanda Part II (Verses 894-895) published in 1937 was also not available to Faddegon at the time of his translation of this treatise (1934). I have translated these two Prakrit verses and also reproduced Faddegon's translation thereof. Barend Faddegon's translation, edited with an introduction by F.W. Thomas, was first published in 1935. Its publication was made possible by the “liberality and Testamentary Provision” of Rai Bahadur Jagmanderlal Jaini (J. L. Jaini), to whose memory the publication was dedicated. The footnotes coming at the bottom of the page in Faddegon's translation have been shifted towards the end of the book. Moreover, the numbering of the verses in Book II and III have also been made consecutive so as to tally with the Prakrit text, given at the end of the book and numerous publications on Pravachanasara. Since a number of books on Pravachanasara in Hindi as well as A.N. Upadhye's English Page #25 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PREFACE XXIII translation thereof, follow the pattern of book-wise numbering, e.g. II.5 (for PS 97) and III.8 (for PS 208), I have also retained that pattern for Book II and Book III along with consecutive numbering for the whole book for the convenience of the readers. Like Amrtachandra's commentary of Samayasara, Amrtachandra's commentary of Pravachanasara, though written in prose, also contains poetic compositions or verses, called Kalash (246 in Samayasara, and 22 in Pravachanasara). I have revised translations of these Kalash verses. I have also numbered them and kept them separate from the commentary in prose. The English translation of Faddegon of the 36 additional verses given only in Tatparyavrtti commentary of Jayasena has been given after Amrtachandra's commentary. The glossary in the book has been reproduced from Pravachanasara, translated and edited by A.N. Upadhye. However, references to verses (gathas) have been changed to the consecutive numbering for the whole book, instead of book-wise numbering. I express my sincere gratitude to Shri Ashok Jain of Jain Family Trust for sponsoring the publication of this book. I express my sincere thanks to my sons, Rajendra Kumar Jain and Pradeep Kumar Jain, and my daughter-in-law, Sunita Jain, for their encouragement, support and help of various kinds. I thank my grand-daughter Ruchika and grandson Anekant, who have helped in various ways including proofreading. I also thank Vaishali Gupta for typing the bulk of the manuscript and carrying out corrections. 12 March 2014 JAGDISH PRASAD JAIN Page #26 --------------------------------------------------------------------------  Page #27 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction Jagdish Prasad Jain Kundakunda and His Works Acharya Kundakunda is held in very high esteem among the Jains, particularly the Digambara sect. In fact, he is revered next only to Lord Mahavira and his apostle Gautam Gandhara. Many Jain monks deem it a proud privilege to trace their spiritual lineage from Kundakunda, who is considered to have flourished in the beginning of the Christian era. R.G. Bhandarkar describes Kundakunda as “one of the earliest Digambara authóts whose works are referred to by subsequent writers”. Peterson characterizes him a teacher of great antiquity and renown”.2 Kundakunda's works, all of which are in Prakrit (Pk.) dialect, are read with respect by all sects and sections of Jains. The hallmark of all his works is their focus on spirituality, i.e. attention to our inner dimension. There are five significant works of Kundakunda (KK), viz. Panchastikayasara (PKS), Samayasara (SS), Pravachanasara (PS), Niyamasara (NS) and Baras Anuvekkha (BA) (Twelve Reflections or Affirmations), Of these, the first three have been commented upon in Sanskrit (Sk.) by Amrtachandra (AC) in the 10th century) and Jayasena (JS) (in the 13th century). Thus, we have two recessions of these three works. Panchastikayasara (PKS) deals mainly with the six substances. Samayasara (SS) - which is widely recognized to be the most important of Kundakunda's works – deals essentially with the supreme reality of the transcendental nature of the self. The self is said to have unity or oneness (ekatva) with the embodied soul and materiai karman and the Page #28 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES resultant influx of karmas, etc. modes or categories (padartha) in the transmigratory existence yet maintains its distinctness (vibhaktpana) from them. In Pravachanasara (PS), there is a systematic, philosophical, logical and scientific examination of the following issues - knowledge, the knowables, karmic bondage, auspicious (shubha), inauspicious (ashubha), pure (shuddha), psychic-attention, violence and nonviolence, and description of equanimity and conduct, etc. Two Recensions of Pravachanasara (PS) Kundakunda did not divide Paravachanasara into books, chapters or sections. Amrtachandra has, however, divided it into three Books dealing with the principles of knowledge (jnana), the knowable (jneya) and conduct. Apart from the benedictory (PS 1-5) and preliminary verses relating to the nature of the self and its states-of-evolution (PS 7-12), Book 1 contains four chapters: Pure Psychic-attention (shuddhopayoga) (PS 13-20), Exposition of Knowledge (PS 21-52), Exposition of Joy (PS 53-68), and Good (shubha) Psychic-attention (PS 69-92). Book II has three chapters: Knowable (Substance) in General (dravya samanya) (PS 93-126), Substance in Particular (dravya vishesh) (PS 127-144), and Distinctive Characteristics of soul substance (jiva dravya) (PS 145-200). Book III has four sections, viz. Conduct including negligence (PS 201-231), Path of Liberation (PS 232-244), Good Psychic-attention (shubha upayoga) (PS 245-270), and the five jewels (PS 271-275) pertaining to principles of transmigration (sansara) (PS 271), liberation (PS 272), means of liberation (PS 273-274), and the benefits of understanding the treatise (PS 275). Of the two recensions, Amrtachandra's recession of Pravachanasara contains 275 gathas (verses) divided into three Shrutaskandhas (Books) each dealing with the exposition of Jnana-tattva (knowledge principle), Jneya-tattva (knowable principle) and Charana-tattva (conduct principle) and containing 92, 108 and 75 gathas (verses) respectively. Jayasena's recension, however, adopts the three divisions and terms them adhikaras (Chapters), which deal with jnana (knowledge), darshan (intuition, view) and charitra (conduct). The number of gathas (verses) in Jayasena's recension are 311 with each adhikara having 101, 113 and 97 gathas (verses) respectively. Thus, the recension of Jayasena contains 36 additional verses (9 in Book I, 5 in Book II, and 22 in Book III). Page #29 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION The verses have been numbered according to the Prakrit text given at the end of this book. Thus, if Jayasena's verses are coming before Amrtachandra, it is numbered as 19/1 and 93/1, while Amrtachandra's verses are numbered as 19/2 and 93/2. Similarly, if Jayasena's verses are coming after those of Amrtachandra, they are numbered as 52/2, 135/2, 217/2, 217/3, etc., while Amrtachandra's verses are renumbered as 52/1, 135/1, 217/1, etc. (this has been the case in the rest of the verses). The additional verses given only in Jayasena's commentary of Tattparya-vrtti have been given at the end of the book. The subject matter and contents of Book II indicate that Jayasena's designation thereof as darshan does not seem to be quite correct. At times, he also gives alternative readings and two interpretations of the same verses (e.g. see for instance II.46-47 (PS 138-139). Additional Verses in Jayasena's Recension After examining the contents and the general nature of the additional verses in the longer recension of Jayasena and the position they occupy in the text, Upadhye comes to the conclusion that of the 36 additional verses, 8 verses (viz. 52/2, 68/3, 79/3, 82/2, 92/2 and 92/3 of Book I and 9311, 200/2 of Book II) contain “salutation and benediction”. The second group of 12 verses (viz. 19/1, 68/2, 79/2 of Book I and 135/2, 146/2 of Book II; and 217/2-3, 229/2-4, 239/ 2, and 268/2 of Book III) contain some "explanation and amplification”. These twenty verses, Upadhye observes, “even if they are dropped their absence would not be felt, and even if they are present they do not materially add to the contents of Pravachanasara as a whole.”4 These twenty verses include an additional verse (viz. verse no. 19/1 of second group). In this context, Upadhye observes: “It is something like a gloss on the previous gathas and does not disturb the context very much.” On careful examination of this verse and previous verses, the present author feels that this additional verses does disturb the context as is implied from Upadhye's qualifying phrase "very much”. This verse has no relation whatsoever with either the previous or the subsequent one. However, it does contain two novel assertions or innovative ideas. To the best of my knowledge, it is not mentioned in any other Jain texts and, therefore, seem to be creations of Jayasena's own fertile mind. Page #30 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 4 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Two remarks about this additional verse are required. Firstly, verse 19/1 mentions a new definition of samyak-darshan (enlightened view) when its introductory remark states: "Those who believe in [the] omniscient are samyak-drashti (one having samyak-darshan i.e. enlightened view)." The followers of all religions consider their Gods to possess absolute or complete knowledge, i.e. omniscience. They believe in them and therefore can be said to be upholders of enlightened view. In this regard, verse 80 of Pravachanasara states that he who knows the true nature of the self, through the medium of Arhat (kevali or omniscient) in relation to substance, quality and modification, his infatuation (moha) perishes, i.e. such a person is called samyak-drashti (one having enlightened view about the self), and not simply someone who merely believes in the omniscient Lord. Secondly, the additional verse 19/1 states that those who believe in the best of all objects, i.e. omniscient soul(s), honoured by the gods of heaven, etc., have their miseries brought to nought. The very next verse (19/2 or rather verse 19 of Amrtachandra's recension and also acceptable to Jayasena), on the other hand, affirms: "He whose destructive karman has perished... he himself evolves into knowledge and bliss," i.e. has his miseries brought to nought. In other words, the elimination of miseries or attainment of salvation takes place not simply by belief (i.e. enlightened view), but by the trinity of enlightened view, knowledge and conduct. Jayasena's additional verse 19/1 is being misinterpreted by H.C. Bharill, a follower and spokesperson of Kanjipanthi, in support of his one-sided assertion: "If from the beginningless time the soul is miserable, its only cause (ek matra karana) is absence of samyakshraddhan, or samyak-darshan (i.e. false belief or deluded view); freedom from it is the real freedom, i.e. liberation." Samyakshraddhan is imperative for liberation but as Kundakunda has clearly stated that one having samyak-shraddhan but lacking self-restraint (sanjad in Pk. or sanyat in Sk.) does not attain liberation (PS 237). In this context, Amrtachandra remarks: And for one without self-restraint what can belief, which consists in apprehension (pratiti) of the truth of the self as described, or knowledge, which consists in experiencing (anubhuti) of the truth of the self as described have any effect? Therefore, from belief or knowledge, devoid of self-restraint, there is no attainment of liberation; hence [the idea] that Page #31 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION non-simultaneity of Scripture knowledge, belief in the principles or the categories, and self-restraint could be the path of liberation is refuted. (PS 237 AC) In so far as the third group of remaining 16 verses (viz. 187/2 of Book II and 220/2-4, 224/2-12, 227/2 of Book III) are concerned, A.N. Upadhya observes, one wonders whether the additional information contained in them is consistent with the contents of Kundakunda's other works. If there is any inconsistency, one has to question their authenticity. However, if similar contents are found in other works of Kundakunda, they can be considered acceptable.? After undertaking a strict scrutiny of these 16 verses, Upadhye remarks: The position of II.95*4 [187/2], especially in that particular context, is doubtful. The remonstration against the use of clothes, in 220/2-4, is only an amplification of one of the 28 primary virtues (PS 204, 208-209), and this subject is discussed in detail in Charittapahuda (20 ff.), Suttapahuda (17 ff.), Bodhapahuda (51 ff.)... That women cannot attain liberation, as set forth in 224/2-12, is a topic which represents the Digambara view against that held by the Shvetambaras. It is not only here, but also in Suttapahuda (22 ff.) that Kundakunda states his views almost in the same tone.... The conteries of 227/2 have nothing special, though the gatha disturbs the context. Of the 16 additional verses of the third group, the only consistency with the contents of the five major works of Kundakunda is about his objection to the use of clothes (verse 220/2-4), which Upadhye considers to be only an "amplification” of one of the 28 primary qualities (mulgunas) of a shraman in Pravachanasara verses 204 and 208-9. If this has already been discussed in three verses of Pravachanasara, it was not necessary to further elaborate it by the introduction of three more verses by Jayasena. Upadhye concurs that two of these additional verses (187/2 and 227/2) disturb the context. For the remaining eleven additional verses in this third group of 16 verses, the only comparable references that Upadhye could cite, are related to Ashta Pahuda, in which case Kundakunda's authorship is said to be somewhat doubtful. These 11 verses of the third group maintain that women cannot attain liberation in the same birth. The Digambaras endorse this view whereas the Shvetambaras disagree. Unlike additional verses 220/2-4, Page #32 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Upadhye does not give any comparable reference to the subject in these additional 11 verses to any of the verses in the Pravachanasara of Amrtachandra recession or in any of the other significant works of Kundakunda mentioned above, and also these 11 verses could not be said to be an "amplification” or elucidation of other verses. Another controversy between Shvetambaras and Digambaras relates to eating of food by the kevali (arihanta, the enlightened soul, who has gotten rid of the four ghatia (destructive) karmas, i.e. those karmas which obscure the four excellent attributes of the enlightened soul). This point has been raised and discussed in detail by Jayasena in his commentary on Pravachanasara verse 20. In fact, there does not seem to have been any particular need to introduce this topic at this point since the verse merely states that the kevali does not experience bodily pleasure or pain since he has transcended the realm of the senses. In his commentary, Amrtachandra reiterated this by arguing that just as fire, which has no contact with an iron ball, is not subjected to the heavy blows by a hammer, the pure soul, having transcended the senses does not experience either bodily pleasure or pain. On the other hand, Jayasena discusses the sectarian issue of kevali at length in almost three pages. It seems that he dwells on this controversial topic in order to score a point against the rival sect by using Kundakunda’s “literary reputation” and seeks to display his own intellectual skills (panditya pradarshan). To that end, Jayasena tends to tarnish the image of a great thinker like Kundakunda whose works are the common heritage of all mankind. In fact, at a number of other places, Jayasena's commentary seems to be unnecessarily lengthy. For instance, while Amrtachandra's commentary of Pravachanasara verses 261 and 262 as well as verses 264 to 267 is provided in only one sentence, Jayasena's commentary runs to as many as 8 to 20 sentences. Thus, the additional verses of Jayasena in Pravachanasara, especially the 11 verses of the third group, “appear to be a subsequent interpolation”. 1° (Besides Pravachanasara, additional verses also appear in Jaysena's recension of the text of two other works of Kundakunda, viz. Samayasara and Panchastikayasara). Jayasena has not given any explanation for the additional verses and the circumstances point to him being the author of the verses." The additional interpolatory verses in all three works of Page #33 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION Kundakunda seem to be “the work of someone who had mastered the language in the manner of the original, from which they are considered to be indistinguishable”. 12 This “someone”, it seems, is no other person than Jayasena himself as all his three Sanskrit commentaries start with translation meanings or explanations in Sanskrit of each Prakrit word or phrase coming in Kundakunda’s verse. This is indicative of his proficiency and mastery of the Prakrit language. However, Amrtachandra does not adhere to this practice. In his introduction in English to the 1959 edition of Samayasara, published in Hindi by Rajkrishna Jain of Ahimsa Mandir, Delhi, i.e. almost two decades after Upadhye edited Pravachanasara, A.N. Upadhye seems to have revised his opinion about Jayasena. He observes: To the modern mind there is something heinous in any one tampering with old texts like this. In India, however, many old works have received such treatment even from authors of great merit and originality, who have preferred to remain anonymous, not with the idea of committing a fraud, but from a sense of modesty and selflessness. It is possible that Jayesena put in the additional verses in a similar frame of mind, but the controversial verses in Pravachanasara do not support this charitable interpretation. Many Jaina writers begin their work by inviting the reader himself to rectify mistake of omission and contnission on their part. 13 Amrtachandra was not only older to Jayasena but far more learned of the two Sanskrit commentators. In his commentary, he has incorporated a number of independent Sanskrit poems (known as SS Kalash or PS Kalash). As a renowned scholar, he has himself written a number of excellent works. 14 Amrtachandra's commentaries of the three works of Kundakunda, viz. Samayasara, Pravachanasara and Panchastikayasara, are generally recognized as outstanding. He has sought to elaborate certain points, which would have otherwise been very difficult to understand. However, his commentaries incorporate his own ideas and preferences at certain places. In my own evaluation of the significant concepts and ideas presented in Pravachanasara, I have sought to present as honestly as possible what Kundakunda himself would have wanted to say. To that end, I have even given my own translation at a number of places and have also used the commentaries of Amrtachandra and Jayasena, as well as highlighted views and translations of other scholars wherever necessary. Page #34 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 8 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Motivations behind Jayasena's Commentaries We must seek to examine the issue as to what motivated Jayasena to write his commentaries of the three works of Kundakunda. It seems that Jayasena's motives in mastering the Prakrit language and undertaking the laborious task of writing the extensive Sanskrit commentaries of three outstanding works of Kundakunda was to insert additional Prakrit verses. He also apparently sought to orient these works towards asceticism, emphasize omniscience and pure conscious attentiveness (shuddha upayoga). Moreover, he sought to highlight that these works, especially Samayasara, dealt with the pure self or pure consciousness and, therefore, they needed to be read only by either saints or ascetics. Unlike Amrtachandra, Jayasena in his commentaries has deliberately interpreted "shuddha", even in describing the inherent nature of the self as "free from attachment etc. passions", i.e. pure self. He thus equated the Jaina view regarding the nature of the self with those of Advaita Vedanta and Sankhyr. Moreover, Jayasena has endeavoured to interpret the words "shraman", "muni", etc. from the perspective of ascetics. Jayasena apparently sought to enhance his reputation by exhibiting his intellectual skills by incorporating the stages of moral and spiritual advancement (gunasthan), and seeking to explain issues through some innovative ideas of his own (see the discussion on his additional verse 19/1). In the process, he made various divisions and subdivisions of different points of view which has only created confusion in the minds of scholars and people alike. Instead of an independent work, Jayasena preferred to present his ideas through his commentaries of the works of Kundakunda. Unfortunately, people are generally reluctant to criticize any commentator, even though it may be eating into the very essentials of Jainism, lest it diminishes the common man's faith in the scriptures. This probably explains why Upadhye felt that “excepting” a few verses, which he felt were "dubious in that context" he did not find "that there is any strong case against Kundakunda's authorship, as a composer or compiler, of these additional gathas."15 He wonders why Amrtachandra did not include these gathas in his commentary. He answers the question himself: "My tentative conjecture is that Amrtachandra was too spiritualistic to enter into sectarian polemics; Page #35 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION and possibly he wanted to make his commentary along with it the sublime utterances of Kundakunda, acceptable to all the sects by eliminating the glaring and acute sectarian attacks."16 The use of the words “strong case”, “tentative conjecture," and "exceptions in regard to few verses” indicates that Upadhye was not averse to acknowledging that a case could be made for considering the additional gathas (verses) of Jayasena of “dubious authencity”.!? However, subsequently, as stated earlier, A.N. Upadhye revised his views in his Introduction to Samayasara. Thus, the translation of a religious text, its interpretation or writing its commentary should be undertaken with a sense of responsibility and not for name, fame or personal reputation, lest it distorts the meaning and creates confusion in the minds of people. Even though Jayasena's commentaries are not as good as those of Amrtachandra, his commentaries at some places do contain some good points or explanations. Problems in Translation of Old Scriptures There are several problems in the translation of old scriptures. Firstly, apart from the problem of tampering with the old texts, particularly Kundakunda's works, in the form of additional verses, a far more serious problem is tampering with the concepts and ideas of Kundakunda and distortion of their sense and meanings through commentaries, translations, interpretations, and explanations. This has prevented correct presentation and proper understanding of the great psychological insights and philosophical concepts contained in Kundakunda's works. Secondly, another problem is that Pravachanasara is composed in Prakrit, which at one time was the common language of the people, but is now virtually a dead language. Amrtchandra's first commentary on the scripture was in Sanskrit (which is also not understood by common people) and was written after nine centuries when Prakrit was neither spoken nor written. Thus, one cannot say with certainty as to Amrtchandra's proficiency in Prakrit. It is very likely that he wrote his commentary on the basis of the Sanskrit rendering of Prakrit gathas (verses). At times, this tends to create confusion. For instance, the word "mayacharo" (in PS 44), which in Prakrit means "conduce”, which is natural of maya, i.e. mata or mother, has been erronously Page #36 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES equated with Sanskrit word “maya” (deceitfulness), which is considered an aptitude natural to women, by both Amrtchandra and Jayasena in their Sanskrit commentaries. Accordingly, the sitting, standing, teaching of moral rules, etc. activities of arihant (Enlightened Lord, worthy of worship) are compared not to the natural conduct of the mother, but with the aptitude of deceitfulness considered natural to women (PS 44 AC and JS), which not only denigrates the image of the Worthy Lord but also is damaging to women-folk. In Svayambhu Stotra (35), Samantabhadra eulogizes enlightened Lord Suparshva for giving spiritual instruction and rendering advice for the well-being of living beings in a manner akin to that of a mother to her children. Thirdly, people hesitate to criticize the interpretation of the two Sanskrit commentators even when it is not proper at some places in conveying the true sense of the original author (Kundakunda). But for the proper understanding of the significant concepts of the author, it is necessary to point out the shortcomings in the commentaries and not hesitate to criticize them. Without the rectification of defects, the faultless presentation of the sense or purport of the author becomes impossible. Hence, we should no longer allow any tampering or distortions to tarnish the image of Kundakunda - an outstanding philosopher, an original thinker and a great scientist of the inner recesses of human nature. The absence of proper presentation of the Jaina concepts has prevented Jainism from occupying its rightful place of becoming a world religion. Significant Concepts in Pravachanasara: An Appraisal Pravachanasara is an outstanding work containing a systematic exposition of Jaina ontology, epistemology, psychology and ethics. In the first four verses, Kundakunda pays homage to Tirthankar Lord Mahavira (Vardhman), who has annihilated the four destructive karmas (ghatia karman, i.e. those distorting the nature of the self). As a result, he has become worthy of worship. He is the promulgator of dharmatirtha (the path of dharma, righteousness and piety), i.e. the rules and guidelines for the well-being and moral and spiritual upliftment of living beings. His discourses (pravachana) are the source of the scriptures. All the other promulgators of dharma-tirtha are also liberated souls (siddhas), who have purified (vishuddha) their souls. Page #37 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 11 The Concept of Equanimity (Samya) After paying homage to all the most revered souls, Kundakunda states that having approached their holy station, and devoted primarily to purifying (vishuddha) one's world-view and knowledge, "I rely upon the conduct of equanimity, (sammam in Pk. or samya in Sk.), which leads to the attainment of nirvana (liberation)" (PS 5).18 Conduct based primarily upon an enlightened world-view and knowledge leads to the attainment of the prosperity and happiness in this world and heaven hereafter as well as enduring happiness of liberation (nirvana) (PS 6). Thus, Kundakunda speaks of both abhyudaya, i.e. attainment of prosperity and high status in this world as also nihshreyas (moksha, i.e. liberation). Of the two, moksha is considered superior and indeed the highest goal of human endeavour according to both Jaina scriptures as well as Indian tradition. Kundakunda is no exception to this. It is precisely for this reason that Amrtachandra asserts that liberation is preferable to the transitory happiness of either this world or of heaven (PS 6 AC). Describing the nature and significance of conduct based on equanimity (samo in Pk., samya in Sk.), Kundakunda states: "Conduct is dharma. Dharma is defined as equanimity (sama); and equanimity is said to be a state-of-evolution (parinama) of the soul, in which it is free from infatuation (moha) and disturbance (kshobha)" (PS 7). In his commentary on this verse, Amrtachandra explains that conduct is behaving according to one's innate nature because dharma is defined as the nature of things (vastu svabhavat dharma), which is the manifestation of one's pure consciousness. This constitutes equanimity since it encompasses the inherent qualities of the self. Equanimity, he adds, is a state-of-evolution (parinama) of the soul. This is exempt from the flaw of infatuation (moha), which is the result of the rise (udaya) of view-deluding karman and mental agitation or perturbation (kshobha) caused by the arising of conduct-deluding karman, i.e. attachment (raga) and aversion (dvesh) (PS 7 AC). Moha, raga and dvesh are the greatest enemies of the soul in the path of the liberation the highest goal of human endeavour. Conduct, according to Jayasena, is regarded as dharma. This, in turn, is said to be samo (meaning shama or shaman, i.e. quietitude, calming, subsidence or restraint), which signifies the state-of-evolution of soul devoid of infatuation (moha) and kshobha, i.e. attachment and Page #38 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 12 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES aversion. In other words, it means behaving in accordance with one's pure nature of the consciousness, which is free from the blemish of delusion, attachment and aversion, which are the cause of the transmigratory existence (PS 7 JS). Behaving according to equanimity constitutes the essence of spiritual enlightenment since it seeks to essentially purify one's worldview and knowledge and leads to liberation (PS 5). However, before discussing this further, it is necessary to understand the word sama, samo, samabhava, samaya, samaiyam (samayika in Sanskrit), used in the sense of equanimity. It is also desirable to understand one's own nature (svabhava), dharma, pure thoughts, charitra (conduct), freedom from attachment and hatred (veetragata), shama or shaman (subsidence of passions, i.e. vikara-shaman) and shrama and shraman (saman in Prakrit), which is suggestive of hard work or labour (shrama, effort), which are considered equivalent words. (see Samansuttam, a compilation of Prakrit verses of both Digambara and Shvetambara traditions, verses 78, 100, 230, 232-233, 275, 327-328, 336, 341, 343, 346-347, and 422-423). The emphasis in Pravachanasara verse 7 signifies that enlightened view and knowledge are not able to achieve the objective of happiness unless they are accompanied by enlightened conduct based on equanimity and freedom from infatuation or deluded view (moha) and mental agitation (kshobha), caused by attachment and aversion, anger, etc. passions (PS 7). In other words, the self has the potential to become purified (vishuddha). This means that one has to make efforts to become pure by practicing conduct (charitra) of sama (equanimity) and shama or shaman (subsidence of passions, i.e. vikara-shamana) and undertake shrama (hard work, i.e. be samana in the true sense of the word). Accordingly, that samana, who practices five self-regulations (samiti), the three self-restraints (gupti) of mind, speech and body, controls his five senses, has conquered his passions (kashaya) like anger and is fully endowed with intuition and knowledge, is called selfrestrained (PS 240). Further, it is stated that samana, the practitioner of sama, is he, who considers groups of enemies and friends as the same, pleasure and pain as the same, praise and blame as the same, clay and gold as the same and moreover, maintains equanimous attitude in regard to life and death. (PS 241) Page #39 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 13 In the daily recital of Acharya Amitgati's song on equanimity (samayika), a person is asked to remain equanimous not only among groups of pleasant and unpleasant and enemies and friends, but also even in association or conjunction with love and tragic separation therefrom, and while living in palace or in forest; as also not to have any attachment whatsoever with any one of them. The Buddhists speak of four sets of contrasting conditions or traits (dhammas), viz. praise and blame, gain and loss, pleasure and pain, and fame and disrepute. One is asked to maintain a balanced and equanimous attitude towards them because they are impermanent. The Gita also talks of remaining equanimous in pleasure and pain, victory or defeat, friend and foe, fame and disrepute (Gita 2.38 and 12.18). Self-restraint and Equanimity In his commentary on Pravachanasara verse 241, Amrtachandra observes: Self-restraint is conduct accompanied by enlightened [samyak] intuition or world-view and knowledge. Conduct is dharma; dharma is equanimity; equanimity is a state-of-evolution devoid of infatuation (moha) and perturbation or mental agitation (kshobha). Therefore, equanimity is the characteristic of the self-restrained. (PS 241 AC) +4 Self-restraint is the necessary condition of equanimity, which enables a person to remain calm, retain an equanimous attitude in favourable and unfavourable circumstances, and to transcend the five dichotomies, groups or pairs of contradictory traits (dvandas) of enemies and friends, pleasure and pain, etc. (PS 241) as well as five other dichotomies - preferences, biases, fixations, complexes or knots (granthi). These are mentioned by Amrtachandra as follows: This is mine (mum) or this one belongs to me and this is other (para); this is a joy or pleasant to me and this is a torment or unpleasant; this is an elevation to me and this is humiliation; this man or object is useless to me and this one is helpful or of benefit; this is worth holding or maintaining of myself and that is a complete destruction. All these dichotomies or dualities (dvaita), Amratachandra states, are the result of infatuation. They are based on attachment and aversion. However, in the absence of these traits one continually experiences the self as having for nature pure spiritual vision and knowledge (PS 241 AC). Page #40 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Such an enlightened person, Amrtachandra adds, recognizes the groups of enemies and friends, pleasure and pain, etc. as indistinguishable, i.e. the same, merely as knowables (PS 241 AC). By nature, they are transitory states or conditions, like waves on the surface of water. On the other hand, the knowing subject, which is the substratum of all these states, remains unperturbed like the bottom of the ocean since it truly possesses equanimity in all respects. Therefore, he is neither dejected/perturbed in miseries/failures nor is he elated/hankering amidst pleasures or successes, but maintains his calm in all circumstances. Amtrachandra concludes his commentary by stating that equanimity can be said to be a characteristic of someone who exercises self-restraint, who brings perfection in terms of simultaneity of selfknowledge and knowledge of the scriptures, conviction in principles and categories and self-restraint (PS 241 AC). In other words, if a person is not ignorant of the real nature of the self and the reality of things, considers pleasure and pain etc. to be “amerely knowables”, is not infatuated with reference to objects, and does not feel attachment or aversion, then inevitably he destroys various karmas resulting in liberation. (see PS 243-244 and PS 243-244 AC) Bhagavdagita also emphasizes that equanimity is the characteristic of those who exercise self-restraint when it states that samatva, i.e. equanimity is said to be yoga (Gita 2.48) because yoga is defined as restraint of mental processes (chittavrtti nirodha) (Patanjali, Yogasutra 1.2). Our mind generally tends to always sway in extremes of likes and dislikes. Either we are intensely attached to someone or start hating him madly. Therefore, the balance of mind or intelligence is described as the essence of yoga. In Atmabodha (knowledge of self) (50), Adi Shankracharya repeats what Kundakunda has said (in PS 7), when he states: “Having crossed the ocean of delusion (moha) and gotten rid of attachment and aversion, or likes and dislikes, which are the cause of mental agitations, the self restrained (yogi), united with peace, revels in his own Atman." Samayika The daily practice of samayika (equanimous state of mind for a fixed period, usually 48 minutes twice or thrice in a day) in Jainism Page #41 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 15 is aimed at keeping oneself aloof from all sinful and injurious activities by controlling one's mind, body and speech. Samayika also cultivates an equanimous state of mind by renouncing attachment and aversion to the objects of the world. The purpose of samayika is the cultivation of: (1) equal goodwill (sympathy) (samabhava) towards all religions, towards all races and castes, and towards men and women; (2) equality and evenness (samata) regarding all living beings equal with one's own self and to maintain equanimity of mind both favourable and adverse occasions; and (3) maintaining tranquillity (sama) or balance of mind through restraint or subsidence (shama or shaman) of passions. Thus, by the constant practice of samayika one seeks to attain gradually “inward balance” or mental equipoise and tranquility of mind. It is, in fact, an exercise in samaya, etymologized as the state-of-evolution of self (aya) in equanimity (sama)." Transcendental Nature of the Soul In Samayasara, the supreme reality (paramartha) is said to be verily samaya (paramartha khalu samao in Pk. or paramartha khalu samayah, SS 151), i.e. soul's equanimous state-of-evolution or transcendental quietitude (tranquility or balançę), or transcendental nature of soul (samayasara). This transcends all relative modes and viewpoints (SS 142-144), including contrary traits of bound with karmas or not bound with karmas (SS 142), passionate or not passionate (SS 6), as also dichotomies or dualities of pleasure and pain, praise and blame, etc. Transcending contrary traits or pairs of dichotomies does not necessarily imply negation or annihilation of contradictions or contrary traits. Transcendence signifies that one should not be attached or affected by them. One should remain neutral and maintain one's peace and equipoise. Mental harmony and equipoise is indeed a great spiritual attainment. The self who is devoted to its real nature (samaya pratibaddha) does not favour or take sides with either of them by being attached to one and despising or deprecating the other side or viewpoint (SS 143) but maintains its equipoise, balance or neutral state (madhyastha, PSU 8). As a result, it has no attachment or aversion in regard to any viewpoint. The dual reactions of likes and dislikes or attraction towards the pleasant and repulsion towards the unpleasant arise out of Page #42 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 16 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES attachment or desire and aversion or hatred. To be happy or miserable is the result of the coming into operation or rise (udaya) of karmas (SS 254). Therefore, the enlightened soul, who maintains the insight or vision of equanimity (sammaditthi), does not have any attachment for the sensuous pleasures (SS 370). The Gita also speaks of equal vision (sama-darshan) (Gita 5.18, 6.29). In Niyamsara, it is clearly stated that continuous practice of discriminative insight (bhed-abhyasa) enables the self to distinguish its transcendental nature of consciousness-as-such from human, subhuman, etc. conditions or modes (NS 77), soul-quests, soul-classes and spiritual stages, classified on the basis of senses, psycho-physical differences or moral and spiritual progress of souls (NS 78), attachment, aversion and infatuation (NS 80) and anger, pride, greed, etc. passions (NS 81) and thus becomes established in its own nature (majjhattha) (NS 82) or madhyastha, thereby attaining equanimious conduct (NS 82). Accordingly, he endeavours to maintain his equipoise (sammam) towards all living beings, has enmity or ill-feeling towards none, renounces all desires and expectations, and observes supreme equanimity (samadhi) (NS 104). Characteristics of Equanimity In a separate chapter devoted exclusively to equanimity in Niyamsara, Kundakunda states that a person, who meditates on his real nature free from attachment and observes self-restraint is said to possess supreme equanimity (param samadhi) (NS 122-123). For a person devoid of equanimity (samadarahiyassa in Pk. or samuta rahitasya in Sk.), residing in a forest, mortification of the body, observance of various fasts, study of the scriptures, and keeping silence, etc. are of no use (NS 124). Again, the characteristics which qualify a person to be considered possessing steadfast equanimity (samayika) are the following: freedom from all demeritorious and unwholesome (sinful) actions; observance of three-fold restraint (of body, mind and speech) and control of one's senses (NS 125); an equanimous attitude towards all living beings (NS 126); proximity to his real self during the practice of self-restraints, observances of rules (niyam) and austerities (NS 127); freedom from psychic dispositions of attachment and aversion (NS 128); abstention from mournful and cruel concentrations (NS 129); consistent Page #43 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION renunciation of meritorious and demeritorious or sinful psychic dispositions (NS 130); renunciation of scornful laughter, indulgence, sorrow and hatred (NS 131); renunciation of disgust, fear, sexualinclinations of all kinds (NS 132); and practice of righteous and pure concentrations (NS 133). Samya or samata (equanimity) is rated very highly in Pravachanasara and other works of Kundakunda. Equanimity is described as the characteristic of saman, a person who is equanimous and selfrestrained, who is said to be one who considers the dichotomous pairs or groups, such as enemies and friends, pleasure and pain, praise and blame, clay and gold and life and death as the same (samo or samah in Sk.). In other words, he is devoid of dichotomies of attachment and aversion, etc. In the absence of equanimity, there is only attachment, aversion, passions, violence, discontent, lack of contentment, cruelty, etc. During the transmigratory existence (sansara), things are neither the same nor maintain their natural state or condition of equilibrium (sahava samavatthido in PK, and svabhava, samaavasthit in Sk.) (PS 120). As a result, the soul (jiva), although permanent in regard to substantiality (dravyatva), is non-permanent with respect to modifications, since such is the ittherent nature of sansara (PS 120 AC). In other words, all our interactions in life between our senses and the objects are bound to produce mutually contradictory feelings of pleasant and unpleasant, likes and dislikes, owing to our attachment and aversion, which are the main causes of bondage. In the circumstances, an enlightened person, who seeks to maintain equipoise of mind or equanimity devoid of attachment and aversion that are the cause of deluded view (moha) and mental agitatior. (kshobha), has indeed acquired real spiritual attainment and a characteristic of a liberated soul. Thus, it is stated: “If the soul whose infatuation (deluded view) has gone and who has properly grasped the reality of the equanimous, nature of self forsakes attachment and aversion, then it realises the pure self” (PS 81). In Paramatma-Prakash (100), Yogendu Deva clearly states that he who gets rid of attachment and aversion and is established in equanimity, attains liberation in a short time. The Bhagavada Gita also speaks quite highly of sama (Gita 2.38, Page #44 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 2.48, 4.22, 6.8, 6.9, 6.32, 12.4, 12.18,-13.9, 13.27, 13.28) samya (Gita 5.19 and 6.33), sama-darshinah (Gita 5.18 and 6.29) and samatva (Gita 2.48). In Vivekchudamani (440), Shankara specially states that he who maintains his psychic state of equanimity, when praised or worshipped by the noble people and also when teased, taunted and abused by the wicked people, is indeed a jivanmukta (liberated soul even in the embodied existence). Definition of Dharma Kundakunda has defined dharma in broad and non-sectarian terms in several ways: 1. Dharma signifies moral self-restraint and spiritual self-discipline or conduct (PS 7) based on or accompanied by an enlightened worldview and knowledge (PS 6). Thus, the trinity of enlightened view, knowledge and conduct is declared to be dharma. 2. Dharma is the inherent or essential nature of a thing or object (vastu svabhavat dharma) (PS 7 AC), which exists in all three times (traikalika svabhava). The essential nature of the self (jiva) is sentiency or consciousness (chaitanya) and its function or manifestation (upayoga) (PS 127; see also PKS 16 and 27). 3. Dharma is also defined as equanimity (samya) (PS 7) which means the possession of the qualities or the characteristics of the self (atmaguna) as they are (yathavasthita) (PS 7 AC). 4. Equanimity, which is said to be the synonym of dharma, is described as a state of evolution (parinama) of the soul. It is a state which is completely exempt or free from infatuation (moha) and mental disturbance (kshoba) (PS 7), caused by conduct-deluding karma, i.e. attachment, aversion and anger, etc. passions. 5. Dharma of the soul is also said to be the nature which it holds, takes, assumes, and possesses (dharanant dharmah) or through which it evolves during the time of evolution (PS 8), since it consists of that and is absorbed or engrossed in that (tanmaya). Thus, the soul accepts or assumes the character of its state-of-evolution. When it evolves through the good, or the evil, or the pure, it becomes good, evil, or pure (PS 9). 6. Lastly, dharma is said to be the state-of-evolution of the soul conjoined with pure (shuddha) conscious attentiveness (upayoga), which is the direct cause of the happiness as also the state-of-evolution of Page #45 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 19 the soul endowed with good, righteous or auspicious (shubha) conscious attentiveness, which is the cause of heavenly happiness (PS 11) and gradually leads to the attainment of the highest happiness of liberation (PS 254 AC). Hence, those possessing shuddopayoga or shubhopayoga are both considered saman (shraman in Sk.) (PS 245), i.e. those treading the path of liberation (moksha marg). Shuddha upayoga is defined in Pravachanasara verse 14, shubha upayoga is described in Pravachanasara, 69-70, 157 and 246-249 while ashuba upayoga is described in verse 158. Nature of Dharma Sometimes, dharma is equated with self-restraint (samyamah khalu Dharma) or enlightened world-view (darshan mulo dhammo) or compassion and kindness (daya dharma ka mool hai). A comprehensive definition is provided in Karttikeyanupreksha (verse 478). It states: "Dhammo vastu sahavo, khamadi-bhavo ya das-viho dhammo; rayanttayam cha dhammo, jivanam-rakkhanam dhammo." In other words, the intrinsic nature (svabhava) of an object or living being is known as its dharma, forgiveness, etc. ten moral virtues is dharma, three jewels comprising of enlightened world-view, enlightened knowledge, and enlightened conduct the three combined is also dharma; and non-violence or protection of living beings from any injury or harm is dharma. Dharma in Jainism consists of a set of principles, values, and virtues; it is the science of well-being. Jainism is not, as is generally assumed and believed or as is very often preached and asserted, merely a set of doctrines and dogmas, a bundle of practices, forms, rites, rituals, a code of dietetics, a mode of social life, or a routine of daily conduct. These are not the essentials of Jainism. Jainism is, in fact, a way of life that ensures peace, happiness, and social well-being. It is a prescription for leading a good, peaceful, virtuous and happy life, which can only be realized by conquering our inner enemies, attachment and aversion, anger, greed, etc. passions. Dharma, according to Jainism, does not merely consist in worship, fasts, contemplation, penance or asceticism. They are all means and should not be confused with the ends. The discipline of asceticism is a method and a means, it is not an end. It serves as a means to liberate consciousness from its attachment to instinctive impulses, sub Page #46 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 20 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES conscious motivations and instincts and egoism in order to attain equanimity. Nature of the Self or Soul The self or soul (jiva) is a substance (dravya), an existent reality, whose essential nature or distinguishing characteristic is (chedana uvaogamao in Pk. and chetana upayogamaya in Sk.) (PS 127, PKS 16), i.e. sentiency or consciousness (chetana) and manifestation, function of consciousness or psychic attention (upayoga). (In Tattvartha Sutra (TS 2.8), upayoga alone is described as the defining distinguishing characteristic of jiva). Although both chetana and upayoga are said to be the nature of the self, they are not identical. Upayoga is the application, manifestation, mode, or rather the active, functional and the attentive aspect of consciousness, but not consciousness-as-such (chetana) which is the essence of jiva or the soul substance. Upayoga is the manifestation, modification or the state-of-evolution (parinama) of jiva, which has the form of functioning of the soul substance (PS 127 AC). Thus, the nature of the self in Jainism is eternal (nitya) as well as evolvent (parinami), or parinami nitya, i.e. evolvent and yet eternal, not "unchanging eternal" of Advaita Vedanta and the Sankhya system of philosophy. Panchastikayasara 27 states that jiva is conscious entity (cheda), whose particular characteristic is upayoga (jivo tti havadi cheda uvaoga visesido in Pk., and jiva iti havati chetayita upayoga visheshitah in Sk.) (PKS 27). Amrtachandra explains it by stating that from the internal, self-referential standpoint (nishchaya naya), jiva, in its mundane empirical existence, state or condition (samsara avastha) is consciousness-as-such, because it is endowed with the essence, the internal life source, inalienable psychic or conscious vital force (bhavaprana dharnat). From the external, other-referential point of view (vyavahara naya), the jiva is endowed with or possesses physical, objective, external manifestations of jiva, i.e. dravya pranas (the physical insignia of life), viz. the bio-energies or physical, corporeal characteristics [of five senses, the three energies of mind, body and speech, life duration and respiration] (PKS 27 AC). Chetana (consciousness) remains the eternal, constant factor (dhrauvya) of jiva or soul substance, which is the substratum of all its attributes and modes and exists in all its states or conditions and at Page #47 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION all stages of the evolution of the self, including upayoga, in all three. times. On the other hand, upayoga can transform itself in eiiher direction: enlightened or deluded, towards purity or impurity, good or evil. Since there is no object without a state-of-evolution (parinama), the self is said to be evolvent in nature, i.e. subject to change or modification. It possesses the nature of that through which it evolves during the time of the evolution (PS 8). In other words, it accepts the character of its state-of-evolution (PS 9). Conjunction of the self with other substance, i.e. karman, results in a particular type of upayoga, i.e. manifestation of chetana, which has two modes of psychic-attention or awareness, viz. jnana and darshan (PS 155). When the awareness of an object has some form (sakara), it is said to be jnana (cognition or knowledge). If it is without form (nirakara), it is considered darshan (intuition) (PS 155 and PS 155 AC). These two modes of awareness are intimately related to karmic changes and the relation may be said to be in inverse ratio. The intensity and quality of these two upayogas decreases as the karmic veil becomes thicker and stronger, but they have the chance of fuller manifestation when the karmas either decay or disappear. Shubha (good or auspicious) upayoga and ashubha (bad or inauspicious) upayoga are also related to interaction with karma. In shubha, anger, etc. passions become feeble or mild due to their subsidence, with the result that the karmas also get reduced. Shubha, therefore, has the effect of purifying (vishuddhi) of the self. In ashubha, on the other hand, which witnesses an intensity of passions, the bondage of karma is increased, and the self is imbued with affliction, distress or morbidity (sanklesh) (PS 155 AC). If the manifestation of consciousness is auspicious, the soul accumulates merit (punya); if inauspicious, demerit or sin (papa). In the absence of both, there is no accumulation (PS 156) of either, with the result that only “pure” [in the sense of being unconditioned, unencumbered (nirupadhi), natural (svabhavika) (PKS 58 AC), unmixed, only, kevala (exclusively one's own),20 alone, of the nature of only consciousness-as-such] remains (avatishthate). This is not the cause of conjunction with other substance (sa punab akaranam eva para dravya sanyogasya) (PS 156 AC). In other words, it has no relation with karman whatsoever and is devoid of any conjunction with any Page #48 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 22 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES other substance; it is consciousness (chetana) itself. It is said to be "pure" because it is consciousness-as-such alone (chinmatra, SS 73 AC) or possessing only conscious force (chit shakti matra, SS 36 AC) and because it is not conditioned by karman. In other words, it is non-relational to karman (karma-nirpeksha) parinamika bhava, which is the natural, intrinsic or the inherent nature of jiva or soul, independent of any bias or prejudice of any relative aspect with other (object) (anya nirpeksha) (NS 28) and unconditioned by karman. Pariamika Bhava Because of karmic adjunct, association, entanglement (upadhi) or jiva's interaction with the karmas, Kundakunda speaks of five fundamental qualities (panchagga guna) (PKS 53, jiva gunas, PKS 56), or jiva bhavas (thought characteristics, psychic dispositions or emotional, affective states of consciousness). One of these states of consciousness is the parinamika bhava (consciousness-as-such), which is without beginning and end, the intrinsic, natural state of the self (svabhavika) and is of nirupadhi character (PKS 58 AC), i.e. independent and unconditioned by karman, i.e. karma-nirpeksha (PKS 56 JS). Amrtachandra calls it the essential nature of jiva (parinamika bhava), the essential natural state of consciousness-as-such (sahaj chaitanya lakshan parinamika bhava) (PKS 53 AC). In Yogasara-Prabhrata (1.52) of Amitgati, the self (atman) is said to be devoid of karma and no-karma (gross, physical body), noncorporeal (amurta), beyond old age and death, free from particularities (nir-vishesha) and completely non-relational (asambandha). The parinamika bhava is said to have neither beginning nor end (PKS 53). In other words, as spiritual existence it is eternal; neither is it created nor can it be destroyed. It is called parinamika because of its evolvement nature (parinamena yukta parinamika PKS 56 AC), i.e. subject to change, modification or evolution (parinama), though it is considered to be neutral in the sense that in itself it is neither pure nor impure; it is the basis and the substratum of the other four states of consciousness (jiva bhavas), which are the modes or modifications (paryaya) of consciousness-as-such, and signify the purifying and not sc, i.e. impure psychic states. These four psychic dispositions or conditions of consciousness are the states of coming into operation or the rising of karmas (audayika), Page #49 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION subsidence (aupshamika), the mixed process or state of partly destruction and partly subsidence (kshayopashamika), and destruction (kshayika) of karmas. All of them are causally connected with or related to physical (dravya) karma or karma-upadhi (PKS 56 AC). Since these psychic states cannot happen in the consciousness of a jiva without corresponding changes in material or physical karman, they are said to be the effects of physical karma (karma krta) (PKS 58 and PKS 58 AC). Of these four psychic states, the audayika, accompanied as it is with the coming into operation or rise of deluding karma, is the supportive factor (nimitta) or the auxiliary cause of karmic bondage (PKS 56 JS) and samsara (transmigratory existence of the cycle of births and deaths) and hence represents the impure condition. The other three states of consciousness have a purifying effect (vishuddhi) and are the cause of liberation or emancipation (moksha) (PKS 56 JS). Of these three, the aupashamika and kshayopashamika gradually lead to liberation. Moksha (liberation), signifying as it does liberating the self from the karmic entanglement, as a result of inhibition of fresh karmas and the annihilation of previously bound karmas, is also karma-referential. The parinamika bhava (consciousness-as-such) is not causally connected with either (karmick bondage or liberation (PKS 56 JS). Jayasena here cites an old verse which says: “The parinamika bhava is inactive (nishkriya); the audayika bhava, i.e. coming into operation or rise of karmas is the cause of bondage, while the other three bhavas are the cause of liberation” (PKS 56 JS). Even when parinamika bhava is considered to be inactive, the manifestation of consciousness or psychic-attention (upayoga) makes the soul active (sakriya). Being karma-nirpeksha and nirupadhi in character, i.e. independent of and being unconditioned by karman, the parinamika bhava is not causally connected with either samsara (the mundane worldly existence of births and deaths) or moksha (liberation). It is said to be neither bound nor unbound (SS 142), neither passionate (pramatta) nor dispassionate (apramatta) (SS 6), neither pure nor impure. Moreover, the parinamika bhava is an existent reality in all living beings. Since it is already available to them and is not a thing or condition to be attained as such," one sometimes contends that "theoretically its articulation should make no difference to the behaviour” of living Page #50 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 24 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES beings, particularly the moral and spiritual practitioners or seekers (shraman). Such thinking or belief in reality is not correct. The knowledge and the firm conviction (shraddhan) in regard to the real nature of the self is imperative to distinguish between jiva and pudgal (matter), soul and body. Without this discriminative insight (bhed-vigyan), one cannot have an enlightened view (samyak-darshan) of the fundamental principles of life or the reality of things as they are. Moreover, since this enlightened view is the first necessary precondition in the path of liberation, one cannot attain liberation in its absence. Of course, one has to make efforts by adopting moral and spiritual discipline (conduct) to attain the objective of libration. Pravachanasara verse 159 speaks of the self (consciousness) having the nature or the character of knowing (PS 159) and of establishing itself unswervingly in its own conscious attentiveness (upayoga) (PS 159 AC). In the subsequent verses, the self is distinguished from body, mind and speech, which are declared to consist of material (pudgal, unconscious) substance, while the self (the subjective awareness of "I") is distinguished from them since that awareness of 'I' is not composed of matter (PS 160-162). Jiva Nikaya In Pravachanasara verse 182, the soul substance (jiva dravya) is distinguished from the six classes of earth-bodied, etc. immobile and mobile souls or group of jivas (jiva nikaya),21 which are said to be other (anya) than jiva (PS 182). Jiva [jivatva, jiva tattva or atma dravya, i.e. consciousness-as-such], is one unitary self, its own substance (sva dravya) (PS 182 AC). This is considered to be other (anya) from these several classes of souls (PS 182), because these [conjoint psychophysical conscious entities] have elements of material or physical bioenergies (dravya pranas) (the body, mind, senses, etc.), made up of unconscious material substance (achetanatvat) (PS 182 AC) or that the jiva nikaya are the product of the coming into operation or rise of nama karman (PS 182 JS). The six classes of jiva nikaya are not "pure" consciousness-as-such, but are mixed with some elements of unconscious material substance, just as an ornament is not pure gold but is gold mixed with various elements like silver and copper. The perverse-minded people, however, errneously feel that the composite Page #51 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION or combination of jiva and karma or soul and body comprises the self (SS 42). These jiva nikaya are, in fact, the extrinsic manifestation of consciousness, i.e. the heterogeneous (asamanjatiya) modes (paryaya) of jiva dravya (PS 93 AC), having earth-bodied, etc. immobile class of jiva or animal, human, etc. mobile modes of jiva. The jiva (soul), i.e. the self (appanam in Pk. and atmanam in Sk.) is to be distinguished from other (para, i.e. non-self) according to their own characteristic nature (svabhavam asadya) (PS 183). Jiva or soul is a sentient, noncorporeal, conscious entity, possessing subjective attributes of cognition, feeling and volition. Matter or body, however, is nonsentient, corporeal, inanimate entity possessing characteristic sense qualities of touch, taste, smell and colour. Just as in Pravachanasara, jiva nikaya are distinguished from jiva, i.e. consciousness as such, so also in Samayasara (SS 65-66) the different classes of living organisms (jiva sthana) (SS 66) are distinguished from jiva. The different classes of jiva, comprising of 1, 2, 3, 4 and 5 sensed living beings, whether they are subtle or gross and fully developed or partly developed are no doubt the classes of living beings (jivas). However, since all these are different) sub-species of body-building nama karma, i.e. the result of the fruition of that karma, how can they be called fiva (consciousness-as-such)? (SS 6566). Since all these types of jiva, basically refer to the varieties of the bodies and are conventionally applied to jiva, they are said to belong to the soul only from vyavahara naya (SS 67). Whosoever does not through their respective characteristic natures (svabhava, as consciousness and unconsciousness), know or see the distinction of the self or sva (own) and non-self or other (para), jiva and pudgala that jiva (soul) has through infatuation the perverse conviction (adhyavasana) of other substance being considered self or identified as self, i.e. aham “I am this” [the body, etc.) or this (wealth, etc.) or “this is mine” (mamedam) (PS 183 and PS 183 AC), and does not abandon such notions in regard to body and wealth, etc., takes the wrong path (PS 190). This signifies that it is necessary to discover and distinguish between the real “I” or “true self” (jiva as such or jiva-tattva) from the various classes of souls (jiva-niyaka), comprising of mind, body, senses, etc. The former is the substratum while the latter (also an existent reality during the period of their existence) are Page #52 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES its manifest forms or modes. It is this jiva tattva, the essential nature of jiva, i.e. chetana, sentiency or consciousness-as-such (parinamika bhava), which is existent in all states, stages in the three times (past, present and future) of jiva, whether in its transmigratory and embodied condition or its liberated state, and is said to be other (anya) than the six classes of transmigratory and embodied jivas (jiva nikaya) (PS 182). Jiva tattva is not separate from them (jiva nikaya), though distinguished from them in the sense that it is their underlying substratum. (For a detailed discussion about the distinction between separateness (prathakatva) and otherness (anyatva), see Pravachanasara 106). Bhava and Dravya-pranas Consciousness is considered to be the essence of jiva or its essential nature or property because it is the animating principle, which enlivens a particular living organism and infuses life into the body, the senses and all other bio-energies. In its absence, all the bio-energies remain inactive and lifeless. In other words, the parinamika bhava or bhava prana (the inner, subjective, underlying spiritual reality of jiva, or the internal life source, the inalienable psychic or conscious vital force) is other than the dravya pranas (the physical, objective, external manifestations, the bio-energies, i.e. the ten pranas comprising of five senses, the bio-energies of mind, speech and body, life duration and respiration) In its embodied from of existence, jiva is a conjoint psychophysical, conscious entity, consisting of both dravya-prana and bhavaprana. As such, dravya-prana cannot exist in isolation without bhavaprana, which cannot exist without dravya-prana in jiva's transmigratory, embodied existence. However, dravya-pranas, which are the product of the arising of nama-karman (PS 182 JS), do not exist in the liberated state. While dravya-prana is said to be unconscious material substance, the conjoint psycho-physical conscious entity of jiva nikaya cannot be said to be unconscious (achetan). Bhava-prana, i.e. consciousness-as-such or jiva-tattva, is the underlying substratum of all classes of jiva-nikaya, which are modes or forms of jiva-tattva. Like dravya (substance) and paryaya (mode of substance), they (jiva-tattva and jiva nikaya) cannot be separated though they can be distinguished as manifester and manifested. One class of Page #53 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION jiva, like one mode, can cease to exist and some other class of jiva or mode may arise. But jiva as such (i.e. jiva tattva), being the existent reality in all three times and all states, conditions, stages, forms, or modes, is neither produced nor destroyed. Amrtachandra states that the six classes of mobile and immobile jiva-nikaya (group of jivas) are, indeed, other (anya) than jiva (consciousness-as-such) because they have unconscious, inanimate physical vitalities or bio-energies (achetanatva) in them and jiva is also other (anya) than those due to its essential principle or property of consciousness (chetanatva) (PS 182 AC). In the second sentence of his commentary (of PS 182), Amrtachandra states that although the six jiva nikaya are or have the underlying substratum atman (consciousness) (Faddegon has usually translated jiva as soul and atma as self), they are para-dravya, i.e. other substance in the sense that when conscious jiva is united or bound with other inanimate substance (material karman)] it takes the form of heterogeneous modes of soul substance, the conjoint psychophysical altered entities (as is the case of six classes if jiva nikaya] and that the self (atma) alone (eva) is its own substance (sva-dravya) (PS 182 AC) · Although the vitalities of body senses, etc., which are composed of unconscious material substance; are commingled or mixed up in view of occupying the same space with jiva tattva in the six jiva-nikaya, jiva tattva and the inanimate vatalities (dravya pranas) always maintain their own intrinsic nature (PKS 7) without losing their respective qualities. In his commentary of Pravachanasara 182, Jayasena has also sought to distinguish the immobile and mobile jiva-nikaya from the innate nature of jiva (jiva svabhava). He states that they are other (anya) than or different (bhinna) from chaitanya svabhava (conscious nature) of jiva because they are the product of fruition, coming into operation or arising of mobile and immobile nama-karman, which are achetan (unconscious, inanimate) (PS 182 JS). Although nama-karman is unconscious material substance and the six classes of jivas are undoubtedly not devoid of karman, but, as conjoint psycho-physical conscious entities, they are not devoid of consciousness in their embodied existence. However, one desirous of liberation (moksharthi) abstains from [attachment] to other (para) substance (including body] Page #54 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES and becomes inclined to concentrate on its own substance (sva-dravya) (PS 182 JS). Jiva is said to be different from jiva niyaka (in PS 182). It is the soul substance (jiva bhava, PKS 16-17) or jiva-guna. As such, the (essential nature or) qualities of soul, viz. consciousness (chetana) and its attentiveness or function (upayoga) (PKS 16) is never destroyed (PKS 17). It is distinct both from its modes (paryaya) of six classes of mobile and immobile living beings and from the states, conditions or modes of human, animal, denizens of hell and heaven (PKS 16-17), which have transitory or temporal existence. Both jiva nikaya and human, etc. embodied souls are psycho-somatic states or heterogeneous modes (asamanjatiya paryaya, PS 93-94 AC) of the soul substance consisting of the (combination of) two distinct substances, soul and matter or soul and body. They possesses their own respective distinctive characteristics. Jiva or soul possesses its subjective attributes of cognition, feeling and volition, in all three times and in all stages of life journey, whether transmigratory existenceror liberated state. The material body, on the other hand, is an inanimate entity which possesses its own characteristic sense qualities of touch, taste, smell and colour. For instance, though gold and silver are combined or united in making of ornaments, they do not lose their inherent qualities of yellowness and whiteness, i.e. the two can never become one in nature really (SS 27 AC). Similarly, though the soul and body are found together or united in an embodied individual, they retain their own distinctive characteristics. It is only from an external, other-referential viewpoint (vyavahara naya), they are said to be one, i.e. having unity (ekatva) or oneness, but from the internal, self-referential viewpoint (nishchaya naya) the two can never become one singular substance (SS 27). The human, etc. modes are impure or distorted states or modes (ashuddha or vibhava paryaya) of the soul substance because they are produced or caused by connection or relationship with other substance (PKS 16 AC). In other words, the soul substance in itself, i.e. its natural state or mode (svabhava paryaya) or that its essential nature is pure because it does not have regard to or is independent of any relation with other object (anya nirpeksha, NS 28). Kundakunda declares: “My soul is ever one, eternal, characterised by knowledge and intuition; all other are external substances (bhava), since they all Page #55 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION have the characteristic of being accidental to me.” (NS 102) Pure Nature of the Soul The self (“I”) is one “exclusively one's own (kevala), alone, uncompounded, not connected with anything else” (i.e. anya nirpeksha, NS 28). It is therefore truly pure (aham ekko khalu suddho, SS 38, 73) so much so that not even the subtlest atom of other thing (substance) whatsoever (living or non-living) is mine or related to me as mine (SS 38), and that no other or none else is mine (nirmam) (SS 73, BA 20). Amrtachandra explains the nature of the self as pure as follows: The self is one, alone, only, of the nature of consciousness (chinmatra) and as such it is pure because of being extremely distinct from the nine categories or principles (nava tattva), characterised from the external, other referential view-point (vyavahara naya) as human, animal etc. particular forms, states or modes of soul substance (jiva vishesh), non-living, unconscious matter (ajiva), virtue, sin, influx of karmas, inhibition of karmas, shedding off or destruction of karmas, bondage and liberation (SS 38 AC). Unlike both Kundakunda and Amrtachandra, Jayasena maintains that the self (“I”) is pure because it is different from, i.e. devoid of the impurities of attachment, etc. psychic states or dispositions (ragadibhavebhyoh bhinna aham iti shuddhah) (SS 38 JS). As a result, it is free from the karmas as in the state of liberation. A similar discrepancy is found in the views of Kundakunda and Amrtachandra and those of Jayasena regarding Pravachanasara verse 192 (see infra). In this context, one must mention that the word “suddha" (in Pk. or shuddha in Sk.) in Prakrit and Sanskrit is used in both senses of not having any relation with other (anya nirpeksha, NS 28) and free from attachment, etc. impurities by both Kundakunda in his works as well as by Amrtachandra in his commentaries thereon in different contexts. However, Jayasena's interpretation of shuddha as free from impurities regarding the nature of the self fosters considerable misperception and confusion. In order to dispel such confusion, Amrtachandra distinguishes the nature of the self from bondage and liberation (see supra). To describe nature of the self as pure in the sense of being devoid of or free from all distortions of attachment, etc. impurities (raagadi samasta vibhava rahitam) (PS 192 JS and SS Page #56 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 38 JS) implies the denial of souls transmigratory nature and signify the inability to adopt means (sadhan) to purify impurities (like attachment, etc.) of the self in order to attain liberation. The word “suddha” in Pk. or "shuddha" in Sk. means cleansed, clean, pure (pavitra), faultless, blameless (nirdosh), without impurity (nirmal) sinless, as also “pure, i.e. simple, kevala (only), genuine, true, unmixed (i.e. not mixed with any other substance or contaminated), unmodified, unqualified, veritable, unequalled.” The word “kevald” is translated as “exclusively one's own, alone, only, mere, sole, one, excluding others, not connected with anything else, isolated, absolute, simple, pure, uncompounded, unmingled, entire, whole." Pure and simple means nothing else, only natural, while 'mere' means only (kevala).22 Clarifying the sense in which the nature of the self is said to be pure, Kundakunda states: I (aham) deem the self (appagam in Pk., atmakam in Sk.) as pure (suddha) because it is knowledge and intuition, a supra-sensual supreme reality (mahartha) eternal or permanent (dhruva), stable (achal), without prop or support (PS 192). In his commentary on the above verse, Amrtachandra explains that the self is in fact pure, and only the pure self is dhruva (permanent, eternal) because it is an existent reality (sat) ([it exists in all three times, past, present and future, in all living beings]), without a cause (ahetuka), without beginning or end (anadyantah) and it is selfestablished (or self-proved], nothing else is so. And the self is pure (shuddha) because it is distinguishable or can be discriminated from another substance. It is also indistinguishable or non-discriminated from its own properties with which it has unity (ekatva). This (unity) consists of knowledge and intuition because it transcends the senses and knows the sense qualities of touch, taste, etc. It also remains unperturbed, unaffected and stable (achal) by the various discernible modifications corresponding to impressions of objects, and being without any prop or support of any kind from other” substance. Thus, the self is pure because it is chin-matra (consciousness-as-such alone) (PS 192 AC). While the self, which comprises psychic attention (upayoga), is eternal (dhruva), neither the body nor possessions, neither pleasure Page #57 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION nor pain, neither enemies nor friends, are eternal, (dhruva) for the soul (PS 193), i.e. they are impermanent (asat) (PS 193 AC). In other words, body, possessions, etc. have a transitory existence. The use of the term “asať here cannot be said to be “non-existent” or “unreal” as is misconstrued by W. J. Johnson. He, who having thus discerned the pure self contemplates on the supreme reality of the soul (param appagam in Pk., paramatman in Sk.), be it a householder or an ascetic, destroys the evil bondage of infatuation (moha) (PS 194). The nature of the self, which is considered pure in the sense of being constant or eternal (dhruva), stable, without any support (PS 192), being alone (aham ekko khalu suddho, SS 38, 73, BA 20), having no relation with any other (nirpeksha), is not the same as pure which is devoid of karmas (karma-rahita). In this case, it is said to be pure only when the soul gives up infatuation (moha), etc. (PS 79), when it is free from attachment and aversion (PS 81) or has unity or oneness (aiyatta) with the pure (suddha) self. As such, it is worth acquiring (upadaya) (BA 20), viz. the objective to be achieved, and that the self which becomes purified (visuddha) by giving up attachment, etc., thereby getting rid of karmic bondage (SS 290). Jayasena's Faulty Explanation of Pure Unlike the statements of Kundakunda and Amrtachandra in Pravachanasara (192 above), Jayasena explains that the word “pure” (suddham in Pk., shuddham in Sk.) is devoid of all distortions of attachment, etc. impurities (raagadi samasta vibhava rahitam) (PS 192 JS). In the commentary on Pravachanasara 7, while Amrtachandra argues that the nature of a thing is its dharma (vastu svabhavat dharma), Jayasena feels that the adoption of pure consciousness devoid of distortions and impurities by the self is its dharma (nirvikara shuddha chaitanya dhartiti dharmah). Again, according to Amrtachandra, conduct (charitra) is “behaving according to one's own nature” (svarupe charanam). For Jayasena, conduct is activity in accordance with its nature of pure consciousness (shuddha chit svarupe charanam) (PS 7 AC and PS 7 JS). Similarly, in their commentaries on Panchastikayasara verses on the nature of the self, while Amrtachandra speaks of parinamika bhava (PKS 53 AC), and parinamikah (PKS 56 AC), Jayasena uses “shuddha parinamika bhava” (PKS 53, 56, 58 JS). In his commentary of Page #58 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 32 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Samayasara 6 as well, Amrtachandra explains the nature of the soul, i.e. consciousness (inayak bhava) as “shuddha” in the sense that it is quite different from all other substances, their states, conditions, modes and attributes and that the self is said to be “shuddhd” (pure), in the sense that jiva (soul or conscious entity) can never become a nonsoul and non-living (ajiva) material entity can never become jiva. The two substances, viz. life and non-life or the spirit and matter, are not liable to lose or interchange their nature and that jiva can never assume or have the characteristic attributes of touch, taste, smell, etc. of nonliving material entity or its modes or states of evolution (evashesha dravyantara bhavebhyoh bhinnatvena upasyanman shuddha iti abhilipyate) (SS 6 AC). Jayasena seems to be responsible for the prevalence of the mistaken belief among a large number of Jain scholars, especially the Kanjipanthi (a sect belonging to Kanji Svami), that the nature of the self is “pure” in the sense of being free from impurities. This view is similar to that upheld in both Advaita Vedanta and the Samkhya system of philosophy. Lest there be any doubt regarding the nature of the self as being neither pure nor impure is dispelled by Kundakunda himself through his emphatic assertion in Pravachanasara 8 cited above as well as Pravachanasara 9 which states: “The soul accepts the character of its state-of-evolution. When the soul evolves through the good or the evil, it becomes good or evil. When it is pure, it becomes pure” (PS 9). Lastly, when the word "pure” is used in the sense of purity, i.e. faultless, blameless sense, it signifies the potential to become pure (shuddha). In other words, one has to make efforts to make it pure. If the innate nature of the soul or self is considered to be "pure”, i.e. "pure consciousness”, it indeed becomes problematic to account for the impurity of the self as to how the “pure self” becomes impure. Moreover, if the self is already “pure”, there is no need to either make any efforts or adopt any means such as moral self-restraint, spiritual self-discipline, austerities, etc. to purify the impurities of attachment, aversion, deluded view and anger, pride, greed, etc. passions. Without such efforts, it is not possible to remove the impurities in the self. Without the removal of impurities, the soul cannot attain the highest objective of human endeavour, i.e. the supreme state of Godhood (Paramatma) or liberation. Page #59 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 33 Meaning of the Pure Nature of the Soul Thus, the word “shuddha” (pure) regarding the innate nature of the self or the true identity of the soul (consciousness) signifies the unmixed, chin-matra (consciousness-as-such alone), unconditioned state, or non-relational to karmas (karma-nirpeksha) condition of the self. while the word “vishuddha”, “vishuddhi" (purifying) (in PS 2, 5, 15, 78, 194, 220, etc. and PS 155, 180 AC) is generally used by Kundakunda in the sense of purifying the self, which is the result of the subsidence (aupshamik), partly subsidential and partly destruction (ksayopashamika) or destruction (kshaya) of passions that leads to liberation from the bondage of karman. The material karman (the neuro-physiological processes) cannot be obliterated by physical surgery alone. The conditioning effect and fresh bondage of the self as a result of material karman can only be nullified by the eradication of attachment, aversion, passions and the consequent freedom from karmas (karma-rahita). Kundakunda, therefore, lays greater emphasis on internal aspects or the mental attitude in regard to bondage as well as liberation. Renunciation (tyaga) of worldly concerns devoid of all consideration, regard, relation or expectation of any sort (nirvekkho in Pk., nirpeksha in Sk.) does not occur without purity (vishuddhi) of intention. When the mind (chitta) is not-pure (avishuddha), how can there be annihilation of karman? (PS 220). In Pravachanasara 192 and Samayasara 38 and 73, jiva and its nature is said to be "pure” in the sense that it does not transform itself into another, unconscious inanimate substance (dravyantara) (SS 6 AC) and in karma-nirpeksha parinamika bhava sense. Jiva is also said to be of a knowing nature (inayak bhava or jnayak svabhava). In other words, consciousness of something of knowing nature, which can be either pure or impure, does not necessarily mean that it is enlightened. However, it has the potential to become a pure, enlightened and supreme soul (paramatma). Potential means one has to make efforts to realize that potential. Thus, the nature of the soul (sabhava in Pk. or svabhava in Sk.) is declared to be janago (inayak in Sk.), i.e. something knowing or essentially something-that-knows (PS 200). Since the soul is jnayak alone (eva) through its nature, the only relation it has with other objects is only that of knower and knowable (jneya jnayak). It has no other Page #60 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 34 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES connection like that of possession and possessor. One should, therefore, renounce the notion of “mine” in regard to other objects, including body, wealth, etc. (PS 183, 190, 200 and PS 183, 190, 200 AC and SS 19-23). The unique characteristic of the conscious self is consciousness. The jnayak bhava (the nature of conscious awareness) is not to be confused with cognition or knowledge, which is only one of the attributes or aspects of consciousness. In Pravachanasara 35, Kundakunda observes: “He who knows is knowledge (jo janadi so nanam); but the self does not by the help of knowledge becomes something-that-is-knowing (inayak); knowledge evolves by itself, and all the objects reside in knowledge.” Clarifying the last point in this verse, Amrtachandra observes: “All the objects which are the causes of all the knowable appearances which are (really) the effects of the self-evolving knowledge, in a certain way reside in knowledge” (PS 35 AC). Knowledge is evolution (parinama) of the soul knowing, though the evolution cannot be separated from the evolvent self. Therefore, the forced supposition (klesha kalpana) of a separation of knower and knowledge is superfluous. The concept of jnayak bhava is discussed in detail in Samayasara 6, 7 and 356, etc. . The parinamika bhava is described in Samayasara as: (1) bhutarth (SS 11), i.e. the existent reality which exists in all living beings, in all conditions or states, including liberated state, and in all three times (past, present, and future), is without beginning and end (anadinidhan, PKS 53); (2) paramarth, i.e. the highest or the deeper inner reality of self; (3) pakshatikranta (SS 142), i.e. the transcendental state, which is independent of karmas (nirupadhi), neither bound by karmas nor unbound by karmas (SS 142) and as such neither pure nor impure, and beyond all biases and prejudices of different perspectives or viewpoints (naya paksha), bound, unbound, etc.; and (4) Samayasara (SS 142), the essential nature or the essence (sara) of self (jiva). In Pravachanasara, the word “shuddha” (pure) as in pure conscious attentiveness (shuddha upayoga), is used in the sense of blameless, faultless, pure consciousness, devoid of karma (karma rahita) as also in the sense of being unaffected, unmixed, only, kevala, or unconditioned by karman, i.e. karma-nirpeksha (non-relational to karmas) parinamika bhava, consciousness-as-such or the nature of self. The nature of the self is considered to be pure because it is Page #61 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION consciousness-as-such (chin-matra) and also because it is unique and unmixed and being karma-nirpeksha, having no relation whatsoever with karmas. It is not causally connected with either samsara or moksha, either bondage or liberation. Though the soul is associated with karmas since beginningless time and as such impure but that is not considered the inherent nature of the self. Upayoga The word “uvaoga” (upayoga in Sk.), a “rarity in Shvetambara books”, but referred frequently in Kundakunda's works is translated in several different ways. (See Introduction by F. W. Thomas). This word has been generally translated in Pravachanasara as “psychic attention” by Faddegon and as “manifestation of consciousness” by A.N. Upadhye. (In his footnote to PS 69, Upadhye states: “The term upayoga is very difficult to be rendered into English; the shade of its sense often depends on the context; similar is the case with dharma and other words."]23 W.J. Johnson translates upayoga as “application”. Jacobi translates it as “realization of its (soul's] developments” whereas Deleu translates it as "spiritual function". Frauwallner translates it as Betaetigung, i.e. "work” or “activity", but Johnson prefers to translate it as “perhaps activation' actuation'.” P.S. Jaini tfänslates upayoga as "awareness” and Nathmal Tatia terms it as "active consciousness” (see Nathmal Tatia, Studies in Jaina Philosophy, p. 55; on page 70, however, Tatia translates upayoga as “consciousness,” which is said to be the defining characteristic of soul) (TS 2.8) which would be better."24 In Tattvartha Sutra (TS 2.8), upayoga is said to be the differentia, the definition or the distinguishing characteristic (lakshan) of jiva (soul). The word “upayoga" in Tattvartha Sutra is translated as "attention, consciousness, attentiveness" by J.L. Jaini; "consciousness” and “active or attentive consciousness” by S.A. Jain; and “sentience,” which in turn, is explained as "awareness or consciousness” by Nathmal Tatia.25 Unlike Tattvartha Sutra (2.8) wherein upayoga (conscious attentiveness) is described as the (only) distinguishing characteristic of the soul (jiva), in Kundakunda's works (PKS 16, 27 and PS 127), the nature of soul is said to consist of chetana (consciousness) and upayoga, which constitute the main quality of soul (jiva guna, PKS 16). In Panchastikayasara (PKS 16, 27), Chakravarti translates chetana Page #62 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 36 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES as "consciousness" and upayoga as "manifestation of consciousness" in two ways or two modes of consciousness, darshan (perception) and jnana (knowledge), which "are mainly cognitive or thought elements". Consciousness also includes emotion and will. The affective and volitional or conative element is also recognized in Jaina system.26 In Pravachanasara (PS 127), Faddegon translates upayoga as "psychic attention of thought (chetana)" "manifestation (parinama) of thinking (chetana), august, in the form of consciousness (samvrtti)" (PS 127 AC), while A. N. Upadhye states that jiva is constituted of "sentiency" (chetana) and "manifestation of consciousness (upayoga)". In Pravachanasara, Kundakunda mainly describes three kinds of upayoga - pure (shuddha), auspicious (shubha) and inauspicious (ashubha), which are defined in verses 14, 69 (also 157) and 158 respectively. Three Aspects of Consciousness Kundakunda also refers to the three aspects of consciousness (PS 123-125, see also PKS 38-39), viz. jnana chetana, karma chetana and karmaphala chetana. In other words, the evolution of consciousness (chetana) is considered with reference to knowledge (jnana chetana), which comprehends objects, the self and other, deed or action (karma chetana), which is undertaken by the soul, and fruit of action (both past and present action) (karmaphala chetana), which is either pleasure or pain (PS 123-124). And every soul, according to its own status in the course of evolution is capable of being in its own way the knower (jnata), the actor (karta) and enjoyer (bhokta). Various other Translations of Upayoga In the various translations of Samayasara,27 the term "upayoga" is translated as "conscious attentiveness" (SS 88, 90), “attentive soul" (SS 89), "conscious attention" and "attention" (SS 100) by J. L. Jaini. A. Chakravarti has translated upayoga as "being of the nature of self" (SS 88), "the Self of the nature of upayoga (pure thought and perception)" (SS 89, 90), and “mental activity" (SS 100). The affective, cognitive and volitional or conative modes or functions of consciousness are also known as the three kinds of upayoga, referred to in Samayasara (SS 88-90, 94-95), viz. darshan (this darshan is different from perception and is translated variously as feeling, intuitive awareness, view, world-view, belief, faith), jnana (knowledge or cognitive awareness) and charitra (conduct, volition) [these could be Page #63 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION enlightened but when deluded they are known as deluded view (mithyatva or mithya-darshan), deluded or wrong knowledge (mithya jnana) and wrong conduct (lack of moral and spiritual self-restraints (avirati or mithya-charitra)]. Jethalal S. Zaveri, a Shvetambara scholar, translates upayoga as "consciousness” (pages 90, 100, 135, 138, 151, 163) and “activity of the soul” (page 146). The characteristic quality of the soul is said to be “consciousness (upayoga),” a complex of two cognitive faculties - knowledge and intuition. Of this twofold upayoga, knowledge is described as “apprehension of an object with its contents” and intuition as “apprehension of a thing without its contents” (page 91). Knowledge, he adds, “includes intellect, competence and technique” (page 91). And Vijay K. Jain translates upayoga as “consciousness” (SS 88-90). Chetana and Upayoga are not the same Thus, it is evident that those who follow the line of thinking of Tattvartha Sutra often make no distinction between chetana and upayoga. I. C. Shastri insists that upayoga alone is the essential definition or charactéristic of the soul (jiva) on the basis of Shvetambara scriptures (Bhagavati (II, 10) and Uttaradhyayana Sutras (28, 10)) and Tattvartha Sutta (TS 2.8). He does not refer to Kundakunda's statement that the essential definition or the distinguishing characteristic of the soul substance (jiva dravya) is consciousness (chetana) and manifestation, attention or function of consciousness (upayoga) (PS 127, PKS 16, 27), which are not the same. Upayoga is the application, manifestation, mode, or rather the active, functional and the attentive aspect of consciousness, but not consciousness-as-such (chetana) which is the essence of jiva or the soul substance and is the underlying substratum of all its attributes, modes, conditions and even forms of upayoga. Upayoga is the manifestation, modification or the state-of-'evolution (parinama) of jiva, which has the form of function or mode of soul substance (PS 127 AC). Shastri, however, persists in following the line of thinking of Tattvarta Sutra (2.8), in spite of the fact that he himself quotes Digambara philosopher Vidyananda to the effect that “upayoga means attention or application of consciousness (chaitanya) which is the essence (svatattva) of jiva. Vidyananda points out the difference between essence and definition (lakshana) by stating that Page #64 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 38 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES "the essence is a definition as well as the definee. It occupies both the positions; while mere definition is not necessarily given that position." (TSV, p.318). The self or the soul is declared to be cheda (conscious entity) (PKS 27) and as such is identified with consciousness (chetana). Since upayoga (conscious attentiveness) is only a particular mode of consciousness, it cannot be identified with self. In this context, Shastri states that upayoga is an essential definition of the self. We cannot separate it from the latter. There is no soul without upayoga and there is no upayoga without soul. Yet, we cannot say that they are absolutely one and the same thing. Upayoga is only a part of the psychical function. Other functions are feeling, willing, etc. which, according to Jainism, are not included into upayoga which is the activity of cognition only, a particular expression of consciousness (chaitanya) which covers the entire range of psychical life. This is also one of the reasons for regarding it as the essence and upayoga, as the definition of soul.28 In his introduction to Gommatsara Jivakanda, Jaini observes: Consciousness... is the mighty real characteristics of life. It is the most essential differentia between the living and non-living... you must be alive to read these words. You must be attentive to feel that something is there. You must conate [in the sense of intuition, darshan] these words. Then again you must be attentive to perceive, then alone you begin to know them, i.e. have perception, conception, judgement, retention, memory, recognition, induction, or deduction from them. Consciousness is an active, responsible agent; it is the Doer of all actions; and it is the Enjoyer of the fruits of these actions, good or bad. It is necessary to remember these, lest we should fall into the error of exempting the soul, ego or individual consciousness from all responsibility for his actions, good or bad, and thus at one stroke uproot all ethical distinctions and fullstop to discriminate actions.29 In Kundakunda's works, jiva or appa (atma), i.e. soul or the self, is said to be of the nature of chetana (consciousness) and upayoga (conscious attentiveness, the application, or function of consciousness) (PS 127) [in PKS 16, chetana and upayoga are said to be the qualities or attributes of jiva (jivaguna)], while in PKS 27, jiva is said to have life, consciousness, i.e. conscious entity (cheda in Pk. and chetayita in Sk.) with upayoga as its distinguishing property, special or particular characteristic (upayoga visheshitah). Chetana and upayoga are not the same. Page #65 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 39 Three Kinds of Upayoga Pravachanasara 155, states: “The self (appa in Pk. atma in Sk.) is of the nature of or has for self psychic-attention (upayogatma) and upayoga is stated as knowledge and intuition [vision).” And this psychic-attention of the self is also auspicious (shubha) or inauspicious (ashubha [good or evil] (PS 155), depending on the character of its state-of evolution. When it evolves through the pure (shuddha), it becomes pure (PS 9). In other words, it possesses the nature of that through which it evolves during the time of the evolution (PS 8). In his commentary, Amrtachandra draws our attention to some significant aspects in regard to upayoga. The particular upayoga characteristic of the self (i.e. consciousness) accounts for the absolute distinctness (atyanta vibhakta) of the self (from inert inanimate matter, etc. other substances) and is (also) the cause of the self's conjunction (sanyoga) with other substance (Introductory remark to PS 155 and PS 155 AC). Moreover, upayoga, indeed, is the nature of the self, since it evolves in obedience to its (the self's) character of consciousness (chaitanya anuvidhayi parinama) (PS 155 AC, also SAS commentary of Pujyapada and Akalanka's TRV commentary on TS 2.8), i.e. it (upayoga) has sameness (anvyayı) of nature or character as consciousness. Continuing his commentary on Pravachanasara 155, Amrtachandra states: “And that (upayoga) is knowledge and intuition, since consciousness, according as it is definite or indefinite, has both forms. Now this psychic-attention is specialized in two ways, according to purity and impurity. Of these the pure is without attachment; the impure is with attachment, which again is two-fold good or auspicious (shubha) and evil or inauspicious (ashubha), because of the two-fold character of the attachment, as being in the form of sanity (purifying, vishuddhi) or affliction, distress and morbidity (sanklesha)” (PS 155 AC). The impure psychic-attention (upayoga) is evident or visible in the form of vishuddhi or sanklesh. It thus has a dual aspect of shubha and ashubha or double aspect of punya (righteousness or piety) and papa (evil or vicious). This is the cause of the soul's conjunction with other substance (para dravyasya sanyoga karana). In the absence of punya and papa, only pure psychic-attention remains and that is not the cause of conjunction with another substance (PS 156 AC). In other words, . Page #66 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 40 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES consciousness-as-such (chetana) is not the cause of conjunction with other substances. It is only the imure psychic-attention (upayoga) in the form of shubha or ashubha, which is the cause of conjunction with other substance. In other words, it acts as the supportive factor or the auxiliary cause (nimitta karana) of bondage with other substance (material karman). Good thoughts (shubha parinama) is the cause of dharma (righteousness or piety, i.e. punya) karma, and bad or evil thoughts (ashubha parinama) is cause of adharma (sin or papa); giving up both leads to pure, as a result of which no bondage of karma takes place (PP 2.71). Akalanka's Definition of Upayoga Upayoga is defined by Akalanka as bahya-abhyantara hetu dvaya sannidhane yathasambhavam uplabdhyu chaitanya anuvidhayi parinam utayogah, (Akalanka, Tattvarthavartika: Rajavartika, TRV commentary on TS 2.8), i.e. conscious attentiveness is the state-of-evolution in obedience to its (the self's) character of consciousness, of the nature or character of psychic state, mode or attention resulting from "available” two types of external and two kinds of internal conditions or auxiliary causes being placed together as far as possible in the vicinity or close proximity of one another. The two types of external conditions or auxiliary causes are: (1) atma-bhuta, (intrinsic), i.e. eye, ear, etc. senses, which are formed or developed in the body and associated with consciousness; and (2) anatma-bhuta (extrinsic), i.e. lamp, sunlight, electricity, etc. The two kinds of internal conditions or auxiliary causes of upayoga are: (1) anatma-bhuta (extrinsic), i.e. vibrations in the soul resulting from the material clusters (vargana) suitable for constituting body (gross and subtle), speech, and mind (i.e. structural aspects of physical mind, such as nervous system and brain); and (2) atma-bhuta (intrinsic), i.e. cognition, etc. mental or psychic states dependent on external or internal factors, personal experiences, and the inner capacity and vigour of soul. The word “available" in this definition indicates conditioned state of consciousness, implying thereby that consciousness-as-such is the state of only or purely consciousness, which is the very nature of the soul and the substratum of all its attributes, modes or forms of conscious activity, pure and impure. In other words, even the specific transformations, evolutions or mutations of psychic states, including Page #67 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION distorted, perverted, impure states, of soul (consciousness) is known as functional or applied forms or modes of consciousness (upayoga), just as the transformed states or distorted (vikar) modes or forms of gold such as bracelet, ring, ear-rings and armlet, etc. being in obedience to the character of goldness, are known as gold, which remains their substratum. The Samkhya argue that pleasure, pain and infatuation that are states-of-evolution which adhere to the self's character as consciousness should be characterised as manifestation of consciousness (upayoga). In this context, however, the various transformations of upayoga are said to be the distorted states-of-evolution of knowledge and intuition. Though the two views seem to be contrary or inconsistent to one another, there is no flaw here, since consciousness remains the substratum as much of knowledge, etc. as of pleasure, pain, delusion, etc. Consciousness is the extraordinary general characteristic of the soul or nature (dharma) of the self (atma). Jiva does not lose its nature or property of consciousness, even in close proximity of other substances, which is found in the forms of knowledge, intuition, etc. as also in the forms of pleasure, etc. Though different substances commingle or are mixed up and mutually iifterpenetrating, they are distinguished by their own distinctive intrinsic natures or characteristics. Just as gold though united with silver is distinguished by its extraordinary property or characteristics of yellow colour, density or weight, etc., so also the self, though united (ekatva) with material substance (say body) from the perspective of bondage, is distinguished by its own intrinsic defining characteristic of knowledge, etc. conscious attentiveness (upayoga). The defining characteristic of upayoga is of two kinds: atma-bhuta (intrinsic, inalienable or inseparable) and anatma-bhuta (extrinsic, alienable or separable). Heat is the inseparable characteristic of fire whereas the stick of Devadatta is the separable characteristic. Upayoga is the inseparable characteristic of self (atma). (Akalanka's TRV commentary on TS 2.8). Similarly, jivatva (consciousness-as-such) is an inseparable characteristic of the soul but the human or animal condition (gati) of existence, is a separable state or mode of jiva (soul). Moreover, unlike jivatva, the six classes of immobile and mobile souls (jiva nikaya, PS 182), the 14 soul classes (jiva samasa), classified Page #68 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES primarily on the basis of differences of body, senses and mind, the soul quests (margana sthana) (SS 53) based on psycho-physical living organisms, including sex, passion, etc., and various kinds of living beings (jiva sthana SS 55 and 65-67), having one to five senses and both completely developed and incompletely developed, subtle and gross, are other than consciousness-as-such and separable modes of jiva (soul or consciousness). All of them or all these modes pertaining to the body are given the appellation of jiva or are said to be jiva in the scriptures from the external, other-referential point of view (vyavahara naya) (SS 56 and 67). Rarity of the Concept of Upayoga in Shvetambara Texts Commenting on F.W. Thomas, remark that the conception or the doctrine of upayoga, is a “rarity in Shvetambara books (texts),” – which is “at the heart of Kundakunda's soteriology in the Pravachanasard”, Johnson states: Among the earliest Surviving texts there appears to be no direct reference to upayoga in the Ayaramga, the Suyagadamga, or the Dasaveyaliya Sutras. rm does appear, however, at Uttarajjhayana XXVIII. 10, where it is said that the characteristic of the jiva is manifestation (or application) through (or with) 'knowledge, perception, (darshan), happiness and suffering' (jivo uvaogalakkhano nanenam damsanenam ca suhena ya duhena ya Utt. XXVIII.10). Jacobi translates this as 'The characteristic... of the soul [is] the realization (upayoga) of knowledge, faith, happiness and misery - 1895, p. 153. It is not clear whether upayoga, which can have the meanings 'application', 'manifestation' or employment,' should be taken here in its full technical sense of application' or 'manifestation of consciousness. The passage could mean that nana (jnana, knowledge), damsana, (darshan), etc., are particular types of upayoga, or that upayoga is one of a number of characteristics of the jiva; but in either case it need not mean 'consciousness' as such, although the assumption among commentators and translators is that it does." Kundakunda distinguishes between chetana and upayoga. He identifies the soul (jiva) with chetana or consciousness-as-such or considers chetana to be the essence of jiva, having the nature of upayoga (upayogamaya) (PS 127) or the particular characteristic of (upayoga visheshita) (PKS 27). In Panchastikayasara 16, he states that chetana and upayoga are the attributes of jiva (jiva guna) (PKS 16). However, Amrtachandra, in his commentary thereon argues that chetana can Page #69 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 43 be of the nature of experiencing pure consciousness of knowledge of the self or impure consciousness of the fruits of one's karma. Upayoga, on the other hand, evolves in obedience to the soul's character of consciousness pure or impure depending on whether it is with or without thought constructions (vikalpa) (PKS 16 AC). The following verse of (Uttarajjhayana XXVIII. 11), Johnson remarks, has a different system of classification, (which makes it] clear that uvaoga (upayoga) is one among a number of characteristics of the jiva, and not yet the defining characteristic. The characteristics of the soul (jiva) are knowledge, faith, conduct, austerities, energy (viriyam) and uvaoga (application). Jacobi (ibid.) translates uvaoga here as realization (of its developments). According to Johnson, these two verses of chapter XXVIII of Uttaradhyayana Sutra (Uttarajjhayana Sutta in Pk.), which he acknowledges was “a relatively late addition to the body of the Uttarajjhayana” [this “late addition” could be posterior or subsequent to Kundakunda, and as such the Shvetambara text seems to have borrowed or inherited the concept of Kundakunda's upayoga, though Johnson feels it otherwise since in his mistaken view Kundakunda flourished in the early 5th century AD or later). Johnson maintains that the formal division” of upayoga into jnana and darshan has not yet been made. He ignores Kundakunda's works, Tattvartha Sutra (TS 2.9) and even the Shvetambara text Vihayapannatti (Bhagavati) (II. 10a (147b), which states that guna (essential property or attributes) of the atthikaya (fundamental entity) jiva makes possible uvaoga (the spiritual function) (Deleu's translation). And at (Bhagavati II.10c (149a) it is asserted that the "characteristic (lakkhana) of soul is the spiritual function (uvaoga)”. The soul by its own nature (ayabhavenam) possesses will (viriya) “which enables it to apply this spiritual function in the infinite number of possibilities or modes (pajjava or paryaya) of knowledge (jnana) and intuition (darshan)” – thus the “true nature of soul” (jiva bhava) is revealed through upayoga (Vihayapannatti II. 10c).31 Five Psychic Dispositions of Jiva In Tattvartha Sutra (TS 2.1), Umasvami or Umasvati has described jiva in terms of bhavas (psychic dispositions or states of the soul) of five kinds arising from the four types (subsidential, destructive, partly subsidential and partly destructive, and coming into operation or rise Page #70 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES of karmas, i.e. the fruition of karmas), or conditions of karmas plus the jiva's natural or inherent bhava (parinamika bhava), independent of karmas. These five bhavas are said to be the soul's own psychic states (svatattva). In other words, parinamika bhava is the natural state of the jiva, which is the substratum of, or has the potential to undergo modification(s) (in the form of subsidential, etc. four bhavas (modes)] under the influence of karman and for that very reason, it is in itself non-relational to karman, i.e. karma nirpeksha, independent or different from the subsidential, etc. four types of modifications, not free from or devoid of karman (karma rahita). Evolvement Nature of the Soul At Viyahapannatti XVIII. 10e (760a), Somila, a Brahmin, asks Lord Mahavira whether he is “one or two imperishable (akkhaya) eternal (avvayaya) and stable or constant (avatthiya) or has he different forms in past, present and future (anega-bhủya-bhava-bhaviya)?”, In his reply, Lord Mahavira states: He is all of these, since from the point of view of [the] essence [of his soul, Abhayadeva's vrtti on Viyahapannatti] (davv atthayae) he is one, from the point of view of knowledge and vision (nana-damsan atthayae) he is two; as to paesas or pradesh (space points) he is imperishable (akkhaya or akshaya in Sk.), immutable (avvayaya) (its correct translation should be eternal] and stationary (avatthiya) (its correct translation should be stable or constant)... [but as to uvaoga he) has different forms [(or modes, paryaya)] in past, present and future. Here it is interesting to note that the form of uvaoga, as `spiritual function is something that changes”; [it signifies that it is evolvent (parinami or parinamansheel) and yet eternal and stable or constant); moreover, it is essentially something that the soul changes itself (Note also that jnana and darshan share the same context as upayoga here). 32 This translation of the Shvetambara scripture by Johnson makes it amply clear that the translations of both Deleu and Johnson of the word “avvava” (avvayaya in Sk.) as immutable, i.e. unchanging and of avatthiya (avasthita in Sk.) as stationary in Somil's question and in Lord Mahavira's reply thereto are not correct (see Paea sadda mahannavo Prakrit-Hindi Dictionary, ed. K.R. Chandra (Ahmedabad: Prakrit Jain Vidhya Vikas Fund, 1987). Page #71 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION Moreover, Viyahapannatti also uses the terms “anagarovautta" and "sagarovauttă” to designate two types of uvaoga. Following Schubring's translation of sagara-and anagara-uvaoga, (see Schubring 1962, para 82), Deleu renders these as “faculty of abstract or indistinct imagination” and “faculty of concrete or distinct imagination” respectively (see, for instance, Viy. VI.3.5 (257b), and XIX.8 (770b)). Uvautta is the Prakrit from the Sanskrit upayukta, meaning employed or ‘applicable to'; similarly, upayoga,... have the meaning of ‘application,' ‘manifestation', or ‘employment' (of consciousness). 33 Deleu's use of “imagination” (see above) to translate the term "seems eccentric”. But at Viyahapannati V. 4 (221b), he renders uvautta as “attentive”. At XVIII.8.3 (755a) he defines "sagara” as “formally distinct” and anagara as “formally indistinct”. The Prakrit term “agard” corresponds to the Sanskrit akara "form" or "figure”. Thus, Deleu considers uvautta as "attentive," sagarovautta as “attentive to something with form," and anagarovautta as "attentive to something without form” (i.e. determinate or indeterminate cognition/manifestation of consciousness), corresponding to the two kinds of upayoga, jnana and darshan ('knowing and 'perceiving'). 34 The concept of upayoga (conscious attentiveness) which occupies a prominent place in Kundakunda's works, plays a significant role in life. It is stated that “a substance (including the soul substance) possesses the nature of that through which it evolves during the time of the evolution" (PS 8) and that "the soul accepts the character of its state-of-evolution. When the soul evolves through the good or the evil, it becomes good or evil. When it is pure, it becomes pure.” (PS 9) In other words, it is up to the individual soul how he wants to evolve in the only time he has before him, i.e. the present. Being the lord or the architect (prabhu) of his own destiny (PKS 27), the self is free to evolve through the impure or distorted mental states of anger, etc. passions and attachment, aversion and deluded view, which are the cause of bondage, or desist from them. If the activity of the soul is performed with conscious awareness/ conscious attentiveness, the use of intellect (buddhi-purvak) and sense of responsibility, the self will not prefer to choose a course of action which is detrimental to its interests. However, if an action is undertaken without conscious attentiveness and use of intellect, i.e. abuddhi-purvak and as such under subconscious compulsions, instinctive urges and Page #72 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES impulsive drives, under the influence of the neuro-physiological processes/brain states, i.e. physical karma, and as such "unconsciously planned and executed,” it will be full of “telling errors of perception, memory and judgement” according to neuroscientist Gazzaniga.” These are obviously lacking in coherence, a balanced and detached view, discriminative insight and unity of conscious experience, which are the prerogatives of conscious entity and the domain of conscious attentiveness (upayoga). Importance of Upayoga compared with Mindfulness in Buddhism The concept of upayoga occupies a significant place in Jainism. This may be compared to the importance attached to “mindfulness” in Buddhism. Upayoga enables us to focus one's attention (conscious attention) to the task at hand by concentrating all the energy of both mind and body on one specific target or goal at a time. If one wants to fulfill one's potential, one must focus one's attention on the present, here and now. At that one moment in time, what has happened in the past does not really matter because it has already been, while what may happen in the future is yet to come. Success in life is not possible without the attentiveness of consciousness (upayoga) or mindfulness. Conscious attention, mindfulness is so powerful because it gives us the ability to take charge of our thoughts and feelings. If we do not fully attend to these – if we live our lives in a state of constant distraction - we are condemned to keep experiencing whatever thoughts, interpretations and emotions habitually recur. 36 It is only by the power of attentiveness or mindfulness, i.e. concentrating or focusing all our energy on the present, that one will be able to direct one's cognitive, emotional and conative or volitional faculties or aspects/modes of consciousness in the fulfillment or accomplishment of the objective. In Power of Now, as Eckhart Tolle points out that it is only by becoming deeply conscious of the present moment that one can hope to transform one's mode of consciousness. Otherwise, one will only be a slave to one's instinctive impulses, biases or habits and emotional responses that silently or unconsciously shape the most important attitudes and decisions in one's life. In order to propagate the powerful and wide-ranging benefits of mindfulness practice, extensive research is being conducted by the Page #73 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 47 Centre for Mindfulness in Medicine, established at the University of Massachusetts in 1995 by Jon Kabat-Zinn, under the inspiration of Dalai Lama, the Buddhist leader. The Issue of Shudha, Shubha and Ashubha Upayoga The self of the nature of upayoga is described to be of two kinds, viz. darshan (intuitive awareness) and jnana (cognition or knowledge) (TS 2.9 and PS 155). In Samayasara, upayoga is said to be three-fold, darshan, jnana and charitra (volition or conduct (SS 89-90, 94-95). In a ethico-spiritual context, Kundakunda has also deemed it necessary to discuss upayoga in the sense of pure (shuddha) (PS 14), good or auspicious (suho in Pk. or shubha in Sk.) conscious attentiveness (PS 11, 69-70 and 157) and evil or inauspicious (asuho in Pk. or ashubha in Sk.), psychic disposition or attention (PS 12 and 158). Most people agree that ashubha (inauspicious, unwholesome thoughts or sinful activities) are to be completely abandoned (atyanta heya, PS 12 AC), and shuddha (pure or the absence of passions, attachment, aversion, and deluded view), which is the direct cause of liberation (nirvana), should be sought in every way. There are several misperceptions and a great deal of controversy in regard to shubha. There are acute differences about its role in liberation of the soul and whether it can be considered desirable and to be followed and practiced (upadeya) or is it undesirable and worth renouncing and abandoning altogether (beya)? A group of people known as Kanjipanthi (the followers of Kanji Svami, a Shvetambara monk, who along with thousands of his followers joined the Digambara tradition), firmly affirm that the activity and psychic disposition or conscious attentiveness of shubha or punya (auspicious, wholesome thoughts, righteousness, piety or moral conduct of self-restraint) is as much undesirable and worth abandoning (heya) as ashubha or sinful (papa) activity. In the process, they blur the distinction between shubha and ashubha upayoga by emphasizing that both of them are impure (ashuddha) upayoga. This is a gross misrepresentation of Kundakunda's views in this regard as presented in his works, including Pravachanasara, as well as other Jaina texts. The evolution of the self accompanied by attachment, aversion and a deluded view is the cause of bondage of the physical karman. Of these, deluding view (moha) and aversion (dvesha) are evil or inauspicious (ashubha). Attachment is of two kinds: shubha and Page #74 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 48 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES ashubha. Good (shubha) attachment (prashasta raga) has a purifying (vishuddhi) effect whereas ashubha attachment (aprashasta raga) has the effect of affliction, distress and morbidity (sanklesh) (PS 155 AC and PS 180 AC). Thus, it is asserted that those, who are devoid of evil psychic-attention (ashubha upayoga) by annihilating a deluded view, aversion and disapproved attachment (aprashasta raga) and are sometimes possessed of pure psychic-attention (shuddha upayoga), by putting an end to the arousal of passions (kashaya), and sometimes possessed of good psychic-attention (shubha upayoga) through ripening of excellent attachment (prashasta raga), are, through being themselves abodes of liberation, saviours of men; and others who manifest excellent feelings of devotion to them become partakers of merits (punya) (PS 260 AC). Thus, ashubha attachment (aprashasta raga) is considered undesirable and worth abandoning (heya), whereas shubha attachment (prashasta raga, i.e. excellent attachment) is not deemed to be undesirable. In fact, shubha raga is considered commendable, praiseworthy, desirable and worthy of acquisition (upadeya). A clear distinction is also made between ashubha upayoga (evil psychicattention) and shubha upayoga (good psychic-attention), which is not condemned as undesirable or worth abandoning. Mistaken View of Kanjipanthi in Equating Shubha and Ashubha In support of their mistaken view that "there is no difference" whatsoever between punya (righteousness, piety or merit) and papa (evil or sin) and that both are equally undesirable and worth abandoning, the Kanjipanthi state that both shubha or punya and ashubha or papa are the cause of karmic bondage just as both gold and iron fetters bind a person (PS 77 AC; also SS 146). Shubha also undeniably binds a person but that does not imply that there is "no difference" between shubha or punya and ashubha or papa. Let us now examine the above contention of Kanjipanthi by carefully scrutinizing Pravachanasara verse 77 and Amrtachandra's commentary thereon in the light of Kundakunda's statement in this regard at several places in this very work as well as some of his other works and Amrtachandra's commentaries thereon. In Pravachanasara verse 77 Kundakunda states: He who does not believe that there is nothing particular or special (nasti Page #75 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 49 vishesha in Sk., natthi viseso in Pk.) between punya and papa (i.e. the two are similar) in the way or sense stated above (evam) (this refers to previous verses) moves about, covered with infatuation or muffled in delusion (moha sanchhanna) in the cycle of transmigratory existence. This verse does not suggest that "there is no difference”, whatsoever, as most scholars, including Faddegon, translate it in both English and Hindi. Moerover, the qualifying phrase "moha sanchhana" is very significant in that it signifies that it is primarily because of infatuation (moha) that the self (jiva) wanders aimlessly in the cycle of transmigratory existence. In Pravachanasara 43, it is clearly stated that in the condition of coming into operation or the rise (uday) of karman, only one, who is filled with a deluded view, attachment and aversion necessarily incurs bondage. In other words, the self alone is responsible for bondage by being deluded, attached, etc. This verse (PS 77), as Kundakunda and Amrtachandra point out, has to be understood in the context of previous verses. The immediately preceding verse explains that the sensorial pleasure, of which shubba upayoga is the means (sadhan), is misery alone (eva) (PS 76). Kundakunda states: “Happiness acquired by means of the senses, is dependent, accompanied by obstacles or distractions, interrupted or terminable, cause of bondage and unequal, and hence it is indeed misery only (eva)” (PS 76), or that "it is misery in disguise. Commenting on it, Amrtachandra observes: Sensorial pleasure, although originating from merit, is actually misery, for it is dependent, accompanied by obstacles or distractions, interrupted, cause of bondage, unequal; It is depenent, for it rests on something else, since it has in something else its condition. It is accompanied by obstacles or distractions, for it is utterly confused, since it is attended by different longings, such as hunger, thirst, etc. It is interrupted, for oppositions are noticed in it, since we realize it as proceeding by the rise of good emotionalkarman (sad-vedya=sata-vedaniya) disturbed by the rise of bad emotionalkarman. It is a cause of bondage, for in its outcome it is hard to bear, since it is covered with a thick mass of dust of karman, collecting in the train of the army of the vices, passion, etc., trailing along the road of sensual enjoyments. It is unequal, for it is utterly unsteady, since it evolves through increase and decrease. And it is, indeed misery only. Thus, even merit turns out to be, like sin, the means of misery (PS 76 AC). It the earlier two verses (PS 74-75), it is stated: “If manifold merits, Page #76 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES resulting from (good psychic states of) evolution make the souls, including those of the gods, to necessarily thirst or crave for senseobjects (vishaya trashna) (they are the cause of misery] (PS 74 and PS 74 AC; and that these (souls), then, due to their thirst roused and made unhappy by such thirstings, or cravings, wish for obtaining till death the pleasures of sense-objects, thereby being burnt by misery" (PS 75), since expectation of obtaining joy or pleasures from sense objects is incorrect understanding of the reality of things, i.e. deluded view; it is like a deer's desire of finding water from mirage (mrgatrashna) (PS 75 AC)). In his expectation of obtaining pleasure in sense objects, and feeling unhappy in having unpleasant sense objects, the soul develops likes and dislikes, i.e. attachment and aversion towards them. Attachment, aversion and a deluded view are the direct causes of the influx as well as consequent bondage of karmas since indulgence in sense objects and anger, etc. passions or attachment and aversion, are the characteristics of evil (ashubha) or sinful (papa) psychic attention (PS 180 JS). Given the persistence of the above conditions and circumstances, punya, thus, turns out to be similar to papa. In his commentary on Pravachanasara 77 also, Amrtachandra explains how there is nothing particular or special” between punya and papa alongwith the purport of this verse. He states that the circumstances in which the two (punya and papa) seem to be similar or that the dichotomy or duality of merit (punya) and sin (papa), like a duality of good and evil psychic-attention or of pleasure and pain, is hardly maintainable or sustainable in several circumstances: (1) when things are viewed from transcendental nature of the self (paramarthatah) (karma-nirpeksha parinamika bhava, i.e. consciousnessas-such having no relation to karmas, which is beyond dualities and relative opposites of good and evil]. As a result, both punya and papa cannot be considered to be an attribute of the soul and as such they are said to be similar, i.e. “there is nothing particular or special” between punya and papa (anatma-dharmatva avisheshatvat); (2) when prosperity and higher status, etc. is acquired through or as result of punya karma, which is also the condition thereof, one takes pride, in his superior status, position or condition. This leads to an egotistical (ahankarik) difference between punya and papa, like a gold and iron fetter, (thereby giving rise to adhyavasana bhavas (the psychic Page #77 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION dispositions of pride, greed, etc. passions)]; (3) if such a person chooses the path of righteousness, good or virtuous activities (dharma or punya) [for the purpose, desire or the expectation of obtaining position of lord of heaven (Indra), etc. prosperity, wealth, etc. and sense pleasures in the future (i.e. nidan) (dhammam bhoga nimittam, and not for demolishing the karma (SS 273-275)]; (4) as a consequence thereof, one's psychic attention or cognitive, volitional and emotional activities, functions and processes of the mind (chitta bhitti) becomes darkened, obscured or coloured (uparakta) (with the adhyavasana bhavas of pride, greed, etc. passions, delusion (mithyatva), lack of self-restraints (avirati), attachment, aversion, etc.); and (5) as a result, one comes to scorn or disdain one's property, energy, vigour or capacity (shakti) for purification (vishuddhi)] or pure psychicattention (shuddha upayoga). In this way, he experiences or suffers bodily misery (and mental distress] as long as the transmigratory existence of the cycle of births and deaths (samsara) lasts (PS 77 AC). Conscious of the above-mentioned sombre aspects of punya, one should keep oneself away from being attached to pleasant objects of senses or nurturing a feeling of Aversion towards unpleasant objects, and orient oneself in the direction of purification of one's psychicattention (PS 78 and PS 78 AC) through self-restraint (samyam) and austerities (tapa), etc. (PS 14). By behaving in the manner described above, i.e. indulgence in and attachment to sense objects (vishaya) and pride, greed, etc. passions (kashaya), which are the characteristics of evil (ashubha) attachment (PS 180 JS), those endowed with auspicious or good psychic-attention (shubha upayoga) and great deal of merits (punya) will be acting like those imbued with evil or sin (papa). The pleasures of sense objects, acquired by the virtuous activities (punya), eventually lead to misery (PS 76 and PP 2.59). The worldly prosperity and name, fame (vaibhava), etc. obtained by virtuous deeds leads to pride (mada or ahankara), and pride generates deluded intellect (mudha mati), which, in turn, leads to sinful, vicious acts (papa); such punya is not desired (PP 2.60). -. Both Kundakunda and Amrtachandra were well aware that their description between punya and papa was selective when they stated Page #78 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES that under these circumstances, there is nothing “particular or special (vishesha)” between punya and papa (PS 77) and that the dichotomy or the duality (dvaita) between them is not sustainable (PS 77 AC). Similar sentiments were expressed when they argued that “how can (shubha or punya) be considered to be good, virtuous or desirable (sushil) when it leads (jiva) into the transmigratory existence of the cycles of births and deaths (samsara)” (SS 145), binds the soul, as ashubha does, in the same manner as fetters made of gold or iron bind a person (SS 146) and is destructive of independence of the self (SS 147). Kundakunda and Amrtachandra were aware that there is considerable difference between punya and papa, or shubha and ashubha (see PS 11-12, SS 145 AC). Amrtachandra points out that shubha differs from ashubha on four grounds, i.e. in its nature (svabhava), cause (karana), effect (experience or anubhava of fruition of karmas) and in substratum (ashraya) being supportive of the path of liberation. Shubha (punya) is the path of liberation (moksha marg), while ashubha (papa) is the way to only karmic bondage (bandha marg), (shubhashubhau moksha bandha margau) (SS 145 AC, see also SS 145 JS). While evil (ashubha) or papa is to be absolutely abandoned (atyanta heya) (PS 12 AC), shubha, endowed with commendable or excellent (prashasta) attachment, has purifying (vishuddhi) effect (PS 155 AC and PS 180 AC), which gradually (kramatah) brings about the highest happiness of nirvana (liberation) (PS 254 and PS 254 AC), and, thus, not only ieads to liberation of oneself (PS 259 and PS 259 AC) but also help others to attain liberation (PS 260 and PS 260 AC). If Kundakunda omited mention of the worthy attributes and the commendable role of punya and shubha and preferred to emphasise the more sombre aspects of shubha or punya (in PS 77, and in SS 145-147), then he had a reason for doing so. He leaves it to the reader to discover why he chooses to do so (Amrtachandra has endeavoured to help the reader in this respect through his commentaries of PS 77 and SS 145). Th situation is somewhat similar to Andrew Hacker's comment about Machiavelli. Hacker states: Only a few have the intelligence and insight to cut through the ideological prisms which distort the perceptions and wrap the mind ... Machiavelli says: “It may be said of men in general, that they are ungrateful, voluble, dissemblers, anxious to avoid danger, and covetous of gain.” ... (this) is Page #79 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 53 not the whole truth ... Machiavelli is no fool, and he knows full well that his description is selective and one-sided. He is aware that men are often trustworthy and loyal, helpful and friendly. If he omits mention of these worthy attributes and chooses to emphasize the more sombre ones, then he has a reason for doing so. It is the reader's responsibility to discover why Machiavelli selects this particular emphasis ... The theorist's main tools, in short, are the depth of his intelligence and the range of his imagination. ... Men are both brave and cowardly, trustworthy and deceitful, good and evil. The trouble with taking account of all the facts is that it admits all the ambiguities ... Generalizations are always risky, but to be meaningful they must come down on one side or the other. A political (spiritual] theorist has to be committed to a point of view, and this often entails uttering a half-truth or selecting a single tendency for disproportionate emphasis. He must, in sum, have the courage to speculate on the important questions and to put the facts aside when they get in his way ... Albert Einstein has this to say: "In the field of politics and social science there has grown up a justified distrust of generalizations pushed too far. When thought is too greatly dominated by such generalizations misinterpretations of specific sequences of cause and effect readily occur doing injustice to the actual multiplicity of events. Abandonment of generalization, on the other hand, means to relinquish understanding altogether. For that reason I believe one may and must risk generalization so long as one remains aware of its uncertainty.” Out of My Later Years (New York: Philosophical Library, 1950), p. 252. ... The goal of theory is to enhance the understanding. And great knowledge rises out of those insights which only the engaged mind and the quickened insight are able to create. 37 After stating what he does (in PS 77), Kundakunda states: he who understands the reality of things thus and no more entertains attachment or aversion towards objects, thereby purifying his psychic attention (upayoga), puts an end to pain originating from the body (PS 78). In the very next verse, he states: “If any one, after giving up sinful undertakings and even getting ready to undertake efforts in good conduct, does not get rid of infatuation, etc., then he does not attain the pure self.” (PS 79) Here Kundakunda emphasises giving up sinful undertakings, but does not speak of giving up good (shubha) conduct. Even punya (merit), it is argued, turns out to be like sin, the means of misery (PS 76 AC), if the result is experiencing of misery, born Page #80 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES from the body (PS 72), and leads only to thirst, craving or longing for sense objects (PS 74 and PS 74 AC). Shubha is preferable to Ashubha When Kundakunda says that there is anothing particular or special (vishesha)” about punya (righteousness, virtuous), as compared to papa (sin), he implies that when viewed in general or as generalization, punya and papa appear similar, he is well aware that, when viewed in their particular aspects, there is an obvious difference between them and that punya or shubha is definitely preferable to papa or ashubha. This is evident from the following: (1) The difference between good and evil is reflected in the definition of good (shubha or punya) (PS 69, 157) and sin or evil (ashubha or papa) (PS 12, 158), which represent dissimilar characteristics and consequences of the two; (2) if punya or dharma (righteousness and piety) was not preferable to evil, Kundakunda would not have 'spoken of refraining from sin (papa) and of striving for virtuous activities, thereby joining the path of righteousness (PS 259); (3) If there was no difference between punya and papa, Kundakunda would not have spoken of being devoid of evil or inauspicious psychic attentiveness or conscious manifestation, having pure or good psychic attention, and of being devoted to what is excellent (prashasta) (PS 260); (4) a samana can be either of pure (shuddha) or good (shubha) psychic attention (PS 245, 260), but Kundakunda nowhere states that a person having evil or inauspicious (ashubha) psychic attention can be a samana, and (5) of the shubha and ashubha psychic states or modes, infatuation (moha) and aversion (dvesh) are evil or inauspicious, while attachment (raga) is inherently both auspicious (shubha) and inauspicious (ashubha) (PS 180). Clarifying this, Amrtachandra observes that attachment, which is said to be both good and evil, has a dual role or character. Whereas auspicious, excellent or commendable attachment has a purifying (vishuddhi) effect, ashubha leads to affliction, distress or misery (sanklesh) (PS 155 AC and PS 180 AC). In other words, just as from similar germs (seeds) there is variance of produce due to variance of Page #81 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 55 soil, so from similar psychic-attention characterised as excellent attachment, there is variance of fruit, due to variance of receptacle or beneficiary (patra), since different occasions lead to different effects (PS 255 and PS 255 AC). Kundakunda goes on to give two additional explanations: (6) The activities imbued with good or auspicious attachment are not censurable (PS 247, 253), implying thereby that evil or inauspicious activities are censurable. (7) Whereas ashubha is imbued with affliction, distress or morbidity (sanklesha) (PS 155 AC and PS 180 AC), shubha (auspicious, wholesome thoughts or meritorious activities), i.e. punya or righteous conduct should not be completely abandoned (sarvatha or atyanta heya) even though it is imbued with commendable attachment (prashasta raga) and as such leads to karmic bondage since it leads one towards sanity and has a purifying effect (vishuddhi) (PS 155 AC and PS 180 AC). Moreover, it enables one to gradually (kramatah) attain the highest happiness of nirvana (libration) (PS 254 and PS 254 AC). Thus, it not only leads to liberation (PS 259 and PS 259 AC) but also helps others to attain liberation (PS 260 and PS 260 AC). Those who are imbued with sin or evil and indulge in sense objects and passions (vishaya kashaya), [do nor attain liberation and] cannot become saviours [of other] (PS 258). Excellent attachment (prashasta raga), thus, has a dual role. Kundakunda's description in the above-mentioned verses in Pravachanasara or in Samayasara 146 that just as a shackle whether made of gold or iron, binds a person, so also activity good (shubha or punya) or bad (ashubha or papa), equally binds the jiva, is deliberate. He seeks to draw our attention to the fact that the good or evil nature of an activity depends on the good or evil intention of a person and that the attachment that exists in shubha is commendable or excellent (prashasta) or contrary to that, i.e. aprashasta. If the prosperity, good birth, health, etc. obtained through virtuous karmas (deeds) is wasted or exhausted in sensual pleasures, such pleasures of sense objects, acquired by the virtuous activities (punya), is indeed misery (PS 76 and PP 2.59). In this context, one should note that when shubha or punya is considered merely a "means of sensorial pleasure" (PS 69 AC), it facilitates sensual enjoyments, which enable one to get attached to or Page #82 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ G THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES indulge in sense objects. However, they do not compel us to be either attached or indulge in them or debase us. Shubha or punya is not inherently bad. It basically depends on one's intentions and how one chooses to make use of the facilities at his disposal. One may either squander one's wealth in gambling, drinking, etc. or prefer to make judicious use thereof. Human life offers numerous opportunities to swerve from the path of righteousness and piety (dharma). Merits (punya) are of different kinds (see below) and play different roles. It is only when (jadi in Pk., yadi in Sk.) it gives rise to the craving for sense enjoyments (visaya tanha in Pk., and vishaya-trashna in Sk., PS 74), then only such people wish to obtain sense pleasures, which leads to unhappiness and misery and eventually death (PS 75). Mundane souls are usually seen to have a tendency towards indulging in such craving for sense objects (PS 74 AC). They covet them in the hope of enjoying them. As a result, they are afflicted by them until the end (PS 75 AC), since craving for sensorial pleasure is the cause of bondage (PS 76), even if it originates from merit (punya) (PS 76 AC). “Detached from the senses, you are free. Attached, you are bound.” (Ashtavakra Gita 15.1-2) Kundakunda deemed it necessary to warn people beforehand so that they could be cautious, alert and on guard in regard to this general tendency. It is in this context that Kundakunda states (Pravachanasara 77) that there is “nothing particular or special” between punya and papa. Similar to the duality of good and evil (shubha and ashubha) upayoga or of pleasure and pain, he adds, the duality of punya and papa does not exist or is not maintainable from the transcendental perspective (paramartha) as they are not of the nature of the self (PS 77 AC). In other than a transcendental perspective, the difference between the above pairs of duality does exist. In fact, the two can never be equated. It would be a gross misperception and a totally wrong view to assert that there is no difference whatsoever between the two. Shubha (auspicious, wholesome) righteous moral conduct is undoubtedly preferable to ashubha (inauspicious, unwholesome thoughts or sinful activities), which is worth abandoning (heya) on all counts. If conscious attentiveness is good or auspicious (shubha), the soul accumulates merit (punya); if evil or inauspicious (ashubha), sin (papa). In the absence of both, there is no accumulation of karmas (PS 156). The ash:ubha upayoga “must be completely abandoned” Page #83 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION (atyanta heya) (PS 12 AC) because its growth or accretion leads the self to become a rogue, an animal or inhabitant of hell. It is also continuously beset by thousands of pains, as a result of which it strays incessantly (PS 12). Moreover, a person whose psychic attention is evil or inauspicious (ashubha) is steeped in sensual pleasures and passions, addicted to wicked words, bad thoughts or evil intentions and bad companionship. He also tends to be violent or cruel and inclined to perverse ways (PS, 158). However, a person characterized by “cessation from sin, who possesses equanimity towards all righteous (dharmika) persons and strives for the totality of meritorious or virtuous qualities has entitlement for following the right path” (PS 259). As a result, such a person is the abode (aayatan) of liberation (moksha) and merit (punya) (for oneself as also others (svayam parasya) (PS 259 AC). Such persons, who are free from ashubha upayoga by annihilating all deluded views and aversion, are sometimes possessed of pure (shuddha) conscious attentiveness as they have put an end to all passions from arising. They are also sometimes possessed of good or auspicious (shubha) conscious attentiveness through the arising of commendable or excellent attachment (prashasta raga). They are themselves (svayam) the abode of liberation and are saviours of other] men and those who manifest feelings of devotion to them become partakers of merits (punya) (PS 260 and 260 AC). In Pravachanasara 180, Kundakunda clarifies that infatuation and aversion is ashubha, attachment (raga) is either shubha (good) or ashubha (evil). Attachment, Amrtachandra observes, has a dual role or character: it is shubha (or prashasta] when it is purifying or oriented towards sanity and purity (vishuddhi), and it is ashubha when it is imbued with affliction, distress or morbidity (sanklesha) (PS 155 AC and PS 180 AC). Thus, shubha has purifying (vishudhi), beneficial effect whereas ashubha, which is imbued with affliction and distress (sanklesh), and invariably leads to bondage, is harmful to the self. A person who refrains from sin (papa) and strives for meritorious (punya) qualities is an adherent of the path of liberation (PS 259 and PS 259 AC). Those, who are free from ashubha and are endowed with pure or auspicious (shubha) psychic-attention, are not only themselves able to cross the (mundane existence of transmigratory cycle of births and deaths), and attain liberation but also help others to attain Page #84 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES liberation (PS 260 and PS 260 AC). A person with auspicious (shubha) psychic-attention, having commendable or excellent (prashasta) conduct, has the ability to gradually (kramtah) attain the highest happiness of nirvana (liberation) (PS 254 and PS 254 AC). Therefore, ashubha and shubha cannot be equated with one another. The status or the position of the arahantas (those who have annihilated the destructive karmas and are therefore worthy of worship) is the fruit of punya, i.e. virtuous or meritorious karmas and their activities is the result of the arising of the karmas (audayika karman). They are considered to have annihilated the cycle of karman (kshayika, i.e. pure) since they are free from infatuation, etc. (PS 45). As such, they do not cause any damage or distortion to consciousness (chaitanya vikar), or karmic bondage (bandha), but are in effect the cause of liberation (moksha) (PS 45 AC). Leaving aside the exceptional case of arahantas, the coming into operation or the rise (audaiyika) of karmas is generally considered the cause of karmic bondage. The annihilation (kshaya) of passions or karmas represents the purity or the pure (shuddha) state of consciousness, which was earlier impure. The other two conscious states of subsidence of passions (aupshamik) and subsidence-cum-destruction (kshayopshahmik) have the effect of purifying (vishuddhi) the impurities of karman or passions existing in the soul or consciousness. All these four conscious states (bhavas) are karma-referential and are said to be the modes or modifications (parinama or paryaya) of consciousness-as-such. The fifth conscious state of parinamika bhava, which is the innate nature of the self, is non-relational to karmas as it is independent of karmas (karma nirpeksha). It is the substratum of the first four bhavas, i.e. states of consciousness. It is eternal, constant or stable (dhruva), i.e. existent in all three times (past, present and future). It is considered neither pure nor impure, even though it has the potential to become pure. This signifies that that the self has to make efforts to make it pure. Thus, vishuddhi presupposes the existence of the karma-infected self and includes subsidence or partial abatment of passions. In the state or condition of subsidence of passions, the self is in a position to undertake the good, auspicious or meritorious (shubha) activities of self-restraint, which have a purifying effect, and are a necessary Page #85 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION means to complete freedom from passions or eradication of karmas, i.e. liberation. It has already been clarified by Amrtachandra in Pravachanasara 180 that commendable attachment (i.e. prashtha raga or good psychic attention (shubha upayoga)] has a purifying effect (vishuddhi), while ashubha (inauspicious or evil) attachment is of the nature of affliction, distress and morbidity (sanklesha) (PS 180 AC). Moreover, good evolution leads to merit (punya) while ashubha is the cause of sin (papa) (PS 181). Explaining shubha and ashubha, Jayasena states that devotion of the five revered souls (panch parameshthi), etc. is shubha (auspicious) attachment [i.e. commendable or excellent (prashasta) attachment], while attachment to sense objects (vishaya) and anger, etc. passions (kashaya) is ashubha (i.e. worth abandoning or not praiseworthy (aprashasta)] attachment (PS 180 JS). When a person's mind is in the grip of intense emotional agitation caused by passions or sinful, evil, and unwholesome thoughts (ashubha), his impulsive actions and reactions are conditioned by karmas, i.e. instinctive impulses, so much so that one behaves like a puppet in the hands of karmas and is wholly dependent on them. It is only in the state of upashama (subsidence of passions), when the deluding karma is held up, even if temporarily, that the soul can have a glimpse of the truth of the reality. It is only then that the self can have peace of mind in which one can assess the situation calmly and dispassionately and develop a definitive self-conscious predilection which illumines the spiritual journey leading to the ultimate goal. In other words, the calmness of mind resulting from the subsidence of passions alone enables a person to think properly regarding the choices, evaluate the consequences of one's actions and to arrive at appropriate decisions. It also enables one to make efforts (purushartha) and use one's conscious attentiveness (upayoga), independently of karma-upadhi, i.e. the instinctive impulses and subconscious motivations, in the direction of moral and spiritual advancement. The process of upashama (subsidence or abatement of passions), thus, occupies an important place in the spiritual thought and moral conduct of the Jains. Thus, the Jaina concept of self-restraint, control and conquest of senses and subsidence of passions is quite different from value-free Freudian psychology of repression. The subsidence or abatement of passions (like feebleness of anger, pride, greed, etc.) Page #86 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES is an auspicious (shubha) thought activity whereas the severity and intensity of passions (kashaya) is an inauspicious (ashubha) thought activity. One does not become a purified soul (visudha appa in Pk., vishuddha atma in Sk.) at one go or in one step. The purification of the jiva, infected with karmas since beginningless time, takes place by degrees (PS 5 AC). In this way, a person who is endowed with shubha upayoga or subsidence of passions gradually (kramtah) attains the highest happiness of nirvana (liberation) (PS 254 AC). The attainment of the state of pure self or pure consciousness free from karmas is always gradual, i.e. from ashubha to shubha and then to shuddha (pure). In Pravachanasara it is specifically stated that shubha is purificatory (vishudhi) (PS 180 AC) unlike ashubha, which is of the nature of morbidity, affliction and misery (sanklesha) (PS 180 AC), and gradually leads to liberation (PS, 254 AC). Acharya Vidayasagar has stated: “bin shubha upayoga ke hot na shuddha upayoga”, i.e. there cannot be pure conscious attentiveness without first having wholesome thought activities or good or auspicious conscious attentiveness (shubha upayoga). Strangely, the Kanjipanthi want to enjoy the fruit of moksha (nirvana) without practicing self-restraint of moral rules of non-violence, etc., i.e. the good and meritorious activities of shubha upayoga (good or auspicious attentiveness) which have a purifying effect (vishuddhi) for the self and are the means (sadhan) of liberation. In his lectures, H.C. Bharill doggedly persists in his one-sided mistaken view and continues to insist that shubha (good or auspicious) is not different from ashubha (evil or inauspicious) psychic disposition and is the cause of only bondage. Misperceptions persist not only about good or virtuous activities but also regarding the effects or consequences thereof. This is the reason that Samantabhadra referred to instances where many hermits, ascetics, etc. are seen performing sacrificial acts with the expectation or desire of begetting children, wealth and a berth in heaven or the best of the other world (Svayambhu Stotra 49). Thus, it is quite apparent that Kundakunda, Samantabhadra, etc. acharyas (preceptors) were fully aware of the tendency of people to indulge in several good activities (such as worship, devotion, charity, fasting, etc.), external austerities and refrain from physical injury or Page #87 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 61 violence, even when their psychic dispositions are not purified of the impurities of passions like attachment, aversion, anger, pride, etc. Kundakunda, therefore, had to observe that he who practices austerities, moral rules (non-violence, etc. vrata or vows), observances (niyam) and virtuous activities, but is devoid of paramartha, i.e. do not understand the real transcendental nature of the self and are not devoted to the purification of the soul by giving up impurities of attachment, passions, etc. do not attain liberation (nirvana) (SS 152153). In Pravachanasara, it is clearly stated that in the absence of the proper understanding, or an enlightened view of things [which sets the goal (lakshaya), the direction and the orientation of one's activities (whether towards inner peace and happiness or towards worldly attractions and sense pleasures)], the practice of vows like non-violence, observances (niyam), study, comtemplation (dhyana) and charity (dana) does not lead to the attainment of liberation from rebirth. It results in one obtaining a state characterised by pleasure (PS 256). In Samayasara, it is also stated that good deeds (i.e. dharma or punya, i.e. righteousness and piety comprising of vows, carefulness, i.e. samiti, restraints of mind, speech and body (gupti), rules of conduct and austerities) should be performed not for the purpose of future enjoyment (bhoga-nimittam) but for the destruction of karmas (karmakshaya-nimittam) (SS 273-275). The mention of the word "evam," i.e. "in the way described" in verse 77 of Pravachanasara refers to preceding verses (PS 63-68 and 69-76), which deal with sense enjoyments with good or auspicious (shubha) psychic attention (upayoga) being the means (sadhan) thereto. If the soul thirsts merely for sense objects as a result of good or virtuous (punya) activtities (PS 74) and as happiness acquired by means of senses is, indeed, misery (PS 76), how is there any (distinction between) good or evil psychic attention? (PS 72). Pravachanasara verse 77 is to be viewed in the above context. This verse makes it amply clear why Kundakunda omits mention of the worthy attributes of good or auspicious psychic attention, selects the particular description (of PS 77) as such, thereby choosing to emphasize the more sombre aspects. One should always be vigilant, lest one slides back into sense enjoyments or be deluded by attractions of worldly prosperity, name, fame and success, etc. Page #88 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 62 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Moreover, since it is necessary that after giving up evil (papa) activities, one has to adopt good or auspicious psychic attention in order to attain pure psychic attention, Kundakunda stresses that one should not be content with all that one can achieve by good psychic attention. One should, he argues, should strive to make use of all the facilities or the means of good health, noble birth, etc. afforded by punya, to advance further in moral and spiritual development in order to attain durable and lasting peace and happiness. One should not forget that "if anyone, although giving up sinful undertakings and even getting ready to undertake efforts in good conduct, does not get rid of infatuation, etc., then he does not attain the pure self" (PS 79), but moves about, covered with infatuation or deluded view (moha), in the terrible transmigratory existence of the cycle of births and deaths (PS 77). In Pravachanasara 180, Amrtachandra clarifies that commendable attachment (prashasta raga), i.e. good psychic attention (shubha upayoga), has a purifying effect and is part of purification (vishuddhi). Ashubha (evil), on the other hand, is of the nature of affliction (sanklesha). Good state-of-evolution of psychic disposition, he adds, leads to merit (punya), while ashubha is the cause of sin (papa) (PS 18). Shuddha and Shubha Upayoga Pravachanasara 11 states that when the state-of-evolution of the soul or consciousness through dharma (conduct, duty, equanimity, righteousness, moral precepts or piety) is accompanied, conjoined or endowed with pure (shuddha) conscious attentiveness, in the sense of practising self-restraints (sanyam) and austerities (tapa) (PS 14), it leads to the happiness of nirvana (liberation). When it is endowed with good or auspicious (shubha) attentiveness, it leads to the happiness of heaven. Both are adherents of dharma and also followers of the path of liberation. While shuddha (pure) upayoga is capable of being the direct cause of liberation, shubha upayoga, being conjoined with attachment and therefore somewhat lacking the efficacy of directly accomplishing its objective of liberation is in some respect (kathanchit) productive of contradictory effect (viruddh karya) of bringing about the bondage of heavenly happiness. For instance, whereas massage of hot butter (ghee) Page #89 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION is helpful in reducing pain, but it also causes some pain in the process. Hence, shuddha upayoga is preferable to shubha upayoga (PS 11 AC). A person, who is endowed with shubha upayoga and has excellent conduct, experiences the pure consciousness with a certain degree of attachment, gradually (kramtah, or kramashah) attains the highest happiness of nirvana (liberation) (PS 254 AC). Interestingly, Kundakunda has used conscious attentiveness (upayoga) in regard to shuddha (pure) and shubha (auspicious) in Pravachanasara 11, because upayoga is in obedience to conscious awareness (chaitanya anuvidhayi). This is not the case with ashubha for which the word coming into operation or "arising” (uday) of karma has been used (PS 12) since it is based on instinctive impulses and sub-conscious motivations, even though the ashubha mode is also a pscychic disposition. What is the reason for this? The point that Kundakunda seems to emphasize here is that in the state of shuddha and shubha, consciousness plays an active role and the functionality of consciousness is accepted. In the state of ashubha, the self apparently ignores the attentiveness or alertness of the conscious entity and follows the diktat or the proddings of instinctive impulses and subconscious motivations, in which the neurophysiological processes or brain states (dravya karma) acts as an extrinsic, auxiliary cause (nimitta karana). Moreover, while a person who is endowed with shuddha or shubha upayoga is considered to be an adherent of dharma (dharmatma) (PS 11), a person endowed with ashubha psychic disposition is not a follower of dharma. The latter is a sinner, hypocritical person, and a rogue, an animal or inhabitant of hell and always beset by thousands of pains, and strays incessantly (PS 12). Such a person “must be completely abandoned” (PS 12 AC) since he strays very far from the path of liberation as his vicious activities lack self-restraint. In his commentary of Pravachanasara verse 245, Amrtachandra points out that shubha upayoga (wholesome psychic attentiveness) is identical to or in harmony with dharma, i.e. righteousness or piety (dharmena sah ekarth samvaya). Because of its favourable disposition towards dharma (dharma sadbhavat), even those having shubha upayoga are also called shraman. But they are not at the same level as those who possess pure conscious attentiveness, who have renounced all passions and as a result are without karmic inflow. A person, who is Page #90 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES capable of attaining pure psychic attention, can adopt a course of action which is desirable. However, a person, who is not able to adopt such a course of action, should adopt the vyavahara path of righteousness of shubha (good, auspicious). This is useful, desirable and worth adopting (prayojanavana) in order to restrain delusion, gratification of sense objects, and passions like anger, etc. and concentration on evil (SS 12 JS). In Pravachanasara, it is stated that “Even though there should result a small stain (some karmic bondage) yet a layman or a saint who is a follower of Jina should through compassion render disinterested aid (nirvekkham in Pk. nirpeksha in Sk.) (i.e. without any consideration or expectation of any kind) to all” (PS 251). In this context, Jayasena observes that catering to the well-being of the other with compassion produces some bondage. Such good or auspicious (shubha) psychic attention or activity is righteousness (dharma) and should be undertaken. Such shubha activities should be nirpeksha, i.e. devoid of any desire or expectation of name, "fame and gain (khyati puja laabha), which is destructive of pure intentions (PS 251 JS). When good or auspicious psychic attention, Jayasena adds, is imbued with an enlightened view, it leads to the bondage of good or virtuous karmas and conventionally (paramparya) leads to liberation. However, if it is not imbued with an enlightened view, it leads only to the bondage of good or virtuous karmas (PS 255 JS). Such a clear and detailed description of ashubha, shubha and shuddha as given in Kundakunda's works, particularly Pravanchanasara, is not found in such detail or clarity in any literature of the world or even in other Jain texts. Shuddha, Shubha and Ashubha in other Works of Kundakunda In Ashta Pahuda In Bhava Pahuda (76), Kundakunda states that while unwholesome or bad (ashubha) thought activities (bhava) are painful (arta) and wicked or wrathful (raudra), shubha (wholesome, good) bhavas are dhammam (dharmam in Sk.), i.e. virtuous, righteous and valuable. In Bhava Pahuda, he clarifies that mere practice or observance of external rules of conduct, including austerities and scriptural study, will not lead to Page #91 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION purity or the accomplishment of the objective of liberation, if there exists a slight taint of psychic impurities of pride, expectation, deluded view, etc. If a person continues to be imbued with internal infatuation or attachment to things, even renunciation of external attachment to objects and possessions is of no use (Bhava Pahuda 44-53). On the other hand, a householder, who is endowed with an enlightened view and is well set in the path of liberation and is free from internal infatuation and deluded view, is declared to be superior to an ascetic who is imbued with a deluded view (Samantabhadra, Ratna Karanda Shravakachara (RKS 33). A person should also have compassion for all living beings (PS 157), knowledge and virtue (Sheel Pahuda 2), observe the five great vows (NS 56-60, Charitra Pahuda 30) and possess virtues like contentment (Sheel Pahuda 19), forgiveness (Bhava Pahuda 107), modesty (Bhava Pahuda 104), moral emotions like fearlessness (SS 228), and universal love (maîtri or friendliness] (Charitra Pahuda 7) and propagation of values (Charitra Pahuda 7) – all these are intrinsically desirable. Experience of these intrinsic values is good in itself. Kundakunda states that good experience (or psychic dispositions or mental states] (shubha bhava), is intrinsically valuable (Bhava Pahuda 76). He speaks of shubha bhava as representing all that is intrinsically valuable (PS 9 and 46). 58 In Sheel Pahuda (verse 28), it is pointed out that although the sea is full of gems, it is called sea because of the water, in the same way as jiva possesses many gems like austerity, reverence, virtue (sheel) and charity. However, it is because of virtue (sheel) that a person attains the excellent state of liberation (nirvana). The five rules of moral conduct including non-violence come under sheel. Commenting on Ashta Pahuda (verse 121), Pandit Jaichand Chhabra observes that auspicious attachment (shubha raga) is the condition or the supportive factor (nimitta) of the bondage of good karmas (punya bandha). However, since it has a purifying effect, it is also the cause of shedding of bad or evil karmas (papa karmas). All religions place a premium on good conduct and virtue. The observance of sheel (virtue) is the sine qua non of a spiritual life. Lord Buddha laid great emphasis on sheel (virtue) and regarded it as the pre-condition for making any progress in a spiritual journey. Sheel (virtue), samadhi (concentration) and prajna (discriminating insight), Page #92 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 66 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES according to him, are the three important milestones on the road to nirvana. Without observing sheet, one will not be able to practise concentration of mind and develop discriminative insight. Sheel is also considered important for developing a higher spiritual life as well as for practicing meditation and attain prajna. Buddhists are mostly satisfied with only mental action (viz. the intention). However, Kundakunda does not rely solely on intention alone even though he too lays greater emphasis on internal aspects of psychic disposition or intentions of the person. He stresses that the role and importance of external conduct (actions) cannot be completely lost sight of or ignored. In fact, it is our actions which reflect our intention and character. They are also the reliable yardstick of the purity or otherwise of one's intentions. For Kundakunda, conduct is dharma. He defines dharma as equanimity (samya), which, in turn, is said to be a state-of-evolution of the soul devoid of infatuation or deluded view and mental disturbance (kshobha), i.e. conduct-deluding karma of attachment and aversion (PS '7). In this way, Kundakunda sought to harmonise internal and external aspects. One cannot realise nishchaya charitra, Pandit- Sadasukh argues, unless one gives up five sins (papa) of violence, etc. and adopts vyavahar (conduct) of the character of the magnificence of internal and external activities (commentary on RKS 49). In other words, one can attain nishchaya charitra only by renouncing sinful tendencies and adopting the excellence of vyavahara conduct of goodness (punya) in both internal and external aspects. In Baras Anuvekkha (BA) Kundakunda categorically states that the good, auspicious or wholesome activity of mind, speech and body (shubha yoga) purifies (pavitti) and is instrumental in the inhibition (samvar) of the influx of evil, inauspicious, unwholesome activities (ashubha yoga). Restraint (nirodh) of the auspicious thought activity is possible by means of pure thought activity (BA 63). And since that which is the cause of inhibition of karma is also the cause of the shedding of karmas (nirjara) (BA 66), shubha is also the cause of shedding or elimination of ashubha karma. It is quite obvious that so long as one does not attain direct pure conscious attentiveness (shuddha upayoga), one has to depend on the vyavahara of the nature of auspicious (shubha) activity. Page #93 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION In Niyamsara (NS) Although karmic bondage is caused by both punya and papa, there is a great deal of difference between the two in many respects. In Niyamsara, self-restraint of the mind (manogupti) is described as avoiding impurities of attachment, aversion, etc. inauspicious (ashubha) dispositions (NS 66). Vyavahara (external, other-referential) conduct is said to consist of five vows (vrata), including non-voilence, five carefulness or self-regulations (samiti), and the three self-restraints (of mind, speech and body) (gupti) (NS 56-70). They constitute practice of austerities from the vyavahara point of view (NS 55) and part of enlightened conduct. This signifies that good or virtuous psychic dispositions and activities are helpful and supportive factors in the purification of the self (atma shuddhi). Shubha activity of the nature of virtuous (punyamaya) vyavahara dharma (righteousness) is a factor in the influx and consequent bondage of karma, However, at the same time, the abstaining or refraining from inauspicious activity of the nature of evil (papamaya) that takes place is to that extent leads to inhibition or restraint (samvara) and destruction or dissociation (nirjara) of karmas. Thus, shubha or punya has a dual role. According to Niyamsara, one should abstain from unwholesome activities (ashubha bhavna parihar) (ŃS 66), which are said to be sinful or defiled, deluded, instinctive or impulsive behaviour, imbued with feelings of attachment and aversion, etc. (NS 66); engage in wholesome (shubha) thoughts and practice moral rules of self-restraint, thereby observing vyavahara conduct of righteousness (NS 55); and endeavour to purify one's thought activities through self-disciplinary methods of repentance, etc. (nishchaya conduct) so as to completely eradicate passions (NS 77-158). The three maxims mentioned above can be summed up in one sentence: “Avoid doing of all evil, practice moral conduct of righteousness and accomplish purity of one's own psychic dispositions.” In Samayasara In order to realize the supreme state of pure consciousness free from karmas, one has to transcend not only ashubha but also shubha, because attachment to shubha also causes bondage of karmas, which leads to mundane wanderings and is destructive of independence of Page #94 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES the soul (SS 145, 147 and 154). Punya is also a hindrance in the attainment of liberation (Nishithachurni, 3329). It was in that context that Kundakunda asserted that both a gold as well as an iron fetter binds a person just as both shubha (wholesome) and ashubha (unwholesome) bind the jiva (self) (SS 146). Rishibhashitani (4515) also states that bondage, whether of a golden or of an iron fetter, is bondage, which is the cause of misery or suffering. The pain caused by a golden stick is also pain. Therefore, one should not be attached to them (SS 147) for an attached person binds karmas (PS 179, SS 167). In shubha upayoga, the self is able to find and tread the proper path (of liberation), but in ashubha upayoga there is no possibility thereof. In his commentary on Samaysara verse 145, Amrtachandra points out that shubha differs from ashubha on four grounds, i.e. in its nature (svabhava), cause (karana), effect (experience or anubhava of fruition of karma) and in substratum (ashraya), i.e. being supportive of the path of liberation. He has also specifically stated that while shubha (punya) is the path of liberation (moksha marg), ashubha (papa) is the way to karmic bondage (bandha marg) (shubháshubhau moksha bandha margau) (SS 145 AC). So long as one does not attain pure conscious attentiveness (shuddha upayoga), one has to depend on vyavahara conduct of the nature of auspicious (shubha) activity. A proper understanding of Pravachanasara 151, 191 and 194 and Samayasara 188, 189 and 206, advises one to practice meditation (dhyana) in order to destroy deluded view and attain the best or the highest happiness in life. However, this does not necessarily negate auspicious (shubha) or commendable attachment (prashasta raga), which leads to righteous or virtuous meditation (dharma dhyana, also called prashasta dhyana), as compared to inauspicious (ashubha) thoughts which lead to mournful (arta) and cruel (raudra) inauspicious meditation (aprashasta dhyana). Similar to inauspicious (ashubha) or detestable, unwholesome (aprashasta) meditations and auspicious (shubha) or righteousness, commendable (prashasta) meditations are (aprashasta) and (prashasta) thought paints or emotional tints (leshya). The (aprashasta) or sinful (papa rupa), i.e. adharma leshyas are: (1) black leshya, which is characterized by wrathful, hostile or pugnacious temperaments, wicked, i.e. devoid of piety and compassion, engrossed in sense objects, pride, Page #95 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 69 etc; (2) blue leshya, which signifies envious and deceitful, passionate behaviour, having intense desire for worldly riches, etc; and (3) grey (kapot) leshya, characterized by angry thoughts, a deluded view, sorrow, fear and envy and is not straightforward. The prashasta (shubha) or righteous (dharma) leshyas are: (1) yellow (tejo) leshya, characterized by an understanding or discerning knowledge as to what is fit or unfit to do, humility, straightforwardness, and practice of compassion and charity, etc., righteousness or virtuous activities, (2) pink (padma) leshya comprising of detachment, forebearance, dispassionate conduct, etc.; and (3) white (shukla) leshya, characterized by self-restraint (gupti) of mind, speech and body, equanimity, etc. According to Uttaradhayana (34/32), a person endowed with shukla leshya can be both with attachment [excellent attachment] or without attachment (veetraga). Shubha and Ashubha in Panchastikayasara (PKS) The psychic states or psychological conditions determining auspicious (shubha) or righteousness (virtue, punya) and inauspicious (ashubha) or vice (evil, sin, papa) are described in Panchastikayasara (PKS) verses 131, 132 and 135-140. These verses clearly state that whenever a jiva is endowed with the mental states of a deluded view (moha), which clouds one's faculty of perception and conviction, attachment (raga) and aversion (dvesh), which distorts the conative, conscious will or volitional (conduct) faculty of consciousness, then they manifest in a mental state characterized by inauspicious, sinful, undesirable, bad thought activities (ashubha parinama). However, the restraint and subsidence of psychic dispositions like attachment, etc. results in peace and happiness of the psyche (chitta prasad). This, in turn, manifests in a desirable, good, virtuous and auspicious mental state (shubha parinama) (PKS 131). Describing the subjective states of good (shubha or punya) and evil (sinful, i.e. ashubha or papa), Panchastikayasara (verse 132) states that good or auspicious (shubha) thought activity, state or condition (parinama) is righteousness (punya), while evil or inauspicious (ashubha) thought activity is sin (papa). In Panchastikayasara (verses 135-140), Kundakunda makes a clearcut distinction between shubha and ashubha while describing the components of punya or shubha parinama (wholesome psychic Page #96 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES dispositions, inclined or oriented towards righteousness) and papa (evil thoughts and sinful activities). The constituent elements of punya, he states, are (a) prashasta raga (commendable or excellent attachment, noble thoughts and aspirations) (PKS 135), such as reverence of perfect souls, devotion to dharma (piety or righteousness), self-restraint and observance of rules of moral conduct in life (PKS 136 and PKS 136 AC]; (b) anukampa (compassion), i.e. feeling of goodwill and sympathy at the sight of needy and the sufferers and the offering of charity or active relief to the thirsty, the hungry and the miserable; and (c) akalushata, i.e. freedom from evil impulses and passions (anger, pride, deceit and greed or covetousness) (PKS 135), which constitute the impurity of the soul (PKS 135-138). The subsidence or abatement of anger, etc. passions, signifies purification (vishuddhi) (PS 180 AC). The three auspicious or good (shubha) psychic dispositions or mental states (bhava) are commendable attachment (prashasta raga), feeling of compassion (anukampa) and, in whose mind there are no evil impulses or passions (akalushata) (PKS 135 AC). Kalushata (impurity) is said to be coming into operation or appearance in mind of jiva (self) of the intense (teevra udaya or rise) of anger, pride, deceit and covetousness or greed, etc. passions, which create a severe mental disturbance (chittasya kshobha) affecting the calmness/peace and balance of mind. The abatement (less intensity or manda udaya) of those passions is one of the necessary conditions of shubha (righteousness or good). One can have auspicious shubha or righteous dispositions only when there is calmness of mind (prasham bhava) due to subsidence (upasham) of passions resulting in calmness of mind, which is also purity or akalushta (PKS 138 AC). The necessary prerequisites of samyak darshan (enlightened view) are prashasta raga (which is equivalent of samvega, i.e. psychic energy geared or disposed towards righteousness), anukampa, and akalushata (i.e. subjective purity arising out of subsidence of passions, which is equivalent or synonymous of prasham). Samyak darshan is considered to be the foundation of dharma (dansan mulo dhammo) and the necessary first step in the direction of salvation. Without it neither knowledge nor conduct can be samyak (enlightened). Kundakunda could not possibly condemn these constituent elements of punya (shubha) and prerequisites of samyak darshan by equating them with papa (evil) or ashubha (unwholesome thoughts). While ashubha results in sinful Page #97 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION thoughts and activities, shubha is helpful in righteousness. Panchastikayasara describes the springs of evil (papasrava) as pramadcharya (negligent acts, thoughtless behaviour, including unnecessary, useless, time-wasting gossiping); negative and impure emotions (kalushata) like anger; hankering for and indulging in sensual pleasures, causing anguish or harm to fellow beings; slandering people openly or covertly; the animal instincts or instinctive impulses and sub-conscious motivations; the soul-soiling emotional tints (leshya), yielding to the temptations of the senses; mournful (arta) and cruel (raudra) dhyana (concentration or meditation), which are said to be ashubha or aprashasta (inauspicious, distorted and perverted) dhyana, evil thoughts and delusion which corrupts the faculties of intuition and will. On the other hand, shubha (auspicious) or prashasta (commendable or excellent) psychic dispositions or thoughts lead to righteous or virtuous meditation (dharma dhyana), which is the necessary concomitant (avinabhavi) of enlightened view (PKS 139-140 and 139-140 AC). Commenting on the Panchastikayasara Verse 171, Jayasena observes that one who considers pure self to be worth acquiring and for that matter undertakes vows like non-violence and austerities, etc. and has a psychic disposition free from the desire for future sense pleasures, is the person endowed with an enlightened view. Such a person binds good or meritorious karma (punya bandha) in the present transmigratory existence due to one's inability to continue to stay in the state of pure self. However, in the next transmigratory existences that person necessarily attains liberation by remaining stable in the contemplation of the supreme reality of self (PKS 171 JS). In his comment on the next verse, Jayasena states that those who believe in vyavahara mokhsa-marg (path of liberation) as a means to the mokhsa-marg leading to pure self and are persons of enlightened view due to having enlightenment with attachment and the practice of observing charity, etc. also customarily (parampara se) attain liberation (PKS 172 JS). Shubha and Ashubha in other Jain Texts In Jai Dhavala Acharya Virasena, in his Jai Dhavala (Book 1, p. 5) commentary on Kashaya-Prabhrata (Kashaya-Pahuda), one of the most authentic Jain Page #98 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 72 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES texts of Digambaras, has acknowledged the possibility of both samvara (inhibitation of influx of karma) and nirjara (eradicating of karmas) by stating that "if eradication of karmas is not considered possible by shubha and shuddha (pure) psychic disposition (parinama), then eradication of karmas will not be possible at all". In other words, while complete absence or freedom from passions may be said to be pure (shuddha), shubha is partial purity (shuddhata) or purification (vishuddhi) (PS 180 AC) of thoughts, i.e. the means (sadhan) of purity or the path of liberation (PS 254 AC). The bondage of punya karma is not the only consequence of shubha. Shubha also leads to the inhibition (samvara) and dissociation (nirjara) of sinful (papa) karma. It also results in a gradual yet continuously higher purification of the self (atma-vishuddhi). Without first having shubha (auspicious) psychic dispocition, one cannot have pure thoughts, which are the most important means of samvara, nirjara and moksha, i.e. the imhibition, dissociation and complete annihilation of karma. This is the conclusion reached in Jai Dhavala. In Adipurana In Adipurana, Acharya Jinasena writes that as a result of punya, one gets or obtains the status of Tirthankara and salvation. Without the particular method or way of first having shubha psychic disposition (parinama), it is not possible to attain pure parinama in one go (Jai Dhavala, Book 14, p. 155). This description is not meant for ordinary people, but for those great noble souls, who are likely to attain salvation in the same birth by destroying the conduct-deluding karmas, thereby advancing fast in spiritual development through the destructive ladder (kshapak shreni). In Jai Dhavala In his commentary on Jai Dhavala, Acharya Yativrashabha remarks: "The parinama is purified in the case of jiva who is starting to destroy conduct-deluding karmas. In this way, this aphorism signifies that more and more shubha and shuddha (pure) parinama is possible only by the destruction of ashubha parinama. This has happened through the infinite times purification (vishuddhi) from the lower thought activity (adhah pravrtakarana)," or the lowest vile stage (jaghanya parinama) (SS 171). Explaining this further, Kanaknandi remarks: Page #99 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 73 Since shubha parinama is the cause of shuddha (pure) parinama, there cannot be shuddha parinama without shubha parinama, because without the cause the accomplishment of the task is not possible in the three times in the three worlds. In the preliminary stages, therefore, shubha parinama is considered desirable (upadeya), not worth-abandoing (heya) for the practitioner or the aspirant (sadhak) of the path of liberation.... Shubha parinama is not only the cause of shuddha parinama, but it is also the cause of inhibition (samvara) and dissociation or falling off (nirjara) of karmas. Moreover, the destruction of karmas cannot take place without shubha and shuddha parinama.39 The purport (abhipraya) that is sought to be conveyed by the words "suba-suddha parinameh?” is that abstaining or refraining from evil and inauspicious (ashubha) activities involved or implied in good, virtuous (punya) or auspicious (shubha) activities leads to or results in the inhibition (samvara or nirodha) and destruction or dissociation (nirjara) of karmas, i.e. purification of the self. Moreover, in the empirical existence, the destruction of the intensity or fruition (anubhaga) of commendable (prashasta) karmas does not take place. On the contrary, the destruction of the intensity or fruition of only aprashasta karmas, i.e. those karmas which are not commendable or excellent, takes place and considered useful (Jai Dhavala, Book 14, p. 153). In Tattvartha Sutra (TS) In Tattvarthasara (verses 103-104 of Chapter IV), Amrtachandra states that punya (righteousness or meritorious act) and papa (sinful act or demerit) are different from one another in both cause (hetu) as well as effect (karya), even though both are the source of transmigration. The cause of punya is auspicious thought activity (shubha bhava). Its effect is calmness and peace of mind, happiness or joy, while the cause of papa is unwholesome or inauspicious thought activity (ashubha bhava) and its effect is misery. In Tattvartha Sutra (TS 6.3), asrava is said to be of two kinds: (1) shubha (good or auspicious) is the cause of punya (righteousness, piety or virtue), while (2) ashubha (evil or inauspicious) is the cause of papa (sin). In this context, (TS 6.3), Acharya Pujyapada remarks: Violence, stealing incontinence, etc. are negative, evil activities of the body. Falsehood, harsh and uncivil language, etc. are the evil activities of speech. Page #100 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 74 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Thoughts of violence, envy, calumny, etc. are evil activities of the mind. The good activities are counter to these.... the good or evil nature of an activity depends on the good or evil intention of the person. Although good or virtuous activities are the cause of punya, i.e. beneficial karma, they are also admitted to be cause of bondage of knowledge-obscuring etc. karmas. That which purifies the soul or by which the soul is purified is punya. [In this way, punya is considered a supportive factor in spiritual awakening and development (sadhana)]. The general effect of good activity is happiness and that of evil activity is pain.40 In his Sarvarthasiddhi commentary on Tattvartha Sutra (TS 7.1 and TS 6.12), Pujyapada stresses that self-restraint (samyam), i.e. to restrain oneself from evil, undesirable, inauspicious (ashubha) activities of injury, etc. and observance of vows like non-violence, truthfulness, etc. is considered as morality, virtuous activities (punya), or righteousness and piety (dharma). Five of the ten moral virtues (dharma) (TS 9.6) are only positive aspects of five moral rules (vows) of conduct like non-violence, etc. and are described to be one of the ways of inhibiting (samvara) of karmic inflow (TS 9.2, 9.3). According to Pravachanasara this is the necessary concomitant of partial purification (vishuddhi) (PS 155 AC and 180 AC), partly because it signifies desisting or abstaining from evil, vicious (papa) activities. The five moral rules are said to have a paradoxical dual nature and are instrumental in inhibiting the influx of karma when practiced with detachment and without any vestige of passion. They also generate karmic influx of beneficial (pleasure producing) karma when practiced with attachment (sarag samyam) as being compassionate towards living beings in general in the worldly sense. Punya and papa are considered significant concepts and separate categories in Samayasara. In fact, no verse in the asrava chapter of Samayasara makes any reference to punya or papa as being part of asrava (influx of karmas) since punya is not merely the cause of influx and consequent bondage of karmas. Punya has a dual role in fostering karmic bondage as well as having a purifying effect (visuddhi) (PS 180 AC) and gradually leading to liberation (PS 254 AC). In Tattvartha Rajvarttika (TRV) Presenting the logical exposition of punyaa and papa, further explains it as follows: Akalanka Deva Page #101 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 75 papa It is said that just as fetters of both gold and iron have the effect of binding a person, thereby making him dependent, so also both punya and are the condition (hetu) or the auxiliary (nimitta) cause (karana) in making the self dependent. Thus, there appears nothing special between the two, yet there is difference between them due to one (punya) being the nimitta of desirable or favourable (ishta) effect (phala) and the other (papa) of undesirable or harmful effect (anishta phala). That which is the condition (hetu) of desirable or favourable condition of existence (gati), genus, caste or class of being (jati), body (sharira), the objects of senses (indriya vishaya) is punya. And that which is the hetu of undesirable gati, jati, body and the objects of senses is papa. Thus, there is difference between punya: and papa.41 42 As a result of punya, one is endowed with thirteen qualities including prosperity, health, family and friends, devotion to triple jewels of enlightened view, knowledge and conduct, control of senses, etc." Thus, punya is desirable not only for the success in the worldly life but also for the attainment of liberation. In this context, Vidyananda remarks: "The attainment of liberation also (api) is possible by the supremely excellent punya and the effort (purushartha) for distinctive conduct pertaining to enlightened view, knowledge and conduct." (Akalanka's Ashta-shati commentary on Samantabhadra, Apta-Mimansa, p. 257.) Shubha (punya) has a double or two-fold role: it has binding effect and for that reason considered undesirable from the perspective of shuddha (pure), which is the direct cause of liberation, and to be given up. At the same time, it plays a significant role in getting rid of the impurity of evil (ashubha or papa) and has purifying (vishuddhi) effect (PS 155, 180 AC), and as such regarded a helpful factor in the liberation of soul, in the same way as soap is helpful in cleaning the dirt of the cloth. And just as, for the whiteness of the cloth the presence of soap is unnecessary and is also to be removed or separated, so also in the pure state, punya is unnecessary and is also to be given up. But as the soap cleans the dirt and, after cleaning the dirt, gets itself separated, in the same way punya also is helpful in getting rid of the dirt of the impurity of evil (papa) and after papa is gotten rid of and purity is realized, punya itself is also given up. Explaining the role and contribution of shubha, Akalanka Deva further points out: Page #102 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 76 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES but It is not our conception or idea that shubha is the cause of only punya, punya is [definitely] caused by shubha alone (eva). Hence, it is not denied that shubha can be the condition (hetu) of papa (sin) [or ashubha], since good or auspicious activities are also admitted to be cause of bondage of knowledge-obscuring etc. karmas. . . . Intensity of bondage is primary (pradhan bhuta); it is the auxiliary (nimitta) cause of pleasure and pain. The superior purifying (vishuddha) disposition (parinama) is the nimitta of all the excellent or superior (utkrashta) intensity of bondage of the nature or class (prakrti) of shubha. Likewise, the most severe disposition imbued with affliction, distress or morbidity (sankless) is the nimitta (auxiliary cause). of the most intense bondage of all the ashubha class of karmas. Although excellent shubha parinama is also the condition of the low or the minimal (jaghanya) intensity of bondage of the ashubha class of karma, yet shubha is considered to be the cause or the condition (hetu) of punya (beneficial karma). This is because even if one might incur the minimal, slight or little bit of harm, affront, disservice, or misconduct (apakara), it produces or results in a great deal or vast amount of beneficence or beneficial effect (upakara) and, therefore, it is considered to be beneficial (TRV commentary on TS 6.3). Similarly one should understand the aphorism: "Evil, inauspicious or unwholesome (ashubha) actions cause harmful or sinful (papa) karma" [TS 6.3]. It is said: "By purification (vishuddhi), the excellent intensity of the shubha class of bondage takes place, while by distressful or afflicting (sanklesh) dispositions ashubha class of bondage takes place. The sequence (krama) of low or minimal (jaghanya) intensity of bondage is reverse of that, i.e. by vishuddhi the jaghanya bondage of ashubha karma and by sanklesh the jaghanya bondage of shubha karma (Panchsangraha 4/445, cited by Akalanka in his TRV commentary on TS 6.3).43 44 Shubha yoga (the joining of jiva with auspicious vibratory activities, which is the condition of righteousness), according to Vidyananda, is the outcome of shubha dispositions (parinamas) such as the disposition of non-violence, speaking of truth, respect of scriptures and contemplation of consciousness (atma chintan), etc." It is of the nature of vibration in the space-points of consciousness (atma), engrossed in or devoted to, as also well disposed towards an enlightened view, sex fidelity, speaking beneficial words, inclination or liking for austerities (taporuchi), etc., because it is part of purification (vishuddhi). In other words, shubha yoga is the cause of purification. It is the deed or action Page #103 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION (karya) of vishuddhi, being the outcome of previous vishuddhi. It is in itself of the nature of purification of soul (atma vishuddhi). The case of ashubha yoga is the antithesis of all that since it is engrossed in a deluded view, etc. and is the cause, the outcome, and is in itself of the nature of affliction, misery, distress and morbidity (sanklesh). 45 In Apta Mimamsa (AM) The spiritual content and the influx of karmas and the consequent bondage of punya and papa is not determined by the hedonic aspects of pleasure and pain caused to others (AM 92) or the self (AM 93). All this depends on whether pleasure and pain are part of purification (vishuddhi) or affliction or morbidity (sanklesh) (AM 95). This state of affairs, as Akalanka's commentary clarifies, is known or understood by the existence or the absence of concentrations or meditations (dhyana) of affliction, sorrow or mournful (arta) and cruel or wrathful (raudra) characterized by inclination or tendency towards violence, falsehood, stealing, and safeguarding possessions or objects of sensual gratification. Thus, if it is maintained that sin is necessarily accumulated as a result of causing pain to others while virtue is the result of causing pleasure to others, then even an inanimate entity or a person who is free from passions like anger, pifde, greed, etc. should possibly suffer bondage inasmuch as both can somehow be a supportive or an auxiliary factor (nimitta) in causing pain and pleasure to others (AM 92). Inanimate objects like milk and butter are the cause of happiness to others, whereas poison and weapons result in causing pain or harm (even killing) to others. Similarly, dispassionate enlightened souls become a supportive factor in causing unhappiness to the relatives of the person who is being initiated in asceticism. At the same time, they impart happiness to disciples through their lectures. If it is maintained that virtue is necessarily accumulated as a result of causing pain to oneself while sin is the result of causing pleasure to oneself, then even a conscious entity (e.g. a sage or a noble person who is free from attachment) can possibly acquire a stock of sins/ virtues inasmuch as even such a person can be a supportive factor in causing some kind of unhappiness/happiness to himself in certain situations (AM 93). A detached person who practices austerities often causes pain to his body and experiences happiness from the contentment and equanimity derived from his understanding of the Page #104 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES reality of things. If these are considered to cause bondage to a person, then one would not be able to attain liberation. It may, therefore, be stated that the influx (asrava) of meritorious or virtuous and demeritorious/sinful genre of karmas through pleasures or pain caused to others or to oneself, is contingent upon if such acts performed are part of purification (vishuddhi) or affliction/ morbidity (sanklesha). In the absence of purification or afflication, those acts will remain ineffective insofar as the influx of punya or papa is concerned (AM 95). Ashtashati commentary of Akalanka (on AM 95) clarifies the nature of sanklesha and what is vishuddhi as follows: The psychic states, modes or forms of concentration of anguish, affliction, pain, sorrow (arta dhyana) or of cruel, wrathful concentration (raudra dhyana) are sanklesha, while vishuddhi is the absence thereof signifying auspicious (shubha) or meritorious or virtuous (punya) psychic states leading to purification and spiritual development, which takes place by the virtuous or righteousness concentration (dharma dhyana) and pure concentration (shukla dhyana). Thus, it is quite evident that the virtuous or sinful character of an act does not depend on how it externally affects the persons involved (qua 'agent' or 'qua' 'other') in this act but on whether it has been performed with bad, evil or good, righteous intentions. 46 Moreover, vishuddhi is described as the stage of being situated in one's own consciousness (svatman avasthanam). In other words, when punya achieves vishuddhi, it fosters spiritual progress whereas sinful or papa leading to sanklesh is conducive to the downfall of the soul. Therefore, righteousness (punya) is said to be excellent/commendable (prashasta) and sin (papa) is not considered to be excellent/commendabie. 47 Shubha, Vidyananda opines, is the condition (hetu) of the objective (sadhya) of purity of the self, with which it has necessarily concomitant (avinabhava).48 In his commentary on Apta Mimansa (AM 95), Akalanka has defined (sanklesh) as the result, effect or the state (parinama) of mournful, distressful (arta), and cruel or wrathful (raudra) concentration (dhyana), and vishuddhi as the absence thereof. Waiting in the shade is preferable to standing in the heat of the sun (Mokshapahu:da 25 and Pujyaypada, Ishtopadesh, 3). Thus, shubha is definitely better than ashubha. Unlike shubha and Page #105 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 79 ashubha, shuddha and shubha are not dichotomous. While shubha is the opposite of ashubha, shubha is said to be dovetailed into and transcended in shuddha. However, there seems to be an apparent contradiction between shubha and shuddha, which is succinctly summed up by Voltaire as: "The best is the enemy of good." »49 This is a perfectionist attitude. The reality, however, is that the good (shubha), which has a purifying effect (vishuddhi) (PS 180 AC) and is partial purity (shuddhata), is continuously purified (vishuddha) until it becomes pure (shuddha). In Mulachara In Mulachara (234) it is stated that punya (merit) is the state of evolution of the self through an enlightened view (sammatta in Pk. and samyaktva in Sk.), knowledge of the scriptures and restraint/ subsidence (nigraha) of passions. Its opposite is evil (papa). Compassion (anukampa) and pure conscious attentiveness (shuddha upayoga) are said to depend upon or considered to be the result of meritorious karmas whereas evil karmas have the opposite effect (Mulachara 235). Under no circumstances does Kundakunda equate ashubha (unwholesome) thought activities with shubha (wholesome) bhavas like compassion, amity, goodwill, etc which are the outcome of subsidence of passions. In Kundkunda's schema, shubha is hierarchically integrated with shuddha (pure bhavas). The higher shuddha does not spurn and repudiate "the lower" shubha. To talk of shuddha repudiating shubha is false dichotomizing. Shuddha, in fact, is not only built upon and rests upon shubha, but encompasses shubha. In Dravya Sangraha (DS) In Dravya Sangraha (verse 45), good or auspicious (shubha) activity is described as restraint from evil, harmful/inauspicious (ashubha) tendencies. Vyavahara charitra (conduct) is said to consist of vows, carefulness or self-regulations and self-restraints of mind, speech and body. Punya (merit) is helpful in liberation, while papa (sin) is an obstacle in liberation. Hence, conduct (charitra) is described as refraining from what is harmful (ashubha) and engagement in what is beneficial (shubha) (DS 45). That which binds the self (atma) or leads to its downfall is evil or Page #106 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 80 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES sin (papa) (Uttaradhyayana churni 2). Like poison, evil or sin (papa) is not beneficial to jiva (the self) (Maransamadhi 613). According to Hemchandra, punya is indicative of feebleness of inauspicious (ashubha) karmas and the onset of a commendable/excellent (prashasta) state, which is the result of the coming into operation/ rise (udaya) of shubha karmas. Dual Role of Shubha Shubha performs a dual role. Since as a result of good/auspicious psychic dispositions (shubha bhava), delusion, passions, etc. become feeble/mild, the bondage of karmas is also somewhat reduced. As a result, one is able to practice moral rules of self-restraint. Shubha has a purifying effect (vishuddhi), which acts as the means (sadhan) of liberation. Since a certain degree of attachment persists, even if it is commendable (prashasta raga), it also results in the bondage of good or meritorious karmas. Subsidence/feebleness or abatemenvof intense passions is the necessary precondition of undertaking shubha (auspicious) vows and moral self-restraints, righteous/virtuous (punya) activities, and spiritual self-discipline. It is only when passions like deluded view, attachment, aversion, anger, etc. subside and one is inclined to moral rules/valules like non-violence, that one develops a clearer perspective of the nature of things, especially the nature of the self and the non-self as well as the relation between the soul and karma, their nexus and interaction. It is only then that one comprehends the difference between papa and punya, including the dual role of punya in causing karmic bondage as well as inhibition and dissociation of karmas. This, in turn, has a purifying (vishuddhi) effect (PS 155 and 180 AC) which eventually leads to liberation (PS 259 and 260 AC). It also enables one to develop a clear understanding of asrava (influx of karmas), etc. and other categories/principles of one's journey in life. The subsidence of delusion, passions, etc. enables the self to be aware of the eventual goal and the direction/capacity/potential of the soul to realize the objective of liberation. In this regard, it is significant to remember that while everyone is striving in their own way for the realization of the ultimate state of emancipation, the quest becomes a self-conscious effort only when a measure of purity has been achieved by the soul. The processes of the deluded karman [both view-deluding Page #107 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION and conduct-deluding) play an important role in the making up of the worldly existence. It is only subsidence (upashaman) of this karman that gives the soul a glimpse of the reality of the nature of things. This process leads to spiritual awakening or an enlightened worldview (samyak darshan). It is also a definitive self-conscious predilection which illumines the spiritual journey leading to the ultimate goal. The process of 'subsidence,' thus, occupies a very important place in the spiritual thinking of the Jainas. So In the case of ashubha bhavas (inauspicous thought activities), on the other hand, the delusion, passions, etc. become intense and therefore the bondage of karmas is also enhanced. Observance of moral rules of self-restraint (vows, etc.) is more desirable than indulging in “unrestrained conduct”. By the arousal of ashubha karmas, the self becomes a rogue, an animal or inhabitant of hell and is always beset with thousands of pains (PS 12, see also PS 158), while the result of good and meritorious karmas is good human birth or heavenly happiness (PS 11). Mokshamarg Prakashak (MMP) Pandit Todarmal, a keen observer of spiritualism and quite conversant with Kundakunda’s works, has categorically stated that unlike ashubha (inauspicious) upayoga, shubha upayoga (conscious attentiveness) is not altogether/absolutely or on all counts, in all respects (sarvatha) worth abandoning or not to be adhered to (heya), thereby refuting the contention of those who seek to equate shubha and ashubha. He has adduced several reasons in that regard under the heading (Shubhopayoga sarvatha heya nahin hai). This heading has been omitted in Kanjipanthi (who hold Pandit Todarmal in high esteem and quote him quite often in support of their one-sided assertions) publications so as not to highlight its utility and significance. Todarmal observes that those persons who hold a deluded view because of misconceptions about nishchaya naya (internal selfreferential viewpoint, i.e. nishchayabhasi mithyadrasthi (a characteristic that is applicable to Kanjipanthi), regard acts like worshipping, to be the cause of the influx of auspicious karmas. These karmas, he adds, should not be adhered to if in renouncing them one keeps onself engrossed in (shuddha) upayoga, i.e. pure conscious attentiveness. It is only in that condition/situation/circumstance, is it desirable/ Page #108 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES beneficial to abandon them. However, if one indulges in inauspicious (ashubha) acts like sensual pleasures or passions, then one would only harm oneself.52 Aversion, Pandit Todarmal adds, results in the bondage of sins whereas non-violence, etc. excellent attachment (prashasta raga) leads to the bondage of merit or virtue (punya). Since both are the cause of bondage, both of them ought to be given up. The passionless state wherein one is free from attachment and aversion is a state where one remains a mere observer and knower (drashta jnata). This state is without any bondage and hence worth attaining (upadeya), However, until such a (passionless pure) state is achieved, one must engage in or continue to observe and follow the conduct of excellent attachment (prashasta raga), i.e. shubha upayoga.” By shubha upaygoa, i.e. good or auspicious upaygoa, one may get a berth in heaven. One may even get an enlightened view of the reality of things by good intentions or it may be good auxiliary cause (nimitta) for the reduction of the duration and fruition of karmas. However, bad or inauspicious (ashubha) upayoga result in one getting a berth in hell or nigoda, etc. Bad intentions or being bad may be an auxiliary cause which increase the duration and fruition of karmas. As a result, the attainment of an enlightened view, etc. becomes extremely difficult. Shubha upayoga enfeebles passions or makes them mild whereas ashubha upayoga makes passions more intense. Therefore, indulging in the acts of intense passions by giving up acts of mild passions is comparable to not eating bitter things but eating poison instead. This is utter ignorance or foolishness. 54 In this regard, he (the nishchayabhashi) [Kanjipanthi) (adherent of a deluded view) mistakenly argues that shubha and ashubha are said to be alike in the scriptures (shastras). (This alludes to SS 146 and PS 77 and PS 77 AC in which they are described as golden and iron chains binding a person, i.e. being the cause of karmic bondage.) It is not, therefore, advisable to delve deeper into their special/particular characteristics. In his reply to this argument, Pandit Todarmal points out that for people, who consider shubha upayoga to be the cause of liberation (moksha) and consider it worthy of adoption (upadeya) and are not therefore able to recognize (the significance of] shuddha (pure) upayoga, shubha and ashubha are said to be similar from the point of view of impurity of karmic bondage. However, when a comparison Page #109 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION is made between the two (shubha and ashubha) as between themselves (paraspara) then it becomes apparent that in case of good/auspicious (shubha) thoughts/mental states, passions tend to become feeble. This leads to a reduction of the bondage of karmas. In case of bad or inauspicious (ashubha) thoughts, passions become intense and thereby lead to an increase in the bondage of karmas. Thus, viewed from this perspective, the good or auspicious (shubha) is considered to be better than the bad or the inauspicious (ashubha) in Jaina scriptures and philosophy. For instance, the disease is only bad irrespective of whether it is less or more serious. However, in comparison to a more severe disease, a less severe disease is better." Therefore, so long as shuddha upayoga (state of pure conscious attentiveness) or passionless conduct is not attained, it is desirable to keep oneself engaged in shubha (auspicious thought activities or virtuous conduct) by getting rid of ashubha (inauspicious thought activities or vicious conduct). But it is not desirable to indulge onself in the ashubha (vicious conduct) by forsaking shubha (virtuous conduct).56 Again, he (the nishchayabashi adherent of a deluded view) argues that “The inauspicious tendency of satisfying the desire of lust or hunger, etc. cannot be avoided and one has to engage in inauspicious proclivity willfully; and he who holds enlightened view wants to avoid desires, therefore, making effort of shubha (pious conduct) is not desirable.”57 In response, Pandit Todarmal stresses that engagement in good and auspicious (shubha) upayoga increases the sense of detachment. As a result, the intensity of sexual urge, etc. as well as the pain and restlessness caused by hunger, etc. is reduced. Hence, it is desirable to practice shubha upayoga.58 In spite of making such effort, if lust and hunger, etc. still cause distress, then in order to satisfy those urges, one should be careful in committing less sin. However, indulgence in unrestrained behaviour in sinful acts by forsaking good and auspicious (shubha) upayoga is not at all desirable. Further, as for the (nishchayabhası) argument that a person who has an enlightened view does not seek any desire while the practice of shubha upayoga requires willful effort, it may be said that though a person does not want to give even a little amount of his money yet wherever he feels that great amount of money is likely to be lost, he Page #110 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 84 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES makes effort willfully to give some quantity of money. Similarly, one who holds enlightened view, does not want to engage himself even in an act involving slightest amount of passion but wherever he feels that inauspicious acts will results in intense passion, he willfully makes effort to engage himself in auspicious acts involving less passions.60 Thus, it is evident that wherever it is possible to attain to pure (shuddha) upayoga of a passionless state, the engagement/involvement in auspicious acts is not desirable. However, where there is a likelihood of inauspicious upayoga, one should make efforts to willfully engage oneself in auspicious upayoga. In this way, indulgence in unrestrained behaviour by forsaking all kinds of external, other-referential moral and other religious practices (vyavahara dharma) is declared to be undesirable and forbidden.61 While one should not exclusively lay emphasis on external practices or means (bahya sadhanadi hi) of dharma, it must be clearly understood that in comparison to indulgence in sinful acts, external moral and religious practices (vyavahara dharma), such as adoration (bhakti), donation (dana), fasting, etc. penance (tapa), vows/moral rules of conduct like non-violence, acts of worship and promotion of dharma, etc. and study of scriptures are not prohibited even though they cause bondage of punya (merit, virtue) or auspicious karmic bondage. One should not, however, remain satisfied by the mere observance of such vyavahara practices but continue to make efforts for the attainment of liberation." In brief, Pandit Todarmal comes to the conclusion that knowing attachment, etc. passions as bad and harmful, one must make efforts to uproot them. There anukrmavishai (step-by-step) [this is exactly the same as Amrtachandra's kramtah], i.e. gradually or step-by-step (PS, 254 AC)], first of all, one should give up inauspicious acts by forsaking intense passions, etc. and should engage oneself in auspicious acts. Thereafter, even by forsaking feeble passions, one should give up auspicious acts also and evolve to the dispassionate or passionless state of purity (shuddhopayoga). 63 Good or auspicious thought activities or moral rules of selfrestraint, which are accompanied by subsidence of passions, have a purifying effect (vishuddhi). They are a means of spiritual development and liberation. However, when good or auspicious (shubha) activities or righteousness (dharma) are practiced only for the sake of sensual Page #111 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION pleasures (bhoga nimittam) (SS 275 and Bhavapahuda 182) or indulged in with passions like attachment or pride, etc., they result in bondage and misery. They do not lead to the destruction of karmas, i.e. liberation. Good deeds (shubha karma) are not to be performed for extraneous considerations, selfish ends or personal gain of name and fame in this world or to seek a berth in heaven, but as a means of purification of the self, keeping in view the final goal of liberation. Kundakunda makes it abundantly clear that those who ignorantly or slavishly observe vows, restraints, etc. moral conduct or practice austerities (tapas) and yearn for punya (merit) in order to get a berth in heaven, attain miraculous powers or even moksha (salvation) in the next world do not know the transcendental (paramartha) nature of the real self (parinamika bhava). They act in violation of the true interests of the self, i.e. peace and excellent happiness (uttam sukha) (paramartha bahira). They neither know the rationale or cause of salvation (moksha-hetu) in the true sense nor are they able to attain nirvana (liberation) (SS 153-154). - In order to destroy the cause of conjunction of the soul with other substances (Amrtachandra's introductory remark to PS 159), viz. material or physical karman (pudgala karman), which act as an auxiliary cause of passions like attachment, aversion, and anger, etc. perverted, harmful, psychic dispositions, resulting in karmic bondage, what is required of the self is to get rid of evil psychic attention. It should not remain stuck in good conscious attentiveness but become established in the real nature of the self (majjatth in Pk., madhyastha in Sk.), meaning neutral or indifferent and meditate upon the self which is of the nature of something knowing (PS 159) and strive for the liberation of the soul. Morality and Spirituality In view of what has been stated in the preceding pages, a futile attempt is made by some people to pit morality against spirituality by obstinately equating punya and papa by relying solely on their bondage aspect, and denying the dual role of punya, including its significant role in purifying (vishuddhi) and liberation. Moral rules of conduct, which provide guidelines to man in leading his life in relation to others in the empirical world, cannot be divorced from the world of his inner thoughts and feelings. Page #112 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES True spirituality is only inner. However, it usually involves some outward expression and manifests itself in moral conduct. The spiritual goal of self-realization or inner purity cannot be achieved by immoral means of himsa (violence), untruth, etc. Thus, the internal and external aspects of spirituality and morality are inter-related, inter-connected and inter-dependent. Morality without spirituality is meaningnless, and spirituality without morality is spirituality only in name. Morality and spirituality or vyavahara and nishchaya charitra is not an either/or situation. They are intimately related to one another and can neither be considered as mutually exclusive nor compartmentalized into watertight compartments. A spiritual culture is inconceivable without an ethical culture. Morality goes hand-in-hand and coexists with spirituality. In fact, the two are inseparable. They are also interdependent in the sense that spirituality helps morality. In turn, morality facilitates/fosters the attainment of the spiritual goal of self-conquest or the eradication of evil tendencies and impurities of the self. Thus, in Jainism, spirituality is the essence of morality and morality is intertwined with spirituality. Spirituality and morality are not identical but they are not separate as they are the internal and external aspects or the obverse and reverse sides of the same conscious entity or the self. Spiritual goals can only be realized by the pursuit of a life of morality, which is the pursuit of righteousness and piety. Spirituality is concerned with internal purity and individual perfection, which is unthinkable without morality. Moral self-restraints are necessary for attaining freedom from instinctive impulses and subconscious motivations. Thus, morality and spirituality are closely related and complementary to one another. Spirituality is the foundation and the basis of morality and morality is its natural offspring and manifestation. In the absence of spirituality, morality would be deprived if its moorings. Without morality, spirituality will degenerate into “mere experiential” mysticism or an intellectual exercise devoid of either content or result. Overall Appraisal of Shubha Shubha (good) psychic-attention (upayoga) is regarded as auspicious (mangala) causing well-being and fostering merit, virtue, or righteousness (punya). It plays an important role in our life. It is Page #113 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION therefore regarded as desirable thing worth-acquiring (upadeya) in all religions of the world. On the other hand, evil or vicious (ashubha) upayoga is considered inauspicious, undesirable and worth abandoning (heya). When good (shubha or punya) karma becomes operational, one gets worldly prosperity, good health, manifold sensual pleasures, including those of heaven, etc. (PS 70, PS 11). If shubha or the excellent attachment (prashasta raga) is oriented towards sanity and purification (vishuddhi) (PS 155, 180 AC), it gradually (kramtah) leads to liberation (PS 254, 259-260). However, with the rise (udaya) of the evil (ashubha) karma, the self becomes a rogue, an animal or inhabitant of hell. It is always plagued by thousands of pains, and strays incessantly (PS 12). After transcending the stage of ashubha (evil) upayoga, the self ascends the stage of shubha upayoga, and thereby embraces the love of righteousness (dharma anuraga), which manifests in respect for the worthy Lord and the enlightened souls like teachers (guru) and saints as well as virtues like charity, moral precepts/moral conduct of selfrestraints of non-violence, etc. (PS 69 and PS 69 AC) and compassion towards living beings (PS 157), etc. Ashubha upayoga, on the other hand, consists of infatuation, both view-deluding (i.e. infatuation) and conduct-deluding (i.e. attachment and aversion). It is inclined towards perverse ways. It is engrossed in sense-gratification (vishaya), and passions (kashaya), practicing passionate bad thoughts, bad hearing, bad intention, bad companionship and violence (PS 158 and PS 158 AC). Explaining shubha and ashubha attachment in Pravachanasara, Jayasena states: “Devotion of the five revered souls (panch parameshthi), etc. is shubha attachment (i.e. commendable or excellent attachment, prashasta raga], while attachment to sense objects (vishaya) and anger, etc. passions (kashaya) is ashubha attachment” (PS 180 JS), [i.e. worth abandoning or not praiseworthy and not excellent attachment, i.e. aprashasta raga. In Samayasara, it is also stated that for people, who are at a lower stage of spiritual development, the vyavahara path of shubha (good, auspicious) is useful, desirable and worth adopting (prayojanavana) in order to inhibit or restrain passions like delusion, gratification of sense objects, anger, etc. and evil concentration (SS 12 JS). Kundakunda says that if the psychic-attention (upayoga) is good Page #114 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 88 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES (shubha), it leads to accumulation, generation or increase of punya (virtue, merit, righteousness, piousness). If the psychic-attention is evil or inauspicious (ashubha), it leads to accumulation or increase of sin or sinfulness (papa). In the absence of both, there is no accession, accumulation or increase of either (PS 156), i.e. bondage of punya papa karma (PS 156 JS). and When psychic-attention (upayoga) is influenced by attachment in the form of sanity or purifying effect (vishuddhi) or affliction, distress and morbidity (sanklesha), it is of a dual aspect, viz. good and evil. It is active as a cause of conjunction with other substances, which receive a double aspect of either merit and sin. However, when non-existence of this impure in both forms is effected, then only pure psychicattention remains. This is no cause of conjunction with any other substance (PS 156 AC). The evolution of the self into infatuation (moha) and aversion (dvesh) is ashubha, while its evolution into attachment is both good (shubha) and evil (ashubha) since attachment has a dual role whereby it is imbued with either sanity having a purifying (vishuddhi) effect or is imbued with affliction, distress and morbidity (sanklesh) (PS 180 and 180 AC). In Tattvartha Sutra, virtuous activities (punya) are also said to have a paradoxical dual nature/role of generating karmic influx and bondage as well as of inhibiting (samvara) of karmic influx (SAS commentary on TS 6.3, and 9.2.3). In Purusharthasiddhyupaya (PSU 221) and in his commentary on Pravachanasara (PS 11), Amrtachandra has described the contradictory effects of good (shubha) psychic-attention by citing the example of hot clarified butter (ghee), which makes things delicious, but if ghee is heated by fire it also causes pain of burning. One should not, therefore, reach the wrong conclusion that contradictory effects occur simultaneously. Dual Role of Shubha Shubha has a dual role in generating karmic influx and bondage as well as inhibiting (samvara) karmic influx, which in turn influences the purification of the self. This signifies that it is not to be blindly or indiscriminately adhered to. As a means to sensorial pleasures (PS 69 AC), it leads to misery (PS 76), if people having plenty of punya, resulting from shubha upayoga indistinguishably experience, like those Page #115 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 89 with evil (ashubha) upayoga, simply misery, conditioned by the body, i.e. by the five sense-organs. Since both miss innate happiness of a transcendental nature (parmartha), a relation of separateness (prthakatva) between good and evil psychic-attention does not hold (PS 72 and PS 72 AC), especially if they (such people) are necessarily perceived as craving for only (eva) sense objects (vishaya trashna) (PS 74 and PS 74 AC). In order to denigrate punya, the Kanjipanthi try to ignore qualifying word "if"." 64 Thus, a person who is immersed in this way in infatuation (moha), continuously moves about in the terrible cycle of transmigratory existence. As a result, according to deeper truth of the transcendental nature of the self (paramartha), a duality of merit and sin, like a duality of good and evil psychic-attention or of pleasure and pain, does not exist. The primary reason for this is that on both sides equally there is no property (dharma) which really belongs to the soul (PS 77 AC). The last sentence of this paragraph has been distorted by Bharill to signify that for the devotees of dharma of the self (atma dharma), both punya and papa are equally adharma (unrighteous, evil, sin) only." In this regard, Amrtachandra describes the way in which one must act to avoid circumstances when punya is similar to papa. 65 (1) If one feels egoistical (ahankarika) pride in practicing punya (acts of righteousness such as charity, compassion, etc.) (PS 77 AC) [because the worldly prosperity and name, fame (vaibhava), etc. obtained by virtuous deeds leads to pride (mada or ahankara), pride generates deluded intellect (mudha mati), which, in turn, leads to sinful, vicious acts (papa); such punya is not desired (PP 2.60)]; (2) when one has expectation of enjoyments of sense objects in future (nidan) as a result of punya because pleasure of the senses indeed spells misery (PS 76 and PP 2.59); (3) if his state of consciousness (chitta bhumi) becomes coloured (uparakta) [with intense attachment, aversion, etc.] due to punya; and (4) if due to punya, he censures, disdains or disrespects, i.e. goes against the purity of the self (suddhatmano vipreet) and does not consider punya as a means (sadhan) of or supportive factor of] pure (shuddha) upayoga (PS 77 AC). However, it is incorrect to equate shubha and asubha, or punya and papa. Shubha, Amrtachandra clarifies, differs from ashubha on four grounds, i.e. in its nature (svabhava), cause (karana), effect (experience Page #116 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES or anubhava of fruition of karmas) and in substratum (ashraya) and fosters the path of liberation because shubha (punya) is the path of liberation (moksha marg) whereas ashubha (papa) is the way to karmic bondage (bandha marg), (shubhashubhau moksha bandha margau) (SS 145 AC). Punya is therefore desirable (upadeya) or worth practicing. From an external, other-referential point of view (vyavahara naya), Jayasena elaborates, there is a difference between punya and papa in regard to the condition (hetu) of karmic bondage, nature (svabhava), effect (fruition or experience) and substrata (ashraya). If virtuous activities (punya), such as self-restraint of moral rules of non-violence, etc. vows (vrata), charity (dana) etc., are accompanied by or associated with an enlightened view of things (samyaktva), they become the traditional (paramparaya) cause of liberation (SS 145 JS). Due to attachment, the self (even with good, excellent or commendable attachment (prashasta raga) (PS 254-255) also) binds karman (PS 179). However, when oriented towards sanity and purification (vishuddhi), (PS 155 and 188AC), thereby experiencing the [transcendental nature of the pure self, gradually (kramatah) brings about the highest happiness of nirvana (liberation) (PS 254 and PS 254 AC). Thus, it not only leads to liberation of oneself (PS 259 and PS 259 AC) but also helps others to attain liberation (PS 260 and PS 260 AC). Shubha occupies a middle position between ashubha and shuddha. It can degenerate into ashubha, if the prosperity and high position, etc. obtained by good or virtuous deeds, leads one to indulge in sense pleasures and pride, greed, etc. passions. Alternately, it can rise to become the pure self as it also has a purifying (vishuddhi) effect if it is oriented towards sanity, righteousness, self-restraint and piety. It all depends on the use one makes of it. If Kundakunda has pointed out the sombre aspects of shubha or punya, i.e. the possibility of its misuse, that does not imply that one should discard punya or shubha altogether considering it as worth abandoning (heya) like evil (ashubha) or sinful (papa). Misperceptions and Distortions of Kanjipanthi regarding Shubha or Punya In spite of what has been stated above, Kanjipanthi still harbour numerous misperceptions in regard to good (shubha or punya) by Page #117 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 91 selectively using out of context certain portions of the text and deliberately twist/distort meanings and wrongly interpret various statements. These misperceptions are: 66 1. That both good (shubha) and evil (ashubha) are both impure (ashuddha) psychic-attention (upayoga). Therefore, they are equally worth abandoning and emphasis should be laid on getting rid of both of them.67 In response, one may argue that Kundakunda describes upayoga to be of three kinds (viz. ashubha, shubha and shuddha), and not of two kinds (viz. pure and impure) as Kanjipanthi seem to suggest. In Pravachanasara verse 9, Kundakunda specifically states: "The soul accepts the character of its state-of-evolution. When the soul evolves through the good or the evil, it becomes good or evil. When it evolves through the pure, then it becomes pure." (PS 9) In his commentary on this verse, Amrtchandra observes that the states-of-evolution (parinama) of consciousness or psychic-attention (upayoga) of soul (jiva) is good, evil and pure (PS 9 AC), i.e. three kinds. In Pravachanasara 155, upayoga characterized by knowledge and intuition is said to be good or evil. However, in his commentary, Amrtachandra states that upayoga is sub-divided in two ways according to purity and impurity. The impurity which is characterized by attachment, is again two-fold, viz. good and evil [yet these two are not the same]. The good is characterized by sanity having purifying (vishuddhi) effect, while evil is characterized by affliction, distress or morbidity (sanklesha) (PS 155 AC). Jayasena considers this shubha of the nature of attachment or affection for dharma (righteousness or piety) and ashubha of the nature of attachment to sense objects, aversion and deluded view (vishaya anuraga rupa, dvesh moha rupa) (PS 155 JS). The nature of good (shubha) and evil (ashubha) upayoga is described in Pravachanasara verses 157 and 158, which amply brings about the difference between the two. Thus, the states-of-evolution of consciousness are said to be of three kinds: (a) of the nature of sanklesh, which is characterized by overwhelming, non-abstinent, most intense or severe passions (teevra kashaya); (b) vishuddhi characterized by mild or moderate passions (manda kashaya); and (c) pure, which is devoid of passions of anger, pride, greed, etc. It is only when passions subside, that the soul has a mental state (bhava) which is oriented towards veneration of the worthy Lord and moral conduct of self-restraint [such as non-violence, Page #118 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES etc. vows, self-regulation (samiti) and restraints of mind, speech and body (gupti)]. Therefore, these activities are considered to have a purifying (vishuddhi) effect, which in turn acts as the cause of attaining pure psychic-attention and the pure self. Pandit Todarmal categorically states that less intensity or mild passion is better that greater intensity of passion, just as less severity of disease is better than more severity of disease. Only the soul with mild passion is likely to evolve into even more milder state(s) of passion and ultimately become devoid or free of passions, i.e. pure (shuddha). It is for this reason that Acharya Vidyasagara has stated: “One cannot have pure psychic-attention without good psychicattention (bin shubha upayoga ke hot na shuddha upayoga)." 2. There is no difference whatsoever, according to Bharill, between punya (good; virtuous, righteousness) and papa, (evil, sin). A person who thinks that there is a difference between them, he asserts, is a deluded person (mithyadrashti).9 (This is nowhere written in any Jain scripture.] This is a serious mistake, which leads to the inevitable result of nigod (rebirth in the lowest state of development of soul). The avoidance of that mistake leads to an enlightened view of things (samyak darshan) resulting in moksha (liberation). Even if any difference between punya and papa is accepted or acknowledged even from an external, other-referential aspect (vyavahara naya), Bharill adds, one should consider that difference to be secondary (gauna) and negate or deny that difference (gauna karake nishedha karna hai). Thus, this kind of thinking on the part of Kanjipathi is not only patently wrong and misplaced but also dangerous. Impurity (kalushata or ashuddhi) primarily consists in the intensity of anger, etc. passions, and evil impulses. The natural result of good (shubha) psychic-attention (upayoga) or the operationalization of virtuous (punya) deeds leads to the subsidence of passions reflecting calmness of mind (prasham bhava), commendable attachment (prashasta raga), which is oriented towards sanity and purification (vishuddhi or akalushata), compassion (anukampa) and psychic energy geared or disposed towards righteousness (samvega). They are said to be necessary prerequisites of an enlightened world-view (samyakdarshan). Therefore, to equate them with evil (papa) or consider them to be the cause of delusion (mithyatva) is a gross distortion of facts and what is written in Jain scriptures, including the works of Acharya Page #119 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION Kundakunda. 3. That punya and papa are only the cause of influx (asrava) of karmas (TS 6.3) and consequent bondage alone. From this, the Kanjipanthi seek to prove that they both are to be considered as part of influx and bondage of karmas. This is said to be the view expressed in Tattvartha Sutra, which speaks of only seven principles of life (tattvas) (TS 1.4). In his works particularly Samayasara, Kundakunda, specially mentions nine tattvas or categories (padarthas) (SS 13 and PKS 108) including punya (righteousness and piety) and papa (sin, vice). As in the case of asrava, bandha, etc. padarthas, a separate chapter is devoted in the case of punya and papa, which are considered significant concepts and separate categories; in fact, it is significant to note that no verse in the asrava chapter of Samayasara, makes any reference to punya or papa as being part of asrava (influx of karmas), since punya is not merely or simply the cause of influx and consequent bondage of karmas. Punya has a dual role of karmic bondage as also having a purifying effect (visuddhi) (PS 180 AC) and gradually leading to liberation (PS 254 AC). 4. That Jain texts do not mention that good (shubha) activities and virtuous (punya) deeds, such as veneration of the worthy Lord, etc. lead to inhibition of karmic influx... In response, it may be stated that the Sarvarthasiddhi commentary on Tattvartha Sutra (TS 6.3 and 9. 23) specifically points out that the virtuous activities (punya) have a paradoxical dual role in generating karmic influx and bondage as well as inhibiting (samvara) karmic influx. 5. Kanji Svami's assertion that “the objective (dhyeya) of good psychic dispositions (shubha parinamas) is sensorial pleasure”73 is also quite incorrect and misleading. In his commentary, Amrtachandra has described good psychic attention as the means (sadhan) of sensorial pleasure (PS 70 AC). However, neither Kundakunda nor Amrtachandra have considered sensorial pleasure to be the objective of shubha parinama, because in their view, the pleasure, acquired by means of the senses, is indeed misery (PS 76). 6. Bharill's assertion that one gets only external material (of sense enjoyments) as a result of shubha or punya and not peace of self,74 or less intensity of passions (kashaya mandata) is not correct. Apart from prosperity, one also gets calmness of mind due to subsidence of passions (prasham bhava). This is possible only in the conditions of a Page #120 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 94 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES good mental state (shubha bhava) and not in the circumstances when a person's mind is in the grip of intense emotional agitation caused by intensity of passions or sinful evil thoughts (ashubha). 7. That good psychic-attention is the cause of karmic bondage. This assertion is not correct since good psychic-attention, as stated earlier, has a dual role: it is the cause of both bondage and inhibition of karmas and purification (vishuddhi) (PS 180 AC) and leads to liberation (PS 254 and 259 AC). 77 8. That good (shubha) psychic-attention is not dharma or that it cannot be considered to be dharma. The real dharma is pure psychicattention or pure state-of-evolution of the self alone, which is the cause of freedom from karmic bondage." In this context, Pravachanasara states that the innate nature of the soul is to evolve through dharma. This evolution can be pure (shuddha) psychic-attention or good (shubha) psychic-attention (PS 11 and PS 11 AC). When the self is not partaking at all of the evolution of dharma, it gives itself up to the evolution of evil (ashubha) psychic-attention, which lacks even a grain of (lawful or righteous) conduct (PS 12 AC). As a result, it experiences the bondage of a thousand pains and misery, and wanders about as rogue, animal or inhabitant of hell and must be completely abandoned (PS 12 AC). Moreover, good or virtuous mental states and acivities, which are characterised by subsidence of passions and oriented towards selfrestraints, sanity and purification (vishuddhi), also act as the cause of pure psychic-attention as also of pure self. The commendable attachment (prashasta raga) in good psychic-attention gradually (kramatah) brings about the highest happiness of nirvana (liberation) (PS 254 and PS 254 AC). Thus, it not only leads to liberation of oneself (PS 259 and PS 259 AC) but also helps others to attain liberation (PS 260 and PS 260 AC) as has already been stated. Moreover, Acharya Virasena, in his Jai Dhavala (Book 1, p. 5) commentary on Kashaya-Prabhrata (Kashaya-Pahuda), one of the most authentic Jain texts of Digambaras, has acknowledged the possibility of both samvara (inhibitation of influx of karma) and nirjara (eradicating of karmas). He states: "If eradication of karmas is not considered possible by shubha and shuddha (pure) psychic disposition (parinama), then eradication of karmas will not be possible at all." 9. Kanji's contention that the psychic disposition of punya is not the Page #121 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 95 means (sadhan) of dharma, but is the cause of affliction (klesha)78 is not correct because Pravachanasara clearly states that good or virtuous (shubha or punya) is oriented towards sanity, righteousness, or piety (dharma) and purification (vishuddhi). Evil (ashubha) and sinful mental state, on the other hand, is of the nature of affliction, distress and morbidity (klesha or sanklesh) (PS 155 and 180 AC). 10. To say that there is no other dharma except the discourse, sermon or instruction (deshana) of the worthy Lord,79 is only partially true. Similarly, to argue that the attainment of inclination to understand and grasp the reality of things such discourses (deshana labdhi) is the only auxiliary cause of the nature of supportive factor of an enlightened world-view (samyakdarshan) is again a partial truth because there are several other factors, such as subsidence of passions, commendable attachment (prashasta raga), compassion (anukampa), etc. 11. Kanji's statement that the self's good or virtuous (punya) psychic dispositions of compassion or kindness (daya), charity (dana), etc. take place by forgetting the nature of the self, comprising of perception, cognition and being blissful,80 implying thereby that such activities are against the nature of the self and that punya only gives rise to longing (trashna) for and the tendency of enjoying sense-objects31 is patently wrong. In Dhavala, one of the most authentic texts of Jainism, compassion is declared to be the innate nature (svabhava) of jiva (self) (Dhavala, Book 13, p. 362).82 In reply to Kanji's assertion that punya only gives rise to longing and tendency for sense-enjoyments, it may be stated that punya does not say or compel a person to have longing for or indulge in senseenjoyments. Ultimately, it is upto the person, who is the architect and master of his destiny (PKS 27), how one makes use of the facilities and opportunities of prosperity, good health, human birth, etc., obtained as a result of virtuous deeds (punya karma). One may put them to good use or waste and squander his energies and facilities in sense-enjoyments. The Kanjipanthi persist in their mistaken view that there is no difference between good (shubha) or righteousness (punya) and evil (ashubha) or sinful (papa) activities whatsoever, that both are the cause of bondage of karma. In so doing, they are: (1) blurring the difference between the two; (2) ignoring the dual role of shubha or punya pointed by Amrtachandra that it is not only cause of bondage but also of Page #122 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES purification (vishuddhi), which gradually leads to liberation (see PS 155-156, 180 and 254 AC); (3) pitting shubha against shuddha (pure), even though (shubha) is the supportive factor and cause of shuddha; and (4) denying the significant role of self-restraints (samyam) and austerities (tapa) in attaining liberation. The reason why the Kanjipanthi want to deliberately distort the nature of shubha or punya by insisting that there is no difference whatsoever between punya and papa and that both of them are worth abandoning (heya) seems to be to present an easy path of liberation to people so that they do not have to either adopt means (sadhan) of moral conduct and spiritual self-discipline or undertake efforts of selfrestraints (samyam) and austerities to attain pure psychic-attention, pure self and liberation. Knowledge of the self (atmajnana), or obtaining an enlightened view of the self through overcoming of delusion (mithyatva) and meditation of the self (atma dhyana), which is (mistakenly defined by Bharill as] continuing to know the self, is considered sufficient for getting rid of karmas and attaining liberation. In so doing, they seek to revise Kundakunda's teaching and scriptural prescription that an enlightened world-view of the reality of things as they are, including the self, the non-self and the resulting categories of influx of karmas, etc. due to their interaction, knowledge thereof and enlightened conduct devoid of attachment and aversion-the trinity constitute the path of liberation. With a view to circumvent this age-old path of liberation, the Kanjipanthi do not hesitate to propagate that delusion (mithyatva) is an "internal” fault#3 and the most terrible, the most serious, dangerous and great heinous sin or crime (maha bhayankara papa).84 It alone is said to be responsible for the transmigratory existence of the soul, and to belittle, or undermine the significance of conduct-deluding attachment and aversion by stating that they are "external or superficial only”.85 Bharill has the audacity to make such patentently wrong and absurd assertions even when it is specifically declared that "attachment, aversion and deluded view are soul's own inalienable states-of-evolution or modes (ananya parinama)" (SS 371) and that after delusion (mithyatva or moha) (deluded-view] has gone or is given up, “if, (i.e. only when] the self gets rid of attachment and aversion, then (and then only) it obtains the pure self (shuddha atma) (PS 81), i.e. attains liberation, not otherwise. Page #123 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION This is because a deluded-view, attachment and aversion are considered asrava-bhava (psychic states responsible for the influx and consequent bondage of karmas) (SS 176-177). In their absence, the soul is not liable to bondage (SS 167, 178). Without these asravabhava, even the four factors (pratyaya) of delusion (mithyatva), lack of moral self-restraints of non-violence, etc. vows (avirati), anger, etc. passions and vibratory activities of mind, speech and body (yoga), that affect, influence, and condition psychic states (SS 109), which are usually considered to be the causal factors of bondage (SS 109), are not able to bind the soul (SS 176, 178). The Characteristics of Infatuation (Moha) and the Issue of Compassion (PS 85) There is considerable controversy regarding karuna (mercy, kindness or compassion) mentioned in Pravachanasara verse 85. It states: “The (three) characteristics of moha (infatuation) are: (1) the tendency to view things differently or other than what they really are, i.e. wrong perceptions or perverse ascertainment of things or deluded view (mithya darshan); (2) karunabhavo towards animals and men; and (3) indulgence in sense objects.” Due to its inclination towards sense objects, the self is inclined to develop attachment (raga) towards affectionate, pleasant or agreeable objects and aversion (dvesh) in regard to objects considered unaffectionate, unpleasant or disagreeable things (PS 85 AC). Evidently, where only moha is used, it usually (unless context indicates otherwise) implies the above-mentioned three characteristics, viz. deluded view, attachment and aversion. Where moha is used along with raga and dvesh. it signifies only mithya darshan, which consists of mithyatva (delusion) plus the most intense or tenacious anger, etc. passions (anantanubhandhi kashaya). Mithya darshan is called viewdeluding (darshan mohaniya karma), while raga and dvesh are considered conduct-deluding (charitra mohaniya) karma, i.e. the faults of conduct in Jaina terminology Different Works and Scholars on Compassion The controversy regarding karunabhavo relates to deciding whether "karunabhavo” (or karunabhava in Sanskrit) signifies feeling of compassion (karuna+bhava), i.e. samas (conjoint word) in grammar or absence of feeling of compassion (karuna+abhava), i.e. sandhi Page #124 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 98 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES (joining of two words) in grammar. Barend Faddegon, following Amrtachandra, has translated karunabhavo as “feeling of compassion (karuna)”, while A.N. Upadhye has translated it as "absence of kindness (karuna)” (PS 85). There is, thus, a serious difference of opinion as regards what Kundakunda meant by karunabhavo. Amrtachandra interprets it as feeling of compassion (karuna+bhava, i.e. samasa between two words). A number of scholars, on the other hand, maintain that it means absence of kindness (karuna+abhava, a joining, or combination, i.e. sandhi of two words). This, they argue, is evident from what has been stated by Kundakunda in his works, including Panchastikayasara and Pravache:nasara, and other Jain texts. It is argued how the feeling of compassion which is a wholesome, good (shubha) thought-activity and which is a constituent of an enlightened world-view, can be said to be the characteristic of moha, that needs to be destroyed? If compassion is not dharma, can the absence of compassion, i.e. cruelty to animals and fellow beings be called dharnia? Ashta Pahuda (AP) In Bodh Pahuda (25), Kundakunda states that dharma (righteousness, piety) is that which is purified by compassion (daya visudhho dhammo). In Bhava Pahuda (133), muni (saints) are instructed to have compassion towards all six classes of living beings and such compassionate people are said to destroy all sins (Verse 159). Whosoever is compassionate to living beings is considered to have good psychic attention (shubhopayoga) (PS 157). In Sheel Pahuda (19), kindness to living beings, control of senses, truthfulness, non-stealing, chastity, contentment, enlightened view, knowledge and austerity are said to (constitute) the family of virtue. Niyamsara In Niyamsara, Kundakunda speaks of sparahidam (sva-para hita in Sk.), i.e. the well-being of self as well as others (NS 62). In Panchastikayasara, compassion (anukampa), a feeling of goodwill, sympathy and kindness (karuna) at the sight of needy and the sufferers and the offering of charity or active relief to the thirsty, the hungry and the miserable (PKS 137), is considered (see above) as one of the necessary prerequisites of samyak-darshan (enlightened world-view), which is quite opposite of infatuation or deluded view (moha). Page #125 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 99 Compassion is, thus, said to be one of the constituents or prerequisites of shubhopayoga as also of enlightened world-view (samyak-darshan). The additional verse Pravachanasara 268/2 of Jayasena recension defines compassion as: "He who, seeing one thirsty, hungry or miserable, is pained in mind and through pity assists him is compassion." (PS 268/2) Dhavala In Dhavala, compassion (anukampa) or kindness (karuna) is described as one of the four characteristics (together with samvega, i.e. inclination towards righteousness, avoidance of evil deeds, i.e. prasham or subsidence of passions, and astikya, i.e. firm conviction about the reality of things or the fundamental principles of life) of samyaktva (enlightened view) (Dhavala, Book 10, p. 1151). If compassion is the characteristic of samyaktva (enlightened view, which is opposite of moha or mithya darshan), how could it be said to be the characteristic of a deluded view (moha). Compassion is also declared in Dhavala to be the innate nature (svabhava) of jiva (self) (Dhavala, Book 13, p. 362), just the same way as the lamp removes the darkness of itself as also of others. Pujyapada There is a natural tendency or inclination in living beings to feel concerned at the sight of the miserable condition of other beings. Defining compassion, Pujyapada states: "Compassion is the feeling of sympathy of one whose mind is moistened by kindness or distress for the suffering of others as if it were one's own" (Sarvarthasiddhi commentary on TS 6.12). To be sensitive (samvedan-sheel) in regard to the suffering of others is quite natural. Compassion is not only essential for our own peace and mental stability but also essential for human survival as it is the very basis of society. It is because of compassion and kindness (karuna bhava) that the enlightened Lords deliver sermons or discourses for the well-being of living beings. Likewise, the saints give spiritual instruction (upadesha) for the good of the people. Shakespeare Shakespeare talks of mercy, as a virtue which is "twice blest; it blesses him that gives and him that takes" (Merchant of Venice - IV, I). Indeed, purely from one's own point of view and for one's own Page #126 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 100 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES benefit, it would be necessary to cultivate this virtue of mercy, as also another virtue which invariably goes with it - compassion. Both of these are the two sides of the same coin. One cannot exist or be embellished without the other. Dalai Lama In this regard a question may be asked that while one spends his time, energy and money, only others benefit? In other words “how is mercy or compassion” to be considered "twice blest” as is claimed? According to the Dalai Lama, “The first beneficiary of compassion is always oneself” as it "reduces our fear, boosts our confidence and brings inner strength.” It is spirituality of the highest order for it leads to positivity and contentment. It is negation of the feeling of hatred, revenge and criticism of fellow sentients. Compassion, as the Dalai Lama says, is that unique sense of caring which binds people into a single human family. Patanjali Patanjali, while including compassioni (karana) as one of the necessary virtues for obtaining peace and felicity (chittaprasadnam), based his exhortation on practical wisdom. This is because when a person is involved in act of mercy or compassion, he emerges, though for a short while, out of his own cloistered world within, to that real and vast world, where suffering poverty, inequity and despair abound. 86 Commenting on it, K. Vijayaraghavan observes: In this comprehensive view of things, one's own problems, concerns and anxieties would appear less daunting. He would also comprehend that the world outside also includes those immumerable persons and also animals and birds who, though deprived, have much strength, toughness and resilience within. Such exposers have an inspiring impact whereby the resultant broadness in outlook serves to erase the accumulated prejudices, grudges, resentments, conflicts and self-pity from the mind. The 'space' now created within permits entry of noble thoughts and healthy vibrations. Improved focus, which comes about naturally, ensures accomplishments in all ways. The person concerned is, thus, more than compensated for his efforts. Importantly, he is also at peace, in the feeling that he has done his bit. 87 The Bible (These virtues) bring with them that fulfillment within, which only Page #127 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 101 practical experience can vouch for... The Bible aptly pionts out “He that has pity upon the poor lendeth into the Lord” (Proverbs: 19, 17). . . [Since such) virtues benefit oneself too, it would also be necessary to inspire and motivate oneself continually.88 Example of Abraham Lincoln It is said that when Abraham Lincoln was a young lawer (later the future sixteenth President of the United States) was travelling, he saw a piglet hopelessly stuck in the mud. The poor creature was struggling very hard to extricate itself from the marshy land but the more the animal struggled to get free, the more it stuck itself in the mud and was sure to die of thirst or starvation ultimately. Lincoln was wearing a new suit he hadn't owned for very long and most thoughts of compassion or rescue were not really in his priority list right then. Lincoln felt distressed or grieved by its pitiable condition, so much so that when he reached office he could not get the pig out of his head and concentrate on his work. His mind could not be at ease until he got that pig extricated from the mud. He, therefore, went to that place, got down from his carriage to help it out. When he was praised for his goodness, he remarked that what he did was merely to remove a thorn from his owrimind which would have pricked him throughtout his life, if he had not done this simple affordable act. “By showering mercy, compassion, generosity and altruism," Vijayaraghavan remarks, the person concerned does a service to himself too. (Hence mercy is] “twice blest”. 89 Thus, it signifies that one renders aid to others primarily for relieving the anguish, grief or regret (kheda) from one's own mind, thereby ensuring his own peace of mind. In this sense, compassion is also justified from the internal, self-referential point of view (nishchaya naya). Panchastikayasara (PKS) Kundakunda himself has stated that since one's mind (naturally) gets afflicted by grief or distressed (duhkhit mana) at the sight of the thirsty, the hungry and the miserable, he offers relief to them, out of pity (kripa); then such behaviour of that person is compassion (anukampa) (PKS 137), which is the second condition (after noble or commendable attachment, (prashasta raga) generating punya (merit or virtue). The act of compassion implies the feeling of sympathy at the sight of the needy and the sufferers as well as active relief to them. Page #128 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 102 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES This kind of compassion is common to the ordinary mortals and it manifests in only temporary relief. But in the case of the wise ones (jnani) anukampa, i.e. feeling of grief or regret (kheda) manifests in a higher form at the sight of the struggling souls in the ocean of Samsara (PKS 137 AC) and they manifest a generous sympathy and help them towards emancipation. Thus, anukampa is of two kinds, lower and higher according as its result is temporary and superficial or radical and permanent. Tattvartha Sutra (TS) Like compassion or mercy, giving charity (dana) is also for mutual benefit as it benefits both the giver and the recipient. The giver gives for his own benefit with a sense of gratitude to the recipient. Charity, thus, practiced with a pure heart helps weaken karmic bondage (TS 7.38). As a result of charity, one also accumulates merit (punya), thereby benefitting oneself as it is one of the causes of the influx of pleasure-producing (sata-vedaniya) karma (TS 6.12). Charity also benefits others by relieving their suffering. Those who practice these virtues will not harbout any national, racial, religious or class hatred. Thus, the external behaviour of rendering help or assistance to others, resulting from compassionate feeling, naturally leads to the discontinuance or removal of pain of the self and other (sva-para dhukha nivrtti). As a result, it is the cause of peace, happiness and well-being of oneself as well as others (sva-para hita or sva-para anugraha heto). The well-being of oneself is primary and precedes the well being of others. In being kind to oneself (sva-daya), one is being kind to others as well (para-daya). Sva (self) and para (other) or internal and external are inter-related. The accomplishment of any task or deed requires or depends on coordination of both internal and external causes (the intrinsic cause is regarded as primary or the substantive cause, while the extrinsic cause is considered as secondary, supportive or auxiliary cause) is said to be in the very nature things (dravyagatah svabhavah) (Samantabhadra, Svyambhu-stotra, Verse 60). Since karuna is not audayika bhava, i.e. the mental state resulting from the coming into operation or the rise of karman, it cannot be the cause of karmic bondage (Dhavala, Book 13, pp. 381-382). Compassion (karuna) (as described in PKS 137) can be said to be the natural inclination or tendency to be sensitive (samvedansheel) to Page #129 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 103 the suffering of others, signifying willingness to be helpful towards them. In Jai Dhavala (Book 1, p. 96 commentary), compassion results in the influx of punya (merit, righteousness) and of pure conscious attentiveness (shuddha upayoga), while the opposite thereof, i.e. absence of compassion, leads to influx of sinful karmas. Thus, the two most authentic Digambara texts speak highly of compassion. Karuna in Sanskrit means active sympathy, gentle affection and willingness to bear the pain of others. It is a wish for all beings to be free from suffering. The Pali word is “metta”, which means loving kindness, friendliness, benevolence, fellowship, amity, concord, inoffensiveness and non-violence. It is a strong wish for the welfare and happiness of others (parahita-parasukha-kamana) without any selfinterest. Metta is universal, unselfish and all-embracing love. It is a wish for the happiness of all. It is an antidote to selfishness, anger and fear. Compassion and Infatuation are Different Compassion or kindness (karuna) and infatuation (moha) are quite different. As already stated, compassion is said to be the nature (svabhava) of jiva (self), the characteristic of an enlightened worldview (samyaktva) as also the cause of punya or shubha (good, auspicious), dharma (righteousness, piety) having a conscious role (bhumika) of attentiveness. Infatuation is said to have three roles (bhumika), viz. of false perception of things, including nature of self (i.e. moha or delusion), attachment (raga) and aversion (dvesha) (PS 83 AC). It is the perversion of the conscious states, quite opposite of an enlightened view of things and conduct. It leads to sinful (papa) activities, which are considered to be adharma (absence of righteousness, piety, dharma). The absence of compassion signifies mercilessness, cruelty or wrathful meditation (raudra dhyana), which can in no way be described as wholesome, righteous or virtuous meditation (dharma dhyana), and as such can only be considered adharma (Dhyanshatak 27). Infatuation prevents a person from being able to grasp the real nature of the self. One is therefore engrossed in sense pleasures, attached to external objects, and utterly selfish, "having a sense of me and mineness in other substances" (PS 183 and SS 19-23). This makes one forget one's duties. One even tries to exploit others for Page #130 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 104 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES the satisfaction of one's desires. A kind-hearted person, on the other hand, endeavours to help the needy and the poor by sacrificing his money and comfort for their benefit. The activities – mental, vocal or physical – of the mundane self, for the well-being of others are called punya. Such activities of the nature of punya are of two kinds: (1) those that are done for the selfish reasons in the world; and (2) those that are done as a matter of duty and without any expectation. Of the two, the second one is the real punya activity. A unique example of this is 80 years old “birds hospital in the precincts of Jain Red Temple just opposite Red Fort in Delhi. Such activities include reverence or worship of the Lord who is nonattached, study of and reflection on scriptures, being imbued with non-attachment and rendering service to disinterested and detached preceptors and practice of rules of moral and spiritual self-discipline that awakens the power of self-reliance. Kindness to living beings (jiva daya) is of three kinds: the virtuous (punya) activity, which is the cause of the influx and consequent bondage of auspicious (shubha) karma. It involves getting rid of unkindness of the nature of evil or inauspiciousness and represents less intensity or mildness of passions like anger, pride, greed, etc. It is a factor in inhibition (samvara) and dissociation (nirjara) of karmas. It also implies kindness to living beings of the nature of virtuous activities that is also imbued with the “pure” or purifying intrinsic nature and nishchaya dharma (self-referential righteousness). Moreover, it is of the nature of other-referential righteousness and piety (vyavahara dharma), which is the supportive factor or auxiliary cause of the jiva daya of the nature of nishchaya dharma. All these three kinds of jiva daya have their own existence and significance. Compassion and Non-violence Compassion or kindness (daya) is considered the positive psychic aspect of non-violence, which is said to be the basis of all other rules of moral conduct (PSU 42). Since non-violence is said to be the root or the foundation (mula) of dharma (righteousness and piety) (Uttaradhyayana vritti 1-11), daya, being the positive psychic aspect of non-violence, is also said to be mula (foundation, basis or root) of dharma (Dharmaratna Prakarana) because all other practices or observances (anushthana) follow from that. Page #131 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 105 From the description of kindness (daya) in Bhagavati Sutra, it is quite evident that it is considered synonymous to non-violence. There are various forms of compassion (anukampa) which are not a condition or cause of any harm, sorrow, weeping, etc. or fear, to all living beings (Bhagavati Sutra 6-7). The definition and nature of non-violence is also similar. Moreover, kindness (daya), self-restraint (samyam), sense of decency or modesty (lajja), absence of disgust or censure (jugupsa), lack of insincerity or deceit (kapatheenata), endurance or forbearance (titiksha), non-violence and modesty (hri) – all these are said to be synonymous (Uttaradhyayana Niryukti Chapter 3). In Jainism, non-violence has two aspects: not to cause harm, injury or violence and that of friendliness or amity (maitri), compassion or kindness (karuna) and service (seva). The first one is primarily that of abstinence (nirurtti) whereas the second is primarily disposed towards active life (pravrtti). Both aspects are interdependent and, therefore, non-violence is contained in both of them. While infatuation (moha) is worth renouncing (heya), compassion, kindness, mercy (daya), charity (dana), service (vaiyyavrttya) are all noble qualities, which represent good and auspicious psychic dispositions (shubha bhava). They are an excellent or commendable attachment (prashasta raga) and a meritorious activity (punya) that needs to be cultivated. One is asked to contemplate, meditate and practice friendliness towards all living beings, appreciation of other's good qualities, compassion or kindness for the afflicted and equanimity towards those who are ill-behaved. (TS 7.11) In a frenzy of anger, etc. passions, one is almost possessed by instinctive impulses and sub-conscious motivations, as a result of which one is no longer one's own master. By the practice of compassion, one starts rising above the muddy world of desires, greed and anger, etc. passions, and is able to transform his energies in the direction of sanity, righteousness and piety. Moreover, Samantabhadra states that Lord Mahavira's teaching lays emphasis on compassion, self-restraint, renunciation and meditation (daya-dama-tyaga-sainadhi) (Samantabhadra, Yuktyanushashan, Verse 6), which are the four components of karma-yoga. In his commentary thereon, the commentator Vidyananda points out that compassion or non-violence is the auxiliary cause of self-restraint; self-restraint is the cause of renunciation (limitation or giving up of attachment to worldly Page #132 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 106 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES possessions), and renunciation leads to meditation (dhyan aur samadhi).90 Compassion (daya) is rightly said to be the basis of both dharma (righteousness or piety) and ahimsa, which is the negative aspect of compassion. Non-violence is described not only as param dharma (supreme duty), but also param Brahma" - the supreme divine principle or the supreme law for living beings. In Svayambhu Stotra, Shri Shanti Jina is described as the embodiment of compassion and kindness – dayamurti. (Samantabhadra, Svayambhu Stotra, verse 76) The non-attached (veetragt) form (mudra) of Shri Ara Jina reflects vidyadama-daya-param, i.e. being totally engrossed in the pursuit of knowledge, control of senses, and being full of compassion or kindness reflecting dosha-vinigraham, (Svayambhu Stotra, verse 94), i.e. absence of all evils like attachment, lust. In Pravachanasara itself (PS 251), the householders (laymen) as well as saints who are followers of Jina (conquerors of internal enemies) are enjoined to render detached or disinterested (nirvekkha in Pk., nirpeksha in Sk.) aid or help (uvayaar in Pk. upakarg in Sk.) through compassion to others without any consideration or expectation of any kind, even though that might lead to a small stain. In worshipping the Worthy Lord, the devotee might incur, out of attachment, indulgence or omission, slight impiety or sin (savadyalesho). However, that is of not of much significance in comparison to the vast amount of punya (virtue) (bahu punya rashuu) that one earns thereby, since a small quantity of poison does not affect or pollute an ocean full of cool and exhilarating water. (Samantabhadra, Svayambhu Stotra, Verse 58). Similarly, compassion or kindness might lead to a small stain, but that is quite insignificant in comparison to great benefits which accrue particularly to the self in the form of self-restraint or peace of mind, renunciation and contemplation, meditation, etc. The word “nirpeksha” is crucial. It signifies that help to others should be rendered without any interest, desire, expectation or any extraneous consideration of name, fame, etc. (khyati, puja, labha vanchha rahitam, as Jayasena states in PS 251 commentary). Not only householders but also sadhus and shramanas of good psychic disposition are enjoined to render service and help (PS 249-254) with humility and respect (PS 250) to those suffering from disease, hunger, thirst or exhaustion with all their power (PS 252). The only condition is Page #133 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 107 that in rendering service and help one should not hurt living beings (PS 249-250). Commenting on it, Amrtachandra observes that the minds of the followers of Jina are purified by unalloyed kindness. Owing to anekant, their activity is directed towards pure knowledge and intuition of the self. Such people are not forbidden to undertake such an activity characterized by rendering of aid to others (paropakara). If, as a result of compassion, such persons acquire a small stain, it does not matter because the objective is the attainment of the pure self (PS 251 AC). Such activity, Jayasena remarks, is the cause of a small stain but results in a great deal of punya (savadyalesho bahu punyarashi) (PS 251 JS). Rendering help to a person suffering from disease, hunger, thirst or exhaustion occupies a prominent place among the duties of a saint who is enjoined to render such assistance and service with all his power or to the best of his capability (PS 252). This assistance should be nirpekhsa (PS 251), i.e. without any interest, desire (ichchha), expectation, mental clinging (murchcha), sense of mineness (mamatva) and superiority or pride (ahamkara). Even with such activity or conduct of excellent attachment (prashasta raga), the shramans (saints) and householders attain the highest or the supreme (param) happiness (sokkham in Pk., saukhyam in Sk.) of [liberation, moksha] (PS 254). Moha (infatuation) has three roles (bhumika) of false perception in regard to things, including the nature of the self (darshan moha type of delusion) and attachment (raga) and aversion (dvesha), which are conduct-deluding or charitra-moha. The means to destroy them are discussed in Pravachanasara 83-89. The subjects of compassion or kindness (anukampa or karuna), vaiyavrttya or upakaar (rendering service and help to others), service (vaiyyavrttya) are described in Pravachanasara 249-254. Cruelty or violence (the absence of kindness) towards animals or human beings cannot be justified under any circumstances. They cannot also be considered dharma in the sense of the inherent nature of the self (vastu svabhavo dharma)and the ten moral virtues (das dharma) of righteousness or piety. (dharma) of forgiveness, etc. Amrtachandra's Comment on Compassion In view of what has been stated above, it is paradoxical that an eminent scholar like Amrtachandra maintains that the feeling of Page #134 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 108 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES kindness or compassion towards animals and human beings is the second characteristic of infatuation (moha) (PS 85 AC). A number of scholars in Hindi have followed Amrtachandra in their translation of Pravachanasara 85. A few others, especially Acharya Jnanasagar, have stated that the word "karunabhavo" in Pravachanasara 85 should be understood in the sense of an attitude of cruelty (nirdayata) or absence of kindness towards animals and human beings as the characteristic of infatuation (moha), [not in the sense that compassion is the characteristic of moha], along with two other characteristics of moha, viz. deluded view and indulgence in sense objects, resulting in attachment and aversion. To say that a feeling of kindness or pity (daya) is the characteristic of moha, Acharya Jnanasagar adds, signifies that such a compassionate or kind person is a deluded person (mohi, mithyadrashti), i.e. having false perception regarding things, including the real nature of the self, terrible sinner and bahiratma, i.e. exterior self engrossed in sensual pleasures, slave of his desires and attached to external objects and relations. The interpretation or meaning that compassion is the characteristic of moha, he points out, goes against all Jain scriptures. Compassion and goodness is respected in all religions. This error on part of Amrtachandra, he feels, could be the result of negligence (pramad) or it could be the mistake of some other person. the To accuse an eminent acharya of the stature of Amrtachandra of negligence (pramad) does not seem to be proper. It is also inappropriate to conclude that it could be the mistake of some other person because the version of Amrtachandra's commentary of the verse (PS 85) that the sense or thought of kindness or mercy (karunya buddhya) towards sub-human and human beings is (one of the) characteristics of infatuation (moha) is found in several copies of Pravachanasara. Then what could be the reason of Amrtachandra statement? Circumstances in which Compassion could be Deluding Evidently, a moral principle or rule of conduct, including kindness or pity, cannot be universally or absolutely followed blindly by all people in all circumstances and in all times and places, towards all people. In Pravachanasara 257 Kundakunda himself categorically states: "Service, assistance or gift [charity, kindness], etc. activities, bestowed on persons who do not know the transcendental (paramartha) nature Page #135 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 109 of reality and in whom indulgence in sense objects and passions (kashaya) predominate, result (in a rebirth) among low level of gods (devas) or men" (PS 257). be In his work, Purusharthasiddhyupaya, Amrtachandra has pointed to a number of instances in which the thought of kindness may quite tempting but could indeed be deluding and counterproductive since it may really be misplaced and lead to the perpetration of violence or killing which is not justified and can in fact be avoided. For instance, one can argue that killing of one (say tiger, lion, etc.), who kills a number of animals, is justified since it would lead to the protection of many others (PSU 83), that it would be an act of mercy or kindness towards other animals (Amrtachandra, a great votary of non-violence, does not favour that killing). This plausible argument is often raised by sportsmen. They defend hunting on the ground that by doing so they protect humanity from the ravages of ferocious animals. But in reality, apart from the excitement of s sport, the feelings that actuate them in killing a lion may be the expectation of reward. praise or being called bold men. Again, Amrtachandra states: "These kill many lives, and accumulate grave sin." On this basis, it is sometimes said that killing such beings would be an act of mercy towards them. This kind of argument is also misleading. Even those who injure others should not be killed for that reason (PSU 84), since it is also a fallacious argument. Then again, "Those in great suffering will on being killed soon obtain relief from their agony". (PSU 85) This is called mercy-killing (not only of animals, dog, horse, etc. but also human beings) or euthanasia or doctor-assisted death (in which life support is withdrawn from the patient permanently disabled or suffering from incurable disease). This is legalized in one of the states (Ohio) of USA and one of the countries (Netherlands) in the world. In Egypt, some people considered it a pious religious duty to stab their old parents to death, in the belief that by doing so, they relieved them of miseries and infirmities of old age. It is a misconception and indeed a delusion to call such practices an act of mercy. In a number of cases of such mercy-killing of the distressed one, which Amrtachandra does not approve (PSU 85), people, including relatives, may be guided more by ulterior motives of saving money for their own use rather than spending it in the hospitalization and Page #136 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 110 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES treatment of the patient and avoiding the botheration of visiting the patient in the hospital or taking care of the person at home. The practice of so-called mercy-killing is quite different from the Jaina concept of sallekhana, santhara or samadhi-marana. The latter is a bold and noble attempt to face death willingly or voluntarily in a peaceful, natural, noble way. This is done by the person concerned, who undertakes or engages in it, of his own free will through emaciation of one's passions (anger, pride, greed, etc.). Such a person puts aside all enmity, attachment, acquisitiveness, thereby attaining peace of mind and equanimity. He either undertakes a fast or subsists only on liquid food like milk, buttermilk, fruit juice or only warm water. In some cases, this could even result in curing the disease and averting imminent death. In such cases, one should not forcibly and unnecessarily invite death. (For detailed discussion in this matter see Jagdish Prasad Jain, Fundamentals of Jainism, New Delhi: Radiant Publishers, 2005, pp. 215-219). Amrtachandra has also drawn our attention to several other instances where kindness or mercy could be misplaced or deluding. Thus, the belief that “The happy shall, if killed in state of happiness, will continue to be happy (in their next life)” (PSÚ 86). “A disciple desirous of piety... cutting off the head of his own preceptor when he, by means of constant practice, has attained such perfection of concentration, as leads to a good condition of life” (PSU 87); or a person killing himself by zealously giving one's own flesh as food to another starving person, seen approaching in front” (PSU 89). (Selfsacrifice, literally speaking, was at one time considered an act of religious piety, but it is undoubtedly himsa and attempt at suicide is a criminal offence.) After citing the above examples, Amrtachandra observes: “Which person is there who, having an enlightened and pure intellect, having served teachers, well-versed in the various points of view, and having realized the essence of Jaina philosophy, would yield to any kind of] delusions and misconceptions under the guise of ahimsa" (PSU 90). Thus, in practicing compassion or kindness (karuna), one must consider whether one is yielding to (any kind of) delusion and misperception, or is one's kindness accompanied with an enlightened view or is that kindness anchored on the transcendental nature of the self, i.e. the innate nature of soul devoid of delusion and attachment. Page #137 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 111 This is similar to the observance of vows like non-violence and the practice of austerities, etc., which are considered childish in the absence of an enlightened view of things, or when they are devoid of transcendental nature of the self (paramartha bahira in Pk. and paramartha bahya in Sk.) (SS 152-153). Similarly, it has to be considered whether all the good, virtuous (punya) or auspicious (shubha) activities, such as kindness, non-violence, etc. we are performing or engaged in, are the cause of transmigratory existence (SS 153) or leading us gradually to liberation (PS 254 AC). Viewed from the above perspective, it may be said that since Kundakunda was not only a philosopher but also a teacher, he used many key terms that are polysemous and thus capable of more than one meaning (this built-in ambiguity need not necessarily be a defect, but rather an asset). He may have employed the term "karunabhavo" in Pravachanasara 85 to mean that, depending on the context or the circumstances of the case, kindness (karuna) can be considered in both the senses (of samasa and sandhi). In other words, in certain circumstances, the feeling of kindness may be misplaced and considered as a characteristic of infatuation (moha). In other circumstances, the absence of kindness towards sub-human and human beings can be said to be the characteristic of infatuation (moha). Another significant consideration in this regard is whether the person involved or concerned in the act of kindness/absence of kindness (i.e. use of violence or non-violence) is an ordinary layman (say householder) or an ascetic or a spiritual person of a higher stage of moral and spiritual development. When Gandhiji once asked Shrimad Rajchandra, whether we were justified in killing a lion attacking a cow or us?, he replied how can he agree to what leads one to go to hell and result in transmigratory existence? To Gandhi's further remark that the feeling of protecting oneself is a shubha bhava (good psychic disposition), Shrimad Rajchandra stated that any cruel or violent thought and act of killing, even for the sake of protection, is not possible without the thought of affliction (sanklesh), which results in the bondage of sin. A person of the stature of Shrimad Rajchandra, who was much advanced in spiritual discipline, or an ascetic, who had renounced all things, is enjoined, to observe perfect and unqualified conduct (sakal charitra) (RKS 50), may not entertain any violent thought even in self Page #138 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 112 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES defence. On the other hand, a householder, who is still entangled in the world is enjoined to abstain from the deliberate or intentional violence (e.g. such as hunting, offering animal sacrifices, killing for food, amusement or decoration, etc.), which can be avoided by every thinking person without any difficulty and harm to himself. However, he cannot avoid some sort of violence or injury to living beings, that are inevitable in the performance of necessary household activities, such as preparation of food, construction of house, etc. and protection of himself, family members and property against robbers, assailants, etc. Gandhi, a great votary and proponent of non-violence, was fully committed to the principle that violence should be avoided no matter what, since he was quite confident “about the capacity of human nature for degradation or exaltation” (Collected Works of Mahatma Gandhi) (CWMG) (87: 180). In his Nobel Peace Prize acceptance speech, US President Barack Hussein Obama declared to the world that although he has not seen anything weak, passive and naive in the creed and live (life) of Gandhi, he expressed the view that a non-violent movement could not have halted Hitler's armies and that sometimes, the use of force might be necessary and morally justified. In this regard, the following observation is quite relevant. Although Gandhi insisted that German Jews could have followed a non-violent resistance with a high price to invoke the consciousness of ordinary Germans', he thinks even a violent struggle is justifiable in this special case. He states: The German persecution of the Jews seems to have no parallel in history. The tyrants of old never went so mad as Hitler seems to have gone. And he is doing it with religious zeal. For he is propounding a new religion of exclusive and militant nationalism in the name of which any inhumanity becomes an act of humanity to be rewarded here and hereafter. The crime of an obviously mad but intrepid youth is being visited upon his whole race with unbelievable ferocity. If there ever could be a justifiable war in the name of and for humanity, a war against Germany, to prevent the wanton persecution of a whole race, would be completely justified. But I do not believe in any war. A discussion of the pros and cons of such a war is therefore outside my horizon or province. But if there can be no war against Germany, even for such a crime as is being committed against the Jews, surely there can be no alliance with Germany. How can there be alliance between a nation which claims to stand for justice and democracy Page #139 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 113 and one which is the declared enemy of both? Complete Works of Mahatma Gandhi, 74: 239-40). Jayasena's Commentary on Compassion Jayasena was apparently uneasy or concerned about Amrtachandra's commentary (of PS 85), which did not seem quite right to him. The feeling of kindness, he felt, was being contradictory to the self-restraint of supreme indifference (param-upeksha samyamvipreet), which is the characteristic of achievement of pure soul [i.e. from the internal, selfreferential point of view (nishchaya naya)], is the characteristic of moha, while from the external, other-referential point of view (vyavahara naya), the absence of kindness is the characteristic of moha (PS 85 JS). In other words, Jayasena was saying that from nishchaya naya or shuddha nishchaya naya, compassion or kindness (karunabhavo) is the characteristic of infatuation (moha), while from vyavahara naya, the absence of compassion (karunaya abhava) is an attribute of infatuation. In this way, he apparently felt that he was resolving the problem but he did not succeed in his attempt. He, in fact, complicated the issue thereby, in as much as it amounted to saying that one can justify anything, even wrong assertion or act by making use of one or the other viewpoint with or without the context and that nishchaya naya is opposed to vyavahara naya, which are only apparently contradictory, but are not opposite to each other. In their introductory remarks to Pravachanasara 189 both Amrtachandra and Jayasena state that there is non-opposition (avirodha) between nishchaya naya and vyavahara naya, which are complimentary to one another, and not antonyms. The problem is further complicated by the fact that in case kindness is considered a characteristic of infatuation (moha), whether it should be regarded as characteristic of perception or view-deluding infatuation (darshan-moha) or of conduct-deluding (charitra-moha). Since feeling of kindness implies certain degree of commendable attachment (prashasta raga), in which external condition of disease, hunger, etc. of other being acts as an auxiliary factor (nimitta), it should properly belong to conduct-deluding type of infatuation. Prashasta raga, as already discussed, is part of good or auspicious disposition or righteousness (dharma), which has purifying effect and helps in the attainment of liberation and hence cannot be considered adharma. Page #140 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 114 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Moreover, only from the perspective of vyavahara naya, but not from the transcendental perspective (paramartha) that the attributes of affective, cognitive and volition or conduct (darshan, jnana and charitra) can be predicated to consciousness, i.e. the conscious self, which is in reality the indivisible unity of these attributes (SS 7 and SS 7 AC), which cannot be separated from one another. Similarly, in spite of the distinction between the three roles of infatuation (moha), viz. moha, raga and dvesh, i.e. the two divisions of perception-deluding and conduct-deluding, they are, in fact an integrated whole and an indivisible unity; they are differentiated from or spoken of as distinct oniy from external, other-referential vyavahara naya, not from the transcendental perspective of paramartha. Distorted Views of Kanjipanthi on Compassion Proceeding from their perverted logic and one-sided thinking, similar to their views on punya and shubha, the Kanjipanthi, including Kanji Svami himself, have several misperceptions in regard to compassion: 1. That animals and people are miserable only due to their deluded view (mithyatva) regarding the nature of the self is wrong because people experience suffering due to the coming into operation, rise, or fruition of painful (asata) vedaniya (feeling producing) karman, i.e. sinful deeds. This can be rectified by the fruition of pleasure-causing (sata) category of vedaniya karman (TS 6.12), i.e. meritorious activities (punya) or good psychic dispositions (shubha bhava). 2. To argue that the cause of kindness (karuna) is always with reference to the other being is incorrect because the other person/ living being merely acts as an auxiliary factor (nimitta), not the direct cause the feeling of compassion is the inherent nature of jiva (self)). 3. That kindness is prashasta raga (commendable attachment) which only causes karmic bondage and has no role or contribution in the attainment of liberation, has already been refuted in the above discussion on shubha or punya. Karuna, like punya, has a dual role: it results in a small stain, yet it is a means, even if indirect, leading gradually to liberation (PS 254 AC). 4. The argument that kindness is the result of either feeling of attachment or sense of mineness (mamatva) towards other living being or the thought of killing or protecting the other, imbued with a sense Page #141 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 115 of pride/superiority is flawed. It ignores the advice mentioned in Pravachanasara that we are enjoined to render aid to others disinterestedly without any apeksha (nirpeksha), i.e. interest, expectation or feeling of superiority, pride, etc. of any kind (PS 251). It is not in our hands to kill or save another. We can only be a nimitta (an auxiliary factor) in alleviating the suffering of others. Kanji Svami errenously does not assign any role for nimitta. 5. That the other substance or living being is only knowable (ineya), worth only observing and knowing and that one should desist from doing anything in regard to alleviating his suffering as any deed (karma) would only result in the karmic bondage. This perception is the result of the distorted concept of akartratva or akarta (non-doer) of the Kanjipanthi. In fact, this is quite contrary to Kundakunda's description of the self as being karta (doer) and bhokta (experiencer of one's deeds) (PKS 27). The self is also said to be the architect of his own destiny (prabhu) and as such responsible for one's well-being (PKS 27). Kundakunda never denied the utility and significance of being a responsible person, taking charge of one's life, and being an agent of action (karta) concerned about one's own well-being (physical, mental, and spiritual) (sva-kartratva). He only said yoy are not responsible and cannot act for the other. In other words, he denied being an agent of action of the other person (para-kartratva). One cannot spend one's life being merely a spectator and let things drift or happen. . . and things do happen. People often speak of and cite Kundakunda's emphasis on being both knower (inata) and observer (drashta). They also cite J. Krishnamurti's “choiceless awareness”, or being a witness (sakshi bhava). They tend to forget that these statements or prescriptions are made in the context of avoiding indulgence in attachment, aversion and anger, etc. passions or evil psychic dispositions, and not in the sense of being an inactive and lazy person. The Kanjipanthi acknowledge that intelligent persons (jnani) can also have feelings of compassion or kindness, that kindness can never be (kadapi) the characteristic of conduct-deluding and view-deluding karma, and that cruelty (absence of kindness or mercy) is the characteristic of view-deluding (mithyatva). However, they make contradictory statements and continue to persist in their distorted and one-sided thinking. They make selective and out of context use of Page #142 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 116 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES some words/sentences in Jain texts or commentaries of Amrtachandra or Jayasena, thereby corrupting Kundakunda's noble concepts, and propagating views which go against all Jain scriptures. Concept of Svayambhu (Self-Sufficient) The concept of Svayamohu (PS 16) signifies that the self, possessed of conscious attentiveness, is capable of accomplishing virtually anything by itself (svayameva). This includes the destruction of karmas and even attaining the highest state of paramatman (supreme soul), independent of any other factor, i.e. without the help or assistance of any other object or substance (PS 192). That the self itself realizes itself by itself, through its own instrumentality and for itself is best described by Amrtachandra in the form of six components of action called six cases (karakas) (see PS 16 AC). 92 This concept is a sure prescription for self-reliance/self-restraint and self-discipline as described in Niyamsara. This finds expression in “appa so paramappa” (Paramatma Prakash 312) or “appa divvena jaladı” as Jains say. It is also reflected in the Gita, which speaks of atmanam atmaneva uddhareta, i.e. elevate yourself by your own self as well as the Buddhist teaching appa divo bhava, i.e. be your own light or guide. Concept of Omniscience (sarvajnata) Pravachanasara 16 states that the self, when purified in psychicattention through the annihilation of four destructive karmans (ghatia karman) which results in the removal of obstacles, becomes omniscient (sarvajna) by itself and is called self-sufficient, or self-become (svayambhu), i.e. one who realizes his full potentiality by his own efforts. The reason why the soul is capable of knowing all the objects of the whole universe is explained in these words: “The soul is coextensive with knowledge, knowledge is said to be co-extensive with the knowable (i.e. the objects of knowledge); the knowable comprises the physical and non-physical universe, therefore, knowledge is omnipresent.” (PS 23) Moreover, it is stated: “The great Jina is omnipresent (see PS 23), and all the objects (arthas) in the world are within his grasp or belongs to him. The Jina is embodiment of knowledge; and the objects which are said to be within his grasp belong to him because they are objectsof-his-knowledge (vishaya).” (PS 26). Moreover, “The holy Omniscient Page #143 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 117 Lord or the absolute Knower does not seize (accept) or release and does not evolve into anything else; but without exception he sees and knows everything all around” (PS 32). While the Kanjipanthi have misused the concept of omniscience in support of their mistaken concept of non-doing/non-doership principle and determinism of sequence bound modifications (kramabaddha paryaya), etc., 93 Kundakunda categorically states: “From the external, other-referential (vyavahara) point of view, the omniscient Lord intuits and knows all [physical and non-physical objects, the self and other substances) (sarvajna); from the internal, self-referential (nishchaya) point of view, the omniscient necessarily intuits and knows his own self (atmajna).” (NS 159) This signifies that while the omniscient can have direct intuitive awareness, experience or knowledge of his own self, one cannot possibly have that direct experience or intuitive awareness in regard to other objects. His knowledge of all other objects in the universe is, therefore, considered by Kundakunda as a social or religious necessity from the vyavahara viewpoint. “With Kundakunda,” A.N. Upadhye remarks, “sarvajnata (omniscience) is a dogma, a religious heritage and an essential part of the doctrine he represents,”-th the circumstances when different schools of thought have been struggling hard “to prove and establish the omniscience of their respective prophets, for on that depended the very life and death of their systems: it was the omniscience that could give infallibility to their prophets and therefore automatically to their scriptures that constituted the utterances of these prophets.” Sarvajnata (omniscience), Upadhye adds, thus, “came to be accepted and discussed only as a religious necessity.”94 The Exposition of Knowledge Speaking of the unique contribution” of Jainism, particularly Kundakunda in the field of epistemology and its “outstanding solution of the relation between the soul and its knowledge,” Hari Mohan Bhattacharya observes: Jnana or knowledge is to (Jaina) in relation of identity, the essence of the soul. Kundakundacharya, who is perhaps the oldest of the Jaina epistemologists ani stands as a link between the canonical and later classical ways of thinking. remarks in his Pravachanasara (PS 35): jo janadi so Page #144 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 118 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES nanam, he whose knowledge is to be of real significance must be regarded as identical in essence with the soul, which in knowing only modifies itself into knowledge; there is no separation possible of any kind between the knower and its knowledge, the soul which is parinami cannot be regarded as something different from its parinama. Knowledge as parinama is the soul knowing." Relation between the Soul and Knowledge The above statement refutes the view of both the Naiyyayika and the Mimamsaka who have taken the separatist view of the relation between the soul and its knowledge. To the Naiyyayika, the soul is a static reality to which knowledge comes and goes according to the presence or absence of the collection of the conditions (karanasamagri) of knowledge. The Naiyyayika goes to the extent of presuming that since knowledge is the source of karma and therefore of all sin, it should be eliminated to attain moksha. The Mimansaka fare no better in explaining the relation of knowledge to thie soul since they describe it as an avastha or state that comes and goes just like the curved state (kundalavastha) or the straight state (arjavavastha) in the body of a snake in its intrinsic character. Jains also feel that the Advaitist errs since the Advaita theory regards the soul as only the antahkarana vrittis (the psychosis of the internal organ as the determinant of the consciousness is knowledge] which do not have the intrinsic character of illumination of its object for the antahkarana, though an internal sense is no better than the outer sense which is jada or unilluminating in reality. The Advaitist tries to save himself from this difficulty by his supposition of the soul as sakshi or transcendental witness to all intellectual activities. Nevertheless, as a witness the soul cannot lend its illumining character to knowledge of objects. Even the Advaitist concept of anatmamatmopacarat, by stressing the principle of adhyasa (viz. the empirical application of the transcendental power of avidva which rules the realm of empirical knowledge), does not resolve the problem of illumination. The argument that anatamatva of the antahkarana is transformed into anything of the atman by mere magic of adhyasa and as such the antahkarana jada by nature fails to account for the illumination or knowledge of objects. Page #145 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 119 We also notice the same inaccuracy in explaining knowledge owing to failure of the Advaitist to see that knowledge is always by the soul and occurs in the soul if it occurs anywhere as its own modification and knowledge shares in the illumining character of the soul of which it is a modification. Jains also criticize Buddhists in general for denying that mind as a reality ought to enter into the relation with knowledge. The Jaina insists that both the soul and knowledge are closely interrelated, that knowledge is both self-revealing and also revealing its object as a parinama or evolution of the self-luminous soul. Thereby, the Jaina avoids the difficulties encountered by other Indian systems of thought. Thus, the Jaina insists that a proper relation is imperative between the soul and its knowledge. Misplaced Criticisms of Kundakunda by I.C. Shastri There are other critics like Indra Chandra Shastri, who is wellversed in Shvetambara Canons, but have only a superficial understanding of the select verses (PS 23-26 and PS 28-32) of Kundakunda's Pravachanasara (and Amrtachandra's commentary thereon). Shastri is hardly aware of his other works like Samayasara, Niyamsara, etc., and does not holistically comprehend his ethicospiritual standpoints of nishchaya, vyavahara and transcendental aspects. Yet he finds fault with Kundakunda's views in the matter. Such criticism is quite misplaced and reflects his strong prejudice and bias against both the author of Pravachanasara and his commentator Amrtachandra Referring to Kundakunda’s example of a sapphire-gem placed in milk (PS 30), Shastri states: “The knowledge operates on [is related to), objects, just as the sapphire (gem), thrown (placed) in the milk, pervades the whole of it with its lustre (splendour).” The same translation is quoted by Shastri himself (pp. 151-152 of his book], but he goes on to observe: “Kundakunda cites the example of sapphire placed in milk. The sapphire makes the milk appear green without pervading the entire area."9 Thus, although Kundakunda specifically mentions “indraneel ratna" (sapphire-gem), which makes the milk appear “blue," not green as Shastri states. Moreover, Kundakunda uses the word “abhibhuya,” which means dominating, overwhelming or allpervasive. One wonders if the sapphire-gem does not pervade the Page #146 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 120 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES whole of it, then how can it make the whole milk appear blue? The main purpose of this example is to prove that consciousness (samvedana), which, because it is not separated from the self, constantly receives its inherent character in its function of agent or instrument. In other words, in its character of knowledge, consciousness pervades all the knowable appearances (as effects) of all the objects (as causes). Thus, when one metaphorically remarks that by reason of their relation of cause and effect, that "knowledge, dominating or pervading the objects, abides (in them)," there is no contradiction (PS 30 AC, see also PS 35 AC). In the earlier two verses, Kundakunda states in clear terms: The Knower possesses knowledge as his innate nature; the objects, surely, possess the character of knowables with regard to the knower, like shapes or forms with reference to the eye. But they do not abide in each other (PS 28). The Knower, neither entering nor shunning to enter the knowables, verily, in consequence of his surpassing the sense-organs, knows and sees the whole world, as the eye knows and sees the shapes or forms, i.e. the objects of sight (PS 29). Explaining these verses in detail, Amrtachandra observes: The Knower and the objects, owing to their separateness (prthakatva), which forms their individual-nature (sva-lakshan), do not possess occurrence within each other; but they merely possess a mutually related occurrence, effected by the relation between their innate natures as knowledge and knowable. For instance, as the eyes and the things having shapes or forms, which are their objects are respectively ready to receive and to occasion the appearances of the knowables, even without mutual penetration, so the self and the objects are ready to receive and to occasion the appearances of all knowables, without being identical with one another (PS 28 AC). Just as the eyes, not entering, i.e. not taking hold of shapes or forms of the substances with its own spacio-infinitesimal-constituents (pradeshas), nor shunning to enter them, i.e. really appropriating their distinguishable appearances, knows and sees, likewise the soul - of which, since it surpasses the sense-organs, we need not doubt at all that it acts independently of approach - not entering, i.e. not taking hold, with its own pradeshas, of all the things which function as knowables, nor shunning to enter them, i.e. as it were uprooting and then devouring all the knowable appearances which abide in the things, with the aid of the manifoldness of its efficacy, Page #147 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 121 knows and sees. So that, as concerns the knower, who develops an activity (yoga) of manifold efficacy, his entrance into the things, attains just as much reality as his non-entrance (PS 29 AC). Amrtachandra explains the apparently contrary statements regarding Pravachanasara verses 26 and 27 with the help of Jaina doctrine of anekant (multifacetedness or many-sided view of the reality of things). He states that from the internal, self-referential (nishchaya) perspective, the worthy Lord, "knows without moving himself towards all the appearances of the knowables, since he never leaves his own reality svatattva." From an external, other-referential (vyavahara) aspect, the worthy Lord is said to have omniscient knowledge since all the objects in the world are within his grasp (PS 26-27 AC). In Niyamsara, Kundakunda categorically states: "From vyavahara point of view, the worthy Lord knows and intuits all (objects), i.e. he is omniscient; from nishchaya point of view, he necessarily knows and intuits his own self" (NS 159). Unable to properly understand the Jaina doctrine of anekant and the ethico-spiritual viewpoints of Kundakunda, I.C. Shastri mistakenly accuses Kundakunda of causing "confusion". He blames Amrtachandra for taking "the position of Sautantrika, in holding that "knowledge takes the form of object" (pp. 177 and 175 of Jaina Epistemology), when he (Amrtachandra) unambiguously states that "all substances abide in their own characteristic nature" (PS 26 AC) and that "all the knowable appearances... abide in the things" and that the soul, “with the manifoldness of its efficacy, knows and sees" (PS 29 AC). Knowledge, Amrtachandra adds, evolves onto all the distinguishable appearances which exist besides knowledge; and we may say that all the objects which are the causes of all the knowable appearances, which are (really) the effects of self-evolving knowledge, in a certain way reside in knowledge (PS 35 AC). Shastri's contention that both Amrtachandra and Jayasena take "different courses to explain" (p. 175 of his book) Kundakunda's views pertaining to the exposition of knowledge also has no basis since both of them state that the knowable appearances may be compared to the reflection images (when located in the mirror of consciousness) (see PS 31 AC and PS 31 JS). Jayasena uses the word "adarsha", and Amrtachandra mentions "mukura", both terms meaning mirror. Shastri Page #148 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 122 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES cites “adarsha” on p. 175 of his book. Apparently Shastri is unable to comprehend the logic of Kundakunda's statement: “The soul is co-extensive with knowledge, knowledge is said to be co-extensive with the knowable [i.e. the objects of knowledge]; the knowable comprises the physical and non-physical universe, therefore, knowledge is omnipresent.” (PS 23). As stated earlier, both Kundakunda and Amrtachandra categorically state (see PS 28 and 28 AC) that the knower inherently possesses knowledge as his innate nature whereas the objects possess the character of knowables. In other words, the two are quite separate from each other. However, Shastri erronously argues that Kundakunda's statement that “knowledge is coextensive with the objects of knowledge” is tantamount to “physical mixing.” (p. 177 of his book) He is therefore unable to acknowledge the Jaina view of “the limitedness of the soul,” which is “co-extensive with the body”. This, Shastri contends, is reconciled by Kundakunda with the Vedanta view of all-pervasiveness which Kundakunda does “under the influence of the Vedanta” (p. 177 of his book). He is, thus, unable to see the logic of Kundakunda and unable to understand the validity of the vyavahara point of view. I.C. Shastri is also unable to comprehend the rationale of the Jaina concept of the soul, in its embodied existence, which has the same dimensions as the large or small body, in which it resides. As a result, sensation (samvedana) is felt in all parts of the body. The Jaina concept of jiva or consciousness, which is equal in extent to its body, also ensures that the subjective experience of a person is his own personal experience and not of any third person. Moreover, the Jaina view that the soul is co-extensive with the body apparently anticipates contemporary somatic philosophers like Moreleau-Ponty, Gabriel Marcel and Michael Polanyi. However, there is one difference. Unlike the Jaina view that the body can only have physical qualities, the somatic philosophers contend that the body consists of emotions, which is contrary to common experience. The position of the Sankhyas is also untenable because they maintain that “unconscious prakrti carries both psychological and physical qualities” whereas the purusha (self) remains “totally isolated,” because its involvement in matter is illusory. On the authority of Shvetambara scholar Yashovijaya, Shastri argues that the Jaina concept of samudghata alone can be considered Page #149 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 123 to explicitly support the view that the soul is all-pervasive insofar as its power is concerned." In the Nyayakhanda Khadyatika, karika 70 (pages 648-649), Yashovijaya confirms that the soul can pervade the entire universe and is therefore all-pervasive. However, as far as its activities are concerned it is confined to the body. Digambara scholars have also dealt with the subject of the samudghata, which is altogether different from Kundakunda's description of all-pervasiveness or omnipresence of knowledge. Samudghata is "the emanation of the soul-particles or space points from the body, without discarding it wholly and for good". The whole soul does not leave the body. It is, in fact, only "a sort of overflow for some particular reason and the soul returns to the body to be reabsorbed by it" Seven kinds or varieties of samudghata are recognized in Jaina philosophy. Again, Shastri cites the definition of jiva as given in Digambara text Dravya Sangraha (DS 2) by stating that it is characterized by upayoga, etc., without mentioning chetana (consciousness), which can equally be cited as the definition of jiva. He mistakenly observes: "Kundakunda also agrees with the same" (in this regard he refers to PKS 27) (p. 143 of his book), whereas Kundakunda specifically declares in that verse that the soul (jiva) is consciousness (chetana), having a particular characteristic of upayoga, viz. manifestation or function of consciousness in the two cognitive forms or modes of knowledge and perception. (PKS 27). I.C. Shastri also does not seem to give importance to Kundakunda's deep insight distinguishing the soul (jiva), soul substance (jiva dravya) or the essential principle of jiva (jiva tattva), viz. consciousness-as-such from the embodied souls of different classes of living beings (jiva nikaya), possessing bio-energies (pranas) (PS 182) and consisting of two distinct substances, jiva and matter (pudgal), though having unity or oneness (aikibhuta) in consequence of mutual penetration yet distinct in their innate nature (svabhava bhedatparatvena, PS 240 AC), or even when united as one (aikya) like milk and water in one body yet not one due to the distinctness in nature (bhinna svabhavat), PKS 34 AC) and thus having separateness from the body. As a result, the two substances have their own distinct characteristics (jiva or soul possessing its subjective attributes of cognition, feeling and volition, while material body, an inanimate entity Page #150 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 124 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES possessing its own characteristic sense qualities of touch, taste, smell and colour). Jaina Concept of the Soul and its Relation to Knowledge Knowledge, according to Kundakunda, constitutes the inalienable attribute or quality of soul or consciousness (chetana). He states: "He who knows is knowledge (jo janadi so nanam); but the self does not by the help of its knowledge becomes something-that-is-knowing (jnayaka)”; knowledge evolves by itself, and all the objects reside in knowledge (PS 35). Knowledge is the evolution (parinama) of the soul knowing though the evolution cannot be separated from the evolving self. The forced supposition (klesh kalpana) of a separation of knower and knowledge is superfluous (PS 35 AC). In this context, H.M. Bhattacharya observes: A conscious reality is never divorced from its own conscious modifications and qualities in which lies its very life... A parinama (state-of-evolution] or modification issuing from the parinami (the evolving being) or the modifying, and yet not in essential relation with the parinami, is as false an abstraction as the aparinami (unchanging) or immutable real without any parinama or modification. This conception of the self or soul as a dynamic or evolving eternal reality (parinami nitya) something persisting or enduring through its modes cannot be differentiated from knowledge. This view of the self and its relation to knowledge is quite different from the Samkhya “conception of the self as a static and unmodifying (aparinami) eternal principle which does not enter into the constitution of knowledge, but which merely looks on it from a distance as it arises, as a modification of an unconscious principle (prakrti). This virtual separation between the self and knowledge (buddhi) entails an actual stultification of each of them."99 In this context, Nathmal Tatia remarks: Consciousness of the jiva manifests itself in cognitive acts, and is not like the unchanging principle of consciousness in the Samkhya-Yoga school which ascribes the cognitive acts of buddhi (intelligence) which is an evolute of the unconscious principle of prakrti... Consequently [Jainism) does not differentiate the metaphysical soul (jiva) from the epistemic subject (jnata) as is done in Samkhya-Yoga and monistic Vedanta.100 Page #151 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 125 The Jaina concept of the soul and its relation to knowledge also differs from the Mimansakas and the Vaisheshikas, who maintain that jnana or knowing capacity is not the nature of the soul. They regard it as an accidental or adventitious quality generated in the soul on account of its contact with the body, mind, and sense organs. Jnana (knowledge) is, thus, considered to be a distinct entity from the soul. It is said to be brought in association with the soul or jivatma by combination (samavaya) whereby the soul becomes the knower. In other words, the quality of consciousness (chetana) and substance of the soul (atmadravya) are two different entities occasionally or accidentally brought together by extraneous circumstances. 101 If after giving up sinful undertakings and practicing good and auspicious conduct, one does not get rid of infatuation (moha), both view-deluding as also conduct-deluding (viz. attachment and aversion), one does not find the “pure” self (PS 79). Abstention or rejection of every censurable activity of mind, speech and body and being satisfied in the practice of good psychic attention or auspicious conduct is not an end in itself, especially as the danger of submission to the army of infatuation exists or is near at hand. As a result, one obviously girds up one's loins for the victory over the army of infatuation (PS 79 AC). The means of overcoming moha is described in the next verse (PS 80). He who knows the arahanta (one who has destroyed the internal enemies of infatuation, attachment, aversion, anger, etc. passions) with reference to substance, quality and modification knows the self; his infatuation (moha) indeed perishes (PS 80). The sense or the purport (abhipraya) of the verse is that when one compares one's own self with the arahanta, he necessarily comes to know the difference. While arahanta has destroyed both view-deluding as well as conduct-deluding (viz. attachment and aversion) infatuation (moha), he is not free from those impurities of a deluded view, attachment and aversion, which are the direct cause of bondage (SS 188-189, SS 178, PKS 149; see also SS 164-165 JS). Accordingly, one feels inspired to get rid of them, just as after knowing the existence of dirt on the face by looking into a mirror, one necessarily tries to remove that dirt. Though attachment to arahanta is a factor in the bondage of auspicious (shubha) karmas, knowledge in regard to him is the cause of inhibition (samvara) and dissociation (nirjara) of karmas. Page #152 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 126 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES The Exposition of Joy The practice of [prescribed] conduct by shramanas, saints and householders in whom excellent attachment (prashasta raga) is primary is said to lead to the highest happiness (param sokkham in Pk. and param saukhyam in Sk.) (PS 254). This is equated with nirvana sukh (happiness or bliss of liberation) (PS 254 AC). In Samayasara, Kundakunda states that the conscious self, who having [carefully] read the Samaya Prabhratam or Samayasara (the treatise on the nature and essence of the soul), and understood its real meaning and purport, firmly sticks to it, will attain excellent happiness (uttam sukha) (SS 415). This is said to be of the nature of anakulata, i.e. devoid of mental agitation, anxiety, eagerness, uneasiness or distress (SS 415 AC). In Ratnakaranda Shravakachara (Verse 2), Samantabhadra defines dharma (righteousness or piety) as that which liberates living beings from the pain, misery or suffering of the worldly existence and installs in or begets them excellent happiness (uttam sukha). In order to understand the nature of uttam sukha, one has to distinguish it from sensual pleasures, which is in fact misery in the guise of happiness. This is explained in Pravachanasara in the following words: That happiness which is dependent (i.e. rests on something else); connected with detriment or amenable to disturbances (for it is utterly confused, since it is attended by different longings, such as hunger, thirst etc.); interrupted or terminable (for oppositions are noticed in different longings); cause of karmic bondage (karma means crystallized effects of past activities of energies which brings in its train the army of the vices, passion, etc. trailing along the road of sensual enjoyments); unequal (for it is utterly unsteady since it evolves through increase and decrease and is not same for different persons); and acquired by means of the senses is indeed misery in disguise (PS 76 and PS 76 AC). The lords of men, demons and gods, oppressed by their natural (sahaja) organs of senses, unable to withstand that misery, find pleasure in satisfying (ramya) objects (PS 63), which serve to soothe their disease (PS 63 AC). Misery is inherent or natural (sabbhava in Prakrit and svabhava in Sanskrit, PS 64 and PS 64 AC) in the lives of those who find satisfaction in sense-objects, i.e. in sensorial pleasure (PS 64). If this were not their natural urge, there would not be any attempt on their part for obtaining the objects of senses (PS 64). Those who seek Page #153 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 127 pleasure in the satisfaction of sense-enjoyments remain discontented because that necessarily makes them thirst and hanker after the pleasures of senses for more and more sense-objects due to their craving (tanha or trashna in Sk.). As a result, they are afflicted by misery till death (PS 74-75 and PS 74-75 AC). If happiness lies in the external objects of senses, then the pleasure we get in eating the first few pieces of a tasty sweet, say 2-3 rasgullas, then why we do not get similar pleasure in eating 5 or 10 such pieces. Another Jain text, Prashamratiprakaran of Umasvami or Umasvati (Verse 234) observes: The happiness of heaven is indirect, it is beyond our experience. Thus, we may be disinterested in it. The happiness of salvation is still more indirect. Hence, we may have doubts about it. On the other hand, the peace and calm brought about by the subsidence or quelling down the excitement of passions and the happiness resulting therefrom can be directly experienced right here. This happiness is not dependent on other objects, things or beings. It is not perishable either. The so-called pleasures of worldly life, viz. sensual pleasures, are always accompanied by pain. They are never full and unadulterated. They are preceded and followed by suffering. They are transient, passing and short-lived. What people in general consider happiness is mostly sensual pleasure which by its very nature is dependent on worldly objects pleasing to our senses. Prashamsukha, i.e. happiness derived from or resulting from calmness of mind and equanimity, is free from all these shortcomings. The Exposition of Knowlable (Jneya) The object of knowledge (jneya, i.e. knowable) is substance (dravya), which by its nature is an existent reality (sat) (PS 99, 105, PKS 10 and TS 5.29), and is subject to evolution (parinama) (PS 99). Substance is characterized by an indivisible unity of substance (dravya), attributes or qualities (guna) and modes or modifications (paryaya) (PS 93). While a substance does not forsake its innate nature, it is combined (samavedan in Pk., samavetam in Sk.) of stability or persistence (dhruva), origination, and destruction at one and the same moment (ekkammi cheva samaye in Pk., ekasmin chaiva samaye in Sk.) (PS 95, 99, 103). In another of his works Panchastikayasara (PKS), Kundakunda states that the existent reality is the characteristic of substance (dravya sat Page #154 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 128 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES lakshanam, PKS 10; also sat dravya lakshanam, TS 5.29). The existent reality, he adds, is that which is nitya (permanent) (PKS 6). Yet, at the same time, parinami or traikalika bhava parinata (PKS 6), i.e. one that undergoes modifications in all three times (past, present and future), thereby manifesting the characteristic of dravya bhava (PKS 6), dravati (PKS 9) or dravyatva, i.e. “that which by nature, flows towards its modes”. The substance is permanent (TS 5.4) and permanence (nityam) is indestructibility of the essential nature (quality) of the substance (tad bhavavyayam nityam, TS 5.31). The intrinsic nature of substance (tadbhava) is the existence of the past nature in the present. It is that existence, condition or mode, which is the cause of recognition or remembrance. In other words, a thing is seen as having the same nature with which it was seen formerly. So it is recognized in the form, “This is the same as that”. “This is that only” is recognition. 102 Thus, recognition of the object in future proves its permanence. It is noteworthy that while the intrinsic nature of a substance is permanent, it is also evolvent (parinami), i.e. undergoes modifications or changes in its modes. It is, therefore, called parinami nitya. Modification (parinama) of a substance means the continuity of the essential nature of substance and its qualities (guna) through changes (tadbhavah parinamah, TS 5.42). In other words, a substance is the combination of the contradictory characteristics/points of view (sa-pratipaksha) of dhrauvya (indestructibility, constancy or continuity) while undergoing utpad vyaya (origination and destruction), i.e. change or modifications (bhangotpaddhrauvyatmika sa-pratipaksha (PKS 8), (utpad vyaya dhrauvya sambaddham) (PS 95) or utpad vyaya dhrauvya yuktam sat (TS 5.30). Thus, a substance (i.e. existent reality) is neither absolutely changeless or permanent (sarvatha nitya) nor absolutely impermanent, transitory or changing (sarvatha kshanik) (PKS 8 AC). What appears and disappears are modes (paryaya); what persists is substance. Origination and cessation coexist with persistence/stability. There is, Kundakunda elaborates, no coming-into-existence or origination without destruction. There is no destruction devoid of origination. Thereby, he declares that there is necessary concomitance (avinabhava) between one another. By stating that origination and destruction are possible only when there is an abiding something Page #155 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 129 existing as constant or stable (dhruva) (PS 100), he seeks to resolve the argument among philosophers in regard to satkaryavada and asatkaryavada (PS 100) 103 In this manner, when the necessary concomitance (avinabhava) is proved between the triple characteristics (origination, destruction and stability), then depending on the view of non-differentiation, Acharya Kundakunda points out that at the same moment (samaya) the same substance takes the forms, modes, names or states of origination, persistence and destruction, which certainly are inseparably rolled into one. All the three are, therefore, indeed the substance (PS 102). Definition of Substance Substance (dravya) is defined as that which, while it does not “forsake its innate nature [i.e. consciousness in the case of jiva (soul substance)] [TS 5.29), is characterized by origination, annihilation and stability (TS 5.30) and which possesses or is endowed with qualities and modifications (TS 5.38], is called a substance” (PS 95 and PKS 10) (also in TS 5.29, 30 and 38). And again: “Existence is the innate nature of a substance, which is accompanied by qualities and various modifications of its own, and by origination, annihilation and stability at all times” (PS 96). Substance, he adds, is neither created nor destroyed; the coming into existence or origination and ceasing to exist or destruction take place in the modes (PKS 11, 15). Dravya (substance) is indivisible. There is an integral unity of its qualities (guna) and modifications (prayaya), which appear and disappear, originate and undergo annihilation. Kundakunda categorically affirms: “There is without substance no quality whatever and no modification” (PS 110). There is, he adds, neither mode and quality without substance nor substance without mode (paryaya) and quality (PKS 12-13). As dravya (substance), the conscious entity of jiva is endowed or characterized with dravyatva (flow of consciousness in various ways), i.e. that which by nature flows towards or evolves into its modes or modifications (paryaya). These modifications are of two kinds. Firstly, there are modifications in qualities (guna paryaya), which are simultaneous (sahabhavi or sahavarti). Secondly, there are modifications, which take place in the conditions (gati) or modes, such as hellish, human, etc. states of living beings in their empirical, Page #156 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 130 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES mundane existence, which are successive (kramabhavi or kramavarti) and extrinsic. These are called modes of substance (dravya paryaya). The affective, cognitive and volitional qualities along with their modifications in being deluded (mithya) or enlightened (samyak) are simultaneous (sahabhavi or sahavarti) with and intrinsic to the substance or internal aspect or mode of consciousness (sva samaya, SS 2). This is the nature of that (substance), i.e. thatness or the inner principle (antas tattva) of self itself (atman) (PS 94 AC). The substance, undifferentiated from the existence-of-own nature, evolves by itself from one quality into another. It is, therefore, remarked that the qualitymodifications (guna paryaya) are indeed the substance (PS 104). Apart from consciousness, jiva is also said to be endowed with upayoga (function, manifestation or attentiveness of consciousness) (PS 127, PKS 16, 27), i.e. a functional self, i.e. an evolving reality. Affective, cognitive and volitional or conative attributes are the three aspects or functions of consciousness, viz. the internal self-referential aspects or modes of consciousness (sva-samaya) (first line of Samayasara 2). These three attributes (guna) or functions of consciousness (upayoga) are subject to modifications (guna paryaya) and these can be gunantara (PS 104). In other words, they can be transformed from one quality into another, including distorted or deluded (mithya) and enlightened (samyak). If these attributes are deluded, they are the cause of transmigratory existence (samsara) of jiva. If they are enlightened, they constitute the path of liberation (moksha marg) (TS 1.1). The very term dravya (substance) signifies dravyatva, i.e. "that which flows or evolves towards its modes". Thus, the soul (jiva, consciousness) accepts the character of its state-of-evolution, good or evil, pure or impure, and possesses the nature [form, mode or state] of that through which it evolves during the time of the evolution (PS 8-9). Inseparability of Substance, Quality and Modification There is identity (avyatiriktabhava or abheda) of substance and qualities, i.e. there is neither quality without substance nor substance without quality (PKS 13). Similarly, there is the necessary concomitance (avinabhava) of origination, annihilation and stability or persistence, meaning thereby that there is necessary concomitance (avinabhava) between substance (dravya) and its modification (paryaya). In other words, there is no coming into existence or origination without destruction. There is no destruction devoid of origination. Page #157 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 131 Moreover, there is neither origination nor destruction without stability (PS 100). The inseparability of these three constituents is categorically confirmed in the following words: "In the absence of substance, there can be neither quality nor modification" (PS 110). The quality modifications are modifications of one substance, hence quality modifications are indeed substance only (eva) (PS 104 AC). Kanji Svami himself admits at one place that in Pravachanasara "even vikar (agitated, altered or impure states of the mind) are said to be dharma (characteristics or traits) of atma (soul) because it is also the paryaya (mode or modification) of the soul."104 Moreover, a substance is the substratum of both attributes/qualities and modes (dravyam guna paryayashrayam, PKS 10, and TS 5.38). However, while qualities reside permanently in substance, modifications of substance (dravya paryaya) as well as qualities (quality modifications or guna paryaya) appear and disappear. As such, any particular modifications, including distortion or deviation (vibhava) of affective, cognitive, etc. (darshanadi) qualities of self, are transitory, impermanent or "occasional", 105 In view of the clear-cut statements cited above, the modification (paryaya) is (ananya, PS 114), i.e. not separate or different from the substance/entity, which is the substratum (ashrya, PS 93 AC) of that modification. The modification(s) exist within the substance. There is a necessary concomitance (avinabhava) of origination, annihilation and persistence or stability. Indeed, they depend on modification, which are parts (ansha). These modifications, in turn, depend on, rest upon or are sustained by substance. Hence, all these are only substance which is the union, combination or aggregate (samudaya) of all these (PS 101 AC). The necessary concomitance (avinabhava) or inseparability of the three constituents of a substance is described in Pravachanasara 100-103. The substance undergoes modifications by itself, including evolution from one quality into another (gunantara), i.e. quality-modification or modification of quality (guna paryaya). However, the essential nature/characteristic of a substance (e.g. consciousness-as-such or sentiency (chetana)) persists (sat avasthitam, PS 99 or sat vishishtam (PS 104). In other words, jiva (the self or soul) substance, invariably subsists or remains as the background or forms the substratum of all Page #158 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 132 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES its changes or modifications. These include inauspicious, auspicious, or pure states of consciousness or the manifestations, or modes of cognition, feeling and volition, which are inalienable attributes of conscious entity. And this is what constitutes the stability (dhrauvya) constituent of a substance, something stable, persisting or enduring through its modes or in the midst of its changes, modifications or evolutions and makes the existent reality (substance), including jiva, a dynamic, evolvent, permanent reality (parinami nitya), in Jainism, not an unchanging, unevolving, unmodifying entity as is the case in Samkhya system of philosophy and Advaita Vedanta. The substance, quality and modification are said to be inseparable (aprathak). There is no differentiation of place or location. They occupy the same locale (avibhakta pradesh). Nevertheless, there is distinctnessor otherness (anyatva) because there is non-identity (a-tadbhava) among them (PS 106). Logical Distinction between Substance, Quality and Modification To fully comprehend reality, it is evident that there is a logical and conceptual distinction between substance, quality and modification. However, they must necessarily be taken together as they are inseparably rolled into one. Any separation (prthakatva) between them would suggest a cleavage between the evolutes and the evolvent reality, which will reduce each one of them into non-existent entity.106 The qualities and modifications are both distinct (bhinna) as well as not distinct (abhinna) from the substance. “Metaphysically, they are non-distinct or having identity/unity with the dravya (substance), but logically they are distinct from it." Without this logical distinction, there is no other way of apprehending the substance as substance, qualities as such, and paryaya (modification) per se.107 In other words, substance and attributes are inseparable. However, the substance is not the same as its attributes and the attributes are not similar to substance. The difference between the two is only a difference of reference, not one of existence, even though it is a fact that it is the substance that manifests its nature through its attributes. A substance without attributes and attributes dissociated from the underlying substance would all be meaningless abstractions. Attributes therefore can neither exist without the substance nor can the substance be divorced from the attributes. Hence, in the world of reality, there Page #159 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 133 can be no separate existence either of substance or attributes from each other. 108 Likewise, there is “no substance that is devoid of modification, nor there is any modification without an abiding something, a substance” The trinity which comprise a substance are origin, decay and continuance.109 Misperceptions of Kanjipanthi concerning Substance and Mode This section highlights several misperceptions of Kanjipanthi regarding substance and mode in the light of our previous discussion. Firstly, Kanji Svami's assertion that paryaya (modifications) and dravya (substance) are distint existent realities or two separate ontological entities. (bhinna sattayen)" is mistaken. It is, in fact, a gross deviation from Kundakunda's teachings and all other Jain texts, including the Tattvartha Sutra. In making such an argumert, the motive of Kanji Svami is apparently two-fold. On the one hand, he seems to want to pave the way for the self being declared aparinami (without modification). Secondly, he aims to emphasize that psychic dispositions (ragadi bhava) like attachment are not vibhava (distorted, deluded psychic dispositions of self), but para bhava, i.e. psychic states pertaining to or concerning other substance or entity and as such it is not the responsibility of self to make efforts to purify the impurities of attachment, etc. Accordingly, the self or soul is said to be aparinami (changeless). It is said to be “separate from its modification (paryaya)” from nishchaya naya. Kanji Svami, thus, declares that “the absence or negation of paryaya in the substance, in which there is no paryaya."111 Kanji Svami further declares: “I am changeless (aparinami) in all three times (trikali) even in the present time.”l12 The second misperception of Kanji Svami is that he asserts: "It is not that I have the capacity or the potentiality of becoming perfect supreme soul (purna paramatma), but that I am perfect supreme soul (purna paramatma) at present - think as that."113 “My soul (atma),” he goes on to state “is eternally pure consciousness and bliss (nitya shuddha chit-ananda).” This implies that the self, which is said to be already paramatma or “pure consciousness”, need not make efforts or adopt moral and spiritual means (sadhan) to purify the soul, thereby making it perfect. Such deviations, innovations or misperceptions, harboured by Kanjipanthi (a group of Digambara Jains, which are followers of Kanji Page #160 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 134 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Svami, a Shvetambara saint, who joined the Digambara sect) are gross distortions of Kundakunda's teachings and Jain scriptures (agam) as such. The Kanjipanthi opine that dhruva (constancy) signifies aparinami chaitanya tattva, i.e. changeless consciousness."'4 In reality, however, dhruva actually signifies that which exists, subsists or persists as a constant factor in all three times (trikali). This constant factor in jiva (self) is consciousness-as-such (jivatva or parinamika bhava, i.e. atma or soul), which is evolvent (parinami) and the substratum of its attributes of cognition, feeling and volition as also all psychic states, changes or modifications, pure or impure. Substance (dravya), according to Kundakunda, is characterized by permanence or continuity and change. The dhruva (constant, eternal) element in substance comprises its “svabhava, i.e. own nature” (in the case of jiva, its jivatva, i.e. consciousness-as-such), which it never leaves (aparityakta). The evolving or change aspect is concerned with the modifications (paryaya or parinama) of substance and its qualities or attributes (PS 95-96). The soul, which is parinami, H.M. Bhattacharya points out, cannot be regarded as something different from its parinama (evolution, change or modification)."15 Apart from the conscious self, the static self without its conscious modification and mere modifications are both equally meaningless abstractions. 116 The soul in its essence (chaitanya) is a conscious entity/substance, which undergoes modifications (parinama). The self, according to Jainism, is a dynamic reality, something stable in the midst of its changes, a unity in diversity, a being in becoming."!!7 Bhattacharya further observes: A conscious reality is never divorced from its own conscious modifications and qualities in which lies its very life. . .. A parinama or modification, issuing from the parinami or the modifying, and yet not in essential relation with the parinami, is as false an abstraction as the aparinami or immutable real without any parinama or modification. 18 If there is no permanence, B.K. Matilal points out, there cannot be any change/fluctuation, for it is only the permanent that can change. It is only the persisting soul that can transmigrate"? from animal into a human, etc. form, condition (gati) or mode (paryaya). Jainism, including Kundakunda, upholds that substance, including soul (consciousness) substance, the essence of jiva (self), is an existent reality, which is eternal (nitya) in the sense of existing, in all three Page #161 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 135 times (past, present and future) (trikali dhruva). At the same time, it is a dynamic evolvent (parinami or parinamansheel) reality. Contrary to this, the Kanjipanthi, believing in changeless consciousness (aparinami chaitanya tattva),120 assert that “I am changeless or unchanging (aparinami) in all three times (trikali) even in the present time."121 This contention is similar to that of the Samkhya and Vedanta. Although the indivisible unity, inseparability and necessary concomitance of substance, quality and modification has been categorically declared by Kundakunda, Amrtachandra and others, Kanji Svami asserts that paryaya (modification) and dravya (substance) are two separate existent realities or two separate different ontological entities (bhinna sattayen). 122 This is a gross deviation from Kundakunda's teachings and all other Jain texts. The Mechanism of Eondage Substances essentially consist of jiva (self or soul) and pudgala (matter). The essential characteristic of jiva (living being) is sentiency or consciousness (chetana). Its manifestation or function is called upayoga (PS 127 and PKS 16, 27). The self is indeed the agent or doer of its own states (sagassa bhavassu in Pk. svakasya bhavasya in Sk.) (PS 184). Matter, on the other hand, is a non-sentient, corporeal and inanimate entity possessing characteristic sense qualities/attributes of touch, taste, smell and colour. The two substances are the agents (karta) of their own conditions, states, or modes (modifications). In his worldly, empirical existence, the living being is necessarily associated with karmic particles or the material karman. While experiencing the rise (udaya) or coming into operation of the karmic particles, a person who identifies oneself and evolves into a deluded view (moha), attachment and aversion, experiences karmic bondage (PS 43 and PS 43 AC). These three, viz. attachment, aversion and a deluded view, are the cause of karmic bondage (PS 42 and 43 JS). Karmodaya is not the Direct Cause of Karmic Bondage Karmic bondage does neither emanate from the conscious/the knowing nature of a living being nor from the coming into operation of the karmas devoid of attachment, etc. After becoming operational, the karmic particles (i.e. the genes, neurons or brain cells, the RNA, DNA, etc.) of different varieties (knowledge-obscuring, particular Page #162 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 136 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES emotion producing, etc.), result in good or bad (shubha or ashubha) effects. They also disappear [i.e. the karmas fall off or the shedding of those particular karmic particles takes place] and do not cause [fresh] karmic bondage if the self does not evolve into the psychic states of attachment, etc. Deluded view, attachment, and aversion [are jivasya svakasya bhavah, i.e. the self's own conscious states]. In Samayasara, attachment, aversion and deluded view are declared to be the self's own inalienable states-of-evolution (SS 371). Together they constitute [mohaniya karman], which are the [real or direct] cause (karana) of the [fresh] karmic bondage, not karmodaya (the karma-udaya, the rise or the coming into operation of the karmas) (PS 43 JS and SS 164165 JS). In Pravachanasara 45, it is stated that the activities of the self, arising from the operation of the karmas are considered audayiki alone (eva), i.e. the coming into operation of the karmas. In the absence of being affected, infected or coloured (uparanjaka) by the deluded view, attachment and aversion, they do not cause distortions or perversions (vikar) in consciousness (chaitanya). They remain audayiki, i.e. always of an audayiki nature. Hence, they are considered to be destructive (kshayiki) of the karmas, in as much as the coming into operation of the karmas is not the cause of karmic bondage, i.e. having the effect of producing [fresh] bondage of karman (PS 45, PS 45 AC). Jayasena also asserts that karma-udaya devoid of attachment, etc. is not the cause of karmic bondage. Being devoid of a deluded view, etc., it is unable to produce the sense of mineness (mamakara in other objects) and pride (ahankara). The audayiki bhavas (psychic effects or states resulting from the coming into operation of karmas) become the cause of karmic bondage only when they are accompanied by deluded view, attachment, etc. If karma-udaya alone is considered to be the cause of karmic bondage, then due to the karma-udaya, which is omnipresent in worldly persons, they will always continue to cause (fresh) bondage. Consequently, they will not be able to attain moksha (liberation) (PS 45 JS). Owing to its inherent nature (svabhava), if the self does not evolve into an impure mode or state [on the auxiliary condition of the previously bound karmas coming into operation], there is no fresh bondage of karmas. As a result, there will be no transmigration of the cycle of births and deaths (i.e. samsara) for the living beings (PS 46). Page #163 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 137 IS) In its unmixed, non-relational (karma-nirpeksha) parinamika bhava (i.e. in the sense of SS 6 AC) the self is not liable to lose its nature of consciousness and does not get transformed into a material, inanimate object. It also does not evolve into impure states. When all these conditions/causes of karmic bondage (the coming into operation of the previously bound karmas and the presence of attachment, aversion and deluded view), are absent, living beings, by their very nature, will become eternally liberated souls (nitya-muktam). At that stage, there will be absence of samsara. The self evolves into auspicious (shubha) and inauspicious (ashubha) nature (svabhava) because of its own evolving nature and because karmas come into operation. This is similar to a crystal, which by its own nature, evolves or assumes the colours of red and black because of the condition or the association of red japa flower and black tamal flower (PS 46 AC). Thus, attachment, etc. are the cause of karmic bondage (PS 46 JS). In Pravachanasara 173, the question is posed as to how the self (atman), the conscious entity having quite opposite qualities to those possessed by corporeal (murta) material substance – bind material karman? The answer to this question is given in the subsequent verses. Through its likes and dislikes and its perception and knowledge of the objects of senses (PS 174, 176), the self possesses an innate nature of psychic-attention (upayoga), which is conditioned, affected, tinged or stained (uparakta) (PS 175 AC) by deluded view, attachment or aversion. The physical karma or material karman (i.e. neurophysiological processes), acts as the condition or auxiliary cause thereof (nimitta, PS 174 AC). It also affects, influences or conditions subjective psychic bondage (bhava bandha) (PS 174-175 AC), which is an evolution into attachment, etc. (Amrtachandra's introductory remark to PS 179). In its external association/interaction with both desirable (ishta) and undesirable (anishta) sense objects irrespective of the psychic states, the soul perceives or knows them. However, the soul gets stained by attachment and aversion because of its own likes and dislikes. This inevitably leads to karmic bondage (PS 176 JS). Kundakunda categorically states that (only) a attached person binds [fresh] karman (ratto bandhadi kammam). A person, he adds, who is devoid of attachment is liberated from karmas. This is a brief summary Page #164 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 138 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES of the discussion about the bondage of souls (PS 179). Psychic bondage, in turn, acts as the supportive factor/the auxiliary cause that affects, influences or conditions binding of material karman (bhava bandha pratyaya dravyabandha) (PS 176 AC and PS 179 AC). The two types of bondage (the psychic and physical or material bondage) are, thus, mutually related as cause and effect, each of the other, and interact with one another. Each one of them acts as indirect, extrinsic, supportive factor or auxiliary cause (nimitta karana) of the other (PS 177-179, AC). Though material karman is said to be the indirect, extrinsic, auxiliary cause of psychic dispositions or mental states, the self is indeed the (substantive) causal agent or doer of its own bhavas (conscious states) (PS 184). Although the soul exists at all times in the midst of matter, it does not accept, grasp or appropriate karman. It also does not abandon or release the material karman. Hence, it is not the substantive cause of the evolution or modification of material karman (PS 185 and PS 185 AC). Nishchaya and Vyavahara Points of View When tainted with deluded view, attachment and aversion, the self is also sullied by the dust of karma. In the Jaina scriptures, this is described as bondage (PS 188). This is briefly the genesis summary of the bondage of souls as preached by the worthy Lord (Arahantas) from an internal self-referential point of view (nishchaya naya). However, from an external other-referential standpoint (vyavahara naya), it is expressed differently (PS 189). Commenting on Pravachanasara 189, Amrtachandra states that the self is the agent (karta) of its own evolution into psychic dispositions like attachment. According to internal, self-referential nishchaya naya, the self is also the appropriator as well as the renouncer thereof (PS 189 AC). Thus, the perspective of nishchaya naya is considered to be the most effective means of accomplishing (the task) (sadhaktam) of purity because the self not only acts as the agent of attachment, etc. but also as a renouncer thereof (i.e. the self also acts as the agent of transforming or purifying the impure mental states into pure mental states). Nishchaya naya is therefore regarded as the most effective means of attaining the objective of the purity of the self. According to external, other-referential vyavahara point of view, the non-pure state of soul substance (PS 189 AC) regards the evolution Page #165 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 139 of matter as “the self's karman”. In other words, the karmic matter belongs to the soul because of acts performed by the soul. This view also regards the self as “the agent [karta] of the evolution of matter and appropriator and renouncer thereof”. This description consists in describing the non-pure state of soul substance (PS 189 AC). In other words, from vyavahara naya, the self is viewed as the agent of material (pudgala) karma and their modifications. Both these viewpoints, Amrtachandra adds, are correct since substance is conceived in both pure and impure forms (PS 189 AC). In this manner, Kundakunda exhibits the absence of opposition (virodha) between nishchaya naya (NN) and vyavahara naya (VN) (atha nishchaya vyavahara avirodham darshayati) (Introductory remark of both Amrtachandra and Jayasena to PS 189 and SS 58-60). That nishchaya naya (NN) and vyavahara naya (VN) are the internal and external aspects of the same reality and therefore complementary and not contradictory or opposed to each other, is also emphasized in other places. Thus, “if one wants to follow the tenets and principles of Jainism, one should not give up VN or NN. Abandoning VN will amount to undermining the path of rules and guidelines (tirtha) laid down by the worthy Lord. The abandonment of NN undermines one's understanding of the tattvassit.e. the reality of the things as they are or the nature of principles of life (SS 12 AC). The Jaina concept of syadavada (method of conditional predication) is destructive of the opposition between the two nayas (ubhaya naya virodha dhvansini) (SSK 4). Padmaprabhadeva, the commentator of Niyamsara, also finds no contradiction between nishchaya and vyavahara naya (commentary on NS 187). He emphasizes that the teaching of relying only on one naya is not worth accepting; only the teaching which relies on both the standpoints is grahya (acceptable) (commentary on NS 19). Though nishchaya naya and vyavahara naya are apparently contrary perspectives (sapratipaksha) (PKS 8) to one another or may seem to be irreconcilable aspects (pratisiddha, SS 272), the doctrine of anekant reconciles the apparently contradictory viewpoints because they coexist in the same object as inalienable parts thereof. They do not negate, deny or repudiate each other. (Repudiate implies a disowning or casting off as untrue, unauthorized, or unworthy of acceptance.) To negare is to deny the existence, truth, or fact of something. Page #166 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 140 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES To contradict is to flatly deny the truth of an assertion and usually to imply the reverse is true. To deny is to reject as untrue or invalid or to refuse to concede the existence or claims of (something). Contrary can imply extreme divergence (e.g. of opinions, motives, or intentions). It can in particular be used in formal logic or diametrical opposition. In logic, contrary propositions are those in the relation of affirmative and negative within the same degree of generality. Vyavahara naya: and nishchaya naya provide an alternative/optional course or choice in given circumstances. Alternative implies a necessity to choose, usually between two apparently contradictory things. Option stresses a specifically given right or power to choose among two or more mutually exclusive items, e.g. took an option to buy a farm; the many options for careers open to present-day youth. Choice usually implies the right or privilege to choose freely from a number (e.g. of persons, things, or courses). It implies a set of things (called opportunities) that are available. It implies a criterion of selection. This, in turn, implies a wide range of choices and often the need of thought and discrimination in choosing, according to the purport (abhipraya) of the chooser/selector (nayo jnatur abhiprayo, Akalanka, Laghiyastriya 52). Contradictory applies to two things that completely negate each other so that if one is true or valid the other must be false or invalid, e.g. the two suspects made contradictory statements to the police; the real trouble with love is that people want contradictory things out of it. Opposite is an inclusive term, which may replace any of the others but finds its typical application in the description of abstract things that stand in sharp contrast or complete antagonism, e.g. opposite views on a problem; attraction and repulsion are opposite forces; a person of the opposite sex; the boys went in opposite directions. Antithetical stresses clear and unequivocal diametric opposition.' 123 Thus, nishchaya and vyavahara aspects or perspectives are not contradictory but complementary to one another. The lack of opposition between them is best expressed in the Jaina doctrine of anekant, which regards them as coexisting simultaneously as inalienable parts of an object, or relative and complementary to one another (paraspara sapeksha). This phenomenon is also explained by the Jaina Page #167 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 141 concept of arpita anarpita (TS 5.32) whereby a certain aspect/ characteristic is said to occupy a position of prominence or considered primary (mukhya) because of some use, need, relevance or purpose, while the other aspect is considered secondary (gauna) (there being no contradiction between them). This is also evident from the Amrtachandra's example of a milkmaid engaged in churning buttermilk wherein one side of the string is brought in the foreground of attention/focus, while the other aspect/side recedes into the background (PSU 225). The accomplishment of any task (including liberation), Samantabhadra observes, requires or depends on coordination of both internal and external causes (the internal cause is regarded as primary or substantive cause, while the external cause is considered as secondary, supportive, auxiliary cause or its co-adjunct] is said to be in the very nature of things (dravyagatah svabhavah), (Samantabhadra, Svayambhu Stotra, verses 59-60). Material Karman and Psychic States Panchastikayasara verse 134 explains how the empirical self (jiva) by its nature is in itself spiritual and incorporeal (amurta) appears corporeal (murta) because of material or physical karman coming into contact with the possibility of appropriate and mutual interpenetration in the transmigratory (samsaric) state. In the process, the self experiences fresh accretion of karmas and the consequent bondage (PKS 134). The beginningless material karman acts as the supportive or auxiliary factor (nimitta) in attachment, anger, etc. psychic states of jiva. These psychic states, in turn, function as the supportive or auxiliary factor (nimitta) of (knowledge-obscuring, etc.) material karmas. Thus, the two are mutually related as cause and effect, one to the other (PKS 134 AC). Without the corresponding changes in the material karmas, the four psychic states of coming into operation or rise (audayika), subsidential, destructive, or partly destructive and partly subsidential, cannot happen in the consciousness of jiva. These psychic states or dispositions (bhavas) may, therefore, be said to be the effects of physical or material karman (karmakrta) (PKS 58). They should be considered and accepted as such (anumantavyah) (PKS 58 AC). These four psychic states, Amrtachandra points out, are, in fact, Page #168 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 142 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES the states or conditions (avastha) of karma, having reference to material karman. They are not consciousness-as-such (parinamika bhava), which is beginningless, without end, natural, having no relation or reference to karmic adjuncts or encumbrances (nirupadhi). The four altered states of consciousness are produced by the coming into operation of karmas, etc. or mutations of material karman acting as the supportive factor (nimitta) or auxiliary cause. In this situation, even the physical or material karma acquire the doership or the agency of action (kartratva) of the states of consciousness from the external, otherreferential point of view (vyavahara naya) (PKS 58 AC). In reality, the self is the doer or agent of action (karta) of its own psychic states (PKS 59) from the internal, self-referential point of view (nishchaya naya) (PKS 59 AC). The material karmas are the doer (karta) of the psychic states of jiva in the capacity of supportive or the auxiliary factor (nimitta). Similarly, the psychic states are the doer (karta) in the capacity of extrinsic, supportive or the auxiliary factor (nimitta) of material karma from external, other-referential point of view (vyavahara naya). However, from an internal, self-referential point of view, jiva is the doer or causal agent of its own psychic states and material karman is the doer or causal agent of its own mutations or modifications. Moreover, neither the modifications of the psychic states of jiva nor the modifications in material karman can occur without some doer (PKS 60 and PKS 60 AC). In this case, the author makes a distinction between the substantive causal agent (upadana karta) and the extrinsic, supportive or auxiliary causal agent (nimitta karta). In the transmigratory embodied existence, the self does not renounce or abandon the consciousness-as-such parinamika bhava. However, it undergoes distorted impure modifications of its own psychic states, which lead to an adhesive quality of deluded view, attachment, aversion since it is conditioned and affected by the beginningless karmic bondage. Similarly, karmic particles mutate into karma-bhava [of knowledge-obscuring, etc. karmas, PKS 66 AC] (that have the power to condition and affect psychic states) merely by close proximity and mutual interpenetration of the distorted or perverted psychic states acting as the extrinsic, supportive or auxiliary factor (nimitta) in this regard (PKS 65 and PKS 65 AC). There is, however, no direct causal relation between jiva and matter or material karma Page #169 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 143 (PKS 66 AC). Jiva and matter are the causal agent of their own respective modes or mutations from the internal, self-referential point of view (nishchaya naya), yet from the extrinsic (or external), otherreferential point of view (vyavahara naya) they are said to be mutually related as cause and effect each of the other. Jivas and karmic matter are closely interlinked. However, when the time for their separation comes they become separate. The self (jiva) experiences both pleasure and pain, which are the result of the coming into operation or fruition of material karma (PKS 67) because jiva is of the nature of consciousness (PKS 68). The self, being the architect of his own destiny (prabhu), is an active agent (karta), responsible for his own actions, good and bad, physical and mental. It is also the enjoyer or experiencer (bhokta) of the fruits thereof, and covered by infatuation (moha) roams about endlessly in the transmigratory existence of births and deaths (PKS 69). In Tattvartha Rajvarttika (TRV), Akalanka states that the contention that the incorporeal (amurta) self (atma) cannot be subject to or be subjugated by karmic matter, which is corporeal, is an incorrect conclusion since the self (atma), which possesses the inherent trait of consciousness (chaitanya), attains or develops special capabilities or energies owing to beginningless karmic bondage. As the beginningless evolvent (parinamika) consciousñess-as-such, the self is an evolving conscious entity. Its particular modes, such as hellish, etc. conditions of the existence of the self and sensory states of knowledge, etc. also have the character of consciousness. Thus, the self, due to its beginningless association with the material (karman) body, is in some respect corporeal (murtimana). It is not absolutely or completely incorporeal (amurtika) (TRV on TS 2.7.24). Since the self is bound by karmas, it is in some respect (syat or kathanchit) corporeal. However, since it does not leave or renounce its intrinsic characteristics like knowledge, it is also partially incorporeal (amurta). Just as after drinking alcohol, a person becomes deluded or confused and loses his memory, so also as a result of the coming into operation or rise (udaya) of material karman, the intrinsic qualities of knowledge, etc. of the self get affected or conditioned. Alcohol intoxicates, deludes or confuses only the conscious entity, but not the inanimate container of alcohol or the senses, which are devoid of consciousness (TRV on TS 2.7.25-27). Page #170 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 144 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Although the self is bound by karmas since beginningless time, its independent existence is proven because of its own intrinsic characteristics like knowledge. It is said: "There is unity or union (aiyattam in Pk. and ekatva in Sk.) between the self and karmas from the point of view or with respect to karmic bondage still the two are distinct or different with respect to their own distinctive characteristics. Thus, the self cannot be said to be absolutely or merely one-sidedly (ekantah) incorporeal (amurta eva) (SAS commentary of Pujyapada on TS 2.7). Depending on the condition of the supportive factor of the self (jiva), imbued with attachment, the material particles mutate or are transformed into material karman (karmatvam). The consciousness or psychic states of jiva also mutate or are transformed into distorted states like attachment depending upon the condition or the supportive factor of the material karman (Yogasara-Prabrata of Amitgati, Verse 2.31). Thus, the distorted psychic states and the material karma act as the supportive factor (nimitta) or the auxiliary cause (nimitta karana) of one another. They are not the substantive cause (upadana karana) of one another (Ibid., 9.50 and SS 80-81). Neither does karma destroys the intrinsic attributes of the soul nor does the jiva destroy the attributes of the material karma. There is no mutual relation of the destroyed and the destroyer between the jiva and karma (Ibid., 9.49). How changes or modifications in the material objects affect the feelings (bhava) or the attitudes of persons because of their intense attachment to them is aptly described by Samantabhadra in the following words: "Persons desirous of a pot, a crown and gold become sad, happy and indifferent at the destruction (of the pot), origination (of the crown), and persistence (of gold) on account of their causes." (Samantabhadra, Apta-Mimansa, Verse 59) Though the psychological states of sadness, happiness, and indifference are generated in the self, their causes lie in the modifications that take place in the material object existing in the external world. Thus, changes in the conscious mental states and changes in material particles or the neurophysiological states or processes are determined by and linked with their own antecedent or preceding states or events. Nevertheless, each one of them acts as the indirect, extrinsic, subsidiary or auxiliary cause (nimitta karana) of the corresponding Page #171 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 145 changes in the other. The innate nature of things is the reason why only the intrinsic cause or internal factors can be regarded as the direct or substantive cause (upadana karana) of changes or modifications within their own respective entities. On the other hand, extrinsic causes or external factors can be considered only as indirect, subsidiary cause or the supportive factor (nimitta) of changes in the other. The extrinsic, indirect and auxiliary kind of causal interaction does not in any way violate the principle of classic physics that "the physical realm is causally closed in the sense that nothing non-physical can enter into it and act as a cause' >>124 and that "each physical event lay in an unbroken series of antecedent physical events". It also does not violate William James' principles of psychology that "psychological events never take place in a vacuum without some reference to the preceding events". 125 Psycho-physical Parallelism states The Jaina contention that the two events - brain states and inental while interacting with one another, remain quite distinct processes and independent series or sequences (physical and psychic) seems to suggest a kind of psycho-physical parallelism. However, this parallelism is not merely "a temporal correspondence of the two series, but transcended and reconciled by the Jaina concept of nimitta karana" 126 (each one acting as an extrinsic, indirect, auxiliary, supportive or subsidiary factor or cause of the other). Jaina parallelism is, thus, quite distinct from other parallelist theories based on “divine intervention" (Malebranche) and mysterious "pre-established harmony" (Leibniz), which speak only of co-occurrences and never of interaction or causal relationship between the mental and physical realms. 127 The Jaina view differs not only from other systems of Indian philosophy but also from the disjunctive substance dualism of Descartes, property dualisms of David Chalmers and Thomas Nagel, John Searle's "causal reduction," and Max Velmans so-called "complementarity," which is based on deterministic physical laws or processes." 128 - In this way, the Jaina concepts of jiva, the evolving nature of reality, the dual (physical and psychic) aspects of mind, and nimitta karana (the conscious states and brain activities acting as extrinsic, indirect, auxiliary cause or supportive factor of each other) provides "the correct approach to the mind-body problem". This is the goal Page #172 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 146 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES which Thomas Nagel has been seeking, viz. that it should preserve the mental-physical distinction, which must be “essentially biological, not functional or computational”, and “necessarily both subjectively mental from the inside and objectively physical from the outside - just as we are”. 129 Internal and External Aspects The strand of duality of internal and external, psychic and physical or subjective and objective aspects of the self runs throughout the Jaina system, including Jaina psychology and spiritualism. For instance, the jiva is both incorporeal and corporeal and has both internal and external pranas. Similarly, the senses, mind, karma, etc. have both physical as well as psychic aspects in the living organism. It is in the very nature of things (dravyagatah svabhavah) that the accomplishment of any task or deed requires or depends on coordination of both internal and external causes (the intrinsic cause is regarded as primary and substantive cause, while the extrinsic cause is considered as secondary, supportive factor or auxiliary cause). 150 In Pravachanasara, it is stated that it is only when the self evolves into attachment (desire) is it bound by fresh (new) material karma. However, when it is free from attachment, the self is not bound since it is released (muchyate) by any fresh (new) material karma as well as by the old accumulated material karma (PS 179). Thus, psychic disposition of attachment is the most effective (cause) of material bondage. This is a decisive (nishchayatah) summary of the bondage of living beings, i.e. bondage from an internal, self-referential point of view (nishchaya naya) (nishchayena bandha) (PS 179 and PS 179 AC). Subsequently, it is stated that when the self is tainted by a deluded view, desire or attachment and aversion it is sullied by karma dust, which is described as bondage (PS 188). In his introductory remark to the next verse (PS 189, and SS 5860), Anirtachandra states that Kundakunda elaborates on the absence of opposition, conflict or contradiction between nishchaya naya and external other-referential point of view (vyavahara naya) (atha nishchaya uyavahara avirodha darshayatı) as follows: “This is the summary account of the bondage of souls, preached by worthy Lord (Arhats) from nishchaya naya, from vyavaharu naya it is expressed otherwise” (PS 189 AC). In other words, from the nishchaya point of view, the self Page #173 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 147 (jiva) is the karta of a deluded view (moha), attachment, aversion and passions, etc. psychic bondage (bhava bandha). On the other hand, from the vyavahara point of view, the self is said to be the karta of dravya (material or pudgala) karmic bondage (PS 188-189). In this context, Amrtachandra states that since the self is the causal agent (karta) of its own states-of-evolution of psychic dispositions like attachment, he is both the appropriator and the renouncer thereof from the perspective of nishchaya naya (PS AC 189). He, thus, emphasizes the internal aspects of the purity of the self. In other words, the self is the agent of impure mental states as well as the agent of transforming or purifying such impure mental states into pure psychic dispositions, because it is attachment that binds karma (PS 179 and SS 150). In this way, nishchaya naya is said to describe or emphasize the internal self-referential purity aspect. However, vyavahara naya (PS 189 AC) stresses that "the evolution of matter is the self's karman”. In other words, the karmic matter belongs to the soul or are deeds done by the soul, and that “the self is the agent (karta] of the evolution of matter and appropriator and renouncer thereof”. The preceding sentences describe the impure state of the empirical self. In other words, from vyavahara naya, the self is viewed as the agent of material (pudgala) karma and their modifications. Amrtachandra further observes that “both these viewpoints are correct, since substance is conceived in both forms, as pure and as impure”. However, in this case nishchaya naya is considered to be the most conclusive (sadhaktam) because by emphasizing the internal purity aspect of the thing, the internal self-referencial viewpoint of nishchaya naya is regarded as the most effective way of achieving the objective of purifying the self (PS 189 AC). In all his works, Kundakunda lays greater emphasis on or assigns higher priority or importance to internal aspects, though external aspects are not lost sight of. The intrinsic cause (svanimitta), Amrtachandra points out, is considered the primary factor in the transformation of a person, while the other external factors act as subsidiary or auxiliary cause (para nimitta), which must also be present.131 In Pravachanasara also, Amrtachandra states that of the two kinds of negligence in self-restraint, viz. external and internal (PS 211-212 AC), the internal one is the more serious one (baliyan), and Page #174 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 148 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES not the external (PS 217 AC). The importance accorded to the inner aspects or psychic dispositions is reflected in Kundakunda's views regarding the mechanism of bondage. It is also evident from the description of conduct of living beings, including the practice of nonviolence, etc. which is the subject matter of Book III of Pravachanasara. The internal aspects are obviously more important than the external aspects since it is the sole responsibility of the jiva (self), who alone, being the agent of its own psychic states of attachment, aversion, passions, etc., can get rid of them. Since these perverted, impure psychic states and passions are the cause of (karmic) bondage, the only way of annihilating physical or material karman (neuro-physiological processes) is to either abstain or get rid of them. They cannot be removed by any surgical procedure. Moreover, it is generally recognized that the mind or mental states alone are the cause of both bondage as well as liberation (mana eva manushyanam karanam bandha mokshayoh) of men. W.J. Johnson's failure to comprehend this leads him to mistakenly criticize both Kundakunda and Amrtachandra for stressing the “internalized or dematerialized cause of karmic bondage”, thereby making it [primarily] a matter of infatuation and passions, and also criticizing them for "internalization of himsa” (violence). 132 The Concept of Non-violence (ahimsa) in Pravachanasara There are a number of verses in Pravachanasara dealing with the concept of non-violence. Amongst these, the most important ones are verses 216-219. Pravachanasara 205 speaks of being devoid of violence, etc. But what constitutes himsa? Is it the "harm unto living beings," i.e. avoidance of external violence, such as destruction of the material vitalities of others? Or is violence primarily the result of internal negligence (pramad), i.e. passion-infected psychic disposition, or both. In the Shvetambara "canonical texts”, particularly Bhagavati, Thanang and the Uttarajjhayana, Johnson states that the emphasis is on the physical and material”133 aspects of violence, i.e. “harm unto living beings”. On the other hand, Kundakunda and Amrtachandra as well as Tattvartha Sutra of Umasvami or Umasvati, along with Pujyapada's commentary of Sarvarthasiddhi give greater importance to internal negligence or passions, i.e. injuring the psychic dispositions of his Page #175 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 149 own self through passion-infected thoughts and emotions. Thus, we have two translations of Pravachanasara 216. The translation by A.N. Upadhye states: “Careless activities of a monk [shraman) when sleeping, sitting, standing, and walking are always known as continuous harm unto living beings."134 The words “unto living beings” do not exist in the original Prakrit verse. The other translation of Pravachanasara 216, based on Kundakunda's views in the matter and Amrtachandra's commentary thereon, is reflected in Faddegon's translation: “Heedless action in lying, sitting, standing, going, etc. is considered to be at all times continual hurt (himsa) to the shramana-state” (PS 216). Negligence is an impure mode or manifestation of consciousness. As such, it is violative of the innate nature of jiva or the real identity of the self. This point is explained and clarified in verse 217 as follows: “A living being may die or live, on the part of the careless one the act of hurting is certain: by the mere fact of hurt he who is careful in his observances incurs no bondage.” (PS 217). Commenting on this verse, Amrtachandra remarks: Impure psychic-attention is internal negligence; the taking of another's life is external. Whether the taking of another being's life occurs or does not occur, to the actual impure psychic-attention, proved by the careless conduct, which does not occur without it, the nature of hurting certainly belongs: and to the non-existence of impure psychic-attention, proved by the careful conduct, which occurs without it, the nature of hurting certainly does not belong, as is shown by the fact that the taking of another's life does not involve bondage: therefore internal negligence is the more serious, and not the external (PS 217 AC). The additional verse (PS 217/3) in Jayasena's recension adds: “Even so, the external should be recognized, simply as being an occasion for the internal negligence.” (PS 217/3) Greater Emphasis on Psychic Dispositions A shraman of careless conduct is deemed to be the cause of taking the life of beings (and consequently incurs bondage). However, if one always behaves with care, then, like a lotus in water, one remains unassoiled or uncontaminated (PS 218). This means that if, in spite of the dispassionate activities of mind, body and speech, any living being is injured, it cannot be called himsa (violence), since the Page #176 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 150 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES corrupting element of passion is missing (Amrtachandra in PSU 45). In Samayasara, Kundakunda categorically states: “Whether one kills or not kills living beings, the bondage is caused by the psychicdisposition or thought/impulse (of killing or violence) (adhyavasana); this is the epitome of the bondage of souls from the internal, selfreferential point of view” (nishchaya naya) (SS 262). In Jai Dhavala (41, page 93), it is stated: “Whatever action is performed by a person imbued with attachment, aversion or deluded-view leads to violence and hence he is considered a violent person. In other words, attachment etc. thought activities or psychic dispositions alone is the cause that instigates or promotes violence.” When the jiva causes harm to the pranas of the self and other living beings (jivayoh) owing to infatuation and hatred (aversion), it definitely leads to bondage of karman, such as knowledge-obscuring, etc. (PS 149). The material vitalities (dravya pranas) of “the other” (para-jiva) are sometimes hurt and sometimes not hurt. By being passionate, the soul always causes injury (himsa) to the subjective pranas or psychic vitalities of the self. It therefore binds itself with knowledge-obscuring, etc. material karman. Thus, injury to the psychic vitalities, i.e. bhava himsa, of the self through passions becomes the cause of material karman (paudagalik karman) (PS 149 AC). The internal negligence or passions of anger, hatred, etc. (pramad), which cause violence to the self and later result in violence or injury to others, is undoubtedly more serious (PS 217 AC) and not the external, physical violence (dravya himsa). In any case, injury to other living beings should be avoided for purifying one's own thought activities (parinama vishuddhi) (PSU 49 AC). Since the jiva (i.e. prani, one having or possessing pranas, i.e. bioenergies or material, physical vitalities) and the vitalities (pranas) are bound together in the organism and closely united (aiyatta in Pk., and ekatva in Sk.), they cannot be completely distinguished or considered distinct (vibhakt). Therefore, it is inevitable that the jiva will experience pain (dukkha) when these bio-energies separate. Thus, it is evident that the destruction of the bio-energies, or vitalities of living beings (prani) is the obvious cause of pain. Such violence (himsa) is certainly considered adharma (absence of righteousness or piety) (TSV commentary on TS 7.13, Vol. 6, p. 566). In Jainism, himsa (violence) is of two kinds, viz. psychic violence Page #177 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 151 and physical violence. The destruction of psychic vitalities (pranas) is ine:itable in one's passionate activity or careless conduct (TSV on TS 7.13, Vol. 6, p 570). Amrtachandra considers all sins like falsehood to be "external forms of violence" of the purity of psychic states of the soul (PSU 42). Moreover, since these sins are destructive of the inherent nature of the self (atma-svabhava), they are tantamount to violence. Generally speaking, non-violence is defined as the transformation of one's conduct characterized by self-restraint whereby no physical or mental harm is caused to others. First of all, non-violence makes us conscious of the existence of other. It takes into account the convenience and inconvenience of all and declares the right of all to remain alive. It is reflected as nonviolence in conduct, syadavada (method of conditional predication) in speech or expression, and anekant (multifacetedness of reality) in thought. This is the philosophy of life of Lord Mahavira. The non-appearance of thoughts or feelings of attachment, passions, etc. is undoubtedly non-violence (ahimsa) whereas their appearance is himsa (violence). In brief, this is the essence of non-violence in Jain texts (PSU 44). Amrtachandra adds: "He, who, not knowing the true nature of things, relies solely or one-sidedly on the internal aspects of negligence alone (eva), is an ignorant person (balah); he is careless and lazy in external conduct and destroys all external, moral discipline related to others" (PSU 50). In other words, moral accountability is directly conditioned by subjectivity. The avoidance of external violence is considered desirable and advisable as a means for maintaining the purity of the thought activities or mind by an agent. In comparison to psychic dispositions or thought activity undertaken knowingly or with the use of intellect (the discriminating faculty), sometimes those undertaken unknowingly, without the use of intellect, leads to bondage of greater sin. Therefore, ignorance or lack of discriminative insight or knowledge (ajnana) is considered a special (type) of fault or sin and counted as one of the [five] kinds of delusion (TSV commentary on TS 7.13, Vol. 6, p 570). Tattvartha Sutra on Non-violence The internal aspects of violence are discussed and emphasized by not only Kundakunda and his commentator Amrtachandra, but also Page #178 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 152 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES by Umasvati in the Tattvartha Sutra, Pujyapada's Sarvarthasiddhi commentary thereon as well as in certain Shvetambara texts and scholars. In Tattvartha Sutra (TS 7.13), himsa is defined as pramattayogat pranvyaparopanam himsa, i.e. the destruction of bioenergies, life-principles, or vitalities (prana) due to negligence or passion is himsa. Muni Vidyananda defines violence as the passionate state together with the separation/ ending of bio-energies (pranas) of the self (sva) or other (para). In other words, violence occurs when a passionate activity of body, speech or mind causes harm, injury, or separation of one's own or someone else's psychic or physical pranas (TSV commentary on TS 7.13, Vol. 6, p. 564). The contention that himsa does not merely hurts vitalities of living beings but that injury even results owing to the mental condition of passions and negligence is said to be a revision of the concept of violence as enumerated in Shvetambara canonical texts such as Bhagavati, and Thanang, which lay emphasis on merely physical aspects of violence. The Tattvartha Sutra, Johnson opines, is the earliest extant Jaina work in Sanskrit written between 150 C.E. and 350 C.E. He affirms: "It is not only the one text that both Digambaras and Svetambaras recognize as authoritative," but the commentaries on it, whether by Digambara or Svetambara authors, "present almost identical explications of Jaina doctrine". In any case, the differences between the Svetambara and Digambara doctrine are not relevant for our discussion, which focuses on the problems which are fundamental to both traditions. Johnson admits that he himself has used the Sarvarthasiddhi of Pujyapada (Devanandin) (c. fifth century C.E.) in conjunction with the Tattvartha Sutra "rather than the alleged auto commentary, the Tattvarthadhigama Bhasya (also known as the Svopajna Bhasya)" since there is considerable doubt whether Umasvati himself wrote the "auto commentary". Bronkhorst has presented a convincing case for attributing it to a Svetambara of the fourth century C.E. (at the earliest) whereas Zydenbos dates it to the fifth century A.D. The Sarvarthasiddhi, Johnson adds, might be using a version of the Tattvartha Sutra which is "at times closer to the original than that used in the Bhasya". There is also some evidence that the Tattvartha Sutra itself was composed in "a Digambara milieu, while the Bhasya Page #179 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 153 has marked Svetambara features she cites Bronkhurst and R. Williams in that regard). .. The Sarvarthasiddhi ... often develops the logical implications of doctrines which are merely stated or formulated in the Tattvartha Sutra”. 135 In stating that merely a "passionate attitude even without the severance of vitalities constitutes violence,"136 Sarvarthasiddhi stresses the internal-psychic disposition of the agent, i.e. the passion and its effect on the agent (himsa to oneself). 137 This is sva-himsa, which occurs first and the severance of vitalities of other beings happens thereafter. A passionate person first hurts one's own self by himself, the severance of other's vitalities happens afterwards or may not happen at all (TSV on TS 7.13, Vol 6, p 570). Pujyapada further observes: He who acts with negligence commits injury whether death is caused to organisms or not. And he who proceeds with proper care does not contract bondage of karma by mere injury. [this seems to be the reproduction of PS 217 as it is exactly similar to it)...He who has passions causes injury to himself by himself. Whether injury is then caused to other living beings or not, it is immaterial. 138 In his Sarvarthasiddhi commentary on Tattvartha Sutra (TS 7.1 and TS 6.12), Pujyapada remarks that self-restraint (samyam) implies restraining oneself from evil, undesirable, inauspicious (ashubha) activities of injury, etc. It also signifies the observance of vows like non-violence, truthfulness, which is regarded as morality, virtuous activities (punya), righteousness and piety (dharma). One of the ways to inhibit (samvara) karmic inflow is through five of the ten moral virtues (dharma) (TS 9.6), which are only positive aspects of nonviolence, etc. five moral rules (vows) of conduct (TS 9.2, 9.3). Dual Role of Moral Virtues Pravachanasara states that non-violence is the necessary concomitant of purification (vishuddhi) (PS 155 AC and 180 AC) partly because it signifies abstention from evil and vicious (papa) activities. The five moral virtues are said to have a paradoxical dual nature in that they are instrumental in the inhibition of the influx of karma when practiced with detachment and no vestige of passion; they also generate karmic influx of beneficial (pleasure producing) karma when practiced with attachment (sarag samyam) as being compassionate towards living beings in general in the worldly sense. Page #180 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 154 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES It is noteworthy that Shvetambara Svopajnya Bhashya commentary on Tattvartha Sutra and Kanjipanthi speak of the vow of self-restraint (TS 7.1) as the cause of (beneficial) karmic inflow only. As a result, it leaves unanswered the question “How can a vow both inhibit and generate karmic inflow?"139 The answer to that paradox is given in the Digambara Sarvarthasiddhi commentary on Tattvartha Sutra and in Amrtachandra's commentary on Pravachanasara verses. In his introductory remark and commentary on Pravachanasara 69, Amrtachandra states that after transcending the state of evil or inauspicious (ashubha) psychic-attention PS 69 AC) good or auspicious (shubha) psychic-attention (upayoga) of the self, comprising of attachment to the veneration of the worthy Lord, ascetic and the teacher, to charity, to moral precepts or moral conduct of self-restraints (su-shila), to fasting and the like, (which is a self with good or auspicious (shubha) psychic-attention (upayoga), (PS 69), is a means (sadhan) to sensorial pleasure (PS 69 AC) rn subsequent verses (PS 70-76), it is stated that while manifold sensorial pleasures may make one apparently happy, but this happiness is tantamount to misery because it is dependent, accompanied by distraction, and interruption. It is the cause of bondage, and unequal since it is acquired by means of the senses. (PS 76)]. In Pravachanasara verses 155, 180, 245-260 and the commentary thereon, both Kundakunda and Amrtachandra state that while evil/ inauspicious (ashubha) is inherently characterized by affliction, distress or morbidity (sanklesh) (PS 155, 156 and 180 AC), shubha or punya (righteousness or piety, i.e. dharma) has a dual role. When it is a mere means of sensorial pleasure (PS 69 AC) or a supportive factor (nimitta) of enjoyment of sense objects (dhammam bhoga nimittam, SS 273275), it has the effect of karmic bondage and is unable to get rid of karmas (SS 273-275). However, when it is a commendable attachment (prashasta raga) oriented towards sanity, it has a purifying (vishuddhi) effect (PS 155 AC and PS 180 AC) that is capable of inhibiting and getting rid of karmas. This, in turn, gradually (kramatah) leads to the highest happiness of nirvana (liberation) (PS 254 and PS 254 AC), and, thus, not only leads to liberation (PS 259 and PS 259 AC) but also helps others to attain liberation (PS 260 and PS 260 AC). Commenting on non-violence, Akalanka remarks: “The entire universe - the seas, the lands and the sky - is full of living beings. Page #181 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 155 He who practices self-restraint and is careful is not liable to any violence (though physical violence may be there)."140 Even when one kills a living being, Siddhsena remarks, one is not guilty of the sin of killing if he is apramatta (i.e. careful, not infected with passion and not negligent).14) The same sentiment is found in Oghaniryukti (748, 749). In Visheshavashyakabhashya (a Shvetambara canon), Acharya Jinabhadra observes: “It is the intention that ultimately matters. " 142 Muni Nyayavijaya too remarks: “Even in the absence of actual overt act of injuring the life forces of others, an evil act of violence is committed through mere entertaining ill-will or ill-thought."143 In view of all that is stated above, one is at a loss to understand why Johnson obstinately persists in his belief that A.N. Upadhye's definition of himsa would seem to be “the most natural rendering, i.e. himsa is harm to living beings as a result of careless physical actions on the part of the monk”. Johnson feels that prima facie himsa is “a purely orthodox doctrine such as might be found in the Dasavaikalika Sutra (Shvetambara canon)".144 Sarvarthasiddhi, he adds, thereby "shifts the whole emphasis of himsa on to the internal state of the agent, i.e. on to passion and its effect on the agent: himsa. . . to oneself” 14 h Like violence (himsa), parigraha (upadhi, PS 219)—the passionate mental state of attachment to or being infatuated (murchha) (PS 221) with external, physical objects – is considered more important than mere possession of worldly objects. Upadhi, i.e. parigraha, is primarily internal negligence, and is therefore worth abandoning (Amrtachandra's introductory remark to PS 219). The feeling of attachment or sense of “mineness” (mamatva) invariably binds the soul and leads to possession of external things (external parigraha). This, in turn, acts as the indirect, auxiliary (nimitta) cause of internal parigraha, i.e. attachment to objects (PSU 113). One should, therefore, abandon all (sarva) upadhi (parigraha) (PS 219), both external and internal (bahittham majjhattham (PS 273). How can one (who is favourably disposed towards parigraha be free from infatuation (murchha) and worldly concerns (arambha) and practise self-restraint (samyam)? And how one who is attracted towards and engrossed in other things, can understand and realize the real identity of his self or the real nature of his soul (atma, i.e. Page #182 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 156 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES consciousness)? (PS 221). Conduct in Pravachanasara Book III of Pravachanasara deals with conduct and path of liberation. There are several misperceptions in that regard and Kundakunda has sought to rectify them. According to “purely orthodox doctrine," as found in Dasavaikalika Sutra and other Shvetambara "canonical texts”, particularly Bhagavati, Thanang and Uttarajjhayayana, Johnson states, Jaina asceticism was usually and primarily viewed in physical and material terms, 146 i.e. painful penance and mortification of the body.147 The glorious sufferings of Lord Mahavira, engaging himself in 12 years of “self-mortifications” and “wandering about leading a life of austerities and bearing hardships of all kinds”, portrayed in Acharanga Sutra, seemed to serve as an illustration and “set a high example of the true ascetic life”. 148 Thus, Jainism along with Samkhya and Buddhist philosophy came to be considered as “essentially pessimistič in worldly outlook," and “temperamentally ascetic,"149 with austerities (tapasya) “emanating from the darker and gloomier view of life”. 150 “Self-mortification” by several kinds of austerities thereby seemed to assume utmost importance in the Jaina order, including the shedding of karmas.!51 Nakedness was supposed to be “the excellent type of Jaina aceticism”. 152 The term “achela” signifies an unclothed state of nakedness, i.e. completely devoid of clothes on the body as well as scantily clothed.153 Nakedness is symbolic of extreme non-attachment to worldly objects to the extent of not having clothes on the body and as such is prescribed in both Shvetambara'54 and Digambara texts. Balance between Internal and External Aspects of Conduct In these circumstances, in Pravachanasara Kundakunda sought to rectify the undue importance attached to the infliction of undue and painful physical hardships on oneself in the name of austerities in the belief that it led to the much desired balance and sanity between internal and external aspects. Internal aspects had “precedence” over the external ones. Kundakunda's concern for balance is reflected in the statement that a shraman does not desire/have any attachment to either food or fasting, either lodging (i.e. residence) or wandering (PS 215). Such a balanced approach is considered appropriate in regard to food and wandering (yukta ahara vihara) (PS 226). Page #183 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 157 While not neglecting austerities (tapa) (tapa is mentioned in PS 202, 214, 227, 263-264 and 268-269), Kundakunda lays stress on the internal aspects or mental attitude. The shraman, who is free from all desire or longing for food, he points out, is, in fact, observing the [internal] penance or austerity of fasting (the first of the external austerities (bahya tapa), as he is devoid of the desire (eshana dosha) (the fault against the observance of carefulness or self-regulation in eating, i.e. eshana-samiti]; for “the internal is more important (than the external). Although taking food, those shramanas are really not taking food and are really abstainers from food” (PS 227 AC). Thus Kundakunda, Johnson remarks, is “consciously reacting to acting against the excessive formalization, the mechanistic pursuit of physical austerity”. 155 28 Primary Qualities (Mulagunas) of Samana In this way, Kundakunda seems to remind the readers that the 28 primary or fundamental qualities (mula-guna) (PS 208-209) of shramanas prescribed by Jinas are not to be viewed merely in external, physical, material terms. In his introductory remarks to Pravachanasara 205-206 and Pravachanasara 207 and in his commentary on Pravachanasara 277, Amrtachandra specifically mentions both external and internal characteristics of shraman. Of the 28 mula-gunas of shraman, except for seven (see PS 208), the remaining 21 characteristics have both internal and external dimensions. These include five vows (vratas) or moral rules of conduct (besides non-violence and parigraha, truthfulness, non-stealing and chastity), the five observances of carefulness or self-regulation (samiti) (besides carefulness in taking food, i.e. eshana, carefulness in walking, speaking, handling of things and disposing of excrements i.e. cleanliness), restraint of five senses (indriya-rodha) and six essential duties (avashyaka) (see PS 207 AC). (For the significance of the study of scriptures (svadhyaya, the 5th avashyaka) see PS 232-237]. The seven mula-guna includes achailakya, which signifies the unclothed state of nakedness as well as the scantily-clothed state. Kundakunda has also used jadhajadaruva (yatha jata rupa in Sk.) (PS 204, 205 and 225), which could mean the nature of self at birth, the child-like simplicity as also the state of nakedness of a newly-born child. A shraman is required to be earnest in regard to the observances of mula-guna (PS 214). In case of negligence, a shraman should seek Page #184 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 158 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES to rectify it by self-reflection and acceptance (alochana) of his fault (PS 211-212).156 The word "samana” (shraman in Sk. which means one who makes efforts), is used throughout Pravachanasara (except in PS 234 where sahu, sadhu, or a sajjan purush, i.e. a noble, simple, straightforward person is used), comes from the root sama, samo, meaning "to quiet,” (shama in Sk.). It is also a state of equipoise (PS 241 AC).157 Thus, shama, i.e. self-restraint (self-control or subsidence of passions), is considered the primary trait of samana (PS 236-237, 240). In fact, at several places (PS 201, 213, 214, 242, 246, 267 and 274), Kundakunda uses the word “samanya” (shramanya in Sk.), meaning the state of samana. The word “samana” is used for Lord Mahavira as well as religious and moral persons. 158 Equanimity Equanimity is referred to in Pravachanasara 7 (see supra) and explained in Pravachanasara 241. Apart from equanimity, the other attributes of a self-restrained (sanjado in Pk. and sanyat in Sk.) shraman are the practice of five self-regulations (samiti), the three restraints of mind, speech and body (gupti), control of five senses, the subsidence of passions, and being endowed with intuition and knowledge (PS 240). Self-restraint is both internal and external (PS 211-212 AC). A shraman is also not attached to food or fasting, lodging or wandering (vihara), possession of things, and other shramanas. He also has no interest in useless, idle talk or gossip (vikatha) (PS 215). · In Niyamsara, Kundakunda categorically declares: “What is good of residing in a forest, the mortification of the body, observance of various fasts, study of the scriptures and keeping silence, etc., if the samana is devoid of equanimity?" (NS 124) The characteristic features of an equanimous person are said to be: freedom from all sinful, unwholesome actions (NS 103 and 125), observance of three-fold self-restraint of mind, speech and body (gupti) and control of senses (NS 125), equality with all living beings (NS 126), observance of self-restraint rules (niyam), austerities (NS 127), freedom from distorted psychic dispositions arising from attachment and aversion (NS 128), abstention from mournful and cruel concentrations (NS 129), renunciation of meritorious and demeritorious or sinful mental states (NS 130), of scornful laughter, indulgence in sense objects, sorrow and hatred (NS 131), disgust, fear, Page #185 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 159 and sexual inclinations of all kinds (NS 132), and practice of righteous and pure concentrations (NS 133). 159 Thus, self-restraint or subsidence of passions (shama or prasham) has necessary concomitance with equanimity. One without the other is not sustainable. Amrtachandra observes: Self-restraint (samyam) is conduct accompanied by enlightened (samyak) intuition and knowledge. Conduct is dharma; dharma is equanimity; equanimity is state-of-evolution of the self devoid of infatuation (moha) perturbation or mental agitation (kshobha) [resulting from attachment and aversion). Therefore, equanimity is the characteristic of the self-restrained (PS 241 AC). In Uttarajjhayana (25.32) a samana is defined as one who is endowed with equipoise (samayaye samano hoi). The same characteristic of a saint (sadhu) is found in Emperor Ashoka's inscriptions in Girnar (13, Girnar). In Buddhist literature as well, the word “samand” is frequently used and a samana is described as one who has controlled all his sins and subdued his passions and is tranquil (Dhammapada 19.10). Importance of Self-restraint Significantly, self-restraint (sanjam in Pk., samyam in Sk.) is considered synonymous with samana. How can one be a samana without self-restraint? (PS 236). A samana is considered to be selfrestrained (sanyat) if he practices five-fold self-regulations (samiti), the three restraints (gupti) (of mind, speech and body), controls his five . senses, has conquered his anger, pride, greed, etc. passions (kashaya) and is completely endowed with intuition and knowledge (PS 240, see also PS 263-264 and 268-269). The three-fold restraint (gupti), which does not figure in the 28 mula-guna, is emphasized in Pravachanasara 238, which states: “That karman which one without knowledge destroys in hundreds of thousands of crores of existences (lives), a knower (jnata) possessing threefold restraint (gupti) (of mind, speech and body) destroys in a mere breath.” In Pravachanasara 226, Kundakunda speaks of being free from passions. In Pravachanasara 268, he advocates the subduing (shamit) or subsidence of passions. In Pravachanasara 272, he speaks of the self being in a peaceful and calm_state (prashanta atma). Since indulgence in sense objects and passions are described as a sin in Page #186 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 160 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Jaina texts (PS 258), one should abstain from them. According to 28 mula-gunas (PS 208-209) of samana, which have both external and internal aspects, apparently only a homeless ascetic can be a samana. However, this is not necessarily so. Kundakunda recognized that the immaculate performance of the 28 primary rules/ values/qualities, especially regarding pure psychic-attention, which is expected of an ideal or complete shraman state (shramanya) (PS 214), is not possible for all samanas, all the time. That is why he stressed the possibility that external negligence in bodily activities (kaya cheshta) (PS 211) and internal negligence in psychic-attention (Pravachanasara 211-212 AC) can occur. He therefore emphasized the need to reestablish them on the correct path, which finds mention in Pravachanasara 208-214. For instance, apart from the worthy Lord Arhantas, the supreme shramanas, who have themselves abandoned all upadhi (external possessions as well as internal parigraha of attachment, aversion and passions) (Pravachanasara 219 AC), it is impossible for a samana to remain in and forever maintain the state of pure psychic attention. In the mundane existence of the embodied self, the psychic disposition is invariably unstable because one has to harmonize and strike a balance between not neglecting self-restraint and not neglecting the body. The former is of fundamental importance as a means towards realizing the principle of the pure self (shuddha atma tattva) whereas the latter is indispensable as a means to self-restraint (PS 230 AC). Kundakunda has therefore emphasized the need to strike a balance and not commit any excess in either food or fasting and lodging or wanderings, i.e. the need for proper food and wandering (yukta ahara vihara) (PS 213, 215, 226-231). Amrtachandra stresses that one should avoid excess of everything (ati sarvatra varjayeta), keeping in view one's age, and capacity for suffering, etc. (PS 230 AC). One should also, he adds, practice austerities and renunciation according to one's capacity (shakti tapas tyaga). The body, he adds, is the means to dharma (righteousness) (sharira madyam khalu dharma sadhanam), which, in turn, is the means to peace and happiness and gradually leads to liberation (PS 254 AC). However, at the same time, he categorically states that even if one has the slightest infatuation or mental clinging (murchha) in regard to the body, etc., one does not attain liberation, even if one knows all Page #187 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 161 the scriptures (PS 239). Exposition of Good Psychic-attention (Shubha Upayoga) The issue of shubha occupies an important place in the path of liberation. The subject was earlier described in 22 verses (PS 69-92) as also in another seven verses (PS 155-159 and PS 180-181) and is again discussed in 26 verses (PS 245-270). Taking a realistic view of things, Kundakunda categorically states that in the Jaina scriptures that shramanas can be endowed with either pure psychic-attention or with auspicious psychic attention (shubha upayoga). Amongst them, those with pure psychic-attention are free from karmic inflow (asrava); others are subject to karmic inflow (PS 245). Therefore, those with auspicious psychic-attention may not be equated or coordinated with those having pure psychic-attention, though they are also considered as shraman (PS 245 AC). Jayasena states that shramanas with pure psychic attention are primary, while those with auspicious psychicattention are secondary (PS 245 JS). Therefore, Kundakunda and Amrtachandra did not deem it necessary to rule them out of the state of shramanya (shraman-hood).. Amrtachandra's commentary (PS 245 AC) advances several arguments why persons with good or auspicious psychic-attention should also be regarded as samana. These are: 1. They are in the proximity of pure psychic-attention, i.e. they are not deprived of having pure psychic-attention for some time. 2. Although they are not able to ascend to the stage of pure psychic-attention due to not being completely free from passions, they are subject to karmic inflow (SS 245). However, they have only mild passions or “small particles of passion” (PS 245 AC), which, unlike those endowed with inauspicious or evil psychic attention, does not prevent them from practicing rules or values of shraman-hood. 3. Since good or auspicious psychic-attention coinheres with righteousness (dharma) and since the “self evolves through righteousness” (PS 11), persons possessing it would be shramanas. 4. Such shramanas of good psychic-attention, whether householders or ascetics (PS 251), engage themselves in devotion to arahantas (PS 246). They show respect coupled with praise and homage to other shramanas (PS 247). They render disinterested assistance to others through compassion, which is to be practiced with no consideration Page #188 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 162 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES or expectation whatsoever (nirpeksha) of any kind or desire of fruit of one's acts of good or righteousness, even though it may result in a small stain (alpa lepa) (PS 249-254). They gradually attain the highest happiness of nirvana (moksha) (PS 254 and PS 254 AC). 5. Since a shraman is endowed with good psychic-attention and has refrained from sin, he has an attitude of equality towards all righteous persons. He is someone who is endowed with meritorious qualities, and is therefore on the right path (sumagga in Pk., sumarga in Sk.) (PS 259), i.e. on the path of liberation (PS 259 AC. 6. Such shramanas, who are devoid of evil or inauspicious psychic attention and endowed with either good or pure psychic-attention, through being themselves an abode of liberation, are able to help others to cross the (mundane existence), i.e. attain liberation (PS 260 and PS 260 AC). However, shramanas with good psychic-attention cannot be equated with shramanas of pure psychic-attention (for definition of pure psychic attention, see PS 14) because they are not of the same level (PS 245 AC) and because they are not completely free from passions. The former are therefore subject to karmic inflow (PS 245 and PS 245 AC) whereas the latter are devoid of all passions and free from karmic inflow (PS 245 and PS 245 AC), which is the direct cause of liberation. Ascetic shramanas having good psychic-attention and householders share a number of characteristics and activities. However, unlike the former, the latter cannot be totally free from worldly concerns and possessions (upadhi or parigraha) (PS 219). As a result, the activities of rendering assistance to others and service, etc. is more prominent in householders (PS 254). Accordingly, Acharya Mahaprajna observes: “The vow of nonpossession cannot be prescribed for a householder. For, an individual totally devoid of possessions cannot make material and economic development, nor can he solve the problem of hunger. . . (Hence] putting a limit on one's possessions, i.e. to put a limit on one's own accumulation of wealth and putting a limit to one's consumption, i.e. to put a voluntary limit to one's individual consumption” are considered foremost (or significant] vows of the code of conduct for the householder. 160 Nevertheless, despite Kundakunda’s emphasis on internal aspects, it was no longer possible to consider a Jaina householder to be “an Page #189 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 163 anachronism,"161 even if it was so when Jaina asceticism was viewed in “purely physical terms”. Jain teachings, Johnson states, were from its beginnings so ascetic-oriented that “prima facie” lay Jainism “would seem to be a contradiction in terms”. 162 We cannot, however, bifurcate the duties of shramanas and householders into watertight compartments. In Kundakunda's works, particularly Pravachanasara, the householders (sagara, i.e. persons with homes) occupy a significant place and even considered samana. The words “sagard” and “anagara” (homeless) are frequently referred to in Pravachanasara (see PS 250, 251, 254 and 275). Meaning of Samana The word “samana” in Prakrit (shraman in Sk.) is used very frequently in Pravachanasara as well as other works of Kundakunda. It has several meanings: subsidence (shaman) of (negative) emotions i.e. anger, etc. passions, or restraint of one's senses; equanimity (sama, samata, samana), one having equanimous attitude as regards enemy or friend, pleasure or pain, praise or blame, life or death, etc; and one who is inclined towards making efforts or exerts himself (shrama or shraman) for his moral and spiritual uplift, i.e. a noble or enlightened person. The wordsamana" can also be interpreted as sa+manas, i.e. one endowed with mind of his own or equanimous mind. The word “samana” as described and explained in Pravachanasara, according to the present author of this introduction, does not necessarily mean an ascetic (the word sahu or sadhu in Sk. also signifies a noble person), even though it is generally used in the sense of an ascetic by many scholars. For that matter, It is also incorrect to conclude, as is often said, that Kundakunda's works are written and meant only for ascetics. The code of conduct for the householders, written by Samantabhadra categorically states: "The householder, who is devoid of delusion, has enlightened view (of the reality of things], and is established in the path of liberation, is superior to an ascetic who is deluded and is devoid of enlightened view” (RKS 33). In Pravachanasara itself, the following characteristics are said to qualify or define samana. (1) a person who has no desire or attachment to sense objects in Page #190 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 164 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES this world and has no expectation in regard to the other [i.e. next world), is self-controlled in food and wandering (yukta-ahara-vihara), and is free from passions (kashaya) is samana (PS 226); (2) a person whose view (ditthi in Pk. and drashti in Sk.) or conviction is not in accordance with scriptures, cannot be selfrestrained (sanyat) and one who does not practice self-restraints, how can he be considered samana? (PS 236), i.e. he is not samana; and (3) a person who maintains equanimity among groups of enemies and friends as the same, treats pleasure and pain as the same, regards praise and blame as the same, clay and gold as the same, and, moreover, maintains an equanimous attitude in regard to life and death by considering them to be the same (PS 241). It is noteworthy that in the three works of Kundakunda, viz. Pravachanasara, Samayasara and Niyamsara, no distinction is made in vows as major-scale vows (mahavratas) and minor-scale vows (anuvratas), meant for ascetics and householders respectively. Moreover, in Niyamsara the five rules of moral conduct like nonviolence and five-fold self-regulation (samiti) as well as three restraints (gupti) (of mind, speech and body) (NS 56-70) (excluded from 28 mulagunas of samana, PS 208-209) have been described as vyavahara charitra. They are also considered as a practice of austerities (NS 55), i.e. conduct of self-restraint from the external, other referential (vyavahara) point of view, relevant, desirable and applicable to householders as well as samanas alike. Eighty-two verses of Niyamsara (verses 77 to 158) discuss in detail issues like conduct from the internal, self-referential point of view (nishchaya charitra) of psychological techniques of self-introspection, repentance (pratikraman), etc., aimed at purifying the mental states at the inner level.163 They are briefly described as pratikraman, alochana, and pratyakhyana in Pravachanasara (see PS 207 AC). Interestingly, in Pravachanasara, the conduct which is endowed with equanimity is said to be free from infatuation (moha) and mental disturbance (kshobha) caused by attachment and aversion (PS 7). Faulty Criticism of Johnson of Kundakunda's Views on Conduct Kundakunda's emphasis on the internal aspects of conduct without denying the importance of physical, external, social aspects is criticized Page #191 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 165 by W. J. Johnson as “internalization”. 164 Apart from threatening "the ethical norm of lay community”, Johnson argues, internal aspects of conduct also jeopardize the “ascetic practice, and thereby the entire structure of Jaina religious and social identity". 165 This allegation has no basis whatsoever because Kundakunda truly places the moral and spiritual conduct of both householders and ascetics on the solid foundations of a rational and balanced approach of external selfrestraint and internal self-discipline or morality and spirituality. One of the earliest codes of moral conduct for the householders (Ratnakarnda Shravkachara, RKS), written by Samantabhadra in the second century A.D., begins the chapter “Necessity for the Adoption of Enlightened Conduct," by stating that “sadhu [one can translate it as the noble or enlightened person or samana of PS) starts to practice the rules of moral conduct by getting rid of attachment and aversion" (RKS 47). “As a result of renunciation of attachment and aversion, one (necessarily] abstains from violence (himsa), etc. sins” (RKS 48). Renunciation is an attitude of mind that is manifested through word and deed; it is an ideal to be attained and it is possible only by cultivating detachment. Johnson blames Kundakunda for his doctrine of upayoga (conscious attentiveness), his “internalization of karmic bondage and his concept of himsa (violence), etc. However, Paul Dundas, the reviewer of his book Harmless Souls, maintains that Kundakunda's emphasis on inner aspects or “interiorisation of the various components of Jaina practice and the concomitant attempt to move the ascetic's ultimate concern away from his relationship with the external world toward his inner being” makes him a “reformer”, 166 who is “consciously reacting against excessive formalization, the mechanistic pursuit of physical austerity”. 167 Thus, "external, ascetic practice” which had become “meaningless” and “without spiritual significance”, Dundas stresses, “had to be reinterpreted by Kundakunda”. Kundakunda was well aware that although the “inner state has precedence and conditions the outer”, external moral conduct of vows (vrata), self-regulation (samiti), etc. (vyavahara charitra) has its importance and value. The moral rules of conduct are the “objective correlative” of the subjective state or attitude.168 Internal purification in the sense of subsidence of the passions is the necessary concomitant (avinabhava) (PS 216 AC) of external moral conduct of non-violence, etc. Page #192 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 166 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES The recognition of the necessity and importance of the value of external moral discipline ensures that Jainism does not become what Johnson calls a "private soteriology". 169 Kundakunda, Paul Dundas remarks, represents a "middle point between two main historic propensities within Jainism: excessive formalization and ritualisation of behavior which diminish the spiritual dimensions of the path and excessive interiorisation of values", 170 which denies the need for external moral conduct (vyavahara charitra) in relation to others. Nishchaya and Vyavahara Charitra (Conduct) This remark of Paul Dundas is very relevant in the discussion of conduct, especially nishchaya and vyavahara charitra (conduct). There are numerous persons who one-sidedly cling to only external, otherreferential vyavahara charitra. As a result, they diminish the internal, spiritual dimension of the path of liberation. There are others, particularly Kanjipanthi, who exclusively depend on excessive interiorisation and deny the validity and relevance of vyavahara charitra altogether under the guise of internal, self-referential nishchaya charitra of their own thinking (which is not the same as nishchaya charitra of repentance (pratikraman), etc. described in Niyamsara). Thus, H.C. Bharill adheres to the mistaken assertion of his preceptor (guru, whom Bharill describes with respect as gurudeva, i.e. preceptor-God), viz. Kanji Svami, that "conduct is only of one kind alone, and that is of the nature of non-attachment, i.e. completely devoid of attachment (veetraga bhavarupa); charitra with attachment is not conduct at all; he who respects it, accedes to it or believes in it is a deluded person (mithyadrashti)". Bharill adds: “Nishchaya (point of view) charitra is the term used only for the non-attached mental state; in reality vyavahara charitra, which has [some degree of] attachment, is not conduct at all, it is only the fault of conduct."171 In this regard, Bharill refers to the introductory remark of Amrtachandra to Pravachanasara verse 6, to the effect that conduct without attachment has desirable result (ishta phala) and therefore, is worth-acquiring (upadeya), while conduct with attachment has undesirable result (anishta phala) and hence to be avoided (beya). This remark in fact points out that as compared to the conduct with attachment or vyavahara charitra, the conduct free of attachment (veetraga charitra), which is the direct and immediate cause of Page #193 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 167 liberation, is preferable and worth acquiring. Since vyavahara charitra has some degree of attachment, which is the cause of bondage, it does not have that privilege since it gradually (kramtah), not directly or immediately, brings about liberation (PS 254 AC). Moreover, the above-mentioned remarks of Amrtachandra has to be seen in the context in which it has been made. Conduct without attachment, anchored or based on enlightened view and knowledge, is the [immediate and direct] cause of liberation. Hence, it is definitely preferable to conduct with attachment whereby one gets the troubles of the heavenly and kingly power, etc. (PS 6 AC). However, Amrtachandra also states that vyavahara charitra, i.e. conduct based on commendable attachment (prashasta raga), which is characterized by subsidence of passions, veneration of the worthy Lord (Arhat) and practice of moral conduct of self-restraint including non-violence, also has a purifying (vishuddhi) effect (Amrtachandra's commentary on PS 155, 156, 180). This gradually (kramatah) brings about the highest happiness of nirvana (liberation) (PS 254 and PS 254 AC), and not only leads to liberation of oneself (PS 259 and PS 259 AC), but also helps others to attain liberation (PS 260 and PS 260 AC). In Panchastikayasara (PKS), Amrtachandra states that an external/ other-referential inclination Spara-samaya pravrtti) [i.e. vyavahara charitra] of the nature of veneration of the worthy Lord (Arhant) (etc.) is not the direct/immediate condition of liberation but traditionally (paramparya) has the disposition or tendency (sadbhava) of being the [indirect condition (hetu) of liberation (Introductory remark of Amrtachandra to PKS 170), even with the troubles (klesha) of heaven, etc. (PKS 170 AC). According to Jayasena, both nishchaya and vyavahara paths of liberation (moksha marg) are the cause of liberation (PKS 106 JS). Amrtachandra contends that the vyavahara path of liberation is the means (sadhan) of nishchaya path, which is the direct cause of liberation (PKS 160-161 AC). This apparently implies that without the practice of vyavahara path of liberation it is not possible to attain liberation. Thus, if someone argues that vyavahara moksha murg is the sole cause of transmigratory existence (sansara), and not of liberation, would, indeed, be considered to be filled with excessive stubbornness. Summing up his exposition of the proper assessment of nishchaya and vyavahara charitra (conduct) or nishchaya and vyavahara moksha Page #194 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 168 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES marg, Amrtachandra observes: One should first give up the tendency to indulge in ashubha (inauspicious or evil) activity (nivarita ashubha karma pravrtti), and adopt vyavahara moksha-marg of the shubha (good or auspicious) activities (samupatta shubha karma pravrttyah), consisting of subsidence of passions, enthusiasm for righteousness and piety, compassion, acceptance of reality of things, the study of scriptures, non-violence, etc. five rules (vrata) of conduct of selfrestraint, the restraints (gupti) of activities of mind, speech and body (yoga in Jain terminology), the five carefulness or self-regulation (samiti), various kinds of austerities etc. All these rules of moral code of conduct, called vyavahara moksha-marg are, in fact, self-restraints (samyam) (PKS 172 AC). Amrtachandra further points out: One should not cling one-sidedly (ekantena) to only vyavahara mokshamarg considering it to be diverse from or completely separate from the objective of nishchaya moksha-marg (bhinna sadhya-sadhan bhava); in that case he will suffer extreme grief or distress. He should certainly understand the two paths (marg properly, along with the compatibility and the harmony between the two paths and thus realize the ideal of nonattachment (veetragatva) as the immediate and the direct cause of moksha (liberation). Only by the practice of vyavahara and nishchaya (paths] being complementary, not contradictory or opposed to each other (avirodhena), one can attain the objective of non-attachment, (veetragata), not otherwise (na punar anyatha) (PKS 172 AC). Pandit Todarmal's manglacharan (opening verse in Hindi) to his translation of Amrtachandra's Purusharthasiddhyupapa is also quite relevant in regard to conduct from vyavahara naya and nishchaya naya. He states: There are those who from nishchaya naya mistakenly assume self (atma) to be pure like liberated souls (siddha-samaan) even in its empirical existence and hence become lazy and negligent about purification of self and make no effort in getting rid of attachment, aversion, passions, etc. internal impurities and thus become unrestrained in their behaviour, not recognizing or caring about purity of their own self, [i.e. renunciation of attachment, aversion, passions, etc. internal impurities). And there are those who consider that mere auspicious thought-activities of charity, sheel (good conduct), and austerities from vyavahara naya alone (hi), even when devoid of internal purification, serves the true well-being of the self, and thereby they do not give up their foolishness. Moreover, there are others, Page #195 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 169 who recognize the path of vyavahara naya and that of nishchaya naya to be separate and different paths and thus become arrogant and insolent. It is only when one has proper understanding of the distinctive features and true nature of both the nishchaya naya and vyavahara naya and regards the former as the cause (karana) [i.e. the primary (mukhya)], or substantive cause (upadana cause) and the latter as supportive (upachaar) factor (or auxiliary cause, nimitta karana], then only one becomes truly enlightened or wise. Apart from Amrtachandra's introductory remark (to PS 6), Bharill also states that a similar view is expressed by Jayasena in his commentary of the said verse. However, Bharill fails to mention Jayasena's observation that as a result of the special kind of karmic bondage of virtuous nature (vishishta punya bandha) that occurs due to conduct with attachment, one gets the kingly power, etc. and that vishishta punya bandha also customarily (paramparya) brings about liberation (nirvana) (PS 6 JS). The Path of Liberation Any discussion of conduct is incomplete without the description of liberation — the highest objective of human endeavour. The path of liberation is discussed in 13 verses (PS 232-244). The first four verses (PS 232-235) emphasize that the study of scriptures is important and necessary for ascertaining with certainty the reality of the principles of life or categories (tattvas or padarthas), particularly the knowledge of the self and the non-self, (sva and para, i.e. other). In other words, the self (atman) and other than self (paratman) have the potential to become the supreme self (param atman). The self and not-self have the psycho-physical nexus and interaction as to how the mental state (chitta vrtti) get stained with the faults (doshas) of attachment and aversion due to being involved in duality by the division of things as favourable and unfavourable or desirable and undesirable (ishta anishta). The material or physical karman also affect, condition or influence (i.e. acting as pratyaya) psychic states, thereby staining mental states with delusion, etc. (mohadi). One devoid of above knowledge is unable to destroy the physical and psychic karman (dravya-bhava karman) (PS 232-233 and PS 232-233 AC). Knowledge by itself is not sufficient to destroy karmas. Pravachanasara 236 states that persons who do not possess enlightened Page #196 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 170 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES view of things because they really lack a discriminative insight between the self and other, and because they believe in identity of the self with the passions (kashaya). As a result, the body does not restrain his longing for sense-objects. Without self-restraint, there can be no shramana-state, otherwise known as the path of liberation. Hence the path of liberation can be nothing but a simultaneity of Scriptureknowledge, conviction in the principle and categories and self-restraint (PS 236 and PS 236 AC). Pravachanasara Verse 237 states that one does not attain liberation by means of scriptural knowledge if one is devoid of enlightened world-view of the nature of reality of things. Similarly, someone having enlightened world-view of things does not attain liberation if he is devoid of self-restraint (samyam) (PS 237). Due to his indulgence in sense-objects and passions, the self continues to lack self-restraint (PS 237 JS). Moreover, a person, who has even the slightest attachment (e.g. to the body) does not attain perfection (siddhi) even if he knows all the scriptures (PS 239). Only a persoff who is free from desire or attachment and the sense of ‘i-ness' and 'mine-ness' (PS 190 and SS 19-23) towards worldly objects is capable of enlightenment and salvation. All the three (viz. scriptural knowledge, enlightened world-view and self-restraint) are necessary for attaining liberation. All three together are imperative for the attainment of liberation (PS 237 JS). In other words, one cannot attain liberation by sticking to a single path of liberation separately or independently of the other two, viz. devotion, enlightened world-view of the reality of things, knowledge alone, or action/inaction only. The example that one can reach the top of the mountain by following any one direction or path, does not apply in the case of the liberation of the self. The self can only be liberated by all three because it is an indivisible unity of its attributes or modes of intuition, knowledge and volition or conduct which are interactive, interdependent and mutually inter-penetrating. The three-fold self-restraints of mind, speech and body (gupti) enables an enlightened person (inani) to destroy the karman in a mere breath (PS 238), i.e. in no time. Unless the mind is controlled, it keeps wavering and drifting about without direction. Hence, restraint of mind is extremely important because it is the sole means to control the mind and to uproot disquietude and agitation (kshobha) caused Page #197 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 171 by attachment and aversion, and thereby attain the state of equanimity (samya, PS 7). Description of Self-restraint Describing self-restraint (sanjad in Pk. and samyat or samyam in Sk.), Kundakunda states: “That samana (shramana in Sk.) who has five self-regulations (samiti), the three self-restraints (gupti) of mind, speech and body, control of five senses, has conquered his passions (kashaya) and is fully endowed with intuition and knowledge, is called self-restrained” (PS 240). Moreover, a samana is “he, who considers the groups of enemies and friends as the same, pleasure and pain as the same, praise and blame as the same, clay and gold as the same and maintains an equanimous attitude in regard to life and death” (PS 241). Commenting on it, Amrtachandra observes: Self-restrained (samyam) is conduct accompanied by enlightened (samyak) world-view and knowledge. Conduct is dharma, dharma is equanimity; equanimity is a state-of-evolution of the self devoid of infatuation or deluded view (moha) and perturbation or mental agitation (kshobha) (caused by attachment and aversion). Therefore, equanimity is the characteristic of the self restrained (PS 241 AC). Thus, sama (equanimity), sanyat or samyam (conduct of selfrestraint), (or shaman, i.e. subsidence of passions, etc. as also samiti, i.e. self-regulation) and samana (shraman in Sk.) [i.e. one who is oriented towards the path of liberation and makes efforts in the direction of sanity and purification), are considered to be closely interrelated terms. A samana is one who is self-restrained or who practices self-restraint. This is evident from the categorical statement that without self-restraint how can one be a samana (shramana)? (PS 236). The shramana-state is also equated with the path of liberation. Amrtachandra states: “And for one who has not attained self-restraint there can be no shramana-state, otherwise called the path of liberation, which is convincingly held to be in a state of mental concentration (ekagra gatatva rupam)” (PS 236 AC). Enlightened World-view, Knowledge and Conduct constittue the Path of Liberation In Pravachanasara 242, it is categorically stated that the shramanya (i.e. practice of moral and spiritual self-restraints and self-discipline) Page #198 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 172 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES of a person who is endowed with enlightened world-view, knowledge and conduct [devoid of attachment and aversion], the three together (yugapat) with mental-concentration or one-pointed attention (ekagratah), is complete (PS 242). In other words, such a person is capable of attaining liberation Or that the three together constitute the path of liberation. In Samayasara also, it is declared by the worthy Lord (Jina) that the enlightened world-view, knowledge and conduct jointly comprise the path of liberation (SS 410). In Panchastikayasara (PKS), enlightened conduct, devoid of attachment and aversion, together with enlightened world-view and knowledge is described as the path of liberation (PKS 106). In his commentary on Pravachanasara 242, Amrtachandra states that just as in the case of panak (a drink mixture) there is an experiencing of one, though consisting of many, so also the path of liberation, otherwise called shramana-hood, is said to be characterised as mental concentrations (ekagrata) or repose in itself (atma-nishthtva), though comprising of the three modes (paryaya) [characterised by mutual-interpenetrations, i.e. mutually inter-dependent and inter-active] of the self or soul substance, viz. darshan, jnana and charitra (enlightened view, knowledge and conduct). Amrtachandra further states that according to the external, otherreferential point of view (vyavahara-naya), which, since it involves differentiations (bheda), considers chiefly the modes, the statement is that "enlightened view, knowledge, and conduct are the path of liberation." According to the internal, self-referential point of view (nishchaya-naya), which, since it consists in an identity (abheda), consider chiefly the substance, it is that "mental-concentration is the path of liberation." (PS 242 AC) According to reliable evidence (pramana), everything consists in difference and identity (PS 242 AC). Thus, that path of liberation, which, according to the attitude of the conceiver, becomes plural, though one, and thereby exhibits triple characteristics and again oneness, - that path, stable, with existence is dependent upon [the purport (abhipraya)] of seer and knower (drashtr-jnatr) (PS Kalash 16). Naya is defined, described and explained as the purport (abhipraya) of the knower (Akalanka, Laghiyastraya 49). Samayasara (verse 7) states that darshan, jnana, charitra, are said to Page #199 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 173 be (three modes of consciousness) from vyavahara naya. However, from the (transcendental perspective) there is no such differentiation, just pure consciousness-as-such (janago-suddho in Pk. and jnayak-shuddha in Sk.). If a shraman, who is ignorant about the nature of the reality of things, is infatuated because of addiction to the “other” substance, and feels either attachment or aversion, then he is bound with various karmans (PS 243). However, if a shraman is not infatuated with objects and does not have either attachment or aversion (dvesha), then he inevitably destroys the karmans. (PS 244). Freedom from infatuation or deluded view (moha), attachment (raga) and aversion (dvesha) play the most significant role in liberation (PS 243-244). A person devoid of self-restraint does not attain liberation even if he has knowledge of scriptures or is convinced of the nature of reality of things (see PS 237). In the earlier verses as well, it is stated that without the renunciation of worldly concerns, devoid of all consideration or expectation, the purification of intentional mental states does not take place. When the mind is not pure, how can the annihilation of the karman take place (PS 220) or the liberation of the self take place? One must understand that renunciation is a state/an attitude of mind. It is a stare of detachment, not necessarily asceticism (e.g. going to the forest). In Niyamsara, it is categorically stated: “What is the good of residing in a forest, mortification of the body, observance of various fasts, study of the scriptures and keeping silence, etc., if the samana is devoid of equanimity” (NS 124). It is simply impossible for a person favourably disposed towards worldly objects (upadhi, parigraha) to be free from infatuation (sense of mineness), incidental sins inevitable in worldly activities (arambha) and lack of self-restraint (asamyam). A person, who is engrossed in other, external things, cannot understand or realize the real nature of or the true identity of his soul (PS 221 and PS 221 AC). In Pravachanasara 14, a shraman is described as a person who has the following qualities. A person is a shraman if one is of pure psychic-attention, when one is well aware of the categories (padarthas), including the self and the non-self, and the sutras (the scriptures) [for the definition of Sutra, see PS 34) which explain them, when he possesses self-restraint (samyam) and practices austerities (tapas), gives Page #200 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 174 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES up attachment and considers pleasure and pain the same (sama). Obviously, pure psychic-attention (shuddha upayoga) is the direct means of attaining pure self or pure consciousness, i.e. the liberated state. Distortion of the Path of Liberation by Kanjipanthi Liberation usually means getting rid of one's karmas. In this context, K. Ramakrishna Rao observes: “In Indian thought, one's actions good or bad deposit karma. Good actions produce meritorious karma and bad actions deposit black [bad) karma." The accumulated karma lies dormant in the chitta (the mental stuff which contains instinctual tendencies inherited from previous lives and the effects of past actions) like a seed in the ground to sprout at an appropriate time. When karma leads to action in this manner, that action, in turn, again produces new karma. This cycle continues indefinitely unless broken by efforts towards self-realization, i.e. liberation (moksha) or nirvana. "72 According to Patanjali's Yoga Sutra, karma is said to be “recorded in the unconscious by any action or thought a person has done”. The karmic memory trace (samskara), it adds, remains in the unconscious as “a predisposition toward doing the same action or thought again in the future”. 173 To this description, one may add that in Jainism karma is material in nature recorded in neuro-physiological processes (physical or dravya karma or physical mind). It has the power to affect, influence and condition the adhyavasana bhavas (SS 190), i.e. psychic states like bhava karma (e.g. passions like delusion (mithyatva), lack of self-restraints (avirati), anger, etc. passions, and vibratory activity of mind, speech and body (yoga). The material or physical (dravya) karma and the psychic (bhava) karma act as the auxiliary cause (nimitta karana), and not the substantive cause (upadana karana), of one another (SS 80-81). Moreover, it is action, imbued with attachment or desire that is considered to bind the self with karman (PS 179), not each and every physical action, which is devoid of attachment, etc. psychical states (bhava). Accordingly, attachment, aversion and deluded view (mithya darshan) are said to be asrava bhava (SS 177-178), i.e. the direct cause of the influx of karma and the consequent bondage. In other words, psychological bondage is more significant than material bondage of physical karma. Moreover, the coming into operation, rise (udaya) or fruition Page #201 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 175 (vipaka) of material karma alone is not the cause of fresh karmic bondage. This does not produce karma again (thereby continuing the karmic cycle indefinitely as some systems of philosophy in Hinduism seems to imply). This occurs only when the self (jiva) itself evolves into psychic states of the nature of attachment, etc. (SS 132-136 and 164-165 JS). In other words, the only way to get rid of karmas and attain liberation (moksha) is by completely renouncing attachment, aversion and deluded view. Faulty View of Bronkhorst regarding Liberation Johannes Bronkhorst proceeds from the assumption that actions produce karma and the accumulated karma, on coming into operation or karmic seed sprouting at an appropriate time, produce fresh karma again. This results in the (karmic) cycle (karma santati, i.e. continued succession of karma) continuing indefinitely, He presents a strong, logical case in arguing that since actions produce karma, one can only escape the results of one's actions by inaction or somehow putting an end to all' activity. He states: The early Jainas, and many other Indian ascetics with them, applied this principle literally, and suppressed all bodily and mental activity (restriction of the mind, of the sense organs or quite simply all bodily and mental activities, indicative of severe practice of external penances and austerities of the ascetics]. The pains and suffering which these kinds of practices provoke were looked upon as signs that old karma was being destroyed. Once all the old karma is destroyed [by asceticism), no new karma being added (due to non-performing of new actions), it was sufficient for the ascetic to (come across natural death or] fast to death, motionlessly, and no new births would await him. The other method shares the same essential concern. One can only be freed from the result of actions by not committing them. According to this second method, one has to discover that one is not identical with the active parts of the personality. All that is required is that one realizes this important insight. Once one stops identifying with the body and the mind, i.e. with all those aspects of the person that are active, one is no longer bound by the actions that have been committed by those parts. Usually this insight consists in the discovery of one's real self, one's soul, which is (thought to be completely inactive by nature. These two methods of liberation are or organically related to the doctrine of karma. They constitute, in a way, natural answers to the Page #202 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 176 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 174 problem posed by this doctrine: Rebirth being occasioned by one's actions, only inaction can stop it." [Escape from the cycle of rebirths was accepted as the highest religious aim.] It is believed that the "insight into the true nature of the self is the necessary, or even [a] sufficient condition for the attainment of liberation from the cycle of rebirths. The self, it is believed, has to be permanent and unchangeable, precisely because it does not participate in any actions."175 Accordingly, the knowledge of the inactive or non-active nature of the self, or concerning the need to practice mental and physical inaction, is considered sufficient in order to be liberated from the effects of one's actions. In this context, Bronkhorst observes: Why did this knowledge of the self signify, for so many Indian [Samkhya and Kanjipanthi] liberation from the effects of one's actions? Precisely because it implied that one is not identical with the active parts of one's personality, i.e. the body and the mind. Well, this is exactly what the [liberating insight of the] knowledge of the not-self does for the Buddhists. It teaches that none of the constituents of the personality are the self. If we understand this to mean that one should not identify with these constituents, we come to the same kind of insight as that of the self for the non-Buddhists. A major difference is, of course, that an empty spot seems to remain there where the non-Buddhists believed to find a soul, but the effect of non-identification with one's action is exactly the same. 176 This passage, Bronkhorst states, illustrates how "a doctrine that was explicitly rejected, found its way into the Buddhist texts through a back-door". "The reason," he adds, is "easy to guess: because in the case of such an insight it was clear why it could constitute a solution to the problem posed by the doctrine of karma. The effects of action can only be avoided through non-action. Knowing that one's active parts are not really one's self, implies not being affected by the results of those actions". 177 The first method of Bronkhorst, viz. of undergoing pains and suffering by undertaking extreme practices of external penances and austerities and suppression of all bodily and mental activity, for the destruction of karmas, did not particularly appeal to Kundakunda because he has consistently laid greater emphasis on internal aspects of renouncing deluded view, attachment and aversion in order to get Page #203 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 177 rid of the karmas and attain liberation. As for the second method of Bronkhorst, viz. of not identifying with body and mind, the active parts of the self and being completely inactive, Kundakunda specifically states that the self in the doer of yoga (the activities of mind, speech and body) and upagoya (function of conciousness) (SS 100) and the self in the doer (karta) and experiencer (bhokta) of his actions (PKS 27). Mistaken Concept of Non-doership or Inactive Self of Kanjipanthi As already stated, the objective of liberation can only be realized by enlightened world-view of the reality of things, knowledge and conduct, which necessarily involves will and effort. The very concept of psychic-attention (upayoga), which is the nature of the self and on which Kundakunda lays emphasis, signifies active consciousness and permanent and yet evolvent personality, not inactive, unchangeable (aparinami) self. Therefore, Kanjipanthi's advocacy of an inactive self and exclusive emphasis on knowing the permanent and unchangeable self is contrary to the teachings of Kundakunda. In Pravachanasara, Amrtachandra asserts that a person who first has recourse to an active behaviour (pravrtti) based on good psychic attention (shubha upayoga), and gradually (kramatah) by proper selfrestraint advances to complete abstinence (nirvrtti), experiences an absolutely everlasting state, consisting in knowledge and bliss (PS Kalash 17). In other words, it is only in “an absolutely everlasting state of ... knowledge and bliss,” i.e. the liberated state of soul, that one can be said to be krta-krtya, i.e. he has nothing more to do or accomplish anything. But till that stage of “complete abstinence (nivrtti)” is reached, one has to “take recourse to active behaviour (pravrtti).” In his commentary on Panchastikayasara verse 59, Amrtachandra asserts that non-doership (akartrtva) of jiva (soul) is not desirable and acceptable (PKS 59 AC). Yet the Kanjipanthi persist in harping on the concept of the inactive self (akarta or akartrtva). Thus, Hem Chand Jain, a Kanjipanthi adherent/follower, mistakenly states: “Jain philosophy is basically that of non-doing/non-doership as this principle is established with omniscience and the sequence bound modifications (krama baddha paryaya).”!78. This means that whatever “particular modification will take place in a particular substance at a particular Page #204 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 178 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES time is pre-determined". This so-called novel concept of krama baddha paryaya, which is propagated by Kanji Svami and his followers, is extremely detrimental and deterministic concept that robs the soul of its independence. It gives rise to inactivity and laziness. It denies the importance and significance of the effort, which is against Jain principles, and is not mentioned in any Jain scripture.' 179 According to Kundakunda, external, other-referential (vyavahara) moral conduct (charitra) consists of self-restraint, five vows (vrata) of non-violence, etc., five self-regulations or carefulness in action (samiti) and three restraints of mind, speech and body (gupti) (NS 56-70), which have characteristics of dharma (righteousness and piety), samyam (selfrestraints) and tapa (austerity, NS 55). The internal, self-referential (nishchaya) conduct of repentance (pratikraman), etc. includes methods of spiritual self-discipline (NS 77-158). Along with enlightened view and knowledge of reality of things, vyavahara and nishchaya conduct are considered to be the authentic means (sadhan) of liberation. The ascetic activities of tapas, according to the orthodox ideology, comprises performance of six external (bahya) practices and six internal (abhyantar) austerities or penances (tapas), including prayashchitta (pratikraman, etc.). These are also oriented towards external aspects. For instance, the performance of Shvetambara annual samvatsari pratikraman on the eighth day of Paryushan is primarily a congregational ritual action (kriya). In this tradition, recitation of a Prakrit liturgy is recited accompanied by various hand gestures and bodily postures. In this endeavour, each Jain publicly recognizes all possible wrong thoughts, statements, and deeds from the previous year, and strives to minimize their karmic effects through the statement of disavowal of intention behind them. One of the most public expressions of these themes of confession and community harmony comes at the conclusion of the performance of Samvatsari Pratikraman, when the members of the congregation say to each other individually, "micchami dukkadam" - a Prakrit phrase that literally means, "may my improper actions be without consequence." "180 Kundakunda's self-disciplinary methods like pratikraman are described in detail in Niyamsara. Those are well-tried psychological techniques of self-transformation, which are directly related to the internal purification of the soul. Only when one indulges in selfintrospection and self-analysis and acknowledges one's faults and Page #205 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 179 weaknesses, can one remove those shortcomings and the accumulated evils of the past. There is simply no other way. However, this has to be a continuous process if one really wants to change onself. However, the Kanjipanthi maintain that knowledge of the inactive self is the easy way to liberation of the self from the cycle of births. They are averse to the adoption of means (sadhan) for the purification of the self through the efforts of vyavahara and nishchaya charitra (conduct), which are prescribed in Niyamsara, or the adoption of self-restraints (samyam) and austerities (tapas) described in Pravachanasara (PS 14). In Pravachanasara, knowledge of the reality of things or categories (padartha), including the self and the non-self, samyam (self-restraints) and tapa (austerities), along with detachment and equanimity in pleasure and pain, are significant constituents of pure psychic attention (shuddha upayoga) (PS 14). Psychic activity is stated to be good (shubha) since it leads to accumulation of punya [karma]; if it is evil (ashubha), it leads to accretion of sinful (papa) [karma]. However, in the absence of both psychic attention, there is no accession [of karmas] (PS 156). A person whose psychic-attention (upayoga) is purified (vishuddha) puts an end to all the pain and miseries relating to the body (PS 78). Such pure self or pure consciousness (shuddha atma) is, in fact, devoid of karmas (karma-rahita). It is considered the supreme soul (paramatma) or liberated soul, which can only be attained by efforts of moral selfrestraints and spiritual self-discipline, which have been described in Niyamsara and Pravachanasara. Though Kanjipanthi profess to hold Kundakunda in high esteem and consider themselves to be mumukshu (desirous of moksha), they do not concur or adhere to his prescription of vyavahara and nishchaya charitra (conduct) for attaining the highest objective of human endeavour, i.e. (moksha). They continue to emphasize and harp on the inactive self, whose knowledge, they feel, will liberate one from the cycle of births. In their mistaken one-sided conviction, they do not feel any need to make any efforts in that regard. The only duty/ obligation of the soul (atma) is knowing. This alone, they maintain, is sufficient for the destruction of deluded view as well as conductdeluding attachment and aversion.181 Undue Emphasis on Knowledge as the only Cause of Liberation The only thing, Bharill asserts, that one has to do is to know the self and continue to know it. To know the self is knowledge, while to Page #206 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 180 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES continue to know the self is meditation (dhyan), and that meditation (of self] is conduct (charitra). He maintains that one need not make any other effort or activity whatsoever to destroy karmas. 182 However, he mistakenly believes that one binds punya (karma) by the worship and meditation of the supreme soul (paramatma). The meditation of one's own soul, on the other hand, Bharill says, leads to both the destruction of karmas and delusion (mithyatva). Kanjipanthi also erroneously maintain that whatever good activity (shubha or punya) a person undertakes will only beget him material for sense enjoyments (bhog samagri). This is the inherent nature of pain/misery and the cause of transmigratory existence (sansara). 183 Knowledge of the self is in itself considered to lead to the destruction of karmic bondage and liberation. This belief of the Kanjipanthi sect is similar to that of Shankara - the proponent of Advaita Vedanta - who consistently rejects the view that in addition to knowledge action is also necessary for achieving liberation (jnana karma samuchchayavada). Delusion (mithyatva), i.e. ignorance about the nature of the self, Bharill argues, results from the mistake of regarding punya as desirable or worth acquiring (punya mein upadeya buddhi). This mistake pertains to the nature of reality of things, particularly the soul (tattva sambandhi bhool). According to him, this is a great heinous crime (maha bhayankara papa) which makes one continuously wander in the transmigratory existence (sansara) till he rectifies that mistake. 184 This statement is a gross distortion of Kundakunda's views. Attachment, aversion and deluded-view (mithya darshan, not mithyatva), according to Kundakunda, are the cause of influx and bondage of karmas (SS 177-178) as well as of transmigratory existence (sansara). The various misperceptions and misconceptions entertained by Kanjipanthi regarding good (shubha) and righteousness (punya) have already been discussed earlier. For the destruction of infatuation (moha) and for obtaining or acquiring or acquisition of enlightened world-view, knowledge and conduct, Bharill observes, one has to merely (matra) know the supreme soul (paramatma). Except knowing, he claims, one does not have to do anything else. Paramatma, he argues, is other (para) than self. Nevertheless, as “a consequence of knowing paramatma (arihant] one is able to know one's own soul or self (atma) and he who knows one's Page #207 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 181 own self (atma), his infatuation (moha) perishes”. 185 Bharill adds: Soul's work is only to know (thereby denying or side-tracking all other activities, properties or attributes of soul, including darshan and charitra), to know self (sva) and other (para); therefore only know, know, know and know; know the other, know the self, know the self and other; know self different from other, know and continue to know. Continue to know your own self as own self, continue to know uninterrupted or constantly and nothing else is to be done. By this alone, enlightened world-view, knowledge and conduct all will be accomplished and not only viewdeluding (moha) but conduct-deluding: (moha) [i.e. attachment and aversion) will also be destroyed. You yourself will become (Bhagawan, God) in your present paryaya (condition, state or mode of existence). You are Bhagawan (God) by nature; if you want to be God in your present state (paryaya), then continue to know self in this way . . . you will be omniscient (sarvajna), completely devoid of all attachment (veetragı). In this way, it is determined that for the destruction of infatuation (moha) the only means or way (upaya) is to know one's own bhagawan atma (divine soul), and if one wants to proceed further, one can include in this knowing the nature of God with respect to substance, attribute and mode (dravya-guna-paryaya).186 The above quotation highlights that Bharill not only presents a very perverted argument, which is not only contradictory to what Kundakunda has written but is also against all authentic Jain texts. Let us examine in detail the above statement of Bharill, which is made as a commentary on Pravachanasara verse 80. It may be pointed out that the word “moha" that is used in this verse only refers to viewdeluding moha (darshan moha) and not conduct-deluding moha, comprising of attachment and aversion. This has also been pointed out by Jayasena (PS 80 JS). (Even Bharill is well a'vare of this as he has himself acknowledged it.] 187 The next verse makes this amply clear. It states that even after getting rid of deluding view (moha, mithyadarshan) and properly grasping the reality of the self, if one gives up attachment and aversion, then only one obtains the pure self (PS 81). One must therefore remain fully awake in order to get rid of attachment and aversion (PS 81 AC). It is only in this manner that all the enlightened souls have become emancipated (PS 82). Page #208 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 182 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Earlier verses specifically state that he who understands the reality of things and gets rid of attachment and aversion (raga dvesha) purifies his upayoga (PS 78). Again, if after giving up sinful activities and even getting ready to undertake efforts of good conduct, one does not get rid of infatuation, etc. (mohadi) (i.e. both view-deluding and conductdeluding, attachment and aversion, etc.), then he does not attain the pure self (PS 79). This is because deluded view, attachment and aversion are the cause of bordage of karmas. It is only by renouncing them that one can attain liberation. Since attachment and aversion are part of conduct-deluding moha, one can get rid of them only through undertaking action, conduct, efforts or adoption of means (sadhan) for the purification of the self. Mithyatva is the only Cause of Karmic Bondage? On the other hand, Bharill's mistakenly maintains that delusion (mithyatva) or darshan-moha (deluded-view or mithya darshan), is the cause of karmic bondage “in spiritualism"..(adhyatma). “The agitation or disturbance (gadabad) concerning charitra-moha (conduct-deluding, i.e. attachment and aversion)", he argues, is only external or superficial (upari). This assertion of Bharill is totally mistaken in view of Kundakunda's categorical statement that "attachment and aversion and moha (deluded view) are the soul's own inalienable states, modes, or states-of evolution (ananya parinama)” (SS 371). Bharill also states that “any confusion or disturbance concerning darshan-moha is internal” [i.e. much more serious). 188 in this regard, it is worth noting that in his commentary on Pravachanasara 189, Amrtachandra states that the self is an agent (karta) of its own evolution into psychic dispositions such as attachment, etc. It is therefore the appropriator as well as the renouncer thereof from internal, self-referential nishchaya point of view (PS 189 AC). As a result, it acts as the agent of transforming or purifying the impure mental states into pure mental states. In this sense, the adoption of nishchaya naya is considered the most effective means of achieving the objective of the purity of the self (PS 189 AC). In this context, Jayasena raises the question as to how can nishchaya naya, that speaks of the self as the agent or doer (karta) and enjoyer or experiencer (bhokta) of attachment, etc. mental states, be considered worth acquiring (upadeya)? He answers the question himself Page #209 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 183 by stating that only when the self knows that it is an agent of mencal states like attachment, that these psychic states alone become the cause of bondage, it is only then that the self will contemplate/think of renouncing mental states like attachment. It is only then that the self will become pure (PS 189 JS). Since impure mental states like attachment are the self's own psychic dispositions (SS 371), the self alone has the capacity and the power to get rid of them. Either Bharill apparently does not know or chooses to deliberately refrain from making the distinction between mithyatva and mithyadarshan. Unlike the former, mithya-darshan includes, besides mithyatva, the most intense/tenacious passions like anger (anabtanubhandhi kashaya), which are related to conduct and requires immense effort for its eradication. Since passions (kashaya) characterize evil (ashubha) (PS 158), it is only through subsidence of passions (upasham or prasham), i.e. in the condition or state of shubha (good) that one obtains enlightened view (samyak-darshan) and proceeds further in the direction of self-restraints (samyam) and austerities (tapa), etc. These are the characteristics of pure psychic-attention (shuddha upayoga) (PS 14), leading to pure self (shuddhatma), i.e. liberation. Again, Veer Sagar Jain, a Kanjipanthi adherent/follower, echoing Bharill's above-mentioned mistaken view, states: Mithyatva (delusion) alone is the basic or fundamental cause of all the miseries and sufferings, not anything else . . . Anger, pride etc. passions (kashaya bhava) are not, in fact, the basic malady (mool roga, i.e. basic disease) as they are only the symptoms; the basic malady is delusion alone because it is only due to that jiva considers other objects as favourable or unfavourable, and which gives rise to anger, pride etc. (similar to Bharill's mistaken view that attachment, aversion are extrinsic (symptoms)]... Therefore, just as a skilled physician attends to and treats the real malady, not the (external) symptoms, which are automatically set right, so also with the destruction of delusion, anger, pride, etc. psychic states are automatically, on their own are destroyed. Moreover, the unfailing remedy or the means for the destruction of delusion is ... experiencing of self (atmanubhuti) alone, none else . . . Atmanubhuti is the essence of all the scriptures (sampurna dvadashanga), because the path of liberation, begins only with that, undergoes development or growth thereby and also reaches its completion thereby, i.e. leads to liberation. 189 [In this easy path of liberation, there is no mention of adopting any means of self-restrains and austerities, etc.) Page #210 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 184 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Samvara and Nirjara are Essential for Liberation The path of liberation or the destruction of karmas, including deluding karma, consists of the prevention of the influx of new karma (samvara) and the shedding off previously accumulated karma (nirjara). The solution to the problem of karma is based on the strategies of samvara and nirjara. The two have been analyzed in terms of both the [external) physical processes (dravya) and the psychology of bhava (intention), which is considered primary and of much greater significance. That the accomplishment of any task or deed is contingent on the coordination of both internal and external causes [the intrinsic cause is regarded as primary and substantive cause, while the extrinsic cause is considered as secondary, supportive, or auxiliary cause) is said to be in the very nature of things (dravyagatah svabhavah)” (Samantabhadra, Svayambhu Stotra, verse 60). Kundakunda's scheme of vyavahara self-restraints consist of samiti, gupti, etc. (samyam) and nishchaya self-disciplinary activities consist of pratikraman, etc., also called tapas. These have been described in Niyamsara and have been discussed above. They are real psychological practices concerning the prevention of the influx of new karma (samvara) and the shedding off of previously accumulated karma (nirjara), which is essential for attaining liberation (moksha). The samyam, tapas, and equanimity mentioned in Pravachanasara 14 are in fact, samvara and nirjara. They are considered to be important constituent parts of pure psychic-attention (shuddha upayoga), which alone is said to be the only refuge (sharan) for human beings (PS 78 AC). The discussion of samvara focuses upon limiting and controlling one's behaviour in accordance with the goal of attaining a state of total (self-restraints or] equanimity (samyam) in order to reduce and ultimately stop the influx of new karma. This is to be done through observances such as the three restraints (gupti) and the five selfregulations (samiti). However, the discussion of nirjara focuses “upon conscious ... activities (tapas) designed to scrub off karma that is already binding the soul”. 190 Bharill's contention that attaining godhood does not require anything beyond knowing one's own self and continuing to know that, goes against the age-old wisdom: “It is only by effort that any task or work is accomplished, not by mental wish or desire, just as the deers Page #211 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 185 do not enter the mouth of the sleeping lion.” The lion has to make efforts to catch the deer. “The only place,” as Donald Kendall states, where success comes before work is in the dictionary.191 Empirically speaking, moksha is krta-sadhya, 'what is yet to be”; what is yet to be accomplished through man's knowledge, will, and effort. To bring the desired objective (moksha liberation is the highest objective to be attained) into existence or to realize it involves will or effort; value arises therefore by the conscious effort we make to realize it, and realizing it means overcoming the obstacles to its realization. 192 In the introductory verse to Tattvartha Sutra, the worthy Lord is said to be “the destroyer of the mountains of karmas” (bhettaram karma bhubhratam), and the destruction of karmas is not an easy task; it requires great deal of effort. In spite of what is stated above, Bharill still persists in his mistaken view that the one and only one (eka matra) means (upaya) of attaining liberation, of being happy, of getting rid of transmigratory existence (samsara), and of putting an end to the psychic states or modes of infatuation (moha), attachment and aversion, is the path comprising of the method, technique or the process (prakriya) of knowledge of the self (atmajnana) and meditation of the self (atma-dhyana) alone. 193 In support of this mistaken view, Bharill does not hesitate to distort the important concepts of pure psychic-attention (shuddha upayoga), meditation (dhyana), conduct (charitra), etc., given in Jain texts, including Kundakunda's works. Although it may be said that he who knows Arahant (the worthy Lord) with reference to substance, qualities and modes, knows the self (atma). This can be considered as (one of the] the means for the destruction of deluding-view (PS 80). However, to argue that it is the sole method for the destruction of conduct-deluding attachment and aversion is totally incorrect. In fact, Amrtachandra states, that the verse emphasizes that after attaining enlightened view, one must eradicate attachment and aversion in order to realize the pure self lest the soul be robbed of the valuable enlightened world-view due to negligence (pramad). Therefore, one must be fully awake, in order to get rid of attachment and aversion (PS 81 AC), which is possible only through the conduct of self-restraints (samyam) and austerities (tapas) which are the characteristics of pure psychic-attention (shuddha upayoga) (PS 14), and the means of attaining the pure self (shuddhatma). Page #212 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 186 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Kanji's Distortion of Pure Psychic-attention Bharill, however, distorts the meanings of shuddhatma and conduct, etc. when he tries to prove that the method to get rid of attachment and aversion is “experiencing of pure self” (shuddha atmanubhuti) or/ and meditation of self (atma dhyana). Conduct, he adds, “completely devoid of attachment (veetraga) is of the nature of experiencing of the pure self”. This is “restrictive or obstructive (pratibandhak) of attachment and aversion, thereby getting rid of them.194 He seems to rely upon Kanji Svami's interpretation of Pravachanasara verse 14 that “pure psychic-attention (shuddha upayoga) is attention-oriented towards the nature of self, moving away from good and evil (punya and papa)”, and that “stability or constancy (sthirata) in the nature of self is austerity (tapa)."195 Kanji is deliberately distorting the meanings of pure psychic-attention and austerity (tapa). The twelve kinds of external and internal austerities are referred by Jayasena (PS 14 JS) and are described in detail in Jain texts, including Tattvartha Sutra.196 Kundakunda has also explained austerities (tapa) both from an external, other-referential (vyavahara) point of view and internal, self-referential (nishchaya) point of view in detail in Niyamsara (NS 56-70 and 77-158), which are also said to be vyavahara and nishchaya conduct. 197 The concept of pure psychic-attention (shuddha upayoga) is described in clear terms in these words: “A shramana is called a man of pure psychic-attention, when he knows well the categories (padarthas), [including self and non-self, and their interaction), and the sutras (the scriptures) (for the definition of Sutra, see PS 34] which explain them, when he possesses self-restraint (samyam) and practices austerities (tapas), gives up attachment and considers pleasure and pain the same (sama)” (PS 14). Bharill's description of meditation of the self (atma dhyana), which is said to be the method and path of getting rid of attachment and aversion and attaining liberation, viz. “knowing and continuing to know the self”198 is also a distortion of what Kundakunda has written. Kundakunda states: “He, who observes rules of self-restraint, niyam and austerities, and meditates on his true self through virtuous concentration (dharma-dhyana) and pure concentration (shukla dhyana), (is said) to have supreme equanimity (param samadhi)” (NS 123). This cannot be divorced from atma-dhyana. Virtuous and pure Page #213 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 187 concentrations or meditations (dhyana) are described in Tattvartha Sutra and other Jaina texts."99 Thus, Bharill seeks to present an easy way or soft option to people of knowing and inaction, which has no basis whatsoever in Jaina texts, including the works of Kundakunda by propagating certain myths. These include his presentation of atma jnana (knowledge of self), without the knowledge of the non-self and other derivative categories that are resultant categories due to the interaction of the self and nonself, without the firm conviction of the reality of the nature of the nine categories, including punya and papa. A second myth is his socalled atma dhyana (meditation of self) of the nature of continuing to know the self, and atmanubhava, shuddhatmanubhuti, atmasakshatkara, etc. A third myth is the concept of shuddha upayoga advocated by the Kanjipanthi. The three are mere myths which are ingenious inventions meant to confuse people, distract their attention from the true path of sadhana (adoption of proper means) of self-restraints (samyam), etc. for purification and liberation. Bharill's intention is to present an easy way or soft option of knowing and inaction, which has no basis whatsoever in Jaina texts, including the works of Kundakunda. Bharill's atma jnana is not the atma jnana that Pravachanasara speaks of. Atma jnana (self-knowledge or knowledge of self), according to Pravachanasara, is only possible when it is simultaneously accompanied by knowledge of the Scriptures, faith or conviction in principles or categories of jiva, ajiva, etc. and self-restraint (sanyat or samyam) (as described in PS 240) (PS 240 AC). Similiarly, the pure psychic-attention (shuddha upayoga), which can lead to salvation, discussed by either Bharill or Kanji Swami is different from what has been described, defined and explained in Pravachanasara (verse 14). Moreover, Bharill's so-called atma dhyana (self-meditation) is neither the virtuous meditation (dharma dhyana) nor the pure meditation (shukla dhyana) of Jain scriptures, including Tattvartha Sutra. It is also not simiiar to Kundakunda's supreme equanimity or mental concentration (param samadhi), which has been described in Niyamsara (verse 123). To support his mistaken view regarding getting rid of attachment and aversion, Bharill also cites Jayasena's commentary of Pravachanasara verse 81. This verse describes conduct-deluding attachment and aversion as restrictivelobstructive of conduct which is completely Page #214 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 188 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES devoid of attachment (veetraga charitra) having the characteristic of experiencing pure self (PS 81 JS). However, Bharill deliberately omits the most crucial qualifying conditional word “if in Kundakunda's original text “(jahadi jadi in Pk. and jahati yadi in Sk.) and Jayasena's words “yadi tyajati”. In other words, one acquires or obtains the pure self (appanam lahadi suddham, PS 81) and then and only then does he becomes liberated if he gives up attachment and aversion (PS 81 JS). In this regard, Bharill also refers to Jayasena's observation that "abheda ratnatrya parinata jiva," i.e. the soul evolved as identity of enlightened view, knowledge and conduct obtains pure self and becomes liberated (PS 81 JS). He adds: [The soul] “does not attain liberation through' bheda ratnatrya,' i.e. the three – enlightened view, knowledge and conduct together.”200 This addition is conspicuous by its absence in Jayasena's commentary and is against statements of both Amrtachandra and Jayasena that they as well as identity of them, i.e. both bheda and abheda, i.e. three and one (identity/unity thereof) or vyavahara and nishchaya conduct constitute the path of liberation (PS 242 AC and PS 242 JS). The method of getting rid of attachment and aversion, is only through self-restraints and austerities as discussed in Kundakunda's works (NS 56-158, PS 14, 240's etc.) and other Jain texts. As for Bharill's observation that except for knowing the self, nothing else is to be done and that by harping on the inactive self (akarta) one can attain godhood, it may be said that action is the insignia of life. As long as one lives one must act. “None can ever remain inactive even for a moment" (Gita 3.5); action is superior to inaction and even the maintenance of one's body would not be possible by inaction (Gita 3.8); and that one cannot attain perfection by mere renunciation of action (Gita 3.4). If we remain ignorant of the real nature of the self, we will undoubtedly be inclined to perform activities (of mind, speech and body) in bondage to body consciousness (the self is body alone), and in accordance with our instinctive impulses of fear, sexual desire, mere satisfaction of sensual pleasures, passions like anger, pride, and greed, delusion and non-restraint. Therefore, ascertainment and knowledge of the reality of things or categories (padarthas), including the real nature of the self, is a necessary first step. However, that alone does not suffice for attaining godhood or liberation. Page #215 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 189 It is also essential to know the psycho-physical nexus and interaction, including the fact that the bondage of various karmas takes place because of infatuation (moha), attachment and aversion with reference to other objects (PS 243). By getting rid of these impurities, one invariably destroys various karmas (PS 244). To that end, one has to adopt means (sadhan) and undertake efforts for the purification (vishuddhi) of the self through self-restraints (samyam) and austerities (tapas) (PS 14), as well as five self-regulations (samiti), three selfrestraints of mind, speech and body (gupti), control of senses and conquering passions like anger, pride, and greed (kashaya) (PS 240). When the soul cannot remain without doing something, if it does not consciously undertake dispassionate action in the direction of selfrestraint (samyam) and austerities (tapas), along with detachment and equanimity (shuddha upayoga) or sanity and purification (vishuddhi), i.e. shubha upayoga (PS 155, 156, 180 AC, PS 259, 260 and 259260 AC), its activities will be based on instinctive impulses and subconscious motivations. As a result, the self slides into unrestrained behaviour of sense-gratification and anger, etc. passions (vishaya kashaya), i.e. the evil conscious action (ashubha upayoga) (PS 257, 258). Active and Evolvent Aspect of the Self The essential nature of the soul, according to Kundakunda, is consciousness (chetana). It is characterised by upayoga (PKS 16, 27, PS 127), which represents the active, functional and evolvent (parinami) aspect of the self. The self, he points out, possesses the nature of that through which it evolves during the time of the evolution (PS 8). In other words, it accepts the character of its state-of-evolution. When the soul evolves through the good or the evil, it becomes good or evil. And when it evolves through the pure, it becomes pure (PS 9). If the soul is not considered to be evolvent (parinami, changeable) in nature, or if it is described as unchangeable, the soul, which is associated with karma since beginningless time, will not be able to get rid of the karmas and become pure self (shuddhatma) or pure consciousness, i.e. liberated soul. Only the liberated soul (siddha state of the soul) is said to be krta krtya, i.e. he has accomplished all that needs to be accomplished and no longer needs to do anything else. While consciousness-as-such (parinamika bhava) is the fundamental reality of the being, pure consciousness of the soul or self (shuddhatma Page #216 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 190 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES or Paramatma) is becoming, i.e. an effectual reality thereof. This being is not separate from the becoming but present in it. That being and becoming are not mutually incompatible but necessarily concomitant of one another is possible only when we accept the fundamental reality of the self as a dynamic or evolvent eternal reality (parinami nitya). It is something stable in the midst of its changes, a being in becoming, or persisting through its modes, i.e. one characterized by both continuity and change, as Jainism states. In this context, H.M. Bhattacharya observes: A conscious reality is never divorced from its own conscious modifications and qualities in which lies its very life... A parinama (state-of-evolution] or modification issuing from the parinami (the evolvent being) or the modifying, and yet not in essential relation with the parinami, is as false an abstraction as the aparinami (unchanging) or im:nutable real without any parinama or modification.201 The evolutionary characteristic or atman of the being (consciousness-as-such) forms the background or the substratum of changes of the states or modes of consciousness. It is devoid of any relational modes and relative aspects of karmas (karma nirpeksha), i.e. neither pure nor impure. This makes possible the evolution of the jiva or the empirical soul or the self, which is impure due to karmic bondage since beginningless time, becoming pure consciousness (shuddhatma). The Sankhya system of philosophy and Advaita Vedanta uphold the concept of the eternal self as an unevolving, unchanging or unmodifying (aparinami) and “pure". If one endorses this argument, the question arises that if the nature of the self (being) is held to be unchanging and “pure”, how and when does it initially come into contact with the karmas and become impure and how the soul, associated with karmas since beginningless time, become pure? There are people who mistakenly hold that Kundakunda's works, including Pravachanasara are meant only for ascetics. This is belied by what we have discussed above and by the frequent references to sagara (persons with homes) and anagara (those without homes) (see PS 250, 251, 254 and 275) and by the characteristics of samanas described in Pravachanasara. That Pravachanasara is written and meant as much for both householders and ascetics is clearly stated by Kundakunda in the concluding verse (PS 275), which observes: “He, who, practicing the conduct of householders or the homeless, Page #217 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION [properly] understands this scripture [entitled Pravachanasara], acquires the essence (sara) of the Divine Discourse(s) (pavayana in Pk. Pravachana in Sk.)." He, thus, understands the real nature of the reality of things, including the self (never before experienced). The self persists throughout the endless stream of the three times (past, present t and future) and is the foremost among all substances. It realizes the noble objective for living beings, viz. the supreme state of the self (bhagwanta atma), which is endowed with the nature of the self-intuiting divine knowledge and bliss (PS 275 AC). NOTES 191 1 R.G. Bhandarkar, Report on the Search for Sanskrit Manuscripts (MSS), 1883-84, P. 91. Peterson, Report for 1983-1984, P. 80. This is the conclusion that A.N. Upadhye reaches after a long survey of the available material and detailed examination of the views of different scholars on the subject of Kundakunda's date. See A.N. Upadhye, Sri Kundakundacharya's Pravachanasara (Agas, Gujarat: Paramshruta Prabhavak Mandal, 1984), Introduction, pp. 10-23. Pravachanasara was first published before 1935. 4 Upadhye, n. 3, P. 49. 5 Ibid., P. 48. 6 See H.C. Bharill's article in Darshan, Jnana Charitra (Delhi), August 2008, p. 15. 7 Upadhye, n. 3, p. 49. 8 2 3 9 Ibid., PP: 49-50. Upadhye observes: "My tentative conjecture is that Amrtachandra was too spiritualistic to enter into sectarian polemics; and possibly he wanted to make his commentary along with it the sublime utterances of Kundakunda, acceptable to all the sects by eliminating the glaring and acute sectarian attacks." However, it seems that he has no objection to the phrase "jatha-jada-ruva" (yatha jatarupa in Sk.) or the natural form as of a child on birth (nudity) of a monk (PS 204-206 and 225). The phrase is also mentioned in the Shvetambara text Uttradhyayan Sutra 22 and 34. See Upadhye, n. 3, pp. 51, 52 and footnote 5 on p. 51. The only comparable references to this topic, raised in these 11 additional verses of third group, which Upadhye could cite are from "Ashtaprabhrata or Ashta-pahuda," ("Eight Presents"). This is also generally attributed to Kundakunda, though W. Denecke doubts Kundakunda's authorship. Dialectically, he finds that six pahudas are earlier than Page #218 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 192 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Samayasara, etc. The presence of Apabhramsa in these pahuds is cited as the reason. While other works of Kundakunda has thematic unity, this work (Ashta-pahuda) is of compilatory character. It is clear from the contents that each pahuda is meant to be an independent treatise. There are several other factors in regard to Ashta-pahuda to which A.N. Upadhye has also drawn our attention. In some of them like Charitra (Conduct) Pahuda and Bodha (Enlightenment) Pahuda, the exposition of the subject matter is very systematic, while in others like Sutta (Scripture) and Bhava (Psychic State or Disposition) Pahuda: appear to be merely compiled that is why perhaps the ascetic emblem prescribed for women is included in Sutta-pahuda. Bhava-pahuda contains legendary references and its contents are extensively varied (Upadhye, n. 3, pp. 34-35). The other four pahudas are Darshan (view, attitude or conviction), Moksha (Salvation), Linga (Insignia) and Sheel (Morality) pahudas. Linga-pahuda discusses the issue of dravya-linga (a monk having mere external appearance) and bhavalinga (having immaculate psychic dispositions), while Sheel-pahuda is particularly concerned with chastity aspect. The first six of these pahuds (shat-pahuda), grouped together as an independent work, is commented upon in Sanskrit by Shrutasagar. His commentary is very dogmatic in nature containing severe criticism of other religions reflecting religious intolerance with the result that the editor of this work was compelled to remove such references. See Saubhagyamal Jain Ranvka, ed. Shat-prabhratam (Shat-pahuda) together with Sanskrit commentary by Shrutasagar, Hindi translation by Aryika Suparshvamati (Jaipur: Shanti-devi Badjatya, Gauhati, 1983), Do Shabda by editor, p. 19. Upadhye opines that it is imaginable that "traditionally compiled texts might be attributed to Kundakunda because of his literary reputation". However, he is reluctant "to cancel the current tradition" that Kundakunda be accepted as the author of these pahudas. Upadhye, n. 3, p. 35. Siddhasen Divakar, on the other hand, was frank enough to tell King Vikramaditya that he would not support the traditions which had been established by our ancestors and which had passed the test of time, unless they held true on examination. He observes: "I am not here to justify it for the sake of saving the traditional grace of the dead irrespective of the wrath I may have to face." Cited in Jagdish Prasad Jain, Fundamentals of Jainism (New Delhi: Radiant Publishers, 2005), pp. 297-298. Since most of verses in Ashta-pahuda are significant and add to our understanding of various moral and other issues, we are not opposed to Page #219 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 193 14 that work being considered to be a work of Kundakunda. However, one must be cautious about both unnecessary additions/interpolations as well as misinterpretarions/distortions of Kundakunda's ideas in the commentaries of the works attributed to Kundakunda. Ahimsa Mandir Prakashan, Samayasara (New Delhi: Ahimsa Mandir, 1959), Introduction by A.N.Upadhye, English Translation of text by Rajkrishna Jain, p. 1. 11 Ibid., p. 2. Ibid., p.1. Ibid., p.2. See Jagdish Prasad Jain, The Art and Science of Self-Realization. Purushartha Siddhhyupaya of Amrtachandra Suri (New Delhi: Radiant Publishers, 2007), p. 26. 15 Upadhye, n. 3, p. 50. 16 Ibid., pp. 51-52. 17. Ibid., p. 48. 18 The concept of nirvana is discussed in detail by Kundakunda in his work Niyamsara. See Jagdish Prasad Jain, Salvation through Self-discipline: Niyamsara of Kundakunda (New Delhi: Radiant Publishers, 2005), verses 179-183. 19 See Fundamentals of Jainism, n. 9, pp. 201-202. 20 See Monier Williams, Sanskrit English Dictionary (Delhi: Motilal Banarasidass, 1999), pp. 1082 and 310. 21 Jiva nikaya consists of six kinds of jivas (the five classes of earth-bodied, etc. one-sensed (immobile) (sthavara) jivas and the mobile (trasa) jivas (living beings), having two to five senses, as also body, mind, etc., which includes animals and human beings. We also know that in Jain texts, both Digambara and Shvetambara there are no other jiva(s), other than the six classes of jiva, except liberated souls and it is these jiva-nikaya, none else, that are embodied and transmigrate in the world or are liberated. The liberated souls are different from them, but they are not meant here. If it were so, Kundakunda himself would have mentioned it or the commentators would have referred to it. 22 See Sanskrit-English Dictionary, n. 20. 23 Upadhye, n. 3, p. 390. 24 W.J. Johnson, Harmless Souls (New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1995), pp. 97-100. J.L. Jaini, ed. , Tattvartha Sutra by Umasvami (Delhi: Barrister Champat Rai Jain Trust, 1956), p. 39; Sarvarthsiddhi commentary on Tattvartha Sutra by Pujyapada, see S.A. Jain, Reality (Madras: Jvalamalini Trust, 25 Page #220 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 194 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 26 SAA 1992), p. 55; and Tatia, Nathmal, That Which Is translation of Tattvartha Sutra (San Francisco: Harper Collins, 1994), p. 39. See A. Chakravartinayanar, Panchastikayasara: The Building of the Cosmos (New Delhi: Bharatiya Jnanapitha, 1975), pp. 12, 20 and xxviii. 27 See J.L. Jaini, The Sacred Books of the Jainas, Vol. VIII, Samayasara by Kundakunda Acharya (New Delhi: Today & Tomorrow Printers & Publishers, 1990); A. Chakravarti, Samayasara of Kundakunda (New Delhi: Bharatiya Jnanapitha, 1971); and J.S. Zaveri, Samayasara by Acharya Kundakunda (Ladnun: Jain Vishva Bharati University, 2009). 28 Indra Chandra Shastri, Jaina Epistemology (Varanasi: P.V. Research Institute, 1990), pp. 142-143. 29 See J.L. Jaini, tr., The Sacred Books of the Jainas, Vol V: Gommatsara Jiva Kanda (The Soul) (GSJK), by Nemichandra Siddhanta Chakravarti (Lucknow: Central Jaina Publishing House, 1927), Introduction, pp. 38-39. 30 Harmless Souls, n. 24, pp. 97-98. 31 Ibid., pp. 98-99. 32 Ibid., pp. 99-100. 33 Ibid., p. 100. 34 Ibid, pp. 100-101. 35 See Jagdish P. Jain, “Jaina Psychology," in K. Ramakrishna Rao, et al, ed., Handbook of Indian Psychology (New Delhi: Cambridge University Press under the imprint of Foundation Books, 2008), pp. 57-74. David Michie, “Test Cricket and Mindfulness," Times of India, 11 August 2011. 37 Hacker Andrew, Political Theory: Philosophy, Ideology Science (Toronto: The Macmillan Company, 1969), pp. 6-7 and 20. 38 Kamal Chand Sogani, “Ethical Philosophy of Kundakunda,” in Pandit Bechardas, Doshi Smrti Granth, edited by Madhusudan Dhaky and Sagar Mal Jain (Varanasi: Parsvanath Vidhyashram Shodha Sansthan, 1987), pp. 7-8. 39 See Kanaknandi, Punya Papa Mimansa (Baraut, Meerut: Dharma Darshan Vijnana Shodha Prakashan, 1992), pp. 5 and p. X. 40 Pujyapada's Sarvarthasiddhi (SAS) commentary on Tattvartha Sutra (TS) 6.3, translation mine. 41 See Akalankadeva, Tattvartha-Vartika (Rajavartika (also called Tattvartha Rajvartika (TRV), commentary on Tattvartha Sutra 6.3 (New Delhi: Bharatiya Jnanapitha, 1993), on TS 6.3, translation mine. 42 Cited in Punya Papa Mimansa, n. 39, p. 10. 43 Tattvartha Rajvartika , n. 41, pp. 507-508. Page #221 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 195 44 Tattvartha Shloka Vartika (TSV) commentary on TS 5.16, Commentator Manakchand Kaundeya, ed. and published by Pandit Vardhaman Parshvanath Shastri (Sholapur, 1969), Vol. 6, p. 439. 45 Ibid., p. 440. 46 Nagin Shah's commentary on Samantabhadra's Apta-Mimansa (AM): Critique of an Authority, translated by Nagin Shah (Ahmedabad: Jagruti Dilip Sheth, 1999), p. 83. 47 Samantbhadra. Devavgam aparnama Apta-Mimansa, translated by Jugal Kishore Mukhtar (Delhi: Veer Sewa Mandir Trust, 1967), p. 98. Translation mine. 48 Tattvartha Shloka Vartika commentary on TS 6.3, See n. 44, p. 443. 49 Cited in Economic Times, 19 August 2009. 50 C.R. Jain, Jaina Psychology (Allahabad, 1929), p. 13. 51 Todarmal, Mokshamark Prakashak (MMP), edited by Parmananda Shastri (Delhi: Sasti Granthmala Karyala ya, Veer Sewa Mandir, 1950), pp. 301302 (published 16 years befo 'e this work was first published by Kanjipanthi from Sonagarh in 1966). 52 Ibid., p. 301. 53 Ibid., pp. 332-333. 54 Ibid., p. 301. 55 Ibid. 56 Ibid., pp. 301-302. 57 Ibid., p. 302. 58 Ibid. 59 Ibid., p. 303 and 305. 60 Ibid., p. 302. 61 Ibid., pp. 302-303 and 305. 62 Ibid., pp. 313-314 and 305-306. 63 Ibid., pp. 305-306. 64 Hukum Chand Bharill, Pravachanasara Anushilan, Vol 1 (Jaipur: Pandit Todarmal Smarak Trust, 2005), p. 312. 65 Ibid., pp. 331 and 334. 66 Ibid., p. 343. 67 Ibid., p. 301. 68 Moksha Marg Prakashak, n. 51, pp. 301-302. 69 Bharill, n. 64, p. 328. 70 Bharill's talk on Zee Zagran TV, 11 July 2010. 71 Bharill, n. 64, p. 340. 72 Ibid., p. 299. 73 Kanji Svami, Divyadvanisara, p. 142, cited in ibid., p. 306. Page #222 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 196 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 74 Ibid., p. 317. 75 Kanji, n. 73, p. 159, cited in ibid., p. 321. 76 Ibid., p. 301. 77. Ibid. 78 Kanji, n. 73, p. 155, cited in ibid., p. 318. 79 Ibid., p. 301. 80 Kanji, n. 73, p. 158, cited in ibid., p. 321. 81 Ibid. 82 See also detailed discussion on compassion in this Introduction. 83 Bharill's talk on Zee Zagran TV, 15 July 2010. 84 Bharill, n. 64, p. 336. 85 Bharill, n. 83. 86 See K. Vijayaraghavan, “Twice blest and sublime virtues," Economic Times, 29 June 2009. 87 Ibid. 88 K. Vijayaraghavan, “Spare a thought for the less fortunate,” Economic Times, 6 July 2009. 89 See Ibid., 29 June 2009. 90 See Samantabhadra, Svayambhu Stotra, translated by Jugal Kishore Mukhtar (Saharanpur, 1951), p. 81 footnote. 91 Samantabhadra, Svayambhu Stotra, Verse 119. See D.K. Goyal, The Path to Enlightenment: Svyambhu Stotra of Samantabhadra (New Delhi: Radiant Publishers, 2000), p. 182. 92 See also Jagdish Prasad Jain, ed., The Enlightened Vision of the Self. Svarupa Sambodhana of Akalanka (New Delhi: Radiant Publishers, 2005), Foreword, pp. 57-58. 93 See Br. Hem Chand Jain, “Omniscience,” in International School for Jain Studies, Study Notes, V.2.0 (New Delhi, 2008), p. 312. For a critical appraisal of krama-baddha paryaya, see Jagdish Prasad Jain, ed., Jain Dharma: Vyakti-svatantrya aur Svavalambana ka Dharma (Krambaddharupi Ekanta-niyativada) (New Delhi: Jain Mission, 2005). See also Jagdish Prasad Jain, ed., Jo jo Dekhi Veetraga ne, so so hosi Veera re athava hoi hai vahi jo Ram rachi rakha; Sarvajnata aur Niyativada (New Delhi: Jain Mission, 2005). 94 Upadhye, n. 3, pp. 76-77 and footnote 1. 95 Hari Mohan Bhattacharya, “Essentials of Jaina Metaphysics and Epistemology," in Nalin K. Shastri, ed., Namami (Tijara/Alwar, Rajasthan: Shri 1008 Chandraprabha Digambara Atishaya Kshetra, Dehra, Tijara, 2005), pp. 316-317. 96 Jaina Epistemology, n. 28, p. 174. Page #223 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 97 Ibid., p. 150. 98 See The Jaina Antiquary (Arrah), June 1939, pp. 24-25. Cited in The Enlightened Vision of the Self, n. 92, p. 17. 99 Prameya Kamai Martanda, pp. 25-26 and Pramana/Mimansa, Cited in Ibid., p. 15. 100 Nathmal Tatia, cited in ibid., P. 16 197 P. 49. 101 See ibid., p. 5. 102 See Reality, n. 25, pp. 156-157. 103 Malvania, Dalsukh, Agam yug ka Jain Darshan (AJD) (Jaipur: Prakrit Bharati Academy, 1990), p. 239. 104 Harilal Jain, Atma Prasiddhi. Kanjiswami's Discourses on 47 Spiritual Qualities of Soul, translated by Maganlal Jain (Agra: Shri Kundakunda Kahan Granthamala, 1994), p. 33. 105 See Reality, n. 25, p. 166. 106 See The Enlightened Vision of the Self, n. 92, Appendix 1, P. 93. 107 Kalipada Mitra, "The Jaina Theory of Existence and Reality," Indian Culture (Calcutta, 1939), pp. 322-323. 114 Dravya-drishti Prakash, n. 111, p. 202. 115 Cited in The Enlightened Vision of the Self, n. 92, p. 15. 116 See ibid., p. 16. 117 See ibid., p. 17. 118 Ibid. 108 Chakravartinayanara, n. 26, p. 92. 109 Siddhasena, Sanmatisutra, ch. 1, Verse 12, cited in The Enlightened Vision of the Self n. 92, Appendix 1, P. 91. 110 Nagardas B. Modi, et al, compiled, Dravyadrashti Jineshwar: Kanjiswami's Discourses, translated by Maganlal Jain (Bambai: Shardaben Shantilal Shahpariwar, 1996), p. 48. 111 Ramesh Chandra Sogani, ed., Dravya-drashti Prakash (Bhavanagar: Veetrag Sat-sahitya Prasarak Trust, 2004), Bole 586, p. 200. 112 Ibid., p. 204. very 113 Dravya-drishti Jineshwar, n. 110, P. 2 and quote of Kanji in the beginning of the book 119 Cited in ibid., P. 38. 120 Dravya-drashti Prakash, n. 111, p. 202. 121 Ibid., p. 204. 122 Dravya-drashti Jineshwar, n. 110, p. 48. 123 The Merriams-Webster Pocket Dictionary of Synonyms (New York: Pocket Books, 1972), pp. 270, 84, 51, 90, 352. 124 J.R. Searle, Mind: A Brief Introduction (New York: Oxford University Page #224 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 198 Press, 2004), p. 207. 125 Cited in W.E. Craighead and C.B. Numeroff, eds., The Corsini Encyclopaedia of Psychology and Behavioural Science, 3rd ed., vol. 1 (New York: John Wiley and Sons, 2001), p. 357. For a detailed discussion on mind-body interaction, see also Fundamentals of Jainism, n. 9, pp. 24-41. 126 See Chakravarti, n. 27, P. 54. 127 Fundamentals of Jainism, n. 9, 128 See Jain, n. 35. 129 See ibid. 130 The Path of Enlightenment: Svambhu Stotra of Samantabhadra, n. 91, Verse 60. P. 404. THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 131 Amrtachandrasuri, Laghu Tattva Sphota, ed. by Padmanabha S. Jaini (Ahmedabad: L.D. Institute of Indology, 1978), Verse 391, p. 133. 132 Harmless Souls, n. 24, pp. 142, 146, 154 and 159. 133 Ibid., pp. 48-49. 134 Upadhye, n. 3, PP. 40-41. 135 Harmless Souls, n. 24, pp. 46-47. 136 Reality, n. 26, p. 197. 137 Harmless Souls, n. 24, p. 197. 138 Reality, n. 25, p. 197. 139 Translation mine, based on Nathmal Tatia, That Which Is: tr. of Tattvartha Sutra, n. 25, pp. 169 and 156; Reality, n. 25 and original Sarvartha siddhi 140 See Akalankadeva, TRV commentary on TS 6.3, n. 41, translation mine. 141 Siddhasena, Dvatrinshika, 3.16, cited in Fundamentals of Jainism, n. 9, P. 160. 142 Cited in ibid., p. 160. 143 Nyayavijaya, Muni, cited in ibid., pp. 160-161. 144 Harmless Souls, n. 24, p. 157. 145 Ibid., p. 52. 146 Ibid., p. 157 and 48-49. 147 Y.K. Mishra, Asceticism in Ancient India (Vaishali: Research Institute of Praktit, Jainology & Ahimsa, 1987), pp. 18, 30, 37, and 65. 148 Ibid., p. 34. 149 Upadhye, n. 3, preface. 150 Mishra, n. 147, pp. 18 and 15. 151 Ibid., P. 65. 152 Ibid., P. 35. 153 Ibid., p. 36. 154 Acharang Sutra, 1.9.1. Page #225 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION 199 155 Harmless Souls, n. 24, p. 223. 156 For details, see Salvation through Self-discipline. Niyamsara of Kundakunda, n. 18. 157 See also Mishra, n. 147, p.6. 158 Ibid., p. 7. 159 For details, see Salvation through Self-discipline, n. 18. 160 Acharya Mahaprajna, "Spiritual Solution to economic problems," Economic Times (New Delhi), 20 April 2009. 161 Harmless Souls, n. 24, p. 27. 162 Ibid., introduction, p. 1. 163 For details, see Salvation through Self-discipline, n. 18. 164 Harmless Souls, n. 24, p. 165. 165 Ibid., p. 184. 166 Paul Dundas, “The Laicisation of the Bondless Doctrine: A New Study of the a Development of Early Jainism, A Review of W.J. Johnson Harmless Souls,” Journal of Indian Philosophy, Vol. 25(5), October 1997, p. 502. 167 Harmless Souls, n. 24, p. 223. 168 Ibid. 169 Ibid., p. 223. 170 Dundas, n. 166, pp. 502-503. 171 Bharill, n. 64, pp. 41 and 39. 172 K. Ramakrishna Rao, Consciousnes Studies: Crow Cultural Perspectives (North Carolina: McFarland & Co., 2005), p. 205 and 201: 173 Harold G. Coward, “Psychology and Karma,” Philosophy East and West, 33:1(January 1983), p. 54. 174 Johannes Bronkhorst, “The Boddha and the Jainas Reconsidered," in N. K. Wagle and Olle Quarnstrom, eds., Approaches to Jaina Studies. Philosophy, Logic, Ritual and Symbols (Ontario: The Centre for South Asian Studies, University of Toronto, 1999), pp. 87-88. 175 Ibid., p. 89. 176 Ibid. 177 Ibid. 178 See Hem Chand Jain, n. 93. 179 See Jagdish Prasad Jain, n. 93. 180 John E. Cort, "Fistfights in the Monastery: Calendars, Conflict and Karma among the Jains," in Approaches to Jaina Studies, n. 174, p. 37. 181 Bharill, n. 64, pp. 373 and 364. 182 H.C. Bharill's TV Talk on Zee Zagran, 14 June 2010. 183 Ibid. Page #226 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 200 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 184 Bharill, n. 64, p. 336. 185 Ibid., p. 375. 186 Ibid. 187 Ibid., p. 380. 188 Bharill's TV Talk on Zee Zagran, 15 July 2010. 189 See Veer Sagar Jain," America mein hui adhyatma ki sukshma charcha," in Shruta Samvardhini (Lucknow), December 2009, pp. 9-10. 190 Cort, n. 180, pp. 48-49. 191 Span (New Delhi), July-August 2010, p. 16. 192 N.A. Nikam, “Some Basic Concepts of Indian Culture," in Krishna Roy and Chhanda Gupta, Essays in Social and Political Philosophy (New Delhi: Indian Council for Philosophical Research, 1983), pp. 199 and 196. 193 H.C. Bharill, Samayasara ka Sara, p. 104, cited in Bharill, n. 64, p. 378. 194 Ibid., p. 381. 195 Cited in ibid., pp. 81-82. 196 For a detailed discussion in the matter, see Fundamentals of Jainism, n. 9. 197 For a detailed discussion on this subject, see Salvation through Self discipline, n. 18. 198 Bharill's TV Talk, 14 June 2010. 199 For detailed discussion in the matter, see Fundamentals of Jainism, n. 9. 200 Bharill, n. 64, p. 381. 201 See The Enlightened Vision of the Self, n. 92, p. 39. Page #227 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Translator's Preface I owe great thanks to Professor (F.W.] Thomas for having helped me with the English idiom of the translation. When some years ago I acccepted Prof. Thomas's invitation to translate the Pravachanasara and Tattvadipika [commentary of Amrtachandra thereon) for the Jain Literature Society, I was not sufficiently aware of the difficulties which the commentary, with its intricate syntax, would give me. I am deeply grateful to Prof Thomas for undertaking to write the introduction. .. at a time when an indisposition due to a constitutional nervous disease hindered me from doing it myself. Despite such personal drawbacks during these last years I have realized the joy of a deeper and better understanding of the Jain religion. Amsterdam 1934 B. Faddegon Page #228 --------------------------------------------------------------------------  Page #229 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introductory Remarks by FW. Thomas The Pravachana-sara, 'Essence of the Scripture' (or ‘of the Doctrine,' since pravachana does not necessarily imply writing), is an early and authoritative Jaina text in Prakrit Gatha stanzas, embodying the teaching of the Digambara sect....Of the two Sanskrit commentaries one, the Tattva-dipika, ‘Lamp of Truth,' or Tattvapradipika, 'Illuminator of Truth,' by Amrtachandra Suri, is a tika expounding the whole text; the other, the Tatparya-vrtti, 'Exposition of Purport,' by Jayasena Acharya, is of a more general, less literal, character. . . . The present English translation represents the Prakrit stanzas of Kundakunda together with the commentary of Amrtachandra but the Tatparya-vrtti by Jayasena and the Hindi exegesis in the Braj dialect by Hemaraja have been consulted. Kundakunda was a kavi, writing in Prakrit verse for a wider public ... there is in it, especially in the Prabhrtas, a warmth more characteristic of a preacher than of a plain dogmatist, and poetry is by no means absent. The very fact that Kundakunda's work is in Prakrit is highly significant, seeing that every one of his famous successors in the Digambara school preferred Sanskrit exclusively .... In the works attributed to Kundakunda there are no allusions to particular scriptures, and it would be a difficult task, and premature, to estimate his relation to the pre-existing texts. The expression sara, 'essence,' occurring in the titles of four of his works, the Pravachanasara (also a sub-title of the Panchasti-kaya-gatha), Niyama-sara, Rayanasara, Samaya-sara, does not imply a mere summary of the content of books; and in fact all his titles have reference to topics, not to treatises. Upon the perfection and all-sufficiency of the Scriptures he constantly dwells, as in Moksha-prabhrta, v. 90: ... Page #230 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 204 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES ‘Righteousness is faith in the Nirgrantha doctrine, a religion void of himsa, free from the eighteen faults, divine.' But he is a preacher who lays stress upon the topic in hand : and so in the most affecting of his compositions, the Bhava-prabhrta, treating of bhava, ‘realization' or 'sincerity,' we read (v. 164)... 'Why babble at length? Gain, religion, pleasure and final release, and other pursuits, all depend upon sincerity. And in the Sila (Sheel-prabhrta, on morality (v. 19), he declares that... Mercy to living creatures, self-restraint, truth, honesty, chastity and contentment, right faith and knowledge, and austerity are [but] the entourage of morality.' His manner of working, therefore, is that of a teacher at home in his subject and its several parts (and how should a Jaina dogmatist not be so?), and not of mere popularizer of pre-existing compositions. He would have disclaimed, as emphatically as does Ishvarakrshna, any departure from the strictest orthodoxy of his school; but his celebrity is that of a poet (kavi), sage (muni), ecclesiastic (pat:a-dharin), not of a commentator... The Pravachana-sara, as arranged in the commentary, is in three chapters, containing respectively 92, 108 and 75 Gatha stanzas. In the commentary the chapters (shruta-skandha) are entitled — I. Jnana-tattva-prajnapana, 'Exposition of the truth as to Knowledge'; II. Jneya-tattva-prajnapana, 'Exposition of the truth as to the Knowable'; III. Charananusuchika-chulika, Appendix, hints on Conduct.' The second commentary, by Jayasena, supplies and discusses a number of extra stanzas [gatha) and stanzas 24-34 of Chapter II seem out of place and have the air of an interpolation. The first chapter treats of the soul and its evolution, knowledge and its relation to objects, the perfect knowledge of the saint, bondage and release, pleasure and pain, merit and demerit. The second chapter discusses objects, existence, substance, quality and state; the syad-vada and naya doctrine (quodammodo' doctrine of ‘aspects”); matter, origination and destruction; time, space, atoms, vital powers; souls and their evolution, the self, karma and bodies, soul-activity and contemplation. The third chapter deals with conduct, including the topics of renunciation, self-restraint, discipline, the recluse, food, residence, association, psychical attention (upayoga), faith and study Page #231 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTORY REMARKS BY F.W. THOMAS 205 of scripture... There is nothing in Kundakunda's doctrine which did not pre-exist in the actual Jaina canon. As we know from the inscriptions published by Buehler (Epigraphia Indica, I, pp. 371 sqq., II, pp. 195 sqq.), the organization of the Jaina community was in the first century A. D. in full maturity, and the several orthodoxies will have been elaborately systematized. Kundakunda was posterior to this; and in regard to his works the only question concerns the emphasis which he lays upon particular doctrines. This also can be considered only in relation to the present text, the Pravachana-sara, since, as we have seen, the several writings are concerned with most departments of Jaina doctrine and religious life. Of the more general logico-epistemological doctrines the syad-vada, or anekanta view, is everywhere affirmed, and in II.22-23, the nayas and the accompanying sapta-bhang are clearly expounded. Allied to this doctrine, which regards the truth of all true statements as relative to a context or an 'aspect,' is the conception of substance elaborated in the text (II.1, sqq.). A substance is an universal, identical with the existence of the thing, and embracing the thing and its qualities (guna), and its states or modifications (paryaya) and their qualities. The nature of a substance is its evolution as a single principle in states composed of the three ‘moments' of origiñation (utpada, sambhava), persistence (dhrauvya, sthiti), and annihilation (vyaya, nasha). While these ‘moments' are logically and epistemologically antithetic, their real status is an inseparable unity, the substance (II. 3-8). In this connection (II.1) appears the distinction between 'lengthwise' (ayata, urdhva) and 'crosswise' (vistara, tiryak) generality (samanya), the former being the identity of successive states of a thing, the 'concrete universal,' while the latter is community of property in separate things. The substance to which this conception is most prominently applied is the self (atman), which is identified with knowledge (1.27 sqq). The self is a generality, embracing all its particular states, whereof it is also the creator (kartr, II. 92-94). In its perfect condition (kevala) it is omniscience and truth and identical with the Jaina faith (samaya) itself (1.8, 92). Essentially it never loses this condition, and no other action is performed by it (II. 92-93). All other states or acts attributed to it are due to matter (karma or pudgala) wherewith it is associated. From this association results the condition of jiva, or soul, which is Page #232 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 206 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES self combined with vital powers (prana, II. 53-55); the various stages manifested in saints, divinities, human beings, animals, plants, denizens of hell, etc.; and the four not perfect kinds of knowledge known as mati (=smrti sense knowledge), shruti (inference, etc.), avadhi and manah-paryaya (III. 34-35). Properly the self knows by direct intuition (pratyaksha) all substances, states, etc., in all times and places, without operation of senses. Sense-knowledge is indirect (paroksha), the senses being a material accretion. The stages (avagraha, iha, etc.) in a senseperception which are known to the canonical works are clearly contemplated in the text (1.21, 59). In Kundakunda's very frequent reference to upayoga there must be some special point. The word has very rarely been cited by European writers on Jainism; we can mention only Cowell, in Colebrooke's Essays, vol. I, p. 446, who renders it by 'the true employment of the soul's activities'; Jacobi (translation of Umasvati's Tattvarthadhigamasutra, in the Zeitschrift der Deutschen Morgenlandischen Gesellschaft, vol. 60, p. 302), who gives 'geistige Funktion (Vorstellen),' 'mindfunctioning (presentation)'; Dr. L. D. Barnett (The Antagada-dasao and Anuttarovavaiyadasao translated from the Prakrit, pp. 141-142), who prefers 'energy'; and Professor Von Glasenapp (Der Jainismus, p. 177), who renders by Vorstellen, 'presentation'. The Sanskrit dictionaries do not refer to the technical use of the word; but it is clearly expounded in Umasvati's own commentary upon his Tattvarthadhigama-sutra and in editions of Jaina texts published in India, e.g. in the Dravya-samgraha of Nemichandra (ed. S. C. Ghoshal, p. 9), as a sort of inclination which arises from consciousness,' in the Gommata-sara, Jiva-kanda (ed. J. L. Jaini, p. 326), as 'conscious attentiveness or attention'; while in the great Prakrit dictionary, Abhidhana-rajendra, the equivalent uvaoga is the subject of a long article. Upayoga is the fundamental property of a living soul, the power of attending; and, as it exists even in the lowest forms of life, it corresponds, in its range, to the modern expression 'response'. In creatures of superior intelligence it embraces, as darshan and jnana respectively, a general or formless awareness of things (anakara-jnana, Dr. Barnett's 'indefinite apprehension') and a determinate awareness (Dr. Barnett's 'definite apprehension'). When free from error, darshan, as a general 'outlook,' is identical with the Jaina faith. This conception of upayoga appears in Kundakunda's other works (e.g. Panchastikaya-gatha, v. 40, Samaya-sara, v. 107); its Page #233 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTORY REMARKS BY E.W. THOMAS 207 prominence in his writings and its rarity in Shvetambara books may indicate a superior importance in the Digambara teaching. Attention may be drawn also to the discussion of time (II.48 sqq.), as an infinite of one dimension, passing through each infinitesimal (pradesha) of space. There are also some other special features in the Jaina doctrine of infinitesimal particles. The distinction of infinite (ananta) and incalculable (asamkhyeya) numbers is likewise of interest: see J. L. Jaini in Gommata-sara, Jiva-kanda, pp. 20 sqq. The nigodas, or nikotas, minute living creatures, are mentioned in Sutra-prabhrta, v. 18) The commentator, Amrtachandra, composed commentaries also on the Samaya-sara ( Tatparya-vrtti) (Atma-khyatı] and the Panchastikayagatha. He is known, moreover, as author of independent works, Purushartha-siddhy-upaya, Samaya-sara-kalasha-nataka, and Tattvarthasara. ... His commentary on the Pravachana-sara is elaborate and of a severe, almost painful, precision, which leaves nothing to be supplied and by no means shrinks from reiteration. He is an excellent master of Jaina Sanskrit: he employs a fullness of phrase which not unfrequently gives an impression of an enjoyment of sonorous circumlocution and complicated sentences rather than of a simple striving for exactitude, and which renders the work of interpretation and translation extremely difficult; but no special charity is required for recognizing in the remorsefessness of style the outcome of an inflexible religious faith. Like other Jaina writings, the commentary is entirely void of personal display; but there are some few passages where it adopts a strain of enthusiasm and even indulges in verse. In the long travail of composing and verifying the translation, which may, it is hoped, convey a fairly correct impression of Digambara thought and style, Professor Faddegon and his editor have been much indebted to Brahmachari Shitalaprasada of Surat, who has perused the whole, for valuable suggestions and corrections and to Mr. Herbert Warren for much loyal and patient cooperation. Page #234 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 2 Summary of Significant Concepts A N Upadhye [Note: The figures in brackets indicate Verse no.] 1. The Doctrine of Three Upayogas The soul is constituted of the manifestation of consciousness [upayoga] which is in the form of knowledge or cognition and which flows in one of the three channels: inauspicious, auspicious or pure (9, 155). A being of inauspicious manifestation of consciousness (ashubha upayoga) is steeped in sensual pleasures and passions, is given to false scriptures, evil intentions and wicked works, is cruel, and goes astray (158). The inauspicious one is a cause of sinful karmic influx (156, 245). Under the influence of this upayoga the soul wanders for long as a low graded human being, a sub-human being and a hellish one subjected to thousands of miseries (12). The auspicious manifestation of consciousness (shubha upayoga) is characterised by devotion of God, ascetic or preceptor and by the practice of philanthropy, virtues, fasts, etc. (69) and by compassion towards all the living beings (157). It incurs only the meritorious influx of karmas for the soul (157, 245). It leads the soul to heavenly pleasure; and even if one is born as a sub-human, human or divine being there are plenty of pleasures of senses (11, 70). A monk with Shubhopayoga shows a respectful behaviour towards elderly monks, offers instructions on faith and knowledge, maintains students, and helps co-monks without causing harm to any living beings (247-248). Page #235 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ SUMMARY OF SIGNIFICANT CONCEPTS 209 Immunity from the contagion of the above two upayogas is the characteristic of pure manifestation of consciousness (shuddha upayoga) which is not open to karmic influx (156, 245) and leads to the annihilation of all the miseries (181). The soul with this upayoga develops religious experience (dharma), which is a spiritual state of transcendental, self-born, super-sensuous, unparalled, indestructible. .. happiness (13-14). In Shuddhopayoga the physical pains are no more, and one knowing the nature of reality is above attachment and aversion. . . he is equanimous (7, 78). 2. The Principle of Knowledge Really speaking, the soul (atman) is the knower and essentially an embodiment of knowledge (127, 28 etc.). Knowledge is the self, and knowledge cannot subsist anywhere else than in the self; self and knowledge are co-extensive, neither less nor more (23); if the self is smaller, then knowledge being insentient cannot function; if larger, it cannot know in the absence of knowledge (24-5). In a sense, however, the self can be taken as wider than knowkedge (27), because it has other characteristics like sukha (happiness), virya (vigour), etc. In view of its being an embodiment of knowledge, the soul is capable of knowing itself, objects other than itself and the combinatory products of the two (36). But this essential knowing ability of the soul is crippled because of its long association with karmic matter (in the form of knowledge-obscuring karman, etc.); and it has come to possess the sense-organs (55, 145). The senses are material in nature (paudgalika) and hence foreign to the real nature of the soul. Whatever is apprehended through the senses is indirect (paroksha), because the soul is not directly apprehending the object of knowledge; that would be direct apprehension (pacchakkham vinnanam) when the soul apprehends all by itself without the aid of senses (56-58). The sense-perception is graded and mediate (ajugavam and parokkham), because it has four stages: outliner grasp (avagraha), discrimination (iha), judgement (avaya) and retention (dharana) (40). After manifesting pure consciousness when the soul becomes free from knowledge-obscuring, conation-obscuring, obstructive and deluding karmas, it comes to be self-constituted and possessed of omniscience (15-16). This omniscience is supersensuous; therein the apprehension of the objectivity takes place directly by the soul without Page #236 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 210 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES the aid of sense-organs; there are no sensational stages, but the apprehension is instantaneous and simultaneous; it is endowed with the potencies of all the senses together as it were; and there is nothing that is not visualised in omniscience. (20-22). The omniscient knows and sees the whole world, the variegated and unequal objectivity of the present or otherwise, neither entering into nor entered into by the objects of knowledge, just as the eye sees the objects of sight (27, 47). Omniscience operates on the objects, just as a sapphire thrown in milk pervades the whole of it with its lustre; omniscience is ubiquitous in its functions, and therefore the omniscient is called omnipresent; and all the objects are within His knowledge (28-31, 35). The external objectivity does not affect Him, though He sees and knows everything completely (32). It is the supernatural characteristic of omniscience that therein are visualised all present and absent modifications of all those types of substances as if in the present (37-39). Omniscience being an extra-sensory form of knowledge (atindriya-jnana) knows any substance with or without space-points, with or without form and those modifications which have not come into existence and those that had come (41). It is also called kshayika-jnana, because this knowledge is the result of the destruction of karmas and does not involve fresh karmas (42, 52). Omniscience is the only knowledge worth the name, because its apprehension is simultaneous and sudden; a single substance has infinite modes, and infinite are the classes of substances: so to know one is to know all and to know all is to know one; it is impossible to exhaust them if they were to be known one after another; thus omniscience is the only knowledge that can really grasp the objectivity (48-51). The development of omniscience is necessarily accompanied by . happiness (59, 19); there is no trace of misery, since the destructive karmas are all exhausted (60). As the sun has light and warmth, so the Siddha, the liberated soul, has . . .knowledge and happiness (68). This happiness is independent of everything, and hence eternal; it is not physical but spiritual (65). It should be completely distinguished from the pleasures of senses after which all the worldly beings are so much enamoured; the pleasures of senses are miseries in disguise, because they are dependent on something else, amenable to destruction, terminable, a cause of bondage and dangerous [unequal] (63-64, 76). . . . Page #237 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ SUMMARY OF SIGNIFICANT CONCEPTS 211 3. The Principle of Knowable (Jneya): Substance, Quality and Modification Substances (dravya), qualities (guna) and modification (paryaya) are called the object of knowledge (87). ...The substance forms the substratum of qualities and modifications, and it is constantly endowed with origination, destruction and permanence without leaving its existential character ( 87, 95, 99, 105). It is the very nature of the substance to be amenable to these three states (99); origination and destruction are simultaneous and interdependent, and are not possible in the absence of the substance (100). This trio refers to modifications and qualities, and the substance, as it forms the essential basis of the three, comes to be predicated of them at that moment (101). The object of knowledge has always one or the other modification (18). One modification originates and the other passes away, while the substance is permanent (103). There is nothing as absolute production or destruction in this world: what is the production of one is the destruction of the other (119). That condition or state (parinama), which in fact forms the nature of the substance is quality, which is a distinguishing mark too (129-130). The transformation of one (form of the) object into the other is the modification with its varieties of figuration (152). The substance, quality and modification are existential (105); as to the relation between the three they are nonseparate (aprthaktva) and non-identical (anyatva): they cannot be separate because they are the co-occupants of the same spatial extense, and they are non-identical because one is not the other (106-110). To illustrate: Soul is a substance; manifestation of consciousness is its quality; and its modifications are hellish, sub-human, human and ... (gods, i.e. denizens of heaven) embodiments which are caused by Nama karman, or even the state of a Siddha, behind all these modifications the soul is essentially the same and permanent (112,113,117-119). The substance is one in view of its substantial it, but it comes to be manifold because of the modifications pervading it for the time being (115). ... 4. Nature of Spirit and Matter, or Jiva and Pudgala The jiva is essentially constituted of sentiency (chetana) and manifestation of consciousness (upayoga) (127); but from beginningless time it is already tainted with karman (121). The development (or Page #238 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES expression) of its sentiency is threefold: with regard to knowledge which consists in the comprehension of the objectivity, with regard to karma which consists in whatever is done (samaraddham) by the soul, and with regard to the fruit of karma which is either happiness or misery; and these three are predicated of the soul (123, 124, etc.). Likewise the manifestation of consciousness (upayoga) is towards jnana and darshana (155) and flows in three channels; inauspicious, auspicious and pure (9), which respectively indicate impiety, piety and purity (11, etc.). Auspicious and inauspicious channels are indicative of transmigratory condition; when the soul is free, it has the pure manifestation (46). The soul in its pure (natural] condition is without sense-qualities, is all the quality of sentiency, is beyond inferential mark and has no definable shape (172); but, here, being in the association of karmic matter, it has received a concrete embodiment (55. 117). The various grades of existence to which the soul is subjected in this round-of-rebirths are due to karmas (117-118). When passionate conditions are developed, the soul though non-concrete is bound by karmas which are concrete, just as the soul though devoid of colour, etc. is able to see colour, etc. (173,174). The soul really speaking is not the direct agent of karmas but only of its states of consciousness which being already tinged with passions etc. receive the karmas (183,184,190). Matter (pudgala) is a permanent substance belonging to non-sentient class of substances (127). . . .Matter is concrete possessed of sensory qualities to its last unit (132). The world is full of material bodies (168), and the aggregatory process is going on because of their inherent qualities of cohesion and aridness (163, etc.). The matter molecules capable of becoming karmas, coming into contact with passional development of the soul, are transformed into karmas (169); further they inflow into the soul and remain there binding it (178). Thus the passionate states give rise to bondage (179-180). .. Being already associated with karman which results in further karmas, the soul, in its embodied condition, comes to have many material adjuncts: the body, mind, speech are all material (161-162). Matter-bodies which are transformed into karmas go to form the bodies that serve as the transmigratory equipments of the spirit; there are five such bodies: the physical, transformatory, electric, translocational and karmic (170-171). The four life-essentials, namely, sense-organs, Page #239 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ SUMMARY OF SIGNIFICANT CONCEPTS 213 channels of activity (mind, speech and body), duration of life and respiration which characterise an embodied soul are all material being caused by the karmas (147-148, etc.). Thus the sense-organs too are made of matter, and the soul in samsara comes to have them, whether it is born in movable (trasa) or immovable (sthavara) bodies (57, 182). 5. Syadvada, or the Theory of Conditional Predication ... A substance is endowed with qualities (or attributes) and modifications; though the substance is the same, it expresses differently because of its passing through different modifications; so when something is to be stated about a substance, viewed through a flux of modifications, there would be seven modes of predication: according to some modification or the other it is stated that a substance is, is not, is indescribable, 'is and is not', 'is and is indescribable', 'is not and is indescribable', and is, is not and is indescribable (114-115)... 6. The Mechanism of Bondage and Liberation The soul being tainted with karman develops states of consciousness which being auspicious or inauspicious receive karmic influx; and it is this karman that binds the soil and revolves it in samsara. Essential characteristics of the soul are all crippled by the karmic encrustation of eight kinds (187/1). The soul in this round-of-rebirths is subject to attachment, aversion and other psychic states tinged with passions which occasion further karmas (243). The way out of this samsara consists in Right (Enlightened] vision, Right [Enlightened] knowledge and Right (Enlightened] conduct (6). The first consists in believing in the nature of things or realities as they are. . . the second consists in comprehending the whole range of objectivity as preached by Arahantas or from the Agamas (81-2; 233 etc.); and the last consists in adopting ...equanimity while practising the essential duties and penances . . . [of the householder and the ascetic] that go to stop the influx and exhaust the deposit of karmas (and thus the self gradually attains the stage of siddha, the liberated soul, by his own efforts). When the soul is free from the four destructive or malignant types of karmas, namely Jnanavaraniya, Darshanavaraniya, Mohaniya and Antaraya, it ... (comprehends all things knowable by itself (15); Having thus realised its real nature and become omniscient),. .. the soul is called self-sufficient (Svayambhut (16). There the spirit develops excellent infinite strength, excessive lustre and super-sensuousness (19). Page #240 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 214 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Then he becomes Siddha [liberated soul] after the remaining four aghati-karmas are destroyed. Just as the sun is all lustre and warmth. He is all knowledge and happiness and a Divinity (68). Page #241 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Book I The Principle of Knowledge Page #242 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Book I The Principle of Knowledge Only the Original Verses are given in bold. The rest is Amrtchandra's commentary. EDITOR TATTVA-DIPIKA "THE LAMP OF TRUTH” (Commentary by AMRTACHANDRA SURI) Benedictory Poetic Composition (Manglacharan) by AC Homage to the Self, which in its innate nature is one principle of consciousness-as-such, that permeates all its attributes and modes, and which attains by its own efforts, the supreme state of soul consisting of knowledge and bliss. (PS Kalash 1) This splendour, this truth, which consists of anekant (the doctrine of the multifaceted nature of reality), and illuminates the world, subdues the mass of darkness of great infatuation (moha) and easily removes it. (PS Kalash 2) This commentary on the Pravachana-sara explains the nature of substances or things as they really are and is composed for the good of fortunate persons desirous of drinking the nectar-juice of Highest Bliss. (PS Kalash 3) [Introductory Remarks by the Commentator in Prose] Here now someone who possesses knowledge of the further and the nearer shores of mundane existence (samsara) — whose light of understanding has expanded abundantly; who, in consequence of Page #243 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 217 attaining the divine many-sided knowledge (of the doctrine of anekant), has lost the conceit of knowledge proclaimed by all one-sided views; who has become ultimately impartial (madhyastha), because he has given up all bias or preference of particular views; and who, moreover, realizes that the imperishable bliss of liberation, containing the ultimate truth, available to us because of the five holy parameshthins and exclusively wholesome for the self, since it embraces all hurnan aims, is an object worthy of acceptance adores the five blessed parameshthins (Siddhas, Arhats, Acharayas, Upadhyayas and Sadhus), preceded by the present Tirtha-nayaka (Spiritual Guide, i.e. Lord Mahavira) and the other Tirthankaras, with homage in the form of prostration (pranamana) and eulogy (vandana); and after this, embracing with all his power the way of liberation, he states his intention. BENEDICTORY VERSES (VERSES 1-5) Detailed Comments on Kundakunda’s Verses 1. I now prostrate myself before Vardhomana, the Tirtha (landing place in the ocean of Transmigration, i.e. Spiritual Guide), promulgator of the law or path of dharma, praised by the best of gods, demons and men, free from the stains of destructive karman. I now, the person perceived by means of self-consciousness, having for self the self of vision and knowledge in their generality, prostrate myself before the holy Vardhamana, the mention of whose name is auspicious and is worthy of being praised by the most excellent Masters (Bhattarakas), Great Gods, Tutelary Deities and Supreme Lords (Parameshvaras). I first bow before him, because he is our present Guide. He is the guru of the three worlds, because he is praised by the best of gods, demons and men; he possesses the rank of a Supreme Lord, which rank is one of unlimited efficacy and fitted for benevolence towards the world, because he is free from the stains of destructive karman; he is capable of saving us, because he is the Tirtha of the yogins, he is the institutor of a conduct of a wise nature, because he is propounder of the Law, i.e. the path of dharma. 2. (I pay obeisance) also to the other Tirthankaras (the promulgators of the order or the path of dharma) and all the Siddhas (liberated souls), and the Shramanas (saints) of pure nature who are engaged in the practice of knowledge, darshan (vision), conduct, austerities and energy (virya). Page #244 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 218 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Then I bow before the other, former Tirthankaras, whose innate pure vision and knowledge may be compared to genuine gold, emerged from the fire, because they themselves are pure; and I bow before all the Siddhas and before the Shramanas, namely the Acharyas, the Upadhyayas and the Sadhus, who have reached the stage of the highest, pure psychic-attention (upayoga), because they are possessed of the practice of the exercises of knowledge, faith, conduct, penance and energy. 3. I pay homage to all of them conjointly and individually, and to the Arbats (perfect souls) existing at present in the region inhabited by man. - Thereafter, fixing my attention on the present time, I glorify all these five Parameshthins in their respective individualities, including the Tirtha-nayakas who now abide in the human region (manushyakshetra) - for, though at present no Tirthakaras abide in this region of ours (Bharat-kshetra), they do exist in the great Videha-country so then I venerate these Parameshthins collectively and separately with laudatory speech as it is taught by the Krtikarma-shastra, namely with the pronouncing of benedictions similar to those used at the time of their consecration in sainthood, which is the bridal day of the Glory of Deliverance. - 4. Having thus paid homage to the Arhats, Siddhas, Ganadharas (direct disciples of Tirthankaras), the groups of Adhyapakas (Teachers) and all the Sadhus (saints). After having thus paid homage to the Arhats, Siddhas, Acharyas, Upadhyayas and all the Sadhus - a homage which, although it proceeds in the two-fold form of prostration (pranati) and the pronouncing of eulogies (vandana), still is one, in as much as every distinction between ourselves and others fades away in consequences of an intensive mutual union, resulting from the relation of object worshipped and worshipper. 5. And having approached their holy station, devoted primarily to purifying vision and knowledge, I rely upon the equanimity (samya) leading to nirvana. And by abundance of purified knowledge and vision having approached the holy station of these Arhats, Siddhas, Acharyas, Upadhyayas and all Sadhus - which station leads to right vision (samyagdarshan) and right knowledge (samyag-jnana), both characterized by Page #245 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 219 the experience of belief in the reality of soul as having for its innate nature pure vision and knowledge, and so being in possession of right vision and knowledge, and having left far behind, although it takes place by degrees, the conduct influenced by attachment (raga) cause of the attainment of bondage through merits, since the soul is still blind through its passions (kashaya) - I now rely upon the tranquillity called the conduct free from attachment, cause of the attainment of nirvana, since the soul is freed from all the filth of the contest of passions. Thus I have obtained the mental-concentration which consists in the oneness of right vision, right knowledge and right conduct; this is what I profess; thus I here am surely following the clear path of liberation. The author now explains how conduct free from attachment and conduct based on attachment have desirable and undesirable results and therefore are to be sought and to be avoided: SELF AND ITS STATES-OF-EVOLUTION (VERSES 6-12) 6. The nirvana of the soul, together with the powers or the splendour (vibhava) of kings (i.e. the best) of gods, demons and men, is reached by means of a conduct based on vision and knowledge. Liberation is reached by a conduct which is based on enlightened world-view and knowledge and free from attachment (raga). For the same reason bondage, which troubles the kingly powers of gods, demons and men, results from conduct based on attachment. Hence, he who desires liberation should follow a conduct without attachment, as having a desired fruit, and conduct with attachment, as having undesired fruit, he should forgo. Now he explains the characteristic nature of conduct: 7. Conduct is dharma. Dharma is defined as equanimity (sama); and equanimity is said to be a state-of-evolution (parinama) of the soul, in which it is free from infatuation (moha) and disturbance (keshobha). Conduct is behaving according to one's own nature; activity obeying one's (innate) laws. And this being the nature of things is dharma, it means the manifestation of pure consciousness (pure in the sense that it is different from other substance(s) and not different from its own properties (PS 192, AC)]. And this is equanimity; for Page #246 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 220 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES in it we possess the qualities of the self as they are. And equanimity is a state-of-evolution of the soul, a state which is completely exempt from blemish because there is no longer any infatuation and disturbance, which were caused by the arising (udaya) (the arising of karman out of its latent condition) of vision-infatuating (darshanmohaniya) and conduct-infatuating (charitra-mohaniya) karman. Now he investigates what is to be understood by the conduct of the self: 8. A substance possesses the nature of that through which it evolves during the time of the evolution. Therefore the soul, evolved through dharma, must be considered to be dharma. Whatever substance evolves at a certain time through a certain form of existence takes at that time the nature of that existence, like a piece of iron evolved through heat. Therefore this soul, evolved through dharma, is dharma, thus is settled what we must understand by the conduct of the soul. Now he investigates the good (shubha), evil (ashubha) and pure (shuddha) states of the soul: 9. The soul accepts the character of its state-of-evolution. When the soul evolves through the good or the evil, it becomes good or evil. When it evolves through the pure, it becomes pure. When the soul evolves through a mental-state (bhava) of attachment (raga), either good or evil, it becomes good or evil, possessing the character of its state-of-evolution; like a crystal evolved through the colour (raga) of the China rose (japa) or the Tamala flower (tapiccha). But, when it evolves through a pure mental-state exempt from attachment, it becomes pure, possessing the character of its state-ofevolution; like a crystal evolved through the pure, colourless condition. Thus is settled what we must understand by the good, evil and pure condition of the soul. Now he investigates evolution, as being the innate nature of things: 10. There is no object without a state of evolution; there is no state-of-evolution without an object (arth); the object, in the form of substance, attributes and modifications, has developed from existence (astitva or satta). No thing (vastu) receives existence without evolution, because a thing evolves through substance, etc., because these are never seen apart, because anything without evolution would resemble a donkey's Page #247 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK 1: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 221 horn, and because it would be repugnant to the evolution which is seen, for instance, in cow's milk. Neither does evolution receive existence without a thing, because, if there were nothing for it to abide in, the unwished-for consequence would be that this evolution without an abode would be a void (shunya). But the thing, founded in the substance, which forms its general-aspect according to the verticaldirection (urdhvata-samanya, i.e the common features belonging to one thing in succession of time), in the attributes (gunas), which are the particular concomitants (sahabhavi-vishesha), in the modifications, which are the particular stages (kramabhavi-vishesha), has developed from, and still develops through, existence, which consists in origination (utpada), perishing (vyaya) and continuance (dhrauvya). So then evolution is its innate nature. Now he considers the fruit (phala) of the pure and good states-ofevolution, which arise during the contact with the state-of-evolution called conduct (charitra), in order that one may accept or reject it: 11. When the soul, whose self evolves through dharma (i.e. righteousness and piety) is conjoined with pure psychic-attention (upayoga), then it attains the happiness of nirvana; or, when engaged in good psychic-attention, it attains the happiness of heaven. . When this soul, with its innate nature evolved through dharma, carries out the evolution of pure psychic-attention, then its efficacy (shakti) does not meet with resistance, and thus its conduct is capable of doing what is to be done, and the soul itself reaches manifest liberation. But, when the soul, although having its innate nature evolved through dharma, is in contact with the evolution-state of good psychicattention, then its efficacy, meets with resistance, and thus it is unfit to do what is to be done; its conduet in bringing about what is to be done is to a certain extent checked; and the soul itself reaches bondage, in this case heavenly happiness, as a man sprinkled with ghi (oil) hot from the fire (incurs) the pain of burning. Therefore pure psychic-attention should be accepted, good psychic-attention avoided. Now he considers the fruit of evil psychic-attention, which is utterly to be rejected; for here takes place no contact with a state-of-evolution called (lawful) conduct: 12. By the arising of the evil (ashubha) (psychic disposition) the self becomes a rogue, an animal or inhabitant of hell; And, always beset by thousands of pains, it strays incessantly. Page #248 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 222 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES When this self, not partaking at all of the evolution of dharma, gives itself up to the evolution of evil psychic-attention (ashubha upayoga), then it experiences the bondage of a thousand pains, whilst it wanders about as rogue, animal or inhabitant of hell. Therefore, because of the lack of even a grain of (lawful) conduct, this evil psychic-attention must be completely abandoned. And the soul, thus throwing off all engagement (vrtti) in good and evil psychic-attention, and adopting the engagement in pure psychicattention, gains a prerogative (adhikara) with reference to pure psychicattention. And further, in order to rouse the self, he praises the fruit of pure pyschic-attention: PURE, PSYCHIC ATTENTION 13. The happiness of those advanced in pure psychic-attention is transcendent, springing from the self, supersensuous, incomparable, endless and uninterrupted. The nectar of joy in those who are perfect in pure psychic-attention is: (1) transcendent, (2) springing from the self, (3) surpassing objects, (4) incomparable, (5) endless and (6) uninterrupted; and therefore it should be sought in every way, (i) because it is an extreme, wonderful joy having no precedent all the samsara through, (ii) because it continues based only on the self, (iii) because it is independent of any other abode, (iv) because it is utterly different from anything else, (v) because it does not decrease in the longest succession-of-time (ayati), (vi) because it comes forth without pauses. Now he describes the characteristic nature of self, when evolved through pure psychic-attention: 14. A shraman is called a man of pure psychic-attention, when he knows well the categories (padarthas) and the sutras (the scriptures) [For the definition of Sutra, see PS 34] which explain them, when he possesses self-restraint (samyam) and practises austerities (tapas), gives up attachment and considers pleasure and pain the same (sama). He knows well the categories and the sutras which explain them, because he is capable of decisions (vidhana) and masters a complete knowledge of the distinction between his own (self's) substance and other substances by means of his understanding the contents of the sutras. He possesses self-restraint and has practised austerities (tapas), (1) because he restrains the self in its pure characteristic nature by keeping Page #249 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 223 it away from the different forms (vikalpa) of the longings of the five sense-organs and from the different forms of destroying the bodies of the six kinds of living beings (the five kinds of one-sensed sthavarasouls (immobile ones earth-borne, water-borne, air-borne, fire-borne and plant life) and the trasa (mobile) souls, i.e men and animals etc. possessing from two up to five sense organs), and (2) because he brings to brightness (pratupati) his intelligence, motionless and acquiescent in its characteristic nature. He has given up attachment, because the unblemished characteristic nature of self has been revealed to him by a facility in realizing (bhavana-saushthava) the discrimination of the effects (vipaka) of all the infatuating karmans. He considers pleasure and pain the same, because even under the most subtle examination he no longer experiences the manifold evolutions due to pleasure and pain which arise from the ripening of delightful (sata) and painful (asata) sensation-karman (vedaniya-karman). Thus the Shraman is called a man of pure psychic-attention. Now he describes the attainment of the nature of the purified self, which is the acquisition of pure (shuddha) psychic-attention: 15. He who is pure in psychic-attention and has thrown off the filth of obscuring (avaraniya), obstructing (antaraya) and infatuating (mohaniya) karmans becomes himself the self and comprehends all things knowable. He who has become and remains purified according to his power by means of psychic-attention, i.e. evolution of his intelligence, obtains an excellent efficacy of purity which springs up at every step, and an intelligence completely free from blemish, because the very strong knot (granthi) of infatuation, bound together all the samsara through, is untied; he obtains an efficacy of self expanding without obstacles, because he has thrown aside all karmans which obscure knowledge and intuition, and those karmans which obstruct; having himself become thus, he reaches the boundary of all things which can be known. Here then the innate nature of self is knowledge; and knowledge is nothing less than the things knowable; so then the self, owing to its pure attention, attains the self, which in its nature consists of knowledge, which knowledge, again, pervades everything that is knowable. Now he explains how the acquisition of the innate nature of pure self, originating from pure psychic-attention, depends exclusively on Page #250 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 224 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES the self, inasmuch as it is independent of any other factor: 16. Having thus realised (the full potential of) his nature and become omniscient, deserving of respect from the lords of all the worlds, being himself the self, he is called the self-being (svayambhu). This self in its innate nature is intelligence provided with pure, unlimited efficacy; for all its destructive karman disappears through the dignity of the internal-state (bhavana) of pure psychic-attention; it claims kartrtva (agency, or the function of the grammatical nominative), because of its independence; for it is in its innate nature a knower, possessing pure, unlimited efficacy; it bears karmatva (the relation of the accusative towards the verb), because of its being arrived at; for it is in its innate nature an evolution-state of knowledge, possessing pure, unlimited efficacy; it shows karanatva (the nature of an instrumental), because of its great effectiveness; for it is in its innate nature an evolution-state of knowledge, possessing pure, unlimited efficacy; it manifests sampradanatva (the nature of a dative) because of its being the goal of an action; for it is in its innate nature an evolutionstate of knowledge, possessing pure, unlimited efficacy; it accepts apadanatva (the character of an ablative), because of its being based on immobility; for in its innate nature it is original (sahaja) knowledge, even when at the moment of an evolution-state of knowledge, possessing pure, unlimited efficacy imperfect knowledge in its innate nature, existing previously, withdraws; it appropriates adhikaranatva (the character of a locative), because of its being the abode of the innate nature of an evolution-stare of knowledge, possessing pure, unlimited efficacy; thus by itself (svayam) arising in the form of the six karakas (the six cases of a noun which bear on a verb), it is called svayambhu (selfarising). Or it is called thus because it comes itself (svayam) forth, throwing off in proportion to its rise the destructive karmans, divided into kinds according to their material nature (dravya-bhava). Thus on strict examination (nishchaya) there is no relation of causality (condition of being a factor, karakatva) between the self and anything else (para, something else than the soul, i.e. ajiva or nonsoul);"a for such beings as are intent on the search for means to the realization of the innate nature of their own pure selves are independent. Page #251 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 225 Now with regard to this self-existent being he considers the absolute impossibility of loss (anapayitvam) in the realization of the innate nature of the pure self, and its connection in a certain sense with origination, perishing and continuance: 17. There is in him origination without destruction, annihilation devoid of origination; and, on the other hand, also an inherence (samavaya) of persistence, origination or becoming and annihilation. The origination which is found in the self according to its innate nature of pure self and which is due to pure psychic-attention is exempt from destruction; for in that respect there is no dissolution. And the annihilation which takes place because the impure exists no more is devoid of commencement; for there does not happen a new production. And, since this is ascertained, neither is there a loss. So then the inherence of persistence, becoming, and annihilation in him is not contradictory; for we find here the inherence of an origination exempt from decay, an annihilation devoid of commencement, and a substance [we should read dhrauvyena (permanence) instead of dravyena (substance)] which is the abode of both. Now he explains how the triad of origination, etc., common to every substance, necessarily belongs to the pure self as well: 18. Origination and annihilation are found in every object whatever, and each existent object exists with reference to some mode or other. Just as origination is seen in real gold by way of its modification as a bracelet, and annihilation with reference to a modification such as a previously existing finger-ring, and continuance, because this gold, in both regards, neither undergoes origination nor annihilation with reference to such modifications as yellowness, so we must acknowledge that in all substances there is origination with regard to one modification, annihilation with regard to a second, and continuance with regard to a third. Thus existence (astitva), characterized as substance and consisting of the triad origination, etc., is necessarily found in pure self as well. Now he refutes the doubt how, through the power of pure psychicattention, without sense-organs, knowledge and joy of this self, which is self-existent, can occur: 19/2. He whose destructive karman has perished, whose energy (virya) is sublime without limits, whose splendour is abundant, who Page #252 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 226 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES has risen above the realm of the senses—he himself evolves into knowledge and bliss. 1 bliss. . This self, when its destructive karman has disappeared, because pure psychic-attention is capable of this; when it has risen above the realm of the senses, in consequences of being unblended with the knowledge and vision due to combined suppression (upasham) and annihilation (kshaya); when it possesses unlimited sublime energy, in consequence of the annihilation of all obstructive (antaraya) karman, when it abounds in splendour, called absolute (kevala) knowledge and vision (darshan), resulting from the complete perishing of all obscurations (avarana) of knowledge and vision (darshan) — this self, reaching the self, which in its innate nature is pure intelligenceabsolutely unblemished, because of the absence of all infatuating (mohaniya) karmans, evolves itself by becoming knowledge, i.e. illumination of the self and the other (svapara, self and other; i.e self and non-self),' and bliss, i.e. absence of confusedness. So then knowledge and bliss are the innate nature of the self. And, since innate nature does not depend on anything else, knowledge and bliss of the self arise even without sense-organs. Now he explains how bodily pleasure and pain do not belong to the pure self, because it is without the senses: 20. Bodily pleasure or pain does not belong to him who possesses absolute knowledge or omniscience (kevala-jnana). Know that it is because he has transcended the realm of the senses. Since the pure self does not possess the assemblage of sense-organs, just as little as the fire possesses the entire manifestation of matter which has met together in the iron ball, therefore bodily pleasure and pain, corresponding to the series of impacts of terrible hammer (ghana) blows, does not belong to it. Now he gives the fuller explanation of the characteristic nature of knowledge and the fuller explanation of the characteristic-nature of happiness in two successive passages (see gathas 21-52 and 53-68]; and here he first explains how the perfect-sage (kevalin) has perception of all things, because he has evolved into supra-sensorial knowledge: EXPOSITION OF KNOWLEDGE (VERSES 21-52) 21. For him, who is evolving into knowledge, directly perceives all substances and their modifications; he does not know them by Page #253 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 227 means of stages such as apprehension of an object or sensation (avagraha), etc. Since the perfect-sage does not obtain knowledge by the aid of the senses through the precedent series of avagraha (the taking up the object of knowledge by the senses), iha (the readiness to know more about the things perceived) and avaya (the finding out the determinate or ascertained cognition of a thing), and since he himself, at the moment of the annihilation of all obscurations (avaranas), having accepted in the function of a cause (karana) the innate nature of knowledge which has no beginning, no end, no cause (hetu) and has nothing in common with anything else, evolves, becoming the psychicattention of arising absolute-knowledge, which immediately follows the annihilation of avaranas—therefore the modifications of all the substances are perceptible for him, since they conjointly become a basis for his consciousness inasmuch as all substances, times, places and forms-of-being (bhava) are appropriated by him simultaneously. Now he commences the topic that nothing is hidden from the perception of the Holy One, because he has evolved into suprasensorial knowledge: 22. Nothing is indirect to him, who himself has become one with knowledge, and who is rich in all qualities of the sense-organs, who always transcends the realm of the senses. Nothing whatever is imperceptible to the Holy One at the very moment of the destruction of all obscurations; for he has surpassed the senses, each of which takes up its respective objects and causes the setting to work of the forces necessary for the arising of mundane distinctions (parichchitti); he is rich at all points (since they have for him the same savour) in all qualities of the senses in the form of the distinctions (parichcheda) in touch, taste, smell, colour and sound; he himself illuminates the self and the other by his completeness; he is become miraculous (lokottara) knowledge without restraint; so nothing is imperceptible to him, owing to his simultaneous grasping of all substances, places, times and forms-of-being. Now he explains the equal extension of the knowledge and the self and the omnipresence of this knowledge: 23. The soul is co-extensive with knowledge; knowledge is said to be coextensive with the knowable [i.e. the objects of knowledge); the knowable comprises the physical and non-physical universe; Page #254 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 228 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES therefore knowledge is omnipresent. According to the saying "the substance has its qualities and modifications equivalent to itself,” the self is the extension of the knowledge; for it evolves without becoming more or less than the knowledge; and knowledge is the extension of the knowable; for it abides therein, as fire in the fuel. The knowable is as much as everything; it is the totality of the six substances; it is annihilation, origination and continuance; divided into the division of universe and the beyond-the-universe; revealing itself in characteristic-natures (svarupa) which are covered by an endless series of modifications. Therefore knowledge is omnipresent; for at the very moment of the annihilation of all obscurations it has reached the (other) shore of all the appearances (akara) of objects, divided into the division of universe and beyond-the-universe, and remains in this way for ever unshaken. He states two alternatives which arise when one does not accept the self as having the extension of knowledge, and refutes them: 24. He who does not accept the şelf as coextensive with knowledge, the self surely becomes smaller or larger than knowledge. 25. If the self is smaller, then knowledge (outside the self), being of unconscious nature, does not know; if the self is larger than knowledge, how does this self then without knowledge know? If we allow that the self is smaller than knowledge, in that case knowledge-which may be compared to qualities such as shape (in material things)-going beyond the self, will be unconscious (achetan), because it no longer inheres in the conscious substance which was its abode, and so then does not know. If we admit the other alternative, that it is larger than knowledge, then necessarily the self-which in our comparison ranks together with (material things), such as pots and pieces of cloth-standing by itself and going beyond knowledge, does not know without this knowledge. Therefore this self must be taken as possessing the same extension as knowledge. Now he declares that the omnipresence of self, like its knowledge, is proved by logic (nyaya): 26. The great Jina is omnipresent, and all the objects (arthas) in the world are within his grasp; the Jina is the embodiment of knowledge; and the objects are said to be within his grasp, because they are objects-of-his-knowledge (vishaya). Knowledge, embracilig the appearances (akara) of all knowables, Page #255 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 229 arranged as the modifications of all substances in the three times, is called omnipresent. And also the Holy One, because he consists of such like knowledge, is omnipresent. And so all objects (artha), inasmuch as they are the objects (vishaya) of omnipresent knowledge, are called the objects (vishaya) of the Holy One, who is never deprived of omnipresent knowledge; and, since they are so called, they belong to him. According to the [internal, self-referential] nishchaya-mode of statement, the Holy One, it is true, knows without moving himself towards all the appearances of the knowables, since he never leaves his own reality (svatattva), i.e. knowledge with the extension of the self, characterized by its being the abode of a consciousness (samvedana) of bliss demarked by serenity; however, according to the [extgernal, other-referential] vyavahara-mode the Holy One is said to be everywhere. Similarly, the objects are said metaphorically to belong to him, whilst one considers the appearances of knowables which are auxiliary causes (naimittika) to be based on the self; but in the transcendental sense (paramarthena) of the word there is no mutual going towards each other, since all substances abide in their own characteristicnature. The same argumentation must be understood with reference to knowledge. Now he considers the identity and non-identity of self and knowledge: 27. The doctrine is that knowledge is the self. There is no knowledge without the self; therefore knowledge is the self. But the self is knowledge and something else [also). Since knowledge cannot exist without the self—for knowledge arises, requiring, and using as basis, the self alone, which shows towards it a beginning-less and endless relation of inherence, ensuing from its innate nature, and which, with reference to all other, unconscious things (vastu), has no tendency towards such a relation of inherence—therefore we may say that knowledge is the self. But the self, inasmuch as it is the seat of innumerable properties (dharma), may be knowledge owing to its property of knowledge, while owing to some other property it may be something else. Moreover, the manysided view (anekant) here prevails. By the one-sided view (ekanta), according to which the self is knowledge, the non-existence of Page #256 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 230 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES knowledge would be the absence of consciousness (chetanatva); or (in other words) the non-existence of the self would follow from the absence of its characteristic qualities (vishesha-guna). (For), were the self in every respect knowledge, then, in the case of absence of knowledge (i.e. when the self is in another state than cognition) there would arise for the self non-existence of its other modifications, as having no basis, and of itself also, since it is necessarily-concomitant (avinabhavin) with these. Now he refutes a mutual approach of knowledge and knowable: 28. The knower possesses knowledge as his innate nature; the objects, surely, possess the character of knowables with regard to the knower, like shapes or forms with reference to the eye. But they do not abide in each other. The knower and the objects, owing to their separateness (prthakatva), which forms their individual-nature (sva-lakshan), do not possess occurrence within each other; but they merely possess a mutually related occurrence, effected by the relation between their innate natures as knowledge and knowable. For instance, as the eyes and the things having shapes or forms, which are their objects are respectively ready to receive and to occasion the appearances of the knowables, even without mutual penetration, so the self and the objects are ready to receive and to occasion the appearances of all knowables, without being identical with one another. Now he explains the variety in efficacy which causes the activity (vrtti) of the knower towards the objects, although he is inactive (avrtta) with reference to them: 29. The knower, neither entering nor shunning to enter the knowables, verily, in consequence of his surpassing the sense-organs, knows and sees the whole world, as the eye knows and sees the shapes or forms, i.e. the objects of sight. Just as the eye, not entering, i.e. not taking hold of the shapes or forms of the substances with its own spacial-infinitesimal-constituents (pradeshas), nor shunning to enter them, i.e. really appropriating their distinguishable appearances, knows and sees, likewise the soul of which, since it surpasses the sense-organs, we need not doubt at all that it acts independently of approach? not entering, i.e. not taking hold, with its own pradeshas, of all the things which function as knowables, nor shunning to enter them. i.e. as it were uprooting and Page #257 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 231 then devouring all the knowable appearances which abide in the things, with the aid of the manifoldness of its efficacy, knows and sees. So that, as concerns the knower, who develops an activity (yoga) of manifold efficacy, his entrance into the things attains just as much reality as his non-entrance. Now he explains how knowledge is located in the things: 30. As the sapphire-gem, placed in milk, by its own splendour constantly dominates (the colour of the milk or pervades the whole of it with its lustre, so is knowledge related to the objects. Just as the sapphire-gem, located in milk, is observed to dominate or pervade it constantly with the mass of its splendour, so see we that consciousness (samvedana), which, because it is not separated from the self, receives the character of the self in its function of agent, constantly in its function of instrument, i.e. in its character of knowledge, pervades all the knowable appearances (as effects) of all the objects (as causes). So, when it is metaphorically said, by reason of their relation of cause and effect, that "knowledge, dominating or pervading the objects, abides (in them),” there is no contradiction. Now he explains how the objects abide in knowledge: 31. If the objects do not exist in knowledge, then knowledge is not all-pervasive or omnipresent; alternatively, if knowledge is allpervasive or omnipresent, how should the objects not exist or abide in knowledge? If all the objects do not appear in knowledge, by penetrating into it and committing to it their own complete knowable appearances, then we must agree that knowledge is not omnipresent. But if you agree that it is omnipresent, then the immediate (sakshat) causes of their own respective appearances, which are fit-objects-forconsciousness (samvedya) and may be compared to reflected-objects, coming down to the surface of the mirror of consciousness, are the indirect (paramparaya) causes of appearances-in-our-consciousness (samvedya), which appearances may be compared to the reflectionimages (when located in the mirror of consciousness). So then it is ascertained (read katham na) that the objects abide in knowledge. Now he explains the complete isolation (viviktatva) of (the Omniscient) who sees and determines everything; for, although there is a mutual activity (anyonya-vrtti) of knower and objects, yet neither does he take hold of them, nor let them loose, nor evolve into them: Page #258 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 32. The Holy Omniscient Lord or the Absolute Knower does not seize (accept) or release and does not evolve into anything else; but without exception he sees and knows everything all around. · This self, because according to its innate nature no seizing, no releasing, no evolution into anything else takes place, evolves owing to its characteristic nature of absolute (kevala) knowledge, which is its own principle (tattva), and thus, standing forth like a genuine jewel of motionless and radiant light, it possesses an everywhere glittering efficacy of vision and knowledge; so then it becomes by itself in itself aware of the self in its entirety without remainder. Or, to explain otherwise, by a simultaneous, intuitive-perception (sakshat-karana) of the multitude of all things wavering of notion is excluded, and there is cessation of all supposed acts such as grasping or releasing; in this way (the self as Omniscient Lord or the Absolute Knower), by firstly evolving into all distinguishable appearances and then again not evolving into any appearance, yet sees and knows everything without exception everywhere, whilst remaining in isolation (read vivikta eva). Now he makes an end to the craving (akanksha) to know the difference between a kevala-jnanin (possessor of absolute-knowledge) and a shruta-jnanin (possessor of scriptural-knowledge), by showing that there is non-difference: 33. He who by means of scripture knows the self, which in innate nature is something-knowing (jnayaka), is called by the rshis (sages), the lights of this world, a shruta-kevalin (possessor of absolute knowledge, due to the knowledge of scripture). In the same way as the Holy One is a kevalin (possessor of absolute-knowledge) by means of his realization (samchetana) — by the aid of his absolute-knowledge, amply provided with all the particular forms of consciousness (chaitanya) simultaneously evolved of the self in the self by the self, which self is absolute because it is one with its natural knowing capacity (chetaka-svabhava), and which is (the same as) the great general consciousness (chaitanya), realized by him (sva-samchetyamana) as beginningless and endless, uncaused and unparalleled, likewise is this man a shruta-kevalin by means of his realization—by the aid of his scripture-knowledge, amply provided with several particular forms of consciousness successively evolved of the self in the self by the self, which self is absolute because it is one with its natural knowing capacity (chetaka-svabhava), and which is (the Page #259 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE same as) the great general consciousness, realized as beginningless and endless, uncaused and unparalleled. Enough now of this craving to know the difference (between the kevalin and shruta-kevalin)! We stand firm in our characteristic-nature. Now he refutes with reference to knowledge a distinction based on the shruta as an additional condition (upadhi): 34. The “sutra” is taught by the Jina with words consisting of material-substance. The understanding of it is called both the understanding of the sutra and knowledge. Now scripture is the sutra, and that is the sacred science as the word, materialized with the expression quodammodo” (syadvada) as a characteristic, and first pronounced by the Holy Omniscient Arhat. Knowledge is the understanding of it. The expression “the word heard” (shruta) is metaphorically used for knowledge, inasmuch as it is the cause thereof. Consequently the understanding of the sutra means as much as “scripture-knowledge.” If this “ sutra” is disregarded, because it is an additional-condition (upadhi), then the understanding is left (as that which is essential). And this understanding by the kevalin and the shruta-kevalin is equal in regard to the realization of the self. Therefore there is no division of knowledge due to scripture as a condition. Now he refutes the division which is made between self and knowledge, based upon their functions as agent and instrument: 35. He who knows is knowledge; but the self does not by the help of its knowledge become something-that-is-knowing (inayaka); knowledge evolves by itself, and all the objects reside in knowledge. He who knows by himself-because his self develops an activity (yoga) of the highest supremacy in efficacy, in which agency and instrumentality are united-is knowledge; in the same way as we call fire-in which there rests independently a most effective efficacy of heat-hot, because its action in burning is patent. But the self does not become something-that-is-knowing as Devadatta becomes a cutter owing to a separately existing knife. If it were so (i.e. If the self only became knowing by a separately existing knowledge), then both (i.e. self and knowledge) would be unconscious, and on the conjunction of two unconscious entities no distinguishing could arise. And, even if we accept a process of distinguishing in two entities existing one outside (i.e. independently of each other) the Page #260 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 234 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES other, then a distinguishing in the one in consequence of a process of distinguishing in the other, and an origination of distinction, bearing on objective-being (bhuti), etc., would be without any rule. Furthermore, knowledge evolves into all the distinguishable appearances which exist besides knowledge; and we may say that all the objects which are the causes of all the knowable appearances, which are (really) the effects of this self-evolving knowledge, in a certain way reside in knowledge. So then the forced supposition (klesha kalpana) of a separation of knower and knowledge is superfluous.' Now he explains what knowledge is and what the knowable: 36. Therefore the soul is knowledge; and substance, explained as threefold, is the knowable. This substance then is the self and "the other" evolutions. Since the soul itself evolves in the form of distinguishing and distinguishes by itself independently, therefore the soul alone is knowledge; for other substances cannot evolve and distinguish in this way. But the knowable is substance, which is without beginning and end; for it is connected with the three aspects of time, inasmuch as it shows a varying series of modifications in past, present and future. And this substance, possessing the property of being knowable, is twofold, i.e. it is divided into the self and the other.” For we must accept such a twoness in the object of an experienced, which is aware of a distinction of the self and the other. But in this paragraph the author discusses self-consciousness) how (it is asked) can there be a distinguishing of the self, since it is contradictory that an act should take place upon one's self? Well, what is this act and what the contradiction means? The act which is (supposed to be) contradictory is either origination or understanding (jnapti). An act of (spontaneous) origination, however, is contradictory: since according to the words of scripture not one thing originates from itself. But no refutation occurs with reference to an act in the form of understanding; for the difficulty here is removed by conformity with the act of illuminating. For when a lamp, as illuminator, illuminates another thing as illumin and, then for its own illumination we need not search for a second illumination, since we observe an act of illuminating on its own part; similarly, when the self, as distinguisher, distinguishes something else as distinguend, then for its own distinction Page #261 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 235 we need not search for a second distinguisher, since we observe an act of distinguishing on its own part. Whence is it that the self has the form of knowledge of the substances; and the substances that of knowables for the self? Because they are connected with evolutions. Since self and substances are connected with their evolutions, therefore the evolution of self through knowledge, which finds its basis in the substances, and the evolution of the substances through knowable appearances, which base themselves on the knowledge, appear to be not contradictory. Now he explains how past and future modifications of the substances may be separately contents of knowledge, just as well as those which take place in the present time: 37. All the modifications, existent and non-existent, of these kinds of substances appear, with their particularities, in knowledge, like those of the present. All possible modifications, existent and non-existent, with the fullness of their characteristic natures appearing successively (which is due to the fact that the stages through which their self-realization passes are defined by the three times) all these modifications of all kinds of substances receive at one (The commentator explains the gathas as referring to perfect-knowledge) moment their place on the white-wall of attention (avabodha), with all their particular characteristics well marked notwithstanding the utmost blending, and they appear even as those of the present. And this is not unfit. For, firstly, it is not contradicted by our dailyexperience (drshta). Namely, when even a chadmastha (someone who has not reached absolute-knowledge) reflects on a past or future thing (vastu), its appearance (akara) founded on consciousness is perceived, as in the case of reflection on a present thing. And, secondly, consciousness (samvid) may be compared to a picture. As delineable appearances of past, future, and present things are immediately visible in a picture at one moment, so happens on the wall of consciousness. And lastly, all knowable appearances are not contradictory to present time. As delineable appearances of past and future events are present, so are the knowable appearances of past and future modifications present. Now he explains how non-existent modifications are in a certain respect existent: Page #262 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 236 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 38. The modifications, which have not yet originated, and those which after origination have disappeared. Those non-existent modifications are yet directly perceptible (pratyaksha) to knowledge. The modifications which do not yet partake of origination, and those which have gone to annihilation after having originated what they are, are although non-existent, well-defined with reference to mental-distinction and therefore liable to immediate-perception by means of knowledge; so then they are existent, since their characteristic nature has been planted firmly, like past and future gods hewn out in stone columns. Now he confirms this fact that non-existent things can be perceived by knowledge: 39. If a not yet arisen and an annihilated modification were not directly perceptible to knowledge, who would call that knowledge divine (divya)? If knowledge does not (insert na before karoti) cause the whole set of modifications, with their forms-of-being not yet experienced or previously experienced, to be bound to the self, whilst it in force invades (akramya) these modifications with its great power of splendour, opening out without impediment and unbroken, so that the entirety of their characteristic-natures is simultaneously (akrama) delivered up, how could there be any divinity in this knowledge? Therefore all this is possible for discernment, when it reaches the highest point. Now he examines how sensorial knowledge cannot know that which has passed or has not yet arisen: 40. Those who, by means of iha ("the readiness to know more"), etc., know the object present to the senses are not capable of knowing that which transcends the senses; thus it is taught. Those who, accepting "contact" of objects and sense-organs, i.e. a coming together of the object-of-perception (vishaya) and the perceiver-of-the-object (vishayi), distinguish by means of iha, etc., which arise successively, cannot distinguish the concrete-existence (svastitva) which has passed, nor the time of the concrete-existence not yet arisen, owing to the impossibility (in this case) of the described relation of "thing-to-be-grasped" (grahya) and "grasper." Now he states that everything that may be mentioned falls under the reach of supra-sensorial knowledge: Page #263 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 237 41. The knowledge which grasps things with or without spacepoints, corporeal (murta) and incorporeal things, modifications not yet arisen and modifications annihilated, is called supra-sensorial knowledge. Sensorial knowledge takes place by the aid of indication (upadesh), the internal organ, the sense-organs, etc., as heterogeneous (virupa, heterogeneous, i.e. non-intellectual) causes, and the becoming aware, the putting together (of ideas), etc., as internal and homogeneous (read sarupa instead of svarupa) causes. And, when it takes place, it perceives-with-certainty only things which possess space-points (pradeshas), because it perceives what is gross (sthula); but it does not ascertain things which lack these spacepoints. It apprehends only corporeal things, because its existence depends upon such-like objects-of-the-senses; but it does not comprehend incorporeal things. It distinguishes merely that which is in present time, because only then can the object-to-be-perceived and the perceiver encounter each other; but it does not distinguish that which has happened and will happen. But for knowledge (knowledge and self are here identical) free from obscurations (avarana) and loose from the senses—just as fuel, characterized by various nature, remains fuel for the lightened fire, because the property of being combustible is not outgone,—thus for the self (both the thing-with-space-points and) the thing-without-suchspace-points, the corporeal as well as the incorporeal, the not yet arisen and the past set of modifications are distinguishable, because they do not outgo the property of being knowable. Now he expresses his belief that the act, i.e. the evolution into the knowable object, does not spring forth from (superior) knowledge: 42. If the knower evolves into the knowable object (to evolve into the object = to identity oneself with the object, to feel attachment for it), then he does not possess kshayika-knowledge (knowledge which appears on the destruction of karman); thus the best of Jinas have declared him to be experiencing or enjoying the fruit of karmans. If the distinguisher evolves into the thing to be distinguished, then there is not found in him an innate (svabhavika) cause (nidana) of distinction, engaged in destroying the whole capital of karmans, or, in other words, he does not possess knowledge. For the best of Jinas declare him whose mind is an instrument for the experience Page #264 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 238 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES (sambhavana) of the water of the mirage, by reason of his evolution into the respective objects, to be experiencing (merely) the heavy burden of karmans. Now he investigates whence the act, i.e. the evolution into the knowable thing, and its fruit originate: 43. It is said by the best of Jinas that as a result of karmanparticles coming into operation or rise,' he who is filled with infatuation, attachment and aversion necessarily incurs bondage. The soul abiding in the cycle of existences of necessity possesses particles of material-karman in the origination-stage. And he who, being conscious of their existence, evolves into infatuation, attachment or aversion, joins himself with action, which consists in evolution into the knowable thing. Therefore he experiences bondage, which is the fruit of action. So then action and the fruit of action originate from the arising of infatuation, but not from knowledge. Now he teaches that in the case of Absolute-Sages even the act does not produce the fruit of the action: 44. Standing, sitting down, moving about and teaching of moral rules, etc. activities, which are necessary activities for the Arhats at times, are similar to the (natural] activities of maya (mata, i.e. mother) in the case of women. As women, without any effort, simply because their aptitudes are such, show a natural conduct enveloped in an envelopment of deceit, so the Absolute-Sages, without any effort, simply because their aptitudes are such, perform natural deeds such as standing, sitting, wandering and teaching the law. And this is not contradictory; for we have the example of the cloud. Just indeed as movement, rest, resounding and the throwing out of water are seen in the matter (pudgala) evolved into the form of a cloud, whilst no human effort takes place, thus occur standing, etc., in the Absolute-Sages, without attendant consciousness. Therefore this standing, etc., although kinds of action, are, since they are not preceded by the rising of infatuation, no causes of bondage, i.e. of the fruit of action, in the case of Absolute-Sages. Now he makes it clear that consequently the ripening of merits (punya) has no effect for the Tirthankaras. 45. The Arhats owe their status to or enjoy the fruit of their merits; but their activities, though consequence of or originating from Page #265 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 239 rising-karman (audayika-karman), are exempt from infatuation, etc.; therefore it is considered to be annihilative (kshayika). For the Arhats the fruits of the Wishing-tree of merits are generally and completely full-ripe. Whatever action takes place in them is originated-from-rising-karman, since the self's capacities (sambhuti) are realized (sambhavita) by the experience of this rise (of karmans). Thus even action as described, taking place when the residence of the anointed king Great-Infatuation is utterly destroyed, does not acquire a causality with reference to changes in the spiritual-principle (chaitanya), because the affecting or colouring (uparanjaka) factors, namely infatuation, attachment and aversion, do not exist. So then this act, although always of an originative (audayika) nature, is at the same time annihilative, inasmuch as it is not a cause of bondage (as effect), but is a cause of liberation (as effect). For surely, if this were not accepted, then the ripening of their karmans would tend to the deterioration of their innate nature. Now he refutes the opinion that, just as in the case of AbsoluteSages, so with anybody no deterioration of innate being takes place: 46. If the self by itself, by innate nature, were devoid of auspicious or inauspicious (good or evil) psychic dispositions, then there would be no samsara (transmigratory existence) in the case of embodied beings. If the self absolutely does not evolve through its innate nature of good and evil states, then it abides merely in the pure innate state without deterioration, at every time, under every circumstance. And so all the multitudes of beings would enjoy eternal emancipation, because of their being devoid of all causes of bondage; for their innate nature would be free of its restless unrest." Now this is not admitted; the self, that is, having the property of its evolution, shows a good or evil nature in the same way as the crystal shows as innate nature the colour of the China rose or the Tamala flower. Now again, in connection with the subject under discussion, he greets supra-sensorial knowledge as omniscience: 47. That knowledge which simultaneously (yugapat) knows presently existent things (and) the other objects, all in every direction, various and dissimilar as they may be, is called kshayiki (i.e. the result of the destruction of karmans). Knowledge due-to-annihilation knows in one moment indeed both Page #266 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 240 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES the object with an occurrence in the same time and the object with an occurrence in past or future time, and knows them in all directions completely, although they possess a variety (vaichitrya), showing itself in separateness, individual, accidental, and manifested in several forms, and a dissimilarity (vaishamya), accentuated by mutual opposition and called forth by their generic differences. To this knowledge are simultaneously (tulya-kalam) revealed the multitude of objects coexistent and the multitude of objects belonging to another time, because of the total absence of knowledge-obscuring (jnanavaraniya) karmic matter in the destructional-subsidential state, 12 which is the cause of the coming forth in succession. And (these multitudes of contemporary and not contemporary objects) are revealed (to the soul) in every direction, inasmuch as it is purified in every respect, whilst the purification in a limited respect is merged therein. And all objects are revealed to it, because, as all obscuring karmans perish, the partially-obscuring destructional-subsidential condition (of karmans) no longer persists. Objects, even various, are revealed, because, as the karman which obscures omniform knowledge perishes, the destructional-subsidential condition of karman which obscures non-omniform knowledge is dissolved. Objects, even dissimilar, are revealed because, as the karman which obscures heterogenous knowledge perishes, the destructionalsubsidential condition of karman which obscures homogeneous knowledge is on the decline. But enough of over-elaboration: knowledge due-to-the-annihilationof-karman (kshayika) necessarily knows everything everywhere at every time and in every respect; for it abounds in illumination whose coming forth is unchecked. Now he certifies that one who does not know everything does not know even one thing: 48. He who does not know simultaneously the objects located in the three worlds (heavens, hells and earth) and three times is not capable of knowing even one substance with all its modifications. There is one space-substance, one substance called the principle of motion, one substance called the principle of stationariness, innumerable time-substances in every infinitesimal-particle of space Page #267 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 241 there is one time), an unlimited number of soul-substances, and material substances in an unlimitedly more unlimited number. The modifications of these substances, considered one by one, are unlimited, whirling round in a series of existences without limitation, divided into the kinds past, future and present. The knowable, then, is all this collected; and confronting it there is only some single soulsubstance as knower. Then, as a fire, burning all fuel, evolves into a self which has the appearance of one total fire that evolves through all the modifications of the appearances of the fuel, appearances due to all these fuels, so the knower, knowing all knowables, evolves into a self which has the appearance of one total knowledge that evolves through all the modifications of the appearances of the knowables, appearances due to all these knowables; into a self which is perceptible for self-experience (svanubhava), because it is a spiritual-being (chetana). Thus indeed is the innate nature of the substances. But he who does not know every knowable is like a fire that does not burn every fuel and so does not evolve (read atmanam aparinaman dahana iva) into a self which has the appearance of one total fire that evolves through all the modifications of the appearances of fuel, appearances due to all these fuels; similarly (he who does not know everything) does not evolve into a self which has the appearance of one total knowledge that evolves through all the modifications of the appearances of the knowables, appearances due to all these knowables; and this holds true, although the self, as a spiritual being, remains perceptible for self-experience. Thus it appears that he who does not know everything does not know the self. Now he certifies that one who does not know one thing does not know all things: 49. If one does not know one substance with its unlimited modifications, or the unlimited number of kinds of substances how should he know everything simultaneously? The self is merely knowledge, since only as consisting of knowledge is it a knower. Knowledge, on the other hand, is a great generality (chaitanya-samanya-mahiman), consisting of illumination (pratibhasamaya) and occurring in the individual souls. And this (great-generality) penetrates infinite species (visheshas) (species of consciousness=forms of knowledge=notions concerning objects) in phenomenal form; and these again find their basis in the modifications of all substances. Page #268 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 242 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Suppose, now, that one cannot by his self-experience perceive the self in this form of a great generality which in phenomenal form penetrates infinite species, based on the modifications of all substances; how could this man embrace in his perception all the modifications of substances, which modifications are the basis of the infinite species in phenomenal form penetrated by a great-generality in phenomenal form? Thus it appears that he who does not know the self does not know all things. So then it is proved that from omniscience arises self-knowledge, from self-knowledge omniscience. Consequently, although knower and knowable really differ from the self, which, consisting only of knowledge, possesses consciousness in itself, yet the phenomenon and that which appears encounter each other in their common condition in such a way that it is totally impossible to separate them; so then everything is as it were implanted (nikhata) in the self. And, if this were not so, then, since the knowledge would not meet with complete consciousness in the self, neither could the knowledge be proved to belong to a single complete self. Now he certifies that omnipresence of knowledge does not take place by a process going on successively: . 50. If the knowledge of the knower arises by way of successive awareness of the objects, then it is not eternal, not the result of theannihilation-of-karman, and not omnipresent. Knowledge which arises by supporting itself successively now on this, then on that object is not eternal; for it arises whilst relating to one object, and perishes whilst it is directed towards another object. Neither is it due-to-karman-annihilation; for it receives one specializedform (vyakti) and again another through the arising of karmic matter. Nor, lastly, is it omnipresent; for it is unable to dominate the infinite substances, places, time and forms-of-being (dravya-kshetra-kala-bhava). Now it is settled that omnipresence of knowledge is secured simply by a process of simultaneity: 51. The (knowledge) of the Jina [(jonham=jaina-jnanam (Tatparyavrtti)=jainam (Tattva-dipika). On the grandeur of (that) knowledge, it knows simultaneously all things, which are constantly altered by the three times, in their entirety in all places and varieties. Knowledge due to the annihilation of karman is a supreme greatness of knowledge, an abode of transcendence. When knowledge proceeds by basing itself simultaneously on all objects, then it assumes an eternal Page #269 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 243 nature owing to its finding a place for the appearances of all knowable objects, steady as if carved by an axe (tankotkirna), and its kshayikaness appears with its true nature, manifested by the fact that it reaches all individual-objects (vyakti). Discerning, in its entirety, the great-multitude of all objects (sarvartha-sambhutim corresponds with sarvatra sambhavam in the gatha), constantly altered by the three times and possessing a manifoldness due to innumerable genera-this knowledge, displaying a wonderful grandeur, is omnipresent, inasmuch as it simultaneously arrives at the innumerable substances, places, times and forms-ofbeing. Now, summarizing, he denies, in the case of an action of comprehension (jnapti) by a knower, bondage as fruit of the action: 52/1. The self does not evolve into the objects, does not grasp them, and does not arise in them [i.e. is not produced by them or become one of them], although it knows them; therefore it is said to be free from bondage. In sutra, 43 the author has taught that, when the particles of material karman are at the rising stage, then in consequence thereof, the soul while being conscious of this, evolves itself into infatuation, attachment and aversion, and thus being united with action in the form of evolution into the knowable object, experiences bondage as fruit of that action; but this is not due to knowledge, since bondage was at the outset explained as the fruit of the action of evolution into the object. And since in sutra 32 he has ascribed to the pure self a nonexistence of actions such as evolution into objects, bondage, in the form of the fruit of action, does not happen to the self, though an action of awareness or understanding (jnapti) takes place, since it does not evolve into the objects, does not grasp them, or arise in them. "When owing to the absence of infatuation the self, although knowing completely and simultaneously everything, present, future and past, does not evolve into the other (para, the other),' all its karmic matter being hewn off (annihilated), then it remains liberated, a manifestation of knowledge, illuminating separately and non-separately the threefold world, whilst the knowable appearances are swallowed (pita, i.e. drunk, enjoyed) by the expansion of its mightily unfolded understanding." (PS Kalash 4) Page #270 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 244 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Here ends the section KNOWLEDGE Now, detailing the characteristic nature of happiness, not divided from knowledge, he considers how both knowledge and happiness are sometimes to be abandoned and sometimes to be accepted: EXPOSITION OF JOY (VERSES 53-68) 53. There is with reference to objects, material (murta) and immaterial, a supra-sensorial and a sensorial knowledge; and similar is the case of happiness; what then of these is the best, should be known. Now knowledge and happiness which are material and born from the senses are one thing. And the immaterial and supra-sensorial are a second. Of these four the immaterial and supra-sensorial should be known as by reason of their superiority acceptable. The former of these, arising—by means of material energies of psychic-attention for which combined-annihilation-and-precipitationof-karman is characteristic—from such-like sense-organs, is accidental, owing to dependence on outside factors; it proceeds by succession, finds opposition, is subject to increase and decrease; for this reason this knowledge and happiness, as being destructive, should be abandoned. The second pair, arising, by means of immaterial energies of selfevolution, which are obedient to intelligence and are unaccompanied, from the like supra-sensorial evolutions of natural thought-appearance, is eternal owing to its absolute dependence on the self; it proceeds simultaneously, does not find opposition, is devoid of increase and decrease; for this reason this knowledge and happiness, as being primary, should be accepted. Now he praises supra-sensorial knowledge as acceptable, being a means to supra-sensorial happiness: 54. The knowledge of him who beholds the immaterial, the suprasensorial in material objects (murtani), and the hidden, complete, (embracing) the self and the other, is called pratyaksha (direct/ immediate):13 . Now supra-sensorial knowledge beholds the immaterial, the suprasensorial even in material objects, and the hidden complete (rcad yat sakalam), whether included in own or in other. Such knowledge surely is a seer, owing to its immediateness, with reference to— immaterial Page #271 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 245 (amurta) substances, such as the principles of motion and stationariness, material, but supra-sensorial substances, such as the ultimate atom, that which is hidden in respect of substance, e.g. time; that which is hidden in respect of place, e.g. the pradeshas of space locates outside the world; that which is hidden in time, e.g. nonpresent modifications; that which is hidden in respect of forms-ofbeing, namely fine (sukshma) modifications latent within gross (sthula) modifications; thus with reference to all things, distinguished as own and other. Immediate knowledge indeed, bound to a single self, called the aksha (aksha, from which pratyaksha is derived, is taken as a synonym of atman), and having the immediacy of its manifested infinite purity and beginningless connection with the generality of perfect intelligence (siddha-chaitanya-samanya), does not search for exterior means (read itara-samagrim), enjoys infinity, because of its possession of infinite energies. Knowledge enjoying such prestige, seeing that the knowable appearances no more outgo knowledge than combustible appearances the fire, what can resist such knowledge? Therefore it is acceptable (upadeya). But now he rebukes sensorial knowledge, cause of sensorial pleasure, as deserving rejection: 55. The soul in itself immaterial or incorporeal, 14 becoming incorporeal in material form and then, apprehending with this material (form or body), the material (world), sometimes knows and sometimes does not know that-which-is-fit-for-knowledge (yogya). Sensorial knowledge requires a material instrument-of-perception (upalambhaka) and a material object-of-perception (upalabhya). The soul, in possession of this, although itself immaterial, occupying the material body, provided with the five sensories, apprehends with the material body, as instrument of perception, by way of the applications of its forces (bala)?s to the production of notion (inapti), the material thing, predominantly touch, etc., which, having acquired the propertyof-being-perceptible (upalabhyata), is fit-for-knowledge: and by this apprehension the soul sometimes—repeatedly—if pureness recurs in regard to it, grasps the object, but sometimes, owing to the lack of pureness, does not grasp, by reason of indirectness (parokshatva). Indirect knowledge-based on an extreme unsteadiness in the self, which, in consequence of being enveloped in a knot of very dense Page #272 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 246 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES ignorance-darkness, has its eye closed and in spite of its beginningless connection with the generality of perfect intelligence is unable by itself to distinguish the object, and distracted in a search for the apparatus of exterior means, which it partially obtains and partially does not obtain; excessively enfeebled through the loss of its unlimited energy; and, though aiming at evolution into the other, at every step disappointed because the wrestler Great-Infatuation (maha-moha) is still alive-deserves according to deeper truth (paramarthatah) to be regarded as non-comprehension (anupalambha). Hence it should be abandoned. Now he observes that, since the organs of sense are not capable of proceeding simultaneously towards the totality of their objects, sensorial knowledge must be abandoned: 56. Touch, taste, smell, colour and sound are the material objects (pudgalas) for the sense-organs; the sense-organs do not grasp them simultaneously. The substrata of touch, taste, smell and colour, moreover sound (sound is a material substance according to Jainism), are material objects, fit for being grasped by the sense-organs. But even they are not grasped by the sense-organs simultaneously; for the requisite energy due to destructive subsidence is not present. In the case of the senseorgans the interior discerning efficacy, which is termed destructivesubsidence of [knowledge-obscuring)- karman, proceeds successively, like a crow's eyeball," and is incapable of illuminating in many directions; hence, although the communications between sense-organs and objects are open, an awareness (avabodha) of the objects of all the senses will not take place simultaneously, because of the indirectness (of sensorial experience). Now he ascertains that sensorial knowledge is not direct: 57. The sense-organs are called an exterior (para) substance, and not an innate nature of the self; how then could that which is grasped by them be direct or immediate perception for the self? Absolute knowledge (kevala-jnana), belonging to the absolute (kevala) self, is immediate. But that which arises through observation by means of the sense-organs, which have not the slightest connection with the innate nature of the self and are allotted to the group of exterior substances, inasmuch as they are provided with a separate existence, cannot be immediate-perception for the self. Page #273 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 247 Now he gives in addition a sub-definition of indirect and immediate knowledge: 58. Knowledge of objects from another (agency, i.e. the senses) is called indirect; but, if knowledge is acquired by the soul alone (kevala-jiva), then it is indeed direct. If discrimination of a thing which has become an object-ofknowledge to us is brought about by something other, which functions as a means, whether inner sensorium, a sense-organ, information by another person, a positive-probans (upalabdhi), latent-physicalimpression (samskara), or light, etc., then this knowledge, arising from another, is indicated as indirect. But discrimination which, disregarding every exterior substance, whether internal-organ, organ-of-sense, information by another person, positive-probans, latent-physical-impression, or light, and whatever else of that kind, and taking its own nature as sole cause, in its rise embraces simultaneously all the modifications of all substances, this discrimination is indicated as direct knowledge, since it arises from the self alone. Here accordingly this, being means to natural (sahaja) pleasure, is approved as the Great-Direct-Knowledge. puts forward this immediate knowledge as supremely real Now he happiness: 59. Knowledge, self-born, complete, extended over an infinite number of objects, stainless, devoid of stages such as avagraha (apprehension of an object or sensation), is called exclusive joy. Since it is self-born, complete, extented over an infinite number of objects, without stain, devoid of stages such as avagraha, this immediate knowledge is ascertained to be exclusive joy. For the one definition of happiness is absence of perturbation. Indirect knowledge, in fact, is excessively perturbed by dependence on something else; since it arises from something else; closure of the other doors of knowledge; since it is incomplete; wish to know other objects; since it is connected with [only] a certain number of objects; imperfect awareness (a-samyag-avabodha); since it is stained; fatigue of successively taking up the objects; since it is bound to stages such as avagraha. Hence it is not ultimately real (paramarthatah) happiness. But this knowledge is unperturbed by reason ofself-dependence, since, being born from itself, it stands of itself Page #274 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 248 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES extending with great expansion over the inner nature of the beginningless generality of knowledge; opening of all doors, since, complete in the form of the psychicattention of supreme, immediate knowledge, it stands pervading all the spacial units of the self (read: samastatma-pradeshan); freedom from all desire to know things, since, extended over an infinite number of objects, it stands pervading a supreme multifariety wherein are exhausted the knowable appearances of all things; perfect awareness, since, stainless, transcending all karmans which impede its complete energy, it stands pervading its own nature brilliant with clearest light; freedom from the trouble of successively taking up the objects, since, devoid of stages such as avagraha, it stands pervading the world and that which is beyond the world, which simultaneously yield up their characteristic three-time nature. Hence it is ultimate happiness. Now he refutes the opinion that for the Absolute-Sage even exclusive happiness does not exist, since by the door of evolution trouble (kheda) is possible: 60. The knowledge, which is called Absolute or omniscience (kevalajnana) is happiness, and it is evolution; no trouble therefrom is mentioned; for the destructive karmans are gone to annihilation, i.e. destroyed. As to this: what trouble? what evolution? what difference between pure knowledge and joy, so that pure knowledge should not be joy? The destructive karmans are abodes of trouble; but mere evolution simply is not such. For, since the destructive karmans, creating the great infatuation and instilling the notion of A in regard to non-A, as with one disordered in intellect, cause (read parinamayanti) the self to evolve in regard to an object to be discerned, therefore they become a source (nidana) of trouble (for the soul), which grows wearied in evolving again and again from object to object. But in pure knowledge, as these are absent, how can there be outbreaks of distress? And, since Absolute Knowledge, evolving by itself, possessing an unlimited characteristic nature, resembling a picture-wall (chitra-bhitti), serving as locus for the manifestation of the manifoldness of the discernible appearances belonging to all objects (padartha) characterized by the three times—since this Absolute Knowledge is itself the Page #275 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 249 evolution, how can there be any other evolution by which trouble can come to pass? Add, since simply Absolute Knowledge—while, with its infinite energies in free play owing to absence of all impediments to its proper nature, it pervades the whole three-time appearance of world and nonworld, yet stands in its aloofness absolutely immobile and having undistinguished from itself a freedom from perturbation which is the mark of happiness—is happiness, whence a difference between Absolute Knowledge and happiness? Hence absolute knowledge should by all means be agreed to be exclusively joy. Now again describing the identity of perfect knowledge with joy, he summarizes: 61. This knowledge reaches the limits of (all) objects; it is an intuition (drshti) expanded over the physical and super-physical universe; in it everything that is undesirable is destroyed, but everything desirable is attained. Happiness indeed is caused by the absence of hindrances to one's innate nature. Intuition and intellect are the innate nature of the self. And there does not exist any hindrance to them, since they both open out at will, expanding over the world and the non-world and reaching the limits of objects. Hence happiness caused by this is, if we wish to express the non-difference (abheda), the characteristic nature of perfect knowledge. But, moreover, absolute knowledge is simply happiness, because in it all undesirables are given up and all desirables are obtained. For in the condition of absolute knowledge, since every ignorance which leads to pain, the opposite to the reaching of joy, perishes, and since complete knowledge, leading to joy, arises, therefore absolute knowledge is happiness—so enough of amplification! Now he would have us believe that supremely-real (paramarthika) joy belongs only to Absolute-Sages: 62. The not-qualified (abhavya) 18 do not believe, when they hear that among joys the highest happiness is that of those whose destructive karmans have vanished; but the qualified admit it. To those who have abundance of infatuating and other karmans there may be here a semblance of joy; but because of hindrances to their inner nature and because of perturbation it is an unreal (aparamarthika), popular use of the word “joy”. But the holy Absolute Page #276 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 250 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Sages, whose destructive karmans are annihilated, being free from repugnance to their innate nature and from perturbation, have a joy supremely real, since the above described cause is present and the definition applies. Thus we must believe. But those, not-qualified, who have not this belief, are far from the nectar-beverage of the joy of liberation, and only see the watermass of a mirage. Those, again, who forthwith accept this world, worthy receptacles of auspicious bliss, are qualified-from near (samasanna-bhavya); but those who accept it for the future are qualifiedfrom-far (dura-bhavya). Now he examines the sensorial joy, not supremely real, of those who possess indirect knowledge (paroksa-jnana): 63. The lords of men, demons and gods, oppressed by their natural (sahaja) organs of sense, unable to withstand that misery, find pleasure in satisfying (ramya) objects. Those creatures who through lack of immediate knowledge take refuge in indirect knowledge have a congënial affection for their organs of sense, which are the equipment therefor. So in these persons, having this affection for their sense-organs and, while devoured by the flaring kala-fire" of great infatuation, utterly longing and thirsty, like heated balls of iron (These cause an immediate evaporation of the water fallen on them), and unable to withstand the vehemence of this misery, there arises a satisfaction (rati) with these satisfying (ramya) objects, which serve to soothe their disease. Hence, since the sense-organs must be compared to a disease and the objects to means for soothing the disease, no really-true joy exists for those who have.a limited knowledge (chadmastha). Now he argues that misery is natural as long as there are senseorgans: 64. Know misery to be natural in those who find satisfaction in sense-objects; for, if this were not natural, there would not be any on their part for obtaining the objects of senses. In those for whom these detestable sense-organs are alive (jivadavastha) misery does not depend on accidental-conditions (upadhi), but is natural; for we see their satisfaction with the sense-objects. We behold how, enslaved by the feelings of their incontrollable senses, they rush (abhipata) for objects, although on the point of perishing (asanna-nipata); like the elephant for the touch (sparsha) of Page #277 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 251 the harlot she-elephant; the carp for the taste (svada) of the bait on the hook; the bee for the fragrance (amoda) of the aravinda on the point of closing; the moth for the visual-appearance (rupa) of the lampflame; the antelope for the sound (svara) of the hunter's song. But, if we could admit that their misery was not natural, then this activity of theirs towards sense-objects would not be seen any more than perspiration in one cured of cold fevers, use of aranala-gruel by a patient cured of inflammatory fever, salving with the vata-salve by one whose affection of the eye has passed, filling with calf's urine (read vatsa-mutra) by one who no longer suffers from ear-ache, application of a salve by one whose wound has closed. But it is seen. Hence the possessors of indirect knowledge, whose sense-organs are alive (read jivadavasthendriyah), are naturally subject to misery. Now, in order to show the joy of the liberated self, he refutes the idea that the body is a means to joy: 65. The self, evolving naturally and obtaining the sense-objects desired and approachable to its touch, is itself pleasure; but the body is not. To this self, even in the embodied condition, it is not the body that we perceive to be the means to the attainment of pleasure. For even then, while passing through an imperfect state due to the senses, which under the influence of pronounced delusion, as if they had quaffed maddening draughts, run after objects successively, deeming that "they are desired by us,” the self, evolving by its own nature, which, though its main energy is obstructed, has knowledge, vision and power and is the cause of certain truth, of itself attains to happiness. But the body, since, because of its unconscious nature, it cannot be accepted as the cause of certitude of the evolution called happiness, surely does not function as happiness (In Jainism, the substance and its state are one and identical). Now he confirms this: 66. The body indeed does not in any way cause pleasure to the transmigrating soul, even in heaven; but the self itself by virtue of the sense-objects becomes enjoyment or pain. The tenet (siddhanta) here is that "the body, even when it is an angelic plastic body (vaikriyika-sharira), does not suffice for pleasure”; so that the self itself, by virtue of desirable or undesirable senseobjects, becomes pleasure or pain. Page #278 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 252 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Now he illustrates how, inasmuch as the energy for evolving into pleasure belongs to the self itself, the objects are ineffectual: 67. When the eye of a person removes darkness, then there is no use for a lamp; similarly the self itself is pleasure, what use the senseobjects therefor? Just as some night-walkers, inasmuch as their eyes possess energy for the removing of darkness, do not require for this purpose e.g. the radiance of a lamp, so for this self, in trans-migration as well as in liberation, evolving itself through the state of joy, what should avail the sense-objects, although uselessly sought by ignorant people under the idea that they are means for joy? Now he confirms by an example (the view] that the innate nature of self is happiness: 68/1. As the sun is by itself a light, and is warm, and a god in the sky, so is the liberated soul (siddha) having knowledge, happiness and godhood in the world. As the sun in the sky is by itself, without dependence on another cause, a light, since it abounds in the expanding brightness of its characteristic nature, radiant with a great quantity of light; and as it is warm, because it enjoys a constant evolution into heat, as a piece of iron occasionally evolves into heat; and as it is a god, since its innate nature is adapted to the continuous rise of the nama-karman of a god's condition; similarly in our world the holy self itself, without dependence on another cause, is knowledge, since it is identical with an inborn consciousness, of unerring, unlimited energy capable of manifesting the self and the other”; likewise it is happiness, since it is at ease owing to absence of perturbation and to complete delight originated from satisfaction with itself; and likewise it is a god; for it possesses the characteristic nature of a divine soul, through its associations with majesty and laudation when it appears carved on the stone-columns of the minds of intelligent men, coloured by nearness to the realization of the essence of the self. Hence enough of sense-objects, which merely in appearance are means to the happiness of this self. Here ends the explanation of Joy. Next the chapter on GooD EVOLUTION. Page #279 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 253 Now, entering upon the examination of the characteristic nature of sensorial joy, he propounds the characteristic nature of the means thereto: GOOD (SHUBHA) PSYCHIC ATTENTION (VERSES 69-92) 69. The self which is attached to the veneration of the worthy Lord, ascetics and the teacher, to charity, to mural conduct (su-shila), to fasting and the like, is a self with good or auspicious (shubha) psychic-attention. 20 When the self, transcending the stage of evil psychic-attention which shows itself as attachment to sense-objects and as hatred, the effect of which is misery, embraces the love of righteousness (dharma), a love which manifests itself as satisfaction with the veneration of the worthy Lord, the teacher and ascetics, with charity, moral precepts and fasting, then we may say that it has ascended the stage of good psychic-attention, which is a means to sensorial pleasure. Now he describes sensorial pleasure as a result of good psychicattention: 70. A self in possession of the good, whether it be an animal, man or god, receives in that period manifold sensorial pleasure. By its fitness for good psychic-attention, which is a means to sensorial pleasure, this self, having reached one or other of the three stages of animal, man or god, which stages are the place therefor, obtains manifold sensorial pleasure, as long as it abides there. Now, having thus extolled sensorial pleasure, he denounces it as misery: 71. Happiness born from innate nature is not in the Teaching (of Jina] assigned even to gods. Pained by the sensations of the body, they take pleasure in enjoyable sense-objects. The inhabitants of heaven, surely, are the foremost of those who experience sensorial pleasure; yet even for them there is no innate happiness: on the contrary, innate misery is observed in them. For, besides themselves as they are with the torment of the demon (pishacha), their body, i.e. of the five sense-organs, they fly to delightful sense-objects, in place of falling from precipices. After having by argumentation (yukti) premised that sensorial pleasure should be classified as misery, he now premises that good psychic-attention, which effects merit, cause of sensorial pleasure, is Page #280 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 254 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES not different from the class of psychic-attention, the evil attention, which effects sin, cause of pain. 72. If men, hell-inhabitants, animals and gods, have misery, born from the body, then how is there in these souls (distinction of) good and evil psychic-attention? If even gods, etc., in the plenitude of their merits, gained by good psychic-attention, and the hell-inhabitants, etc., involved in the ruin of sin, due to evil attention, both indistinguishably experience simply misery, conditioned by the body, i.e. by the five sense-organs; then, since both miss innate happiness of transcendental nature (parmarthatah) a relation of separateness (prthaktva) between good and evil psychic-attention does not hold. Now, having admitted, for the purpose of refutation, a separate fruit-bearing merit, caused by good psychic-attention, he raises a point: 73. Those who, bearing a thunderbolt as weapon (i.e. Indra) or ruling an empire, nourish the body, etc. by enjoyments, due to good psychic-attention, attached thereto, seem to be happy. Because Shakras and Emperors, thriving in body, etc., by enjoyments available at will, and extremely fond of these pleasures, as leeches of foul blood, give the impression of being happy, therefore fruit-bearing merits are seen to have arisen from good psychicattention. Now he suggests that the merits just admitted are causes of the germ of misery: 74. Though there are manifold merits, resulting from (good psychic states of) evolution, they make the souls, including those of the gods, to thirst for sense-objects (vishaya trasna). If it is granted that there exists various merits, whose origin is due to the evolution through good psychic-attention, then these necessarily make a thirst for sense-objects to arise in all the transmigrating souls, including even those whose food is nectar. Assuredly, without thirst the activity of all transmigrating souls towards sense-objects, as of leeches towards bad blood, would not be seen; and it is seen. Let us therefore not deny that merits are a base (ayatana) for such craving or thirst for sense objects. Now he proclaims the triumph of merit as germ of misery: 75. These souls, then, their thirst roused and made unhappy by thirstings, wish for obtaining till death the pleasures of sense-objects, Page #281 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 255 thereby being burnt by misery. Then all these transmigrating souls, including the thirsty (gods), their thirst roused and made utterly unhappy by thirstings, even by those originated from merit, since this is a germ of misery, expect pleasures from sense-objects, like water from the mirage. And, not capable of withstanding the tremendous burning of this misery, they experience, like leeches, (the pleasures of the) sense-objects, until they die. For, as leeches, gradually overcome by the victorious sprout-ofmisery (duhkhankura) having its root in thirst, covet the bad sweet blood and even while enjoying it are afflicted with annihilation, so these adherents of merit, like the adherents of sin, gradually dominated by the triumphant sprout of misery, of which the germ is thirst, covet the sense-objects and, enjoying them, are afflicted until the end. Therefore merits may be considered as causes of actual misery in the guise of happiness. Now he explains in manifold ways how sensorial pleasure originated from merit is misery: 76. Therefore that happiness which is acquired by means of the senses, is dependent, accompanied by obstacles or distractions, interrupted or terminable, cause of bondage, and unequal is indeed misery. Sensorial pleasure, although originated from merit, is actually misery; for it is dependent, accompanied by obstacles or distractions, interrupted, cause of bondage, unequal. It is dependent; for it rests on something else, since it has in something else its condition. It is accompanied by obstacles or distractions; for it is utterly confused, since it is attended by different longings, such as hunger, thirst, etc. It is interrupted; for oppositions are noticed in it, since we realize it as proceeding by the rise of good emotional-karman (sad-vedya=satavedaniya) disturbed by the rise of bad emotional-karman. It is a cause of bondage; for in its outcome it is hard to bear, since it is covered with a thick mass of dust of karman, collecting in the train of the army of the vices, passion, etc., trailing along the road of sensual enjoyments. It is unequal; for it is utterly unsteady, since it evolves through increase and decrease. And it is, indeed, misery only. Thus even merit Page #282 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 256 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES turns out to be, like sin, the means of misery. Now, certifying that there is no difference between merit and demerit, he summarizes: 77. He who will not believe that there is nothing particular or special (vishesha) between merit (punya) and sin (papa) [i.e. there is no difference between the two or the two are similar in the way or sense stated above] moves about, covered with infatuation, in the terrible cycle of transmigratory existence (samsara). Thus, in the way described, a duality of merit and sin, like a duality of good and evil psychic-attention or of pleasure and pain, does not, according to deeper transcendental reality (paramarthatah), exist; for on both sides equally we have not to do with a property really belonging to the soul. But he who, conceiving an egotistical (ahankarika) difference between this pair-like two gold and iron fetters!-depending upon the desire or expectation for future sense-pleasures (nidan), thinking "I am the cause (nidana)21 of my prosperity, for instance of my rank as Indra (Lord of Heaven)," still more leans on attachment (anuraga) to righteousness (dharma), experiences bodily misery as long as samsara lasts, his ability for pure psychic-attention being obscured, because the region or wall of his consciousness has become coloured (uparakta). Having thus settled that there is no particular difference between good and evil psychic-attention, now, dismissing all duality of attachment and aversion, and resolved to destroy misery totally, he abides in pure psychic-attention: 78. He who understands the reality of things thus and no more entertains attachment or aversion towards objects, thereby purifying psychic-attention, puts an end to pain originating from the body. He who has correctly distinguished the characteristic nature of things, by completely perceiving the identity of the good and evil psychical-states, and completely banishes attachment and aversion towards all objects with all their modifications, dependent as they are upon distinction of self and other, gives up every dependence on other substances, because he is utterly pure in his psychic-attention; and he puts an end to bodily pain; like fire, which, leaving a piece of iron and not adhering to the essence (sara) of the iron, no longer undergoes the series of violent blows by the hammer. Therefore, this pure psychic-attention is my only refuge. Page #283 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 257 “If now I, although bent upon conduct free from every censurable activity (of mind, body and speech) (yoga), do not eradicate infatuation, etc., in consequence of my adherence to good psychic-attention, then the attainment of the pure self is entirely impossible for me.” So he stands up and gets ready in full might: 79/1. If any one, after giving up sinful undertakings and even applying himself to good conduct, does not get rid of infatuation, etc., then he does not attain the pure self. Although one has taken up the strictest doctrinal (equanimous]22 conduct, characterized by the rejection of every censurable activity (yoga), if he, visited by the strolling lady, called Life-of-good-psychicattention, dopes not make an end (read vidheyatam vikirati) to his submission to the army of infatuation, then it is impossible for him, whilst the danger of great misery is near to grasp the not-confused (avipluta) self. Therefore, I gird myself for the victory over the army of infatuation. In answer to the question “how must I gain this victory over the army of infatuation?” he now examines the means: 80. He who knows the Arahanta (the worthy Lord) with reference to substance, quality and modification knows the self; his infatuation indeed perishes. He who discriminately knows the Arhanta (the worthy Lord) with reference to substantiality, possession of qualities and modifications, surely knows the self, because from the internal, self-referential point of view (nishchaya) there is no difference between the two. The Arhat, moreover, possesses a purified form of self, like thoroughly molten gold; therefore on discriminately knowing him we discriminately know every self. In this case the substance is the constant (anvaya); the quality is the qualifier (visheshana) of the constant; the modifications are the divergences (vyatireka) in the constant. In the holy Arhat, pure in every respect, we may see a threefold similarity to our own mind: That which is the constant, indicated as being “this conscious being," is the substance; the qualifier, which is based on the constant and indicated as “consciousness," is the quality; the divergences in the constant, which are separated from each other, inasmuch as their extension covers a time measured by one moment (samaya), 2are the Page #284 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 258 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES modifications or, what is the same thing, the nodes in the mentalchanges (chid-vivartana). Now, if anyone considers the three times as one and sums up the mental-changes in consciousness only, as pearls in one long necklace; and if he then puts an end24 to the transitory impression of a separate qualifier and a thing-to-be-qualified, and allows the consciousness to be comprised (antarhita) in conscious being, as the whiteness in the necklace; and if he distinguishes merely the self in the manner of the mere necklace, then the differences between agent, object-of-deed and deed in successive moments will die away; and, whilst he thus becomes aware of an actionless state-of-being (bhava), which is only consciousness-as-such, he will resemble a jewel whose spotless light shines motionless, and the darkness of his infatuation will necessarily fade, since it has no longer a basis. If so, then I have acquired the means for vanquishing the army of infatuation. Then he keeps awake with the thought “though I have obtained this talisman, there is the thief, 'heedlessness”. (pramada):26 81. If the soul, whose infatuation (deluded view) has gone and which has properly grasped the reality of the equanimous nature of the self, forsakes attachment and aversion, then it realises the pure self. If, by the means thus described in their characteristic nature, one throws off infatuation and receives the perfect truth about the self, and if one then eradicates attachment and aversion, he realizes the pure self. But, should again and again these two (feelings) return to him, then, under the influence of heedlessness robbed of the talisman of the comprehension (upalambha) of the truth of the pure self, he is inwardly troubled. Therefore, I must remain fully awake, in order to expel attachment and aversion. Now he expounds the view that “this is the one, supremely-real, path towards the Highest Good, shown by the Holy Ones after having experienced it themselves personally." 82/1. All the Arahantas, after having in the manner described, have destroyed the particles of karman and teaching the same, became emancipated. Homage to them! Since all the holy Spiritual Guides, who experienced their progressive career in the past and who, after their own experience of the destruction of all karmic particles in the one self same way, without Page #285 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 259 becoming aware of any twofoldness (for no other way is possible!), then, having as highest authorities taught it thus to others desirous of liberation in present and future times, obtained supreme bliss, therefore that there is no other road to nirvana is ascertained. Enough now of loquacity! My thought is settled! Homage to the Holy Ones! Now he explains the innate nature and the roles of infatuation, which way lays the attainment of the pure self: 83. An infatuated (mudha) state (bhava) of the soul with reference to substance, etc., is called moha (infatuation); covered (avachchanna) with this, the soul is agitated, having acquired attachment or aversion. That infatuated state of the soul, as of one intoxicated with drink, a state characterized by not understanding the truth about substances, qualities and modifications, as described (in gatha 80), is called infatuation. The self which has its self form covered with this, conceiving the other "strange" substance as if it were the substance of self, the quality of other substance as if a quality of self, the modifications of other substance as if states of self; taking hold (upadana) day after day of the other strange substance, since the psychical impression of this is full-grown and stronger; proceeding in duality (the opposed feelings of pleasure and pain), when there is really non-duality, in consequence of the preferences (ruchi) of the execrable organs of sense; embracing attachment and aversion with reference to agreeable (ruchita) and disagreeable things; splitting into two like a dam, beaten against by the rush of swollen water-masses—thus it becomes entirely subject to unrest (kshobha). (in gatha 7). Therefore this infatuation possesses three roles (bhumika) of infatuation, attachment and aversion. Now, designating infatuation a cause of undesirable consequences, he expounds its annihilation in all its three roles: 84. Manifold bondage takes place for the soul which is evolved through infatuation, attachment and aversion; therefore these must be destroyed. For him (whose mental-eyes are) closed in non-apprehension of the truth and who evolves through infatuation (a) or attachment, (6) or aversion, (c) as for an elephant who either has got into a trap covered by a layer of leaves (i) or who has become attached, (ii) to the body of a harlot of a female elephant, or who is enraged and violent28, (iii) at the sight of a hostile elephant-there is manifold Page #286 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 260 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES bondage. Therefore, this infatuation, attachment and aversion, as causes of undesirable consequences, must be radically destroyed by him who wishes for liberation. Now he discerns that these (three vices), discovered by their distinctive marks, must be destroyed as soon as they appear: 85. Wrong perception of things, i.e. other than as they really are, absence of a feeling of compassiontowards animals and men, and indulgence in sense-objects, these are the characteristics (linga) of infatuation. Infatuation, which has three roles inasmuch as it admits of taking, according to its three characteristics, the nature of infatuation through acceptance of wrong perception and knowledge about objects, through a feeling of compassion towards animals and men, who are only worthy of observation, the thought of attachment through inclination towards desired objects, and the thought of aversion through dislike of undesired objects, should be killed at its very rise. Now he considers another means to the destruction of infatuation: 86. By him30 who understands the reality of things as they are from the scripture of the Jina with intuition and other direct means of valid knowledge, etc., the accumulation of infatuation is destroyed; therefore the scripture must be studied. Whereas from a knowing of the Arhat in his inner nature as substance, qualities and modifications a similar knowledge of the self was accepted above (see comments on verse 80) as a means to the destruction of infatuation, that indeed requires another means, as follows: The accumulation of infatuation, which causes the mental-habit (samskara) of attachment to that which is not the truth, is destroyed by him: who has reached the first stage (of the road towards liberation), and who, having mastered the Word as source of knowledge, trustworthy in every respect and guaranteed by the authority of the Omniscient, plays with it and has at his command a full energy of special assuredness (samvedana), emphasized by the mental-habit (of studying this Word), and who by perception or any other means of knowledge not contradictory thereto, which give an ebullition of bliss, and which impart a splendour of bliss to the inind of feeling and intelligent men, distinguishes (read Page #287 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK 1: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 261 paricchindatah) the totality of things according to truth. Therefore the utmost application to study-of-the-sacred-word, well applied with an evolution supported by the knowledge of the meaning (bhava), is another means to the destruction of infatuation. Now he considers how in the sacred-word of the Jinendra the discrimination of objects is set out: 87. Substances, their qualities and modifications are understood by the term artha (object); among these the soul substance is the substratum of the qualities and modifications; thus runs the teaching. Substances, qualities and modifications, although designated specially, may be united under a single term, artha. Here the substances are arthas, because they go (read iyrati instead of prati) to the qualities and modifications or because they are gone to” (aryante) by the qualities and modifications; the qualities are arthas, because they go to the substances for an abode or because they are gone to” by the substances which offer the abode; the modifications are arthas, because they go (read krama-parinameneyrati instead of parinameneti) to the substances in as far as (they form) a successive evolution or they “are gone to” by the substances in as far as (these are subject to) a successive evolution. For just as gold, which we will take here as an example of a substance, going (read iyrat instead of iyarti) to such qualities as yellow, etc., to such modifications as a ring, etc., or “gone to” by them, is an artha, and just as the qualities yellow, etc., going to the gold for an abode or “gone to” by the gold which functions as abode (read asrayabhuta instead of aryabhuta), are arthas; and just as the modifications, ring, etc., going (read kramaparinameneyratah) to the gold in its successive evolutions or “gone to” by the gold in its successive evolutions, are arthas, so elsewhere. And just as in the case of this gold, its qualities, such as yellowness and its modifications, such as a ring, the gold is "the self” of the qualities “yellowness," etc., and of the modifications “ring,” etc., because they do not exist separately (prthak) from the gold, so in the case of substance, qualities and modifications in general the substance is "the self” of the qualities and the modifications, because they do not exist separately from the substance. Now, since, even when we accept the teaching of Lord Jina, which is a means to the destruction of infatuation, it is manly effort that Page #288 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 262 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES produces an effect, he sets manly effort to work: 88. Whosoever, having grasped the teaching of the Jina, destroys infatuation, attachment and aversion, attains within a short time emancipation from all miseries. Whosoever on this very long path (of samsara), full of ever restless unrest (cf. Tattva-dipika on verse 46), has in some way or other obtained the teachings of the kingly Jina, and brings it down, like a sharp sword's edge, with force on his infatuation, attachment and hatred, quickly obtains liberation from all misery; and no other operation, as a gloved hand, is capable of that. Therefore with all my might I resort to manly effort for the destruction of infatuation. The destruction of infatuation follows solely from discriminating (viveka) between the self (sva) and "the other” (para). Therefore, he exerts himself to effect this partition of self and other: 89. If, one really knows the self as constituted of knowledge, and the other, both as connected with (their own) substantial nature, then he effects the annihilation of infatuation. Whoso according to strict examination distinguishes the self, connected with its own, spiritual, substantiality, and “the other,” connected with the appropriates “strange” substantiality, he, having thus completely attained discrimination between self and other, destroys infatuation completely. Therefore I exert myself for discrimination between self and other. Now he summarizes the attainment of the discrimination between self and other must by all means be effected with the aid of the Scriptures: 90. Therefore in accordance with the teaching of the Jina one should understand the self and the other among substances by means of (or with regard to) their qualities, if his soul' wishes for itself freedom from infatuation. By means of some of the infinitely-many qualities mentioned in the Scriptures, namely by means of those which have in addition to generality a characterizing effect (visheshana), so as to exclude application to something else, let intelligent people whose minds are inclined to the giving up of infatuation take up, among the endless series of substances, the discrimination between self and other. To wit, this intelligence which is mine, which belongs to me, which by its fullness of internal and external light is fit for Page #289 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 263 discrimination of self and other, and which, being without another thing as condition, is self-caused (svatah siddha)—by means of this intelligence which, apart from any other substance, either homogeneous or heterogeneous, abides in my self, I know myself's self as a substance firm in the three times. Likewise by means of characteristics which, excluding any other substance, possess separateness (prthaktva) and always abide in the same particular substance I examine strictly (read nishchinomi) space, dharma (the principle of motion), adharma (the principle of rest), time, matter and the strange soul, which are all substances firm in the three times. So then I am not space, not dharma, not adharma, not time, not matter, not another soul, because amid all this ordered multitude of things, resembling the mass of light of many lamps lit in one apartment, my intelligence not swearing from its characteristic nature, shows myself to be something apart. So then for this self, which has determined the discrimination of the self and the other, the sprout of infatuation which causes agitation (vikara) would not come forth. Now he considers how attainment of Duty does not take place without belief in the doctrine taught by the Jina 91. He who, in his state of shramanya, does not believe in these categories (padarthas), with their related generality of existence and various particularities, is not a shramana, therefore dharma does not accrue to him. He who, while controlling himself by ascetism, does not accept with belief, or define, by means of the distinction between self and other, the substances, which obey a general nature, inasmuch as they enjoy a similar existence, and which are yet accompanied by particularities, inasmuch as they possess an existence of characteristic nature, is really no ascetic. Therefore the attainment of dharma, which consists in the attainment of the essence of the self, free from affections (anuraga), cannot take place, just as we cannot expect gold in the case of a person who, not distinguishing between particles of sand and gold, washes dust. After having, with the words “I rely upon the tranquillity leading to nirvana," introduced (in verse 5) the subject matter and having, with the words "the conduct is dharma; dharma is defined as equanimity, examined (in verse 7) the dharma of equanimity, he began (in verse 8) with the words “it is taught that substance possesses the Page #290 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 264 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES nature of that through which it evolves," etc., to explain in what the dharma of the self consists. Then, in order to explain this, with the verse (11) “When the self whose self evolves through dharma is conjoined with pure psychic-attention, it reaches happiness undisturbed,” he began to discuss pure psychic-attention as a means to the attainment of the happiness of nirvana; then good and evil psychic-attention, contraries, were rejected (cf. 46), and the nature of pure psychic-attention was described; finally, emphasizing the innate knowledge and happiness of the soul, which arise by grace of this (pure attention), he detailed the characteristic nature of consciousness (samvedana and jnana are equivalent here) and of pleasure. Therefore, having with attention attained, by the grace of his pure psychic-attention, a total absence of longings for what is “strange” (to the soul), whilst he resorts to a behaviour, lordly and proud (or should we read atma-trptam instead of atma-drptam?) of the self, he now attains complete acquittance of his task, becomes entirely unperturbed, and, with the transitory-impression of preference-and-dislike (bheda) faded away, stands fast in the thought “I myself personally am dharma.” 92/1. That noble-minded shramana, whose deluded view is destroyed, who is well conversant with the Scriptures, and who has established himself in conduct of detachment, is described as dharma itself. It is certainly my wish that the self may become dharma: this is hindered only by an external perception-infatuation. And this infatuation is destroyed by conversancy with Scripture and knowledge of the self; then for me it will never come into re-existence. So this my self, with its earthly career guided by a conduct devoid of attachment, becomes itself Duty, and, since all its hindrances are thrown off, for ever remains steadfast. Enough of disquisition! Hail to Holy Tradition (shabda-brahman), preached by the Lord Jina and sealed with the syadvada (the formula “quodammodo”)! Hail to the acceptance of the truth of the self, which acceptance is based on that (tradition) and by grace whereof the knot of infatuation, tied since the beginning of samsara, is at once unfastened! Hail to pure psychic-attention, consisting in conduct utterly free from attachment, by grace whereof the self is become itself dharma ! “The self, becoming itself dharma, having attained pure psychicattention, and, whilst it enjoys the flowing forth of an eternal bliss, Page #291 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK I: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 265 engrossed into the principle (tattva) of knowledge, obtains the glory which without the slightest agitation shines motionlessly forth from the jewel-lamp spontaneously flashing with ebullient radiance (sphurjajjyotih is here the first member of a compound. A “jewel-lamp," a fabulous lamp in which a jewel is used for a light)”. (PS Kalash 5) “Having thus ascertained without doubt and as it is, the principle of knowledge whose substratum is the soul, and for this purpose desiring to know the principle of the knowable, with a view to its tranquillity, it considers all objects from the point of view of quality, substance and modification, in order that the sprout of infatuation may never again manifest itself.” (PS Kalash 6) Here ends, in the Lamp of Truth, a commentary on the Essence of the Scripture, composed by Amrtacandra-Suri, the first scriptural book, called the Teaching of the Principle concerning Knowledge. Page #292 --------------------------------------------------------------------------  Page #293 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Book II The Principle of the Knowable Note: II. 1, II. 2, etc. denotes gatha (verse) No. 1, 2, etc. of Book II in serial number, while gatha Nos. 93/2, 94, etc. at the end of translation denote consecutive numbering of gathas starting from Book 1, which tallies with the gatha numbering of the original Prakrit text given at the end of this edition and most editions of the work in Hindi. SUBSTANCE IN GENERAL (VERSES 93-126) Now begins the explanation of the principle (tattva) concerning the knowable. Here he explains the proper characteristic nature of the thing as substance, quality and modification: II. 1 The object, indeed, consists of substance; the substances are said to have their essence in qualities. And through these [i.e. both substance and qualities) are the modifications. Those, who are deluded (moodh) in regard to the modifications, are para-samaya, i.e. those who hold the view of reality of things, including the self, "other" than what it is.31 (93/2) (la) Whatever object (padartha) is distinguished by us consists of substance (dravya), inasmuch as it results from the substance, which is an aggregation (samudaya) of cross-wise-generality (vistara-samanya) and lenghtwise-generality (ayata-samanya). 32 (1b) The substances again have their essence in (or chracterised by their] qualities, inasmuch as they result (from the qualities, i.e.) from cross-wise particularities (vistara-vishesha), which abide in one thing (1c) The modifications, again, have both the substance and the quality for essence; for being themselves lenght-wise particularities Page #294 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Book II The Principle of the Knowable Page #295 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 269 (ayata-vishesha), they result no less from the just now defined substances and qualities both. (1d) The substantial-modification (dravya-paryaya) has for condition the apprehending of an unity which contains many substances. It is of two kinds, homogeneous and heterogeneous. (1d-1) The homogeneous substantial-modification consists of several particles of matter (molecules), thus of two, three atoms, etc. (1d-2) Heterogeneous substantial-modifications are e.g. a god, a man; they consist of soul and matter. (1e) The qualitative-modification (guna-paryaya) has for condition the apprehending of lengthwise-manifoldness (ayata-anaikya) owing to qualities. It also is of two kinds, modifications of innate-nature (svabhava) and modifications of derivative-nature ( (le-1) The innate qualitative-modification belonging to all substances is their being subject to manifoldness of increase and decrease, which take place in the six sthanasand arise in succession of time through their respective a-guru-laghu-qualities. 34 (le-2) The derivative qualitative-modification of colours, etc., and intellections (cognitive), etc., is the accession of a manifoldness of particular innate nature, which manifoldness is shown by a higheror-lower-degree (taratamya) with reference to former and later states, and is conditioned by the thing itself or something else (sva-para pratyaya). This now he confirms by an example: (2a) Just as every piece of cloth results from a persisting collection of crosswise-generalities and a passing collection of lengthwise generalities, and consists of these, 35 so every object (padartha) results from a persisting collection of crosswise-generalities and a passing collection of lengthwise-generalities, which collections bear the name of substance; and it consists of substance. (2b) And, just as in the piece of cloth the persisting collection of crosswise-generalities or the passing collection of lengthwisegeneralities, as resulting from the qualities, has the qualities for self, since it is not perceived apart from the qualities, so in [all] objects the persisting collection of crosswise-generalities or the passing collection of lengthwise-generalities, which bears the name of substance, as resulting from the qualities, has the qualities for self, since it is not perceived apart from the qualities. Page #296 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 270 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES (2b-1) And, just as a homogeneous substantial-modification may consist of several pieces of cloth, for instance, two or three pieces, so a homogeneous substantial-modification may consist of several material-components, for instance, two or three atoms. (2b-2) And, just a heterogeneous substantial-modification may consist of several-e.g. two or three-pieces of silk and cotton, so a heterogeneous substantial-modification may consist of several components, soul and matter; instances are a god or a man. (2c) And, just as in a piece of cloth we see the innate qualitativemodification, i.e. the undergoing of manifoldness owing to an evolution which takes place in a manifold and successive form, by way of such a-guru-laghu-qualities as determine gross (sthula) nature, so in all substances we find an innate qualitative-modification, i.e. their being subject to the manifoldness of increase and decrease36, which take place in the six sthanas and arise in succession of time by way of their respective a-guru-laghu-qualities. (2c-1) And, just as in a piece of cloth we see the derivative qualitative-modification of colours, etc., in the accession of a manifoldness of particular innate natures, which manifoldness is shown by a higher-or-lower-degree with reference to former and later states, and is conditioned by (the piece) itself or something else (sva-para pratyaya), so in all substances we find a derivative qualitativemodification of colours, etc., or intellections, etc., in the accession of a manifoldness of particular innate natures, which manifoldness is shown by a higher-or-lower-degree with reference to former and later states, and is conditioned by the substance itself or something else (sva-para pratyaya). For so, and not otherwise, is the preferable exposition of all objects, as it was preached by the Highest Lord, whereby is revealed the innate nature of substance, quality and modification; for many people, basing themselves merely on the modifications and becoming subject to delusion, which is characterized by not properly understanding the reality [the innate nature of self as it is] become para-samaya, i.e. accept only the conditioned modes of consciousness. Having thus commenced incidentally (the topic of the) distinction of sva-samaya-and para-samaya persons, he summarizes it as follows: II.2 The souls, who are constantly engaged in, attached to or find satisfaction only in the modifications, are called para-samayikas but Page #297 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 271 those who rely on the innate nature of the self are known as svakasamayas (sva-samaya). (94) Those who, trusting in the heterogeneous substance-modifications, (asaman jatiya dravya paryaya) consisting in (the combination of) soul and matter-which modification is the one root of all forms of ignorance-become impotent to realize the innate-nature of soul as described, and incur an incapacity in respect of even that, give free rein to an uncontrolled one-sided view, deceived by the notions I (ahankara) and mine (mamakara), and thinking “I here am a man," alone and "this human body is mine” only; fallen away from the use of the word “self” (atma-vyavahara), which means being engrossed exclusively and unwaveringly in the innate nature of consciousness, and taking refuge in the use of the word “man” (manushyavyavahara), in which is ensconced the whole household of actions, loving and hating [being engaged in attachment or aversion] become through attachment to the other” substance, karmic matter, para-samaya. But those who, relying on the sublime innate nature of soul substance which is well established in its qualities and modifications and which is the one root of all knowledge-become able to realize the innate nature of soul, as described, and, overcoming attachment merely to the modifications alone, maintain a firm stand on the innate conscious nature of soul, destroy by their natural appearing many-sided view their acceptance of any one-sided view; they hold no more the notions I and mine with reference to human and other conditions of existence (gatis), or to the bodies belonging to them; taking hold of the self as indivisible unity, which resembles a jewel lamp, carried round through many apartments, they keep thus true to the conception-of-self, which exclusively means the appearance of unwavering spirituality, and, not taking refuge in the use of the word “man” (manushyavyavahara) and all the activities relating thereto, they find-whilst the manifestation of attachment and aversion ceases-rest in the highest indifference (audasinya); and, because every contact with the other” substances is abandoned and the contact with the own substance is exclusively maintained, they become sva-samaya. Page #298 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 272 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Hence, sva-samaya is the essence or inner principle (antas tattva) of the self (atman) itself. - : Now he gives the definition of substance: II.3 That which, whilst it does not forsake its innate nature, is characterized by origination, annihilation and stability and which possesses or is endowed with qualities and modifications, is called a substance. (95) (see also TS 5.29, 5.30 and 5.38) A substance is that which, without commencing a differentiation (bheda) of its innate nature, is characterized by the twofold set of qualities and modifications and the triple set of origination, annihilation and continuation. Here we understand by the innate nature (svabhava) of a substance its connection with existence-in-general (astitva-samanya). This existence will be explained as twofold: svarupa-astitva (existence-ofcharacteristic-nature) and sadrshya-astitva (existence-of-commonnature). By origination we here understand coming forth, by annihilation decay, by stability continuance. Qualities are crosswise-particularities; they are twofold, in as far as they may be general (samanya-guna) or particular (vishesha-guna). Here the general qualities are existence, non-existence; oneness, otherness; to be a substance (dravyatva), to be a modification (paryayatva); omnipresence, non-omnipresence; possession of spacial units, non-possession of spacial units; materiality, immateriality; possession of action, non-possession of action; consciousness, unconsciousness; agency, non-agency; being-an-enjoyer, not-being-anenjoyer; the set of a-gurulaghutva, etc. qualities. Particular qualities are the being a cause of “penetrability” (avagaha), the being an occasion of moving, the being a factor of standing-still, the being the cause of modification of substances, the possessing of colour, etc., consciousness37 and so forth. Modifications are lengthwise-particularities. They have been previously described as fourfold. 38 To (the notions mentioned), origination, etc., or qualities and modifications, substance is related as that which is to be defined to that which defines; but notwithstanding this differentiation there is no real difference, since the substance in its own nature is “suchlike” (tathavidha), as we may understand from the case of an upper-garment. Page #299 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 273 (1) As an upper-garment which has been subject to a state of filthiness, but, being washed, is originating with reference to a state of spotlessness, is then defined (lakshyate) by this origination and in connection with this does not undergo a differentiation in its own nature, but by its own nature adheres to being suchlike. so any substance which has been subject to an original state, and, owing to the vicinity of the proper external causes, passes into a state qualitatively different or quantitatively greater, and, helped (read anugrhitam) by its innate nature-i.e. by its fitness as an own nature, agent and instrument—as an internal favourable condition, is originating with reference to the later state, is then defined by this origination; and in connection with this it does not undergo a differentiation in its own nature, but by its own nature adheres to being suchlike. (2) And, as the same upper-garment, originating with reference to a state of spotlessness and being annihilated with reference to a state of filthiness, is defined by this annihilation, and, in connection with this, does not undergo a differentiation in its own nature, but by its own nature adheres to being suchlike. so the same substance, originating with reference to the later state and becoming annihilated with reference to the original state, is defined by this annihilation, and, in connection with this, does not undergo a differentiation in its own nature, but by its own nature adheres to being suchlike. . (3) And, as the same upper-garment, simultaneously originating with reference to spotlessness, and becoming annihilated with reference to filthiness, and partaking of stability, with reference to its constant state of being a garment, is defined by this stability, and in connection with this, does not undergo a differentiation in its own nature, but by its own nature adheres to being suchlike. so the same substance, simultaneously originating with reference to the later state, and becoming annihilated with reference to the original state, and partaking of stability with reference to its state of being a substance, is defined by this stability, and in connection with this, does not undergo a differentiation in its own nature, but by its own nature adheres to being suchlike. (4) And, as the same upper-garment is defined by qualities—i.e. by crosswise-particularities-and, in connection with these, does not Page #300 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 274 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES undergo a differentiation in its own nature, but by its own nature adheres to being suchlike, so the same substance is defined by qualities-i.e. by crosswiseparticularities-and, in connection with these, does not undergo a differentiation in its own nature, but by its own nature adheres to being suchlike. (5) And, as the same upper-garment is defined by threads which are in its modifications-i.e. its lengthwise-particularities-and in connection with these does not undergo a differentiation in its own nature, but by its own nature adheres to being suchlike, so the same substance is defined by modifications-i.e. by lengthwise-particularities-and in connection with these, does not undergo a differentiation in its own nature, but by its own nature adheres to being suchlike. Now in succession he mentions twofold existence, existence-ofown-nature and existence-of-common-nature (sadrashya-astitva), and of these he describes here svarupa-astitva (existence-of-own-nature): II.4. Existence is the innate nature of a substance, which permeates its qualities and various modifications of its own, as also its origination, annihilation and stability at all times.39 (96) Existence, indeed, is the innate nature of a substance. For why should not this existence be the innate nature of a substance, partaking as it does of oneness with the substance? For both are independent of any other means; both always go on without beginning or end, and in a conditioning, uniform occurrence (vrtti); both differ from that which makes up derivative-nature (vibhava); although there exists a manifoldness in them, inasmuch as the one is the existence and the other the existent, they are not subject to a differentiation with reference to pradeshas (infinitesimal units of space). The full completeness of this (existence) is not seen in a substance, quality or modification, when taken singly, as if they were different substances; for inasmuch as their reality (siddhi) is realized by mutual assistance, their existence (astitva) is one, as may be seen by the case of gold. For,40 as of gold, which is associated with a process proceeding in company with a manifestation of the qualities yellow etc. and the Page #301 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 275 modifications ring etc., as its agent, instrument and seat, the existence by way of the qualities yellow etc. and the modifications ring etc.— which, not perceived in respect of substance, or place, or time, or being apart from the gold, are associated with an actualization actualized by the existence of the gold—is the own nature: so of substance, which is associated with a process proceeding in company with a manifestation of qualities and modifications, as its agents, instrument and seat, the existence by way of qualities and modifications—which, not perceived in respect of substance, or place, or time or being apart from the substance, are associated with an actualization actualized by the existence of substance, --is the own nature. And, as of gold, which is not perceived in respect of substance or place or time or being apart from the qualities yellow, etc. and the modifications ring, etc., and which is associated with an actualization actualized by the qualities yellow, etc. and the modifications ring etc., associated with a process proceeding in company with a manifestation of gold, as their agent, instrument and seat, the existence actualized by these as the fundamental means is the self-nature: so of substance, which is not perceived in respect of substance or place or time or being apart from qualities and modifications, and which is associated with an actualization actualized by qualities and modifications, associated with a process proceeding in company with a manifestation of substance as their agent, instrument and seat-the existence actualized by them as fundamental means is the self-nature. Furthermore, as of gold, which is associated with a process proceeding in company with a manifestation of origination, annihilation and stability of ring, bracelet, yellowness, etc., as its agent, instrument and seat, the existence by way of origination, annihilation, and stability of ring, bracelet, yellowness etc.—which, not perceived in respect of substance or place or time or being apart from the gold, are associated with an actualization actualized by the existence of the gold-is its own nature: so of substance, which is associated with a process proceeding in company with a manifestation of origination, annihilation and stability, as its agent, instrument and seat, the existence by way of origination, annihilation and stability—which not perceived in respect of substance or place or time or being apart from substance, are associated with an actualization actualized by the Page #302 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 276 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES existence of substance-is the own nature. And, as of gold, which is not perceived in respect of substance or place or time or being apart from origination, annihilation and stability of ring, bracelet, yellowness, etc., and which is associated with an actualization actualized by origination, annihilation and stability of ring, bracelet, yellowness, etc., associated with an actualization, actualized by origination, annihilation and stability of ring, bracelet, yellowness, etc. associated with a process proceeding in company with a manifestation of gold as their agent, instrument and seat—the existence realized by these as the fundamental means is the self-nature: so of substance, which is not perceived in respect of substance or space or time or being apart from origination, annihilation and stability—and which is associated with an actualization actualized by origination, annihilation and stability, associated with a process proceeding in company with a manifestation of substance, as their agent, instrument and seat—the existence actualized by these as the fundamental means is the self-nature." Now he states the expression “it is” for existence-of-common-nature (sadrashya-astitva): II.5. The Jina (the worthy Lord), when he preached the dharma, declared that one, common characteristic, “to be an existent," belongs here to all things with their manifold characterizations. (97) Here in all substances, although (1) characterized by a proper existence of their own, (2) proceeding with a developed manifoldness exclusive of other substances and (3) serving as specific characteristic drawing the boundaries between substances, we must recognize an "existence” of common nature, one, (1) a common characteristic, omnipresent, termed “existence,” (2) proceeding with sublation of the developed manifoldness and (3) breaking through the border-line drawn between substances. So the expression “it is” and our discrimination expressed by “it is” concern all objects. If this were not so, then one thing should be called “existent,” another thing “not-existent,” again another thing “existent-and-not-existent,” and again another thing “impossible to describe” (i.e. the syad-vada would with one only of its members prevail for each object). This now is contradicted and cannot be realized, as for instance in the case of trees. As in the case of many manifold trees the manifoldness, founded Page #303 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 277 upon their existence-of-characteristic-nature, which is a particular mark (vishesha-lakshana) and is individual in every case, is sublated by the oneness, constituted by the genus "trees," which is a general-mark (samanya-lakshana) and manifests itself in common so in the case of many manifold substances the manifoldness, founded upon their existence-of-characteristic-nature, which is a particular mark of theirs and is individual in every case, is sublated by the oneness, constituted by their "being," expressed in the words "it is existent," which is a general mark and manifests itself in common. And, as in the case of these trees, although sublated by the oneness constituted by the genus "tree," as a general mark, and manifesting itself in common, the manifoldness founded upon their existence-ofcharacteristic-nature, as a particular mark and individual in each case, still shines forth: so in the case of all substances, although sublated by the oneness constituted by their "being," expressed in the words "it is existent," as a general mark and manifesting itself in common, the manifoldness founded upon their existence-of-characteristic-nature, as a particular mark and individual in each case, still shines forth. Now he refutes the opinion that by substances there is originated another substance and that existence is an object different from substance: II.6. The Jinas have correctly (yatharthatah) stated that substance is existent reality, and is proved (siddha) by its innate nature. Whosoever does not from Scripture accept it as so proved (siddha), is indeed para-samaya. (98) Substances are not produced by other substances, because all substances are realized by their innate nature. And their being realized by their innate nature results from their having no beginning or end. For that which has no beginning or end does not depend on any other efficient factor or cause (sadhan), but is something existent, with its realization realized (siddha-siddhimat) by itself, being provided with its own main efficient cause (mool sadhan), the innate nature of its self, which is the self again of its qualities and modifications. On the other hand, that which is originated by substances is not a new substance, but, because of its accidentality, is a modification, as a double atom, etc., or a man, etc. A substance, on the other hand, being infinite and constant in the three times, cannot be such. Let us observe in the same way that, as a substance is realized Page #304 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 278 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES simply by its innate nature, so an existent (sat) is realized simply by its innate nature. For it has a form-of-being whose development is developed (nishpanna-nishpattimat) (parallel with siddha-siddhimat in the precedent paragraph) by its own innate nature, which has moreover (read sattatmana) existence for self. On the other hand, existence (satta) does not present itself as an object different from substance, so that the substance should be through inherence thereof something-existent (sat). And the existent (sat) and the existence (satta) are not different objects, (a) on the basis of yuta-siddhatva, “I because we do not see in them this mutual separability (read yuta-siddhatvas yadarshanat), as in the case of a stick and the bearer of the stick. Nor (b) does (the thesis) hold by way of mutual-inseparability. And, if one should object that it arises from (read upadyate) the notion “this in that” (ihedam), then we ask on what is this notion "this in that” based?—It is founded on differentiation (bheda). What is this differentiation? Is it of local nature (pradeshika) or (logical) non-identity (atadbhavika)? It is not local, since we have already rejected yuta-siddhatva.—If it is non-identity, that is given already by the saying "that which is a substance is not a quality.” But this differentiation, called non-identity, does not by itself suffice as the condition of the notion “this in that,” since this notion emerges or is submerged independently. If a substance is caused-to-beapproached (arpyate, cf. Tattva-dipika on PS 87 and the explication there given of “artha") by a modification, then emerges the differentiation of non-identity, “this substance possesses a quality,” “this is its quality,” “this upper-garment is white,” “this white quality," and so on (read ityadivat prapashyatah). But, when the substance is causedto-be-approached by a substance, then every unfolding of an impression (vasana) of a quality is lost in us, and regarding only “the suchlike substance," (cf PS 95) for instance a white upper-garment, the differentiation of non-identity is utterly submerged; and, since this differentiation is submerged, any notion based on it is submerged; and again, this being submerged any other object-an idea dependent on a-yuta-siddhatva-is submerged. Consequently the entire substance is left as an unity. On the other hand, when differentiation emerges, then, as it emerges, the notion conditioned by it emerges; and, when this notion emerges, the idea of a second object-due to inseparability (a-yuta-siddhatva)-emerges. But even then, emerging as a modification thereof, it is not separate from the object, as little as the water-wave Page #305 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 279 from the water-mass. This being so, the substance is itself an existent. And he who does not accept this must be considered to be para-samaya. Now he explains that substance, although it consists in origination, annihilation and continuance, is an existent: . II.7. The substance is an existent reality, resting in its innate nature; for every evolution of a substance in the world-of-objects is its innate nature, combined of stability, origination and destruction. (99) The substance, namely, here is an existent, inasmuch as it eternally rests in its innate nature; and the innate nature of a substance consists in its evolution or oneness of stability, origination and annihilation. (A) For as the volume (vastu) of a substance, although in its integrity, one, contains infinitesimal-spacial-constituents (pradeshas), which are its fine portions and are engaged in effecting its ordered extension (vishkambha): so the occurrence (urtti) of a substance, although in its integrity one, contains evolutions, which are its fine portions and are engaged in effecting its ordered process (pravaha). (B And, as the order of the extension is conditioned by the mutual exclusion (vyatireka) of the infinitesimal-spacial-constituents: so the succession in the process is conditioned by the mutual exclusion of the evolutions. O And, as these infinitesimal-spacial-constituents uphold themselves, having origination, annihilation and stability for self, because in their own spot (sthana) they arise and perish by way of their precedent and subsequent forms, and are exempt from origination and decay, inasmuch as everywhere one and the same volume is effected by their being mutually strung together: so these evolutions uphold themselves, having origination, annihilation and stability for self, because at their own point-of-time (avasara) they arise and perish by way of their precedent and subsequent forms, and are exempt from origination and decay, inasmuch as everywhere one and the same process is effected by their being mutually strung together. (D) And, as the limitation-of-volume (vastu-simanta), which consists in the destruction of the precedent infinitesimal-spacial constituents, is the same as the volume-limitation which consists in the origination of the subsequent infinitesimal-spacial-constituents, and the same as the volume-limitation which consists in both together, Page #306 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 280 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES inasmuch as the one volume is produced by their mutually being strung together: the limitation-of-process which consists in the destruction of the precedent evolution is the same as the limitation-of-process which consists in the origination of the subsequent evolution, and the same as the limitation-of-process which consists in both together, inasmuch as the one process is produced by their mutually being strung together. In this manner we must admit that existence possesses a threefold character, because it-(i.e. this existence, or, what comes to the same thing, the described process (pravaha) or series of evolutions)-does not transgress its innate nature, luxuriating, as it does, in the threefold course of evolutions. To take the example of a necklace of pearls: As in the case of a hanging necklace of pearls, of 'efinite length, the threefold is obvious, because, whilst all the pearls are visible each in its place, each subsequent pearl arises (before our perception) in a subsequent place, each precedent pearl does not arise in the subsequent place, the whole necklace (sutraka), which-strings-them-together (sutraka) by means of a mutual stringing together, is present in all their places: in the same manner in the case of a substance, developing with definite eternal activity (vrtti), the threefoldness is obvious, because, whilst all the evolutions are visible each in its own point-of-time, each subsequent evolution arises in a subsequent point-of-time, each precedent evolution does not arise in the subsequent pointof-time, the whole process (pravaha), which strings-them-together by means of a mutual stringing together, is present in all their points-of-time. Now he confirms the necessary concomitance (avinabhava) of origination, annihilation and stability: II.8. There is no coming-into-existence or origination without destruction; there is no destruction devoid of origination; and there is no origination and destruction without stability or persistence. (100) There is no creation without dissolution; no dissolution without creation; there is neither creation nor dissolution without permanence, nor permanence without creation and dissolution. Creation is dissolution, and dissolution is creation; and both creation and dissolution are the permanence, and the permanence is the creation and dissolution. Page #307 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 281 For instance, the creation of the jar is the dissolution of the clod, since being appears as an innate nature of not being another being. And the dissolution of the clod is the creation of the jar, since notbeing appears as an innate nature of being another being. And both the creation and dissolution of jar and clod are the permanence of the clay, since the sameness (anvaya) only appears by means of the divergence (vyatireka) (For the terms anvaya and vyatireka of commentary on gatha 80). And the permanence of the clay is the creation and dissolution of jar and clod, since the divergences do not overpass, transgress or transcend the sameness. And, if this is not accepted, it follows that the creation is something apart, the dissolution something apart, and the permanence again something else. (I) In that case, since there is no cause for the origination of a pot when it asks only for creation, there would either be no coming into being (bhavani) whatever, or an origination of a non-existent. (A) And thus, if the pot does not come into existence, there would be no arising of anything; (B) in the case of the origination of a non-existent there would be origination of sky-flowers, etc. (II) Likewise, since there is no cause for the destruction of the clod which is undergoing annihilation only, there would be either, no annihilation (samharani) whatever or the putting-an-end to a thingreally-existent (sat). (A) And here, in the case of the clod's not being destroyed, there would be no annihilation of anything; (B) in the case of the putting-an-end to an existent there would be an end to the conscious-being (samvid, i.e. the soul), and so on, (III) Likewise, since in the clay, if admitting only continuance, there is no constancy, i.e. continuance, dominated by divergence, there would be no continuance (asthani), or merely the eternality of the momentary. (A) In the case of the non-continuance of the clay there would be non-continuance of all existence; (B) in the case of the eternality of the momentary there would be eternality of the momentary-contents-of-consciousness (chitta-kshana). 42 Consequently we must inevitably accept a substance characterized A Page #308 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 282 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES by a threefold-aspect coming forth without obstacle and inseparably connected (avinabhuta) with creation of a series of posterior divergences (vyatireka), destruction of a series of prior divergences, and stability of constancy. Now he shows summarily that origination, etc., are not (read dravyad anarthantaratvam) objects (arthas) different from the substance: 11.9. Origination, continuance and destruction are in the modifications; the modifications, indeed, are in the substance; therefore necessarily all that is the substance or substance is the substratum of all of them. (101) Origination, decay and stability are dependent (alambante) on the modifications; these modifications again are dependent on the substance. Therefore all that is one substance, and there is no other substance. On the substance the modifications rest; since that which consists of an aggregation (samudaya) has the aggregation for self, as e.g. a tree. As, namely, a tree which consists of an aggregation, has the aggregation of stem, root and boughs for self and appears only as that on which stem, root and boughs are dependent, similarly a substance which consists of an aggregation has the aggregation of the modifications for self and appears only as that on which the modifications are dependent. And the modifications are that on which origination, dissolution and stability are dependent, since origination, dissolution and stability have the property of being portions, as we may see by the example of germ sprout and tree. As, namely, the three portions, termed the states of germ, sprout and full-grown tree, which belong to the tree as the whole, are envisaged together when the properties (dharmas) of each, i.e. destruction, appearance and stability rest upon them: so the three portions, characterized as passing off, coming forth and remaining, which belong to the substances as the whole are envisaged together when the properties of each, i.e. destruction, appearance and stability rest upon them. But if destruction, origination or stability were upheld merely in respect of substance, then everything would be confounded (viplavate). (1) For in the case of mere destruction (A) shunyata of all substance would result, since all the substances, for which the kshana-bhanga (the momentary destruction) is eagerly watching, would be destroyed in one and the same moment (kshana); or (B) there would occur the Page #309 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 283 destruction of the existent.43 (I) And in the case of mere production (A) there would be in each case an endless number of substances, stamped with an origination recurring every instant, or (B) there would occur the origination of a non-existent. (II) And in the case of mere stability there would either be (A) the non-existence of any substance, since there would be no successively existing existences, or (B) kshanikatva (perpetual momentariness). Hence origination, destruction and continuance must be dependent on the modifications, and the modifications on the substance, so that all this is merely one substance. Now, rejecting a differentiation of origination, etc., with reference to moments-of-time (kshana), he explains that the very term dravya (substance) signifies dravyatva”, i.e. “that which by nature flows towards its modes": II.10. The substance at one and the same moment (samaya) takes the forms, modes, names or states of origination, persistence and destruction, which certainly are inseparably rolled into one. Therefore all the three are indeed the substance. (102) (Opponent:) “The moment of birth of a thing (vastu), since it is pervaded (vyapta) merely by this birth, is neither a moment of continuance nor a moment of annihilation. The moment of continuance is neither a moment of origination nor a moment of annihilation, since it luxuriates (durlalita) in the interspace of both. The moment of annihilation, since it belongs to something which becomes annihilated after previous origination and continuance (read utpadyavasthaya), is neither a moment of birth nor a moment of stability. Thus reasoned out, the differentiation of origination, etc., with reference to moments-of-time no doubt obtains an entrance into the mind. And, if it so enters, then it is admitted that substances arises by itself (atmana), persists by itself and perishes by itself.” This is not proved. Originations, etc., belong merely to the evolutions; wherefore a differentiation with reference to the moments? To wit, as, when the finishing of the pot, effected by the potter with stick, wheel and rag, is present, that moment of coming-intoexistence of the produced object is the same as the moment of annihilation of the clod and the same as the moment of persistence Page #310 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 284 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES of the clayness, which is found on both sides-of-the-process (kotidvaya): in the same way, when the finishing (of any thing whatever), effected by internal and external causes, is present, then the moment of coming-into-existence of the posterior modification is the same as the moment of annihilation of the prior modification, and the same as the moment of the persistence of the substantiality found on both sides-of-the-process. And, as origination, annihilation and continuance, which respectively inhere, one in the product, one in the clod and one in the clayness, are conjointly seen at one moment in the clay, which has contact with a threefold innate nature: similarly origination, annihilation and continuance, which respectively inhere, one in the posterior modification, one in the prior modification, and one in the substantiality, are conjointly seen at one moment in the substance, which has contact with a threefold innate nature. And, as the origination, annihilation and stability, which abide in the product, the clod and the clayness, are the clay, and nothing else: in the same way the origination, annihilation and stability, which abide in the posterior modification, the prior modification and the substantiality, are the substance, and not another object. Now he considers the origination, annihilation and continuance of a substance by means of the modifications of several substances: II.11. One modification of a substance originates and another vanishes; the substance has not vanished and has not originated. (103) For, as here one triple atom of homogeneous nature, a modification of several substances, vanishes and another, fourfold, atom arises, and, as these three or four matter-particles remain constant, not vanishing and not arising: in the same way all homogeneous modifications of substances vanish and arise, whilst the homogeneous substances remain constant, not vanishing and not arising. And, as one, characterized as man and possessing a heterogeneous nature, vanishes, and another, god (heavenly being), arises, but the two, soul and the matter, remain constant, not vanishing and not arising: in the same manner all heterogeneous modifications of substances vanish and arise, whilst the heterogeneous substances remain constant, not vanishing and not arising. Thus the substances, in themselves constant, but becoming origination and annihilation through the substance-modifications, are Page #311 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 285 origination, annihilation and permanence. Now he considers the origination, annihilation and continuance of a substance through the modifications of one substance: II.12. The substance, undifferentiated from the existent, evolves by itself from one quality into another; therefore it is said that the quality-modifications (guna paryaya) are indeed the substance. (104) The quality-modifications are modifications of one substance, since the quality-modifications are one substance. For their being one substance may be explained by a sahakara (mango) fruit. As the sahakara-fruit, which, evolving by itself from the green state into the yellowish [white, Faddegon] state, has its own existence affected by the successive states of green and yellowish [white, Faddegon] colour, is with these states of green and yellowish [white, Faddegon] colour one object and not a different object, inasmuch as its existence undifferentiated from them: in the same manner the substance which, evolving by itself from the quality of the precedent condition into the quality of the subsequent condition, has its own existence affected by the qualities of these successive conditions, is with these qualities of successive conditions one substance and not a different substance, inasmuch as its existence is undifferentiated from them. And, as the sahakara-fruit, originating with reference to the yellowish [white, Faddegon] colour, decaying with reference to the green colour, permanent in its being a sahakara-fruit, is origination, annihilation and stability in consequence of these being modifications of one thing (vastu): in the same manner the substance, originating with reference to the quality of the subsequent state, decaying with reference to the quality of the precedent state, permanent in the quality of being a substance (dravyatva-guna), is origination, annihilation and stability in consequence of these being modifications of one substance. Now he supplies a proof that existence and substance are not different objects: II.13. If the substance is not an existent reality, then necessarily it is a non-existent; so how is it a substance: Or is it perhaps something else? Therefore the substance is itself existence. (105) If the substance be not by characteristic nature an existent, then there is a double possibility: it is a non-existent, or it exists apart Page #312 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 286 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES from existence. If it were a non-existent, then, since there would be no stability, it would not maintain itself, and thus the substance would come to its end. If it were without existence, then, maintaining itself apart from existence, it would do away with existence, which has merely that purpose. If, on the other hand, in itself existent, then maintaining itself, because of admitting stability, substance will come about, and maintaining itself without being separate from existence, it will allow existence, which has merely that purpose, to come about. Therefore, the substance, in itself, must be admitted to be existence, since existence and the existent, being not separated, are not different. Now he discloses the definition of separateness and “otherness": II.14. Separateness (prthaktva) is occupying of different place; thus runs the teaching of the Vira (Mahavira); other-ness (anyatva) is nonidentity (a-tad-bhava) [i.e. it is not the same] [a relation between two objects A and B may be formulated as “A is non-B” - Faddegon); how could what is not "that” be one with it? (106) Now occupying of different places is the definition of separateness. This is not attributed to existence and substance; since the quality and that which possesses the quality do not occupy different places, as in the case of a white upper-garment. As, namely, the places of the white quality are also the places of the upper-garment which possesses the quality, so that there is between them no differentiation of place, in the same way the places of existence as a quality are also the place of the substance which possesses the quality, so that there is between them no differentiation of place. Even so there is otherness between them; for the definition of that notion is applicable here. Non-identity (a-tad-bhava) is, in fact, the definition of otherness”; and this is found in existence and substance, since there is no identity (tad-bhava) between the quality and that which possesses the quality, as in the case of the white upper-garment. For, as the white colour, which becomes an object of only one sense-organ, namely the eye, but transcends the reach of the set of all other sense-organs, is not the garment, which falls under the reach of the complete set of sense-organs, and as the garment, which falls under Page #313 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 287 the reach of the complete set of sense-organs, is not the white colour, which becomes an object of only one sense-organ, namely the eye, but transcends the reach of the set of all other sense-organs, so that the two are not identical, in the same manner existence, which: (1) occurs as inhering, (2) lacks qualities, (3) is composed of one quality, (4) is a characteristic (visheshana), (5) a predicate (vidhayika) and (6) has occurrence (vrtti) for characteristic nature, is not substance, which (i) occurs as non-inherent, (ii) possesses qualities, (iii) is composed of several qualities, (iv) is a thing for characterization (wisheshya), (v) a subject of predicates, and (vi) is by nature that wherein occurrence takes place; and substance, which does occur as noninherent, possesses qualities, is composed of several qualities, is a thing for characterization, a subject of predicates, and is by nature that wherein occurrence takes place, is not existence, which occurs as inherent, lacks qualities, is composed of one quality, is a characterizer, a predicate and has occurrence for characteristic nature. Therefore there is not identity of these, existence and substance. For this reason, although in a certain respect they are not different objects (arthas), yet we must not suppose their complete oneness; for “being that” (tadbhava) is the definition of oneness. And that which cannot be thought of as “being that” (i.e. being the same, tad-bhavat), how could it be one? Nay, in their function of quality and that which possesses the quality they are simply not one. This is what is meant. And now, making non-identity (a-tad-bhava) his topic, he expounds: II.15. The substance is an existent, the quality is an existent, and the modification is an existent; in this way is its extension (vistara). 44 Not being that (tad-abhava), which is the “non-existence of that,” (tasya-abhava) is a-tad-bhava (the non-identity). (That tad-abhava (“the not being A”) which is the "non-existence of A” (tasya abhava) is a-tad-bhava (“the being non-A," the non-identity). - Faddegon] (107) As one pearl-necklace extends itself (vistiryate) over a triplicity, namely, the necklace, the string and the pearl, so the one substance extends itself over a triplicity, namely, the substance, the quality and the modification. And, as the white quality of the one pearl-necklace extends itself over a triplicity, namely, the white necklace, the white string and the white pearl, in the same way the existence quality of the one substance extends itself over a triplicity, namely, the existent substance, the Page #314 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 288 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES existent quality and the existent modification. And, as in the one pearl-necklace the white quality is not the necklace, or the string, or the pearl, and as the necklace, the string and the pearl are not the white quality, so that they have mutual “not being that,” and this a-tad-bhava (the fact of being non-A), defined as “not being that,” is based on the fact that one is different (anya) from the other, in the same way in the substance the existence-quality is not the substance, or another quality (of the substance), or a modification, nor are the substance, the other quality and the modification the existence-quality; so that they have mutual “not being that,” and this a-tad-bhava, defined as “not being that,” is based on the fact that one is different (anya) from the other. Now he rejects a-tad-bhava ("esse non-A) as a definition of nonexistence in general: II.16. The substance is not the quality, and the quality is not the tattva (substance), indeed; for, according to the teaching (of Jina), this a-tad-bhava is not non-existence simply. (108) In one substance that which is the substance is not the quality, and that which is the quality is not the substance; thus the nonexistence of the substance under the aspect of quality, or of the quality under the aspect of substance, a non-existence under-a-certain-aspect (tena), is a-tad-bhava. And, since this suffices to justify the notion-of-otherness (anyatva), we may not define a-tad-bhava as non-existence simply, so that, for instance, substance should be non-existence of quality and quality nonexistence of substance. For, were this true, then the result would be either plurality of the substance, or “nothingness” (shunyata) of both substance and quality, or their form as negation (apoha).95 For (I) as the non-existence of thinking substance is unthinking substance and the non-existence of unthinking substance is thinking substance, so that there is a plurality in them, in the same way the non-existence of substance would be quality, and the non-existence of quality would be substance, so that there would be plurality in substance, although it is one. (II) Or, as in the case of non-existence of gold there is non-existence of gold-in-general (suvarnatva), and in the case of non-existence of "being gold” there is non-existence of gold, and thus absolute-nihility Page #315 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 289 (shunyatva) of both, in the same way in the case of non-existence of substance there would be non-existence of quality, and in the case of non-existence of quality there would be non-existence of substance, consequently absolute-nihility of both. And, as the pot would be merely the non-existence of the piece of cloth, and the piece of cloth merely the non-existence of the pot, so that both would have the form of apoha (negation), in the same way quality would be merely the non-existence of substance, and substance the non-existence of quality, so that both would have the form of apoha. Therefore he who wishes oneness, non-nihility (a-shunyatva) and the non-negationness (an-apoha) of substance and quality, must accept a-tad-bhava (non-identity) as described. Now he establishes between existence and substance a relation of quality and that-which-possesses-the quality: II.17. The evolution, having the substance as innate nature, is the quality, not distinguished from the existent (sad-avishishta, "the same as," "identical with the existent," "called existence" cf. Tattvadipika on 105 and 106); the substance, reposing in its innate nature, is the existent; this is the teaching of the Jina. (109) Substance has previously (PS 99) been proved to be the existent reality, since it is always reposing in its innate nature. The innate nature of substance has been called the evolution. That evolution which is the innate nature of the substance is likewise quality, not separated from the existent; this will now be proved. The same astitva (the actuality-of-existence)-which is an occurrence of the characteristic nature of a substance and is termed "existent" (sat), because it reveals what is most essential in the substance-is the evolution, which, being a quality not separated from that existent, is the innate nature of the substance. In the first place, the evolution forms the innate nature of the substance, because the occurrence (vrtti) of the substance, whilst reaching the threefold-aspect (tri-koti) of time (samaya), is evolving every moment through this innate nature. And, further, (this evolution) is a quality, which, undistinguished from the existent, is a predicator (cf commentory on 106) of the substance, because it consists in the occurrence of the substance, i.e. in the actuality-of-its-existence (astitva). Page #316 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 290 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Thus is established between existence and substance the relation of quality and that which possesses the quality. Now he refutes the idea of diversity of the quality and that which has the quality: II.18. There is without substance no quality whatever, and no modification; to be a substance (dravyatva) means to be (bhava); therefore substance is in itself existence. (110) There can not be any quality or any modification, separately (prthak) from substance, as e.g., separately from the gold, its yellow colour or its ring shape. Then in the substance its being a substance, which consists in the occurrence of its characteristic nature and is called the actuality-of-its-existence, does this, whilst it is also a quality, called its being that, occur separately from the substance? Indeed, it does not. Therefore let the substance be the existence, its very self. Now he shows, with reference to substance, that there is no contradiction between its origination from an existent (sat-utpada) and its origination from a non-existent (a-set-utpada): II.19. Substance, which in innate nature is suchlike always, attains a manifestation which, under the substance-aspect and the modification-aspect, is bound to an existent and a non-existent nature. (111) Substance, whose marks are, in the manner described, in their totality undefiled, and which is in nature without beginning or termination, attains manifestation; and this manifestation of substance, when considered under the denotation of substance, is bound to an existent nature, but, when considered under the denotation of modification, bound to a non-existent nature. For (A) When it is called substance and not modifications, then the substance, while-by means of the energies (shakti) of sameness of nature (anvaya, general nature), which (1) are exempt from commencement and termination, (2) proceed simultaneously, and (3) develop the substance-assuming now these, then those particular (vyakti) divergences (vyatireka), which (1) are characterized by commencement and termination, (2) proceed in succession, and (3) develop modifications, has a manifestation bound to an existent nature (sadbhava); as in the case of gold. For, when it is called gold and not modifications, for instance a bracelet, then the gold, while-by means of the energies of its general Page #317 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 291 nature (anvaya), which (1) exists as long as the gold exists, (2) proceeds simultaneously, and (3) develops the gold-assuming now these, then those particular divergences, which (1) exists as long as the modifications, such as a bracelet, exist, (2) proceeds in succession, and (3) develops the modifications such as a bracelet, has a manifestation bound to an existent-nature. (B) But, when called modifications, and not substance, then the substance, while-by means of now of these, then of those, particular divergences, which (1) are characterized by commencement and termination, (2) proceed in succession, and (3) develop modifications, assuming the energies of sameness of nature, which (1) are exempt from commencement and termination, (2) proceed simultaneously, and (3) develop the substance, has a manifestation bound to a non-existent nature, as in the case of gold. For, when it is called modifications, such as a bracelet, and not gold, then the gold, while-by means now of these, then of those particular divergences, which (1) exist as long as the modifications, such as the bracelet, exist, (2) proceed in succession, and (3) develop the modifications, such as the bracelet, -assuming the energies of its sameness of nature, which (1) exist as long as the gold exists, (2) proceed simultaneously, and (3) develop the gold, has a manifestation bound to a non-existent nature. (© But even in the case of denotation by the term “modifications,” when thus origination from a non-existent takes place, the respective particular divergences, which develop the modifications, will, as attaining a simultaneous procedure, share in the nature of the energies of the sameness of nature (anvaya, “general nature”), and make the modifications into a substance. So, through the particular divergences, which develop the modifications, such as a bracelet, and which, as attaining a simultaneous procedure, share in the nature of the energies of the sameness of nature, the modifications (read angadadi-paryaya api), such as a bracelet, will become gold. (D) And likewise in the case of denotation by the term “substance," when thus origination from an existent takes place, the energies of the sameness of nature, which develop the substance, will, as attaining a successive procedure, share in the nature of the particular divergences, and make the substance into modifications. Page #318 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 292 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Thus, through the energies of the sameness of nature, which develop the gold and which in a successive procedure share in the nature of the particular divergences (read tad-tad-vyatireka-vyaktitvam apannabhir), the gold will become the very modifications, bracelet, etc. Therefore the thesis origination from the existent takes place in accordance with the denotation under a substance-aspect, and origination from the non-existent in accordance with the denotation under a modification-aspect” is without fault. Now he ascertains origination from the existent to be un-anyatva (not being another): II.20. The soul which is will be a man or god (celestial being), becoming each time another. Does it then lose its substantiality (dravyatva) (the state-of-evolution]? Not losing this, how does it become another? (112) In the first place, the substance is an existent reality, never forsaking its energy of sameness of nature, which makes up its substantiality (see Tattva-dipika on PS 111(A)]. And further, even in the manifestation (pradur-bhava) of a particular divergence, which is a modification of the substance, the energy of sameness of nature (anvaya) is not lost; and so the substance is not-another (un-anya). Therefore in virtue of negation-of-otherness, origination from an existent (sad-utpada) is proved for the substance. Thus, the soul, being a substance, will necessarily, since the occurrence (vrtti) of a substance craves for a modification, exists in accordance with one of the modifications, hell-inhabitant, animal (tiryag), man, god or liberated soul. Does it, in becoming that, thereby forsake its energy of sameness of nature, which consists in the substance? It does not. If it does not, how could it be “another”; consequently it must be the same with its existence (satta) exhibiting a three-sided aspect (tri-koti) li.e. its existence in all three times) (The same expression occurs in commentary on PS 109). Now he ascertains origination from the non-existent to be anyatva (being another): II.21. A man is not a god, nor is a god a man or a liberated soul; being thus “not,” how does (the soul) admit of identity (un-anyabhava)? (113) The modifications (This and the following paragraph correspond to commeniary on PS 111(B) and (C)], since they exist exclusively Page #319 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 293 during the time of their own particular divergence (vyatireka), which is the modification, are therefore at other times not existent. And, as regards the manifestation of the modifications, which takes place in the time given, according to succession, and threaded through them with its energy-of-sameness, which has a substance-character, in regard thereto the inodifications of nature, since they do not exist before their own several divergences, which constitute the respective modifications, are "others”. Therefore, through this relation of otherness between the modifications it is ascertained that in substance-which is not separated from its modifications, inasmuch as it is the characteristic nature, the agent, the instrument and the abode 46 of the modifications, origination from a non-existent takes place. Thus, a man is not a god or liberated soul; neither is a god a man or liberated soul; being “not” (read asan instead of asat) in this way, “other,” and so that a soul-substance whose modification as man, for instance, is being effected-like a piece of gold, whose secondary state of armlet, for example, is coming into existence-should not be at each stage (pratipadam)“other”? Now he repudiates a contradiction between the anyatva and unanyatva in the one substance: II.22. The soul substance when viewed from the point-of-viewof-substance (dravyarthikena), is the same (not other) in all its altered modifications, but when viewed from the point-of-view-of-modification (paryayarthikena), it is other and not other from the modifications because during a certain time it possesses the nature of that through which it evolves during the time of the evolution. (cf PS 8). (114) With reference to any thing whatever, since it has generality (samanya) and particularity (vishesha) for self, those who consider its characteristic nature possess two (mental)-eyes, which successively distinguish the generality and the particularity, namely one eye for the substance-aspect and another for the modification-aspect. When one looks with only the eye of the substance-aspect open, whilst the eye of the modification-aspect is decidedly closed, then to those who observe only the one generality of soul, placed in the differentiations consisting in being hell-inhabitant, animal, man, god and liberated soul, and do not observe the differentiations, all that manifests itself as soul-substance. Page #320 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 294 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES When one looks with only the eye of the modification-aspect open, whilst the eye of the substance-aspect is decidedly closed (Insert vidhaya in the text), then to those who observe only the several differentiations disposed in the soul-substance, such as the modifications hellinhabitant, animal, man, god and liberated soul, and do not observe the generality, it manifests itself as something else, and again something else. For the substance is, during the times of its several particularities, not other than the particularity of each time, because it has the nature of it; as in the case of fire, which has the nature of the collected (material, gana), of grass, or leaves, or wood. But when with both eyes, the one for the substance-aspect and that for the modification-aspect simultaneously open, one looks in the two directions, then the soul-generality disposed in the modifications such as hell-inhabitant, animal, man, god and liberated soul, and the soul-particularities, consisting in these modifications, hell-inhabitant, animal, man, god and liberated soul, and abiding in the soul-generality, are simultaneously observed. Here the one-eye-view is a partial view, and the two-eye-view is the complete view. In this complete view the anyatva and un-anyatva of substance are not contradictory. Now he introduces the sapta-bhangi,47 which prohibits all contradictory-assertions (vipratishedha): II.23. With regard to some modification or other, it is stated that a substance is (1), is not (2), is indescribable (3), is both ()48 or something else. 49 (115) (1) Quodammodo (syat), it is, (2) Quodammodo, it is not, (3) Quodammodo, it is indescribable, (4) Quodammodo, it is and is not (= 1 + 2), (5) Quodammodo, it is and is indescribable (= 1 + 3), (6) Quodammodo, it is not and is indescribable (= 2 + 3), (7) Quodammodo, it is, is not, and is indescribable (= 1 + 2 + 3), B. (1) With reference to (rupena) itself. (2) With reference to another. (3) With regard to simultaneously of reference to itself and reference to another, Page #321 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 295 (4) With regard to the succession of reference to itself and reference to another (= 1 + 2), (5) With regard to reference to itself, and simultaneity of reference to itself and reference to another (= 1 + 3), (6) With regard to reference to another, and simultaneity of itself and reference to another (= 2 + 3), (7) With regard to reference to itself, reference to another, and simultaneity of reference to itself and reference to another (= 1 + 2 + 3), If in this sevenfold way the substance is described: (1) As being, with reference to itself, (2) As not being, with reference to another, (3) As indescribable simultaneously, with reference to itself and another, (4) As successively being and not being, with reference to itself and another, (5) As being and indescribable, with regard to reference to itself, and simultaneity of reference to itself and reference to another, (6) As not being and indescribable, with regard to reference to another, and simultaneity of reference to itself and reference to another, (7) As being, not being, and being indescribable, with regard to reference to itself, reference to another, and simultaneity of reference to itself and another, thus with reference to each single property of substance, with its unlimited number of properties, this sevenfold-formula-of-restriction, interposing, with its partly meant and partly not meant affirmation (vidhi) and negation (pratishedha), the infallible magic charm of the invariably enunciated word Quodammodo dispels the entire infatuation of contrariety (vipratishedha), unexhausted by the word eva (exclusively). Now, in regard to the soul, which is taken for example as being the object of inquiry, he explains the “otherness” of its modifications, such as man, etc., as being the fruit of actions: II.24. There is no modification (such as man, etc.) which can be called "this one” is eternal; no deed, originated from (any one's) innate nature, is non-existent [i.e. there is no activity which is not the outcome of its nature]; for there is no deed without fruit, although (the fulfilment of) the highest dharma is without fruit. (116) Page #322 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 296 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES For here, in the case of a soul which is subject to samsara and with transformations (vivartana) every moment conditioned by the vicinity of a beginningless karmic matter as accessory-condition (upadhi), every deed is originated (read nirvrttasti) from (the soul's) innate nature. Therefore among the modifications such as man, etc., to which the soul is subject, there is no one, carved out (tankotkirna), whom we could call “the real one,” since each later one is disqualified, as being the fruit of actions directed to the destruction of the respectively precedent, or they may be regarded as fruit of action, due to the soul being still encumbered with infatuation. The action, namely, of a thinking being (chetana) is an evolution of his thinking, characterized by a previous and subsequent state. And this evolution bears fruit for the soul imbued with infatuation, since it causes effects such as human life, etc., in the same way as the evolution of an atom, which is connected with another atom, causes an effect such as a double-atom (diatomic molecule). But, when, at the disappearance of the conjunction with infatuation, it does not produce any effect such as the state of man, etc., -as the evolution of the atom, which has ended its connection with another atom has no longer the double atom as effect--the action is without fruit and is called the highest dharma, since it is the own nature of highest substance. 50 Now he explains how for the soul the modifications man etc., are the results of actions: II.25. Karmic matter called (physique or body-making] “name karma (nama-karman)”1 dominating by its own nature or class or karma, the nature of the soul, makes it (the self) man, animal, hellinhabitant or god (celestial being). (117) The action is indeed self's karma, because it is “the thing to be attained” (prapta) 52 by the self; and matter, whose evolution is attained (prapta) by that occasion (i.e. the action of the self which acts as the auxiliary cause (nimitta) thereof), is likewise karman; moreover, the modifications, such as man, which are its (It, i.e. of the karman in the precedent meanings) effects, may be called the fruit of deed, because they arise from the soul's deed, which is the principal-cause (mula-karana). For, when there is no deed, matter is not karman, because the modifications, which are its effects, do not arise. How now do these (modifications of the self) attain the nature of Page #323 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 297 the effects of karman? It is because the action takes place with domination of the own-nature of the soul by the own-nature of the karman; as in the case of the lamp-light. As, namely, the lamp-light is the effect of the light-substance (jyotis) because it is effected by the own nature of the light-substance, dominating the own nature of the oil, so the modifications, such as man, etc., are the effect of karman, because they are effected by the own nature of karmun, dominating the own nature of the soul. Now he answers the question how in the modifications, man, etc., the own nature of soul yields to this domination: II.26. The jivas (living beings), viz. men, hell-inhabitants, animals or gods (celestial beings) are originated from nama-karman; for, while evolving through their karman (deeds, or conjunctions with matter, or consequences of deeds), these souls do not realize their own nature. (118) In the first place, these modifications, such as man, are originated from the karmic matter called nama-karman. But it is not simply by this that the own nature of soul becomes subdued, just as little as does the ruby in bracelets with rubies set in gold. But that which hinders the soul from maintaining even then its own nature is its evolution into its karma; as in the case of water. As, namely, water does not maintain its own nature of (independent) substantiality and sweetness, whilst evolving, with its infinitesimal-spacial-constituents and its taste, into trees such as the picumanda or the sandal-tree, so neither does the soul maintain its own nature, that is to say, its immateriality, and its possession of unstained pureness, whilst evolving, with its infinitesimal-spacial-constituents and its mental-state (bhava), into karman. Now he explains how the soul, although permanent in its substantiality, is non-permanent in regard to its modifications: II.27. In the midst of the universe-of-souls, subject every moment to annihilation and origination, no one is born, or dies. For origination of one modification is destruction of another. Yet the origination and destruction are different. (119) Here indeed no one is born or dies. Yet, on the other hand, the world of souls, men, gods, animals and hell-inhabitants, annihilation and origination carries with it every moment annihilation and origination, because they evolve with the moment. And this is not Page #324 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 298 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES contradictory, because origination and annihilation are one as well as different. When decay and origination are one, then we have the “thesis” (purva-paksha); but, when they are many, then the “antitheses” (uttara-paksha). For, as in the affirmation “the pot is the pitcher,” since oneness of the characteristic-natures of pot and pitcher is not possible, the clay which is the base (adhara) of them both shows itself, so in the affirmation origination is annihilation," since oneness of the characteristic natures of originations and annihilation is not possible, the permanence which is the base of them both shows itself. Consequently, when the modification god, e.g., arises and the modification man, e.g., vanishes, then, with the understanding that the origination is here the annihilation, the soul-substance, which possesses permanence and is the base of the two states mentioned, is conceived. So at all times, whoso lives, is, in respect of substantiality, carved out (clearly). But further: as in the affirmation “the pot is something else, and the pitcher is something else,” since “otherness” of the clay, the common base of both, is not possible, the characteristic natures of pot and pitcher show themselves, so in the affirmation origination is something else, and annihilation is something else," since "otherness” of permanence, which is the common base of them both, is not possible, the characteristic natures of origination and annihilation show themselves. Consequently, when the modification (paryaye) god, e.g., arises and (read chanyah instead of vanyah) the modification (paryaye] man, e.g., vanishes, then, upon the understanding that the origination is something and the annihilation is something else, the two modifications, e.g. god and man, which represent origination and annihilation, are conceived. So every moment the soul in respect of the modifications is non-permanent. Now he expounds the cause of this non-permanence of the soul: II.28. Therefore during the transmigratory existence (samsara) no one ever remains stable in its same nature; and this transmigration [in mundane existence] is action of the transmigrating substance. (120) Since the soul, although permanent in regard to substantiality (dravyatva), is non-permanent with respect to modifications, we understand how no one in transmigration is at rest in his own nature. And of this non-permanence samsara is the cause, since it is suchlike Page #325 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 299 by its characteristic nature; for it has modifications such as man, etc., for self. And the evolution, called action, which belongs to the evolving substance and consists in giving up a former state and accepting a following state, is the characteristic nature of this transmigration. But whence arises adhesion (slesha) of matter to soul during samsara (which in essence is evolution), so that it receives the nature of modifications such as man? This question he here settles: II.29. The soul, stained with karmic matter, undergoes evolution, connected with karman, thus the karman adheres; therefore karman may be called the evolution. (121) This self-evolution, called samsara, being such as we have described, is the cause of the adherence of material-karman.S4 But what again is the cause of such an evolution. The material-karman is the cause of it. For the self undergoes this adherence, as being conjoined with material-karman. But, if so, have we not the fallacy of mutual dependence (itaretarashraya)? No; since the self, which is bound by materialkarman, existent without beginning, adopts the previous materialkarman as cause. So, since new and old material-karman functions as effect and cause, this suchlike evolution of the self is (speaking metaphorically, figuratively or as formal usage, upachara)) the material-karman; and the self, as agent of its own evolution, is, metonymously, the agents of the material-karman. Now he explains how in the transcendental sense of consciousnessas-such (paramartha) the self is not the agent of material-karman: II.30. The self itself is the evolution; and this evolution is considered to be action, which consists of soul; and action is taken as karma; so (the self) is not the agent of the material] karman. (122) The self itself is the evolution of the self; for that which evolves is nothing else than the evolution, since it is the agent of the characteristic form of the evolution. And its suchlike evolution is action (kriya), consisting of soul; for in the case of all substances action (kriya), characterized as evolution, is acknowledged to be the self (of these substances). And action again is a karma; for it is attained (prapyate) by the Page #326 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 300 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES self independently. Therefore, according to the higher transcendental sense, the self is the agent of that subjective-karma (bhava-karman, or conscious deed), which is essentially an evolution of the self; but it is not the agent of material-karma (dravya-karman), which is essentially an evolution of matter. Then who is the agent of the material-karman?-Matter itself is the evolution of matter; for that which evolves is nothing else than the evolution, since it is the agent of the characteristic nature of the evolution and its suchlike evolution is the action (kriya), as far as it consists of matter; for in the case of all substances action (kriya), characterized as evolution, is acknowledged to be the self (of these substances). And this activity again is a karman; for it is attained (prapyate) by matter, independently. Therefore, in the higher sense, the self of matter is the agent of the material-karman (dravya-karman), which is essentially an evolution of the self (of matter); but it is not the agent of the subjective-karma, which is essentially an evolution of the self. So then the self evolves with its characteristic form of self, but not with the characteristic form of matter. Now he gives an answer to the question "What is the characteristic form with which the self evolves?": II.31. The self evolves as consciousness (chetana); the consciousness is considered to be threefold, i.e. with regard to knowledge, karma (deed or action) and fruit of action (karma-phala). (123) Since, namely, the self's being consciousness means its pervasion of its own quality, therefore consciousness-as-such is the characteristic form of self, and therewith the self evolves. No single evolution of the self departs from consciousness-that is the intent. Consciousness, again, is threefold; for it may be knowledge, deed and the fruit of deed." Here the knowledge-consciousness is evolution through Knowledge; the deed-consciousness is evolution through the deed; and the consciousness of the deed-fruit is evolution through this fruit of the deed. Now he describes the characteristic form of knowledge, deed and fruit of deed: II.32. Knowledge is comprehension (vikalpa) of objects; deed is Page #327 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 301 that which is undertaken by the soul; it is said to be manifold; its fruit is either pleasure or pain. (124) Knowledge is comprehension of objects. What do we mean here by object? Everything which stands out with distinction (vibhaga) between self and other. Clear-distinction (vikalpa) [between self and other) is the presentation of the object's appearance (akara). So we call knowledge the clear-distinction of an object with reference to its own appearance and appearances strange to it, both showing themselves simultaneously as in the interior expanse of a looking-glass. The deed is the thing done by the self: that positive-existence (sadbhava) which is every moment effected by the self, assuming now this and then that mental-state (bhava), is called a deed (karman); for it is attained (prapyate) by the self. And, though uniform, it is manifold (successful or futile); according as the vicinity of material-karman as a condition (required for the purpose) occurs or does not occur. The pleasure or pain to be brought about by the deed is the fruit of the deed. The fruit of a deed, when due (insert yad) to the negation of the vicinity of material-karman as an accessory-condition, is characterized by serenity (anakulatva) and is normal (prakrti-bhuta); it is happiness. But the fruit of a deed, when due to the occurrence of the vicinity of material-karman as an accessory-condition, is abnormal (vikrti-bhuta), since the characteristic of happiness is absent; it is misery Thus we have ascertained the characteristic form of knowledge, deed, and the fruit of deed. Now he ascertains that knowledge, deed, and the fruit of deed are the self: II.33. The self is evolvement by nature; this evolution is with reference to knowledge, deed or fruit of the deed; therefore knowledge, deed, and fruit of the deed must be considered to be the self. (125) Now the self has evolution for self, because we have ourselves stated that “the self is itself evolution.” The evolution, since it has here consciousness for self, is fit to be knowledge, deed, or fruit of the deed, since consciousness consists of these. Therefore, knowledge, deed, and fruit of the deed are the self. Since with this definition of pure substance no connection with strange substances is possible, and since the modifications are dissolved in the substance, therefore the self consists in pure substance. Page #328 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 302 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Accordingly, since from the certitude that the self, when evolved into or reduced to the state of being knowable (ineyatam apanna) (cf. Pravachanasara, 32 and 42) is not pure, a realization of the principle (tattva) of pure self entity results from establishment of the principle (tattva) of knowledge, welcoming now this (realization of the principle of pure self), he concludes the exposition of substance in general: II.34. If the shramana is sure in his conviction that the soul itself is agent, instrument, act and fruit, and does not evolve into something else, then he conceives the (real nature of the) pure self. (126) He who, after having thus ascertained that the self is agent, instrument, act and fruit of the act, no more evolves into the strange (other) substance, attains the pure self, which has exhausted its commingling with strange substances and whose modifications are dissolved in its substance; but none else succeeds in this. Thus, in the days when the manifestations (vrtti) of my self were coloured by passion (uparaga), which rushed forth owing to the vicinity of accessory conditions, namely the bondage by material-karman, familiar from all time, -like a crystal gem, whose manifestations are coloured by a hue (uparaga) which rushes forth owing to the vicinity of the China rose-and when I was a transmigrating soul with a secondary-nature (vikara), superinduced by the other,” even then no one belonged to me; even then I, alone, was agent, independent as I was by my thoughtnature, although impassioned; even then I, alone, was instrument, nearest-cause (sadhakatama) as I was by my thought-nature, although impassioned; even then I, alone, was deed, attained by the self as I was, through the innate nature of the evolutions of my thought, although impassioned; even then I, alone, was the fruit of the deed, happiness, or, with reversed qualities, misery, effected by the innate nature of the evolutions of my thought, although impassioned. And at present, when the manifestations of the self, completely pure and original, flash forth in consequence of the dissolution of the presence of an accessory-condition, namely bondage by materialkarman, familiar from the beginning, -like a crystal gem, when the manifestations of its self, completely pure and original, flash forth Page #329 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 303 through the disappearance of the vicinity of the China rose-when I am exclusively desirous of liberation and have exhausted the secondarynature, superinduced by the other,” now also no one belongs to me; now also I, alone, am agent, independent through my completely pure thought-nature; now also I, alone, am instrument, nearest cause as I am through my completely pure thought-nature; now also I, alone, am deed, attained by myself as I am, through the innate nature of the evolutions of my completely pure thought; now also I, alone, am the fruit of the deed, called happiness and characterized as serenity, effected by my completely pure thoughtnature. Thus to one realizing that the self is one only in the path of bondage as well as of liberation like an ultimate atom, with its oneness realized-no longer does an evolution into other substance take place. And, like that atom, realizing his oneness, he is no more connected with the other”; then through non-connection with other substance he becomes completely pure. Realizing that the agent, the instrument, the deed and the fruit of the deed are all himself, he no more becomes commingled with the modifications; and owing to not being commingled with modifications he becomes completely pure. “Dissevering the self from intercourse with other substance and cleansing by generality the complete set of particularities; thus the pure mode-of-considering-things (naya) plunders the grandeur of Infatuation, and distinguishes the reality (of the nature of self] through deep discriminative insight.” (PS Kalash 7) "When the evolution into the other' has stopped and the delusion of difference between agent, act, etc., has disappeared, this consciousness, having at last realised the principle of pure self, and concentrated in the pure splendour, consisting of consciousness alone, will stand for ever liberated, whilst its innate grandeur shines forth.” (PS Kalash 8) “Having thus levelled the mind in the knowledge of substance in general, (the author) now erects the precipitous heights of the knowledge of its species (vishesha).” (PS Kalash 9) Thus the exposition of SUBSTANCE IN GENERAL. Here begins the exposition of the particularities (vishesha)of substance: wherein he first ascertains the particularization (vishesha) of substance as soul and non-soul: Page #330 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 304 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES SUBSTANCE IN PARTICULAR (VERSES 127-144) II.35. Substance is sout and non-soul. Soul, again, is constituted of consciousness (chetna) and psychic-attention (upayoga); non-soul is devoid of consciousness, primarily material-substance. (127) Substance, even while not forsaking the generality (samanya) of substance, which is the condition (nibandhana) of oneness, yet, since there exist differential characteristics, “mounted” upon this (generality), admits the particularization of soul and non-soul, in consequence of their mutual exclusion (vyavaccheda). Of these two, the soul has only one specialized-form (vyakti), the self-substance. But of non-soul there are five specialized-forms, (1) material substance, (2) substance dharma (principle of motion), (3) the substance adharma (principle of rest), (4) the substance time, (5) the substance space. The differential (i.e. only belonging to one class of substances, and therefore used in the definition) characteristic (vishesha-lakshana) of soul is the fact that it consists of consciousness with its manifestation or psychic-attention; of non-soul, again, it is being without consciousness. The soul is that (substance) in which we see installed a manifestation of consciousness, august, in the form of conscious awareness (samvitti), never absent, and since it penetrates its own properties, shining with characteristic nature. and of psychic-attention, characterized as an evolution thereof and having the form of a functioning of the substance. Where, on the other hand, we see installed an insentient-nature (achetana), inwardly and outwardly, due to absence of consciousness, accompanied by psychic-attention and with characteristics as described, that is non-soul Now he defines the differentiation between the universe and the beyond (a-loka): II.36. That which is located in space, provided with time and asti-kayas (those having extension in space), dharma and adharma (the principles of motion and rest], and conjoined with soul and matter, is at all times the universe [loka]. (128) Of substance (read dravyam) there is what is differentiated by differentiation as universe and the beyond, because these have each its own characteristics. Page #331 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 305 The universe, namely, is characterized by the fact that it consists in inherence of the six substances; but the beyond (or non-universe) is characterized by consisting merely of space. Wherein and with what extension of extremely large space, pervading all substances, soul and matter, which have movement and rest for properties, enact movement and rest; and dharma and adharma, which are the conditions (nibandhana) of their movement and rest, are present enveloping them; and time, the cause (nimitta) of the revolving (vartana) of all substance, for ever luxuriates (durlalita): that which has for definition the consisting of the assemblage of that so extended space and of all other substances without exception is universe. On the other hand, in what extension of space the movement and rest of soul and matter do not take place, and dharma and adharma do not abide, and time does not luxuriate, that is the beyond. Now he ascertains the differentiation of existence-as-action (as motion, kriya-bhava) and qualitative-existence (tad-bhava):"7 11.37. Origination, permanence and annihilation of the universe, comprising of souls and matter, take place by evolution, combination and separation." (129) There is a differentiation of substance according to its possession of action and its possession of mere (qualitative-) being. Matter and soul are both in the possession of (qualitative-) being and of action, because they arise, are permanent and vanish by evolution, separation and combination. But the other substances possess mere states-ofevolution of their own being, because they arise, are permanent and vanish exclusively by evolution. This is certain. Here being is characterized as only its own state-of-evolution; action as movement (or vibration, parispandan). All the substances are in possession of being; for, being through evolution endowed with constancy (anvaya) and divergence (vyatireka), and being permanent, arising and vanishing (by evolution), they have evolution as their proper nature. But material substances possess action as well; for, being separated by movement and combined by combination, and being, on the other hand, permanent, arising and vanishing through separation, they have movement as their proper nature. In the same way, souls possess action also; for, being by movement Page #332 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 306 THE ESSENCE OF JÄINA SCRIPTURES separated from material-substances functioning at that time as karman or no-karman, and being combined with them by combination, and, moreover, arising, being permanent, and vanishing through separation, they have movement as their proper nature. Now he teaches that differentiation of the substances results from differentiation of the qualities: II.38. As marks (linga) by which the substance is distinctly-known as soul or as non-soul we must consider the qualities differentiated by non-identity (with the substances) and by being of an incorporeal or corporeal nature (murta-amurta). (130) Qualities are marks, because by them, as belonging to substance and not to anything else, substance is marked, gone to (lingyate = gamyate). And, being differentiated from substance by non-identity (atad-bhava), according to the saying the substance is not the qualities, and the qualities are not the substance (cf. Pravachana-sara, 108),” they function as marks thereof, when the mark and the possessor-ofthe-mark are known. And these qualities cause in the substances such differentiations as “this is a soul," and "this is a non-soul"; fór they themselves are endowed with differentiation through the fact that (the substances) are differentiated by their distinctive-being (tad-bhava). And, because the differentiation of the (qualities) arises from the fact that a substance is differentiated by this, or that proper nature, therefore, as the corporeal and incorporeal substances are differentiated by their respective-distinctive-being, i.e. by either corporeality or incorporeality, we have certain differentiation of the qualities, “these qualities are corporeal, and those are incorporeal.” Now he expounds the definition and relation of corporeal and incorporeal qualities: II.39. Corporeal (murta) qualities, which can be perceived by the sense-organs, characterise the material substances (pudgala-dravya) and are manifold. The qualities of incorporeal substances should be considered incorporeal (amurta). (131) Perceptibility by the sense-organs is the definition of corporeal qualities; and the very opposite holds true of the incorporeal qualities. And these corporeal qualities belong to material-substance, since this alone is corporeal. The incorporeal qualities belong to the other substances, since all substances, other than matter, are incorporeal. Page #333 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 307 Now he teaches the qualities of the corporeal matter-substance: II.40. Colour, taste, smell, and touch are found in matter, beginning with fine substance and ending with earth. But sound is a manifold (chitra) material-substance. (132) Touch, taste, smell, and colour are perceptible to the sense-organs, since they form objects for them. And these, perceived or not perceived, according as the sensorial-perceptibility has a manifest(vyakti) or latent-form (shakti), belong, in the character of special qualities, to every kind of matter without exception, beginning with the ultimate atom, the fine modification consisting of one substance, and ending with the earth-aggregate, the gross modification, consisting of several substances; and, since owing to their corporeality, they do not inhere in other substances, they prove the existence of matter. That sound also, as perceived by a sense-organ, is a quality should not be suggested; for, inasmuch as it exhibits a manifoldness due to variety-of-nature (vaichitrya), it is taken to be a modification of matter, consisting of many substances. For, if a quality, then, in the first place, sound is not a quality of an incorporeal substance, since the incorporeal substance also would be an object of the auditory sense-organ, inasmuch as quality and thatwhich-possesses-the-quality, as not possessing separate infinitesimalspacial-constituents (pradesha), are realized in the same realization of intuitive awareness. Nor is it a quality of corporeal substance, since the characteristic of a quality is here eradicated by the characteristic of a modification. The characteristic of a modification is, in fact, incidentality; and the characteristic of a quality is constancy (nityatva). So sound, in which durability is eradicated by incidentality, is not a quality. As for the durability found in it, that, we should notice, belongs to the components of the several (objects) and to their qualities, such as touch, etc., and is not found in the modification called sound. But, if sound is a modification of matter, then it is not necessary that it should be, like the aggregate earth, an object for the tactile organ, etc.; for (1) water is not an object of the olfactory organ, (2) light not of the olfactory and gustatory organs, (3) wind not of the olfactory, gustatory and visual organs. And yet water, light and wind (Read evam ab-jyotir-marutah) do not accordingly (1) lack smell, (2) lack smell and taste, (3) lack smell, taste and colour, since it is believed Page #334 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 308 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES that all the kinds of matter possess the fourfold set of qualities, touch, etc. For we see that the same material-components which give rise to (a) the moon-stone, (6) the fire-stick and (c) the barley-corn, which possess the fourfold set of qualities, touch, etc., in manifest-form (vyakta), likewise originate (a) water (read ab-jyotir or ap-pradyotir instead of apradyotir) with unmanifest smell, (6) light with unmanifest smell and taste, and (c) the wind in the stomach with unmanifest smell, taste and colour. And the fact that some quality in some circumstances possesses sometimes a manifest as well as a not-manifest-form, dependent upon a manifoldness of incidental evolutions, is not opposed to the innate nature of an eternal substance. Let it be then that sound is a modification of matter. Now he mentions the qualities of the other incorporeal substances: II.41. The function of space is giving room; the dharma-substance is cause of motion; the substance opposite to dharma has for quality the effecting of rest; (133) II.42. The quality of time is the rolling-on (of events) (vartana); the manifestation of consciousness or psychic-attention is said to be the quality of self. Thus, in short, you should know the qualities of the substances devoid of corporeality. (134) The typical-quality of space is to be the cause of giving universally and simultaneously room to all substances. That of dharma to be at once a cause of movement to all souls and material-components possessing movement as evolution. That of adharma to be at once a cause of rest to all souls and material-components possessing rest as evolution. That of time to be a cause of the fact that all other substances without exception occur according to their modification in a certain moment (samaya). That of soul to be an evolution of consciousness. Thus in this concise enumeration of typical-qualities there is proofof-existence (linga) of the incorporeal-substances. The fact of providing a common room (avagaha) for all substances at the same time, since by reason of non-omnipresent it does not belong to any other substance, suffices to prove space. The fact of causing at one moment, as far as the universe reaches, the movements of all souls and material-components which are evolving Page #335 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 309 through movement,-which property does not belong to time (cf commentary on 48) and the material components, (i.e. ultimate atoms), since these do not possess (several) infinitesimal-spacial-units; or to soul, since this possesses, except in the case of samudghata, only an “innumerable” (asamkheya) (the soul contains “innumerable pradeshas”, cf. next gatha) portion of the universe; or to space, since there is no fluctuation of the limit of the universe and the beyond; nor to adharma, since this is cause of an opposite effect-proves dharma. Similarly, the fact of causing at one moment, as far as the universe reaches, the rest of all souls and material-components, which are evolving through rest-which property does not belong to time and the material-components, since these do not possess (several infinitesimal-spacial-units; or to soul, since this possesses, except in the case of samudghata, only an “innumerable” portion of the universe; or to space, since this is independent of the limit between the universe and the beyond; or to dharma, since this is cause of an opposite effectproves adharma. Similarly, the fact of causing all other substances without exception to occur in moments according to their modifications,which property does not belong by nature to these (other substances), since the occurrence characterized by moments must be effected by another cause-proves time. Similarly, the evolution through consciousness,which evolution does not belong to any of the other substances, since they are insentient-proves soul. Thus the differentiation of substances may be known by the differentiation of the qualities (cf. Amrtachandra's introductory remark to PS 130). Now he teaches the differentiation of the substances with reference to their possessing or not possessing (several) infinitesimal-spacialunits: 11.43. Jivas, material-aggregates, dharma, adharma and space possess innumerable space-points or infinitesimal-spacial-units; but time has no space-points. (135/1) Souls, matter, dharma, adharma and space are possessed of infinitesimal-spacial-units (pradeshas); for they contain several pradeshas. The time-atom (kalanu), however, is devoid of pradeshas, for it is only a (single) pradesha. Page #336 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 310 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES The possession of (several) infinitesimal-spacial-units holds true of soul, because in both its contraction (samvarta) and expansion (vistara) it never leaves the (region of) the innumerable infinitesimal-spacialunits which are coextensive with the space of the universe62; of matter, because although it is a-pradesha, particle-less, when considered as a substance (i.e. atom), owing to its extending over only one pradesha-yet it possesses a fluctuating number of infinitesimalspacial-units, through its modifications having a numerable number, two, etc., an innumerable and an infinite number; of dharma, because it has the nature of extending over innumerable infinitesimal-spacial-units which pervade the whole universe; of adharma, because it has the nature of extending over innumerable infinitesimal-spacial-units which pervade the whole universe; of space, because it has the nature of extending over an infinite number of infinitesimal-spacial-units which pervade everything. But the time-atom (kalanu) is devoid of infinitesimal-spacial-units (a-pradesha), because, considered as a substance, it covers only one infinitesimal-spacial-units, and, considered in its modifications, it has no intermingling. Therefore the time-substance is without spacial-units, and all other substances have spacial-units. Now he teaches where situated are these substances with and without infinitesimal-spacial-units: II.44. Space or sky is in the universe (loka) and that which is beyond the universe (aloka); dharma, adharma [the principles of motion and rest]63 are stretched over the universe; so is time, with the remaining [two] substances, souls (jivas) and material-components. (136) Space is in and outside the universe, since it occurs without any difference as to containing or not containing the six substances.64 Dharma and adharma are in the whole universe, because it is not possible that souls and matter, which move and rest through their causation, move or rest outside the universe or only in one region thereof. Time, too, is in the universe; for its modifications, such as moments (samaya) etc., are found in the evolutions of souls and matter; but it covers one infinitesimal-spacial-unit of the world, since it does not possess pradeshas.65 Page #337 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 311 Souls and matter are in the universe, for good reason, because the world has the inherence of the six substances for self. But, since soul has the property of expansion and contraction over (more or fewer) infinitesimal-spacial-unit, and since matter has the property of smooth (or viscid, snigdha) and rough (ruksha) qualities, which are the cause of its cohesion (bandha), there is no restriction of time, souls and matter between (the limits of) one infinitesimal-spacial-unit (desha, here=pradesha) and the whole universe; thus with reference to their single substantiality 68 their limit is one spacial-unit, but with reference to several substances it is the whole universe, on the principle (nyaya) of the box full of perfumed powder. Now he explains generally the manner in which possession or nonpossession of several infinitesimal-spacial-units takes place: II.45. As are the infinitesimal-spacial-units of space, so are the infinitesimal-spacial-units of the other substances: the ultimate atom is without (plurality of) spacial-units or space-points. By this is explained how the (possession of] infinitesimal-spacial-units? originates. (137) [The author] will himself in sutra 48 give the definition of an infinitesimal-unit of space, as that which is pervaded by an ultimate atom. Here it is taught that there is oneness in the way of defining the infinitesimal-spacial-unit, seeing that, as are the infinitesimal-units of space, so are those of the other substances. Therefore, as space, which is measured (read ganyamanasya) by a portion (amsha) pervaded by one ultimate atom, contains an unlimited number of infinitesimalunits, since it possesses an unlimited number of such portions, so dharma, adharma and the single soul, each measured by a portion which covers one ultimate atom, contain an innumerable number of infinitesimal-spacial-units, since they possess an innumerable number of such portions. And, as the number of infinitesimal-spacial-units contained by dharma and adharma, which have a definite extension, is innumerable, so the number of infinitesimal-spacial-units contained by soul is innumerable, although it possesses an indefinite extension, varying with expansion and contraction—as leather varies in size with dryness and wetness, since its own portions are neither few nor many. The proof of its incorporeal contraction and expansion can be given by mere self-consciousness, since it pervades the body, stout or lean, the Page #338 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 312 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES infant and the boy. As concerns matter, although we have seen that, considered as a substance, it is devoid of infinitesimal-spacial-units, since it only covers one infinitesimal-spacial-unit, yet it has origination of infinitesimalspacial-units owing to its innate nature of being capable of an evolution into viscid (snigdha) and rough (ruksha) qualities of such a kind that they are the cause of the origination of two infinitesimal-spacial-units, etc. So then, in the case of matter, we must infer a possession-ofinfinitesimal-spacial-units numerable, namely two, etc., innumerable and infinite, because through modification it can have a plurality of infinitesimal-spacial-units. Now he ascertains the absence of infinitesimal-spacial-units in the time-atom (kalanu): II.46. The moment (samaya) lacks infinitesimal-spacial-units; it occurs (vartate), while a material-substance (dravya-jata, i.e. atom; cf. note 68) which covers only one infinitesimal-spacial-unit or spacepoint traverses an infinitesimal-unit of the space-substance. (138) The time-moment lacks infinitesimal-spacial-units, because it covers, as a substance, only one infinitesimal-spacial-unit. And it does not, as is the case with matter, through modification have several infinitesimal-spacial-units; for though it is innumerable substance of infinitesimal-spacial-units stretched in a continuous expanse, yet, since these do not commingle, it remains with the extent of only a spacialunit, occupying the space-units one by one, and its only occurring is while an ultimate (material-) atom traverses, with slow movement, the one space-particle in which this (particular time-stream) inheres." Now he makes known the substance and modification of the timeobject (kala-padartha): II.47. A moment (samaya) is what is equal to the movement of (an ultimate material-atom) traversing a spatial particle. The object (artha) which is before and after that (moment) is time. The moment is subject to origination (utpanna) and annihilation. (139) When an ultimate (material-) atom with slow motion passes thrcugh the spacial particle which is pervaded by a time-object measuring one particle in extension, then that moment (samaya), a minute occurrence of that time-object, and equal to the duration (parimana) of that passing through that one particle, is a modification of the time-object. Therefore that object (artha) (artha = padartha = everything that exists Page #339 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 313 objectively) which possesses an eternity manifested (read vyanjitanityatvo) by its existence in an occurrence anterior and posterior to the so-described modification is a substance. So substantial-time (dravya-samaya)72 is not-originated and exempt from annihilation; but modificational-time (prayaya-samaya) is both originated and subject to annihilation. And this samaya (moment) is without portions (amsha):73 otherwise the thesis that the spacial-particle is without portions would not hold good. But not even if one ultimate-atom could move to the end of the world in one moment, would the samaya, for that reason, possess portions, since it would be a particular (vishishta) evolution of movement, like a particular evolution of spacial-containment (avagaha). As, that is, an aggregate of an endless number of ultimate-atoms, which aggregate owing to a particular evolution of spacial-containment (cf. n. 62) has the extension of one ultimate-atom, does not prove for the atom the possession of an endless number of portions (for it does not even possess portions), in the same way the innumerable number of time-atoms,74 -whilst an ultimate (material) atom, owing to a particular evolution of movement, moves from one end of the world to another within one moment (samaya), which is delimited by the evolution of passing through one space-particle pervaded by one timeatom-does not prove that the time-moment possesses an innumerable number of portions (for it does not even possess portions). Now he gives a definition of the infinitesimal-particle of space: II.48. Space, as occupied (nivishta) by a material-atom, is termed pradesha (infinitesimal-spatial unit or space-point); it is capable of affording room to all material-atoms. (140) A part (amsa) of space which can be pervaded by one atom is a spacial infinitesimal-particle. And, this, although one, is capable of affording room to the infinitesimal-particles of the other five substances and, moreover, to aggregates of an endless number of ultimate atoms, if these are evolved through an ultimate fineness. And space, although one undivided substance, may be supposed to consist of parts; for otherwise it would not be capable of affording room to all material-atoms.76 I. But, if one should think that space does not possess parts, then let him lift up two fingers in space and inquire, “Is this one spot (kshetra) or more? And, if one, is it one as a continuous substance Page #340 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 314 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES whose parts are not distinguished-from-one-another (bhinna) or as a continuous substance whose parts are distinguishable?" (IA) In case it is one continuous (a-vibhaga) substance whose parts are not distinguished, then, since the occupied by one finger is, as a part of space, not distinguishable from that of the other finger, one of the two parts does not exist; and therefore, since there are not two or more parts, space would contain merely one infinitesimal-particle, as a material-atom does. (IB) And, in case it is one continuous substance whose parts are distinguishable, this involves the supposition of one continuous substance having (many) parts. (I) If (the interlocutor thinks that the spots of the two fingers are) more than one, is it as several non-continuous substances or as one continuous substance? (II A) If as several non-continuous substances, then space, as one substance, would be an endless number of substances. (IIB) If as one continuous substance, then this involves the supposition of one continuous substance with (many) parts. Now he announces the two conglomerations, in transverse and vertical direction (triyag-urdhva-prachayau):78 II.49. The infinitesimal-space points contained by substances are either one, two, many, or transcending number, or endless (in number). But time has only one space-point, viz. samaya or moment. (141) The conglomeration of infinitesimal-particles is a conglomeration in a transverse direction. And the conglomeration whose occurrence is characterized by moments (samaya) is a vertical conglomeration of them. A conglomeration in a transverse direction exists: for space, because it possesses a fixed, endless number of pradeshas, for dharma and adharma, because they possess a fixed innumerable number of pradeshas, for the soul, because it possesses an unfixed, innumerable number (cf Tattva-dipika on 136) of pradeshas, for matter, because, considered as a substance, it possess one pradesha with the capability (shakti) of forming several pradeshas, and, considered as modification, it possesses two and many pradeshas. But it does not exist for time, because, whether in potential-form Page #341 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 315 (shakti) or in manifest-form (vyakti), it possesses only one pradesha. The vertical conglomeration is not excluded from any substance, since the occurrence of all substances, in its connection with the three aspects (koti) (of time), possesses parts. But there is this difference: the vertical conglomeration of the substances other (than time) is a conglomeration whose occurrence is characterized by the timemoments; but the vertical conglomeration of time is a conglomeration of the time-moments themselves. For the occurrence of the other substances, being something else than the moment (samaya), has qualification by the moment; but the occurrence of time, being identical with the moment, has not that. Now he refutes the opinion that the vertical conglomeration of the time-substance would lack identity (anvaya)79: II.50. If origination and annihilation within one moment are found in any samaya, then that samaya (time-moment) is established in its own nature. (142) The moment, indeed, is the occurrence-part of the time-object (samaya-padartha); in this moment we necessarily find the origination and annihilation of something, because, as arising through the traversing (vyatipata), of a material-atom, it is preceded by a cause. Should these two belong to the occurrence-part, does this then happen simultaneously or successively? If simultaneously, there is no simultaneity, because two contradictory qualities of one thing cannot occur together. And, if successively, there is no succession, since there is no division (vibhaga) in the occurrence-part, owing to its fineness (sukshmatva). Therefore we must necessarily search for something that has the occurrence (vrttimat); and this is the time-object. For of that, even in its single occurrence-part there is origination and annihilation; thus: that same which, in regard to something which has occurrence is, in its occurrence-part, as qualified by that occurrence-part, origination is for the same object which has occurrence, in its occurrence-part as particularized by the precedent occurrence-part, annihilation. If thus origination and annihilation occur in the one occurrence Page #342 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 316 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES part, how is there absence of identity in the time-object? For, even though, as qualified by the precedent and subsequent occurrence-parts, it simultaneously acquires annihilation and origination, why should it not possess permanence owing to its not being annihilated or produced in innate nature? So we have proved that origination, annihilation and permanence belong to the time-object in one occurrence-part. Now he proves that origination, annihilation and permanence belong to the time-object in all its occurrence-parts: II.51. In one moment exist the things (arthas) which are called origination, permanence and disappearance of time (samaya); at all times, therefore, this forms the existence (sad-bhava) of the time-atom (Kalanu, time-stream in one spacial pradesha). (143) In all its occurrence-parts origination, annihilation and permanence of the time-object are present, since we see this in one occurrencepart. And this proves right, because the existence of the particular could not be justified without the existence of the generality. The existence of the time-object follows thus: if both the existence of the particular and the existence of the generality are proved, then in no way whatever can they exist without existence (astitva) itself. Now he proves that time possesses only one pradesha, since otherwise time could not exist:80 11.52. That object in which no (plurality of) pradeshassl exists, and which is not known82 to contain in fact83 even one pradesha, must be admitted to be a shunya (void); for it is (then) an object different from existence. (144) (A) Existence (astitva),84 in fact, is an occurrence, consisting of an union of origination, annihilation and permanence. And this occurrence, if propounded without (even one) pradesha, does not belong to time; for in the absence of pradeshas there is absence of that which occurs. But this (absence) is a void, since the term existence is a synonym for occurrence. (B) Moreover, time cannot be mere occurrence, because occurrence, without something that occurs, is unaccountable. Or, if you would still accept such, how could it have for self an union of origination, annihilation and permanence? (O) If (you then should maintain this as true), because each of the precedent parts is annihilated, each of the subsequent parts effected, and the one own self permanent, inasmuch as this one own self depends Page #343 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 317 on many beginningless, endless and uniterrupted parts, Then no! Whence, indeed, could this oneness be, since there can be no simultaneity of that part, where the annihilation, and of the part, where the origination proceeds? And whence could there be stability, which abides in this oneness of annihilation and origination; since the annihilated part has totally disappeared, and the originating part is just attaining its self, which is brought into existence? This being so, the threefold set of characteristics comes to nought; kshanabhanga (universal-momentariness) is triumphant; eternal substance has its sunset; momentarily annihilated existence-forms (bhavas) raise their heads. Therefore, for fear lest all truth should become confused, we must necessarily search for something that has the occurrence, and that is its abode. Now this is the pradesha (infinitesimal-particle), because a correspondence (anu-vidhayitva) to presence and absence cannot belong to what is not pradesha (a-pradesha). (D) If time thus has pradesha, why not agree that it contains an innumerable number of pradeshas, equal to the space of the universe, as the condition of its being one substance? The reason is non-admission of modificational-time. It is the modification of an ultimate atom passing through the substantial-time, which covers only one pradesha, that we admit as the moment. If the substantial-time consisted of an innumerable number of pradeshas equal to the space of the universe, whence could that be established? If it is urged that, even if this, as one total substance, possesses innumerable pradeshas, equal to the space of the universe, the moment might result from the ultimate atom passing through one pradesha of the substantial-time. Not so, because an occurrence of a part cannot consistently be an occurrence of the whole. The moment is the minute occurrencepart of the whole-time object, not of such and such a single part. Moreover, it would follow that conglomeration in transverse directions conglomeration in vertical direction (cf. the introduction which Tattvadipika gives to 141). Thus, (the moving ultimate atom) first abides with one pradesha (of the supposed innumerable time-pradeshas), then with another, then again with another, so that conglomeration in transverse direction, becoming conglomeration in vertical direction, proves the substance to contain only one pradesha. (E) Therefore, whoever does not wish to assert that a Page #344 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 318 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES conglomeration in transverse direction is the same as a conglomeration in vertical direction must from the very first conclude that the timesubstance contains only one pradesha. Now, after having thus stated the Principle concerning the Knowables, he examines the self by aid of a distinction between knowledge and knowable; and, in order to have the self (atma) completely distinguished, he reveals the reason for the embodied being of the external, other-referential [i.e. from the manifest physical, objective, external characteristic of bio-energies aspect] (vyavahara) soul-condition (jivatva): DISTINCTIVE FEATURES OF JIVA SUBSTANCES (VERSES 145-200) II.53. The world is eternal, complete and consummate with objects having infinitesimal-space-points; what knows that world is the jiva, connected with the fourfold set of pranas (vitalities or bioenergies). (145) Of this world, complete and consummate with all the objects, whose possession of infinitesimal-particles has been examined by us, beginning with space and ending with time, the knower is the soul only, and no other, because of the inconceivable fullness of energy (shakti) which the soul, although placed in the midst thereof, possesses for discrimination between self and "other." Thus the remaining substances are knowable only; the soul substance is both knowable and knowledge. Such is the division between knowledge and knowable. And, although this soul possesses, as cause of an innately-manifested and endless knowledge-energy, and characterized by persistence in the three times, and never absent, inasmuch as it is really its (the soul's) characteristic being,-its true soul-nature (nishchaya-jivatva) [the conscious vital force or consciousness-as-such], yet in the state of samsara, inasmuch as its self is vitiated by adhesion of matter, proceeding in a beginningless stream, we must distinguish a reason for its external, other-referential (vyavahara) soul-condition (jivatva), viz. its being connected with the fourfold set of pranas. Now he states what the pranas are: II.54. The prana of the senses, the prana of force (bala), the prana of duration of life, the prana of respiration,85 -these are the pranas of the jivas. (146/1) Page #345 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 319 The pranas of the senses are the fivefold set of touch, taste, smell, eye sight and ear hearing; the pranas of force (bala) are the body, the voice and the mind; the prana of duration of life (ayu), which is the supportive factor (nimitta) of that, aims at the maintenance of transmigratory existence (bhav dharan); the prana of inhaling and exhaling is respiration, characterized by upward and downward movement. Now by means of an explanation of the pranas he teaches how they are a reason for the condition of soul (jivatva), and, moreover, how they are material: 11.55. That which by means of the four pranas (vitalities) lives, will live, and has previously lived, is called a jiva (a "liver," or soul). But the pranas have arisen from material substances. (147) The soul (the “liver”) lives, will live and has previously lived by means of the material vitalities (called prana) in general. Since, as these vitalities are coming together (of soul and matter) in a beginningless series, and located in one place) in the three times, is the (external) condition (hetu) of the soul principle (jivatva). Nevertheless, it is not the innate nature of soul, since it has arisen from material substances. Now he proves the materiality of the pranas. II.56. The soul, endowed with the pranas, bound with karman of infatuation, etc., enjoying the fruit of karman (karmaphala), binds itself with fresh karman. (148) Because the soul, through being bound with the material karmans of infatuation, etc., is connected with the pranas, and because, by enjoying the fruit of material karman (action) through being bound by pranas, it binds itself again with fresh material karman, therefore the pranas, by reason of being effects of material karmans and causes of material karmans, are proved to be material. Now he reveals how the pranas are causes of material karmans. II.57. When the soul causes, by its infatuation or aversion, 86 injury to the pranas of self and other living beings, then this means bondage in consequence of such karman as knowledge-obscuration, etc. (149) By its pranas the soul enjoys the fruit of karman, enjoying this, it takes up infatuation and aversion; by these it causes injury (badha) to the pranas of the own soul and another soul. Then, sometimes causing, and sometimes not causing, injury to the material-pranas (dravya-prana) 87 of “the other," but (always), through being Page #346 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 320 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES impassioned, causing injury to the subjective-pranas (bhava-prana) of itself, the soul binds (itself with) karmans, of knowledge-obscuring kind, etc. Thus the pranas become causes of material-karman (paudgalika-karman).88 Now he teaches the interior cause of the serial recurrence of material-pranas (pudgala-prana): II.58. The self, stained with karman, acquires again other and other pranas, so long as it does not give up the notion of "mine" with reference to sense-objects, primarily its body. (150) Of this (read yeyam atmanah) serial recurrence of material-pranas the root is beginningless material-karman, enveloping the self; attachment (uparaktatva), showing itself as the idea of "mine" with reference to the body, etc., is the interior cause. Now he teaches the interior cause of the cessation of this series of material-pranas. II.59. He who conquers the senses, etc., and meditates on the self (atmakam = Prakrit appagam = atmanam) endowed with psychicattention is not affected by karmans. How then could the pranas follow him? (151) Non-existence of attachment, which is the root of material-karman, is the interior cause of the cessation of this series of material-karman. And this absence accrues to him who has conquered all other substances such as the senses, like a crystal-gem withdrawn from the influence (anuvrtti) of any support, and who abides in the only (kevala) and stable self, completely pure and consisting merely of psychicattention. Here the purport is as follows: to effect the final distinctness of the self (from that which is other to it) the material pranas, as the cause of the (external, other-referential vyavahara condition of soul's state (jivatva) as such, must be annihilated. Now again, in order to effect the complete distinctness of the self, he describes minutely the characteristic-nature of the modifications, which are the cause of the vyavahara condition of soul's state as such, characterized by gati (kind-of-existence): II.60. A modification is a thing (artha) [e.g. a man, a god, etc.], belonging to a thing (artha) [e.g. the soul] which is certified as existent, and originating by coming into contact with another [i.e.material] thing (artha) (e.g. the conditions or modifications), with Page #347 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 321 varieties such as configuration (samsthana) (the shape of body in which the soul temporarily lives), etc. (152) When of one thing certified as existent in its characteristic nature, which is its definite individuality, there is in another thing, likewise certified in its characteristic nature, which is its definite individuality, a self-attainment achieved under a specialized form, that (other) thing, consisting of more than one substance, is a modification. Such a modification of soul in matter, as of matter in other matter, arising through qualification by configuration and so forth, is actually experienced. And such a modification is logical. For the modification of a single substance, differentiated from the pure (kevala) soul simply as consisting in a connection with more than one substance, is discerned unimpaired within (the composite thing). Now he instances particular modifications: II.61. Men, beings in hell (naraka), animals, and devas, are modifications of souls, metamorphosed by configurations and so forth, through the arising (udaya) of name-karman (nama-karma) (For the term udaya, see note 9 and note 12; for nama-karman, see note 51). (153) Beings in hells, lower animals, men, devas-these in fact are modifications of souls. These, assuredly, as consisting of conjunctions with more than one substance-since this is the cause of the ripening of name-karman matter –have been metamorphosed by configurations and so forth; like the modifications of fire, chaff-fire, coal-fire and so forth through configurations such as agitation, vibration (for khilva read khela), and so on. Now, as the reason for the distinction of own and others, he emphasizes the self's possession of existence, which, despite its mixture with other substances, makes it known as a thing: 11.62. Whoso knows the own nature of substance, dependent upon existence (sad-bhava), stated as triple (stability, origination, annihilation) and having varieties (vikalpa), will not be infatuated with other substance. (154) The own nature of a substance is that possession of existence in a form of its own, which is the individuality and is called that which makes it known as a thing; since the own nature of a substance is dependent upon existence. Inasmuch as the own nature of a substance, when recognized as assuming, in the form of substance, quality and Page #348 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 322 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES modification and in the form of stability, origination and annihilation, a triple variety, dispels infatuation for other substance and so is reason for the distinction of own and other, therefore, in order to effect the distinction of own and other, we must at every point take note of possession of existence in ones own form. Thus: That which has for own nature possession of existence, triple as being (1) substance characterized by unfailing presence of being conscious,' (2) quality, characterized by non-difference from the consciousness, and (3) modification characterized by divergence from the 'being conscious' and also triple as (1) stability by way of being conscious,' which extends to the prior and posterior divergences, and (2) origination and (3) evanescence, as diverging from prior and posterior, that, myself here, is one thing. That which has for own nature possession of existence, triple as being (1) substance, characterized by unfailing presence of not being conscious, (2) quality, characterized by nondifference from the non-conscious, (3) modification, characterized by divergence from the not-being conscious, and also triple as (1) stability by way of not being conscious, which extends to the prior and posterior divergences, and (2) origination and (3) evanescence, as diverging from prior and posterior, that, matter, is another. I have no infatuation: I have distinction of own and other. Now, with a view to an absolute distinctness of the self, he considers the characteristics of the cause of its conjunction with other substance: II.63. The self (appa in Pk., atma in Sk.) is of the nature of psychic-attention (upayoga): psychic attention is stated as knowledge and intuition [vision). And this psychic-attention of the self is auspicious (shubha) or inauspicious (ashubha) good or evil]. (155) Now the cause of the self's conjunction with other substance is a species of psychic-attention. Psychic-attention, indeed, is the own nature of the self, since it evolves in obedience to its (the self's) character as consciousness. And that upayoga is knowledge and intuition, since consciousness, according as it is definite or indefinite, has both forms. Now this psychic-attention is specialized in two ways, according to purity and impurity. Of these the pure is without attachment; the impure is with attachment, which again is twofold, good (shubha) and evil (asubha), because of the twofold character of the attachment, as being in the form of sanity or morbidity. Page #349 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 323 Now he informs us what psychic-attention is cause of conjunction with other substances: II.64. If the psychic-attention is auspicious or good, it leads to accumulation or increase of the soul's virtue or merit (punya); if inauspicious or evil, its sinfulness (papa) likewise is accumulated or increases. In the absence of both there is no accession or accumulation [of karmas]. (156) Psychic-attention, when impure, is cause of the soul's conjunction with other substance. As effected by attachment in the form of sanity (i.e. purifying effect, vishuddhi) or morbidity (affliction, distress, sanklesh), it receives a double aspect, as good or evil, and is active as cause of conjunction with other substance, which receives a double aspect, as merit and sin. But, when non-existence of this impure in both forms is effected, then only pure psychic-attention remains: and this, on the other hand, is no cause of conjunction with other substance. Now he delineates the characteristic form of good psychic attention: II.65. Whoso knows the great Jina, respects the Liberated Souls and also the Homeless Ones [saints]89 and is compassionate to the living beings, his psychic-attention is good. (157) Good psychic-attention, which,-as it consists in a recurrence of vision-infatuating and conduct-infatuating matter reposing in the special condition of destruction and subsidence20-embraces an attachment of a good kind, is engaged in entertaining faith in the Arhats, those Supreme Lords, Super-Devas of Great Devas, Supreme Gods, and the Siddhas and sadhus, and in practising compassion towards the totality of living beings. Now he delineates the characteristic form of evil psychic-attention: II.66. He whose psychic-attention is sunk in passion for senseobjects, addicted to hearing words that defile and pollute the mind, bad thoughts, bad companionship, [and] is violent and inclined to perverse ways, is evil. (158) Evil psychic-attention,—since, as it consists in a recurrence of vision-infatuating and conduct-infatuating matter reposing in the specialized condition called udaya [arising of karman], it embraces an attachment of an improper kind,-is engaged in entertaining faith in perverse ways, other than the Arhats, those Supreme Lords, Super Page #350 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 324 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Devas of Great Devas, Supreme Gods, and the Siddhas and Sadhus, and in practising sense-gratification, passionate thought, bad hearing, bad intention, bad companionship, and violence. Now he essays the destruction of the cause of conjunction with other substance: 11.67. Being free from evil psychic-attention and, not uniting with good conscious attentiveness in regard to other substance, I, becoming established in the real nature of self (majjhatth in Pk.) (madhyastha in Sk., i.e. being neutral or indifferent), meditate upon the self, which is of the nature of some thing knowing. (159) This impure psychic-attention, set forth as cause of conjunction with other substance, proceeds simply from dependence upon recurrence of other substances, reposing in a state of slow or vehement udaya, and not from anything else. Therefore I here become neutral to all other substance. Becoming so, I, released, through nondependence upon recurrence of other substance, from impure psychicattention, good or evil, and having, through embracing a recurrence of the absolute (kevala) self-substance, an evident pure psychicattention, stand with my self of psychic-attention, ever immovably intent (read upayunjams tishthami) upon the self alone. This is my essay to destroy conjunction with other substance. Now he proclaims neutrality in regard to other substance, such as body and so on: 11.68. I am not body, not mind, nor again voice, nor cause of these: neither the doer of action, nor getting it done by others, nor consenting or approving the same. (160) Body and voice and mind I apprehend as other substance: hence I have no partiality for them. In regard to them all I am absolutely neutral. Thus: I am not unconscious, material substance, acting as basis of the characteristic forms of body, voice and mind: these, in fact, maintain their own characteristic forms even without me as an object (read artham antarena) to be basis of their characteristic forms. Hence, having shaken off partiality to body, voice and mind, I am absolutely neutral. Nor am I unconscious substance which is cause of body, voice and mind: these, in fact, are cause even without me as cause. Hence, having shaken off partiality to being their cause, I am absolutely neutral. Nor I am (worker of] unconscious substance which is independent cause of body, voice and mind: these, in fact, are Page #351 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 325 worked even without me as a worker. Hence, having shaken off partiality to their being things worked by me, I am absolutely neutral. Nor I am instigator of unconscious substance which is independent worker of body, voice and mind: these, in fact, are worked even without me as instigator of that which works them. Hence, having shaken off partiality to being instigator of what works them, I am absolutely neutral. Nor am I approver of unconscious substance which is independent worker of body, voice and mind: they, in fact, are worked even without me as approver. Hence, having shaken off partiality to being approver of that which works them, I am here absolutely neutral. Now he ascertains body, voice and mind to be other substance: 11.69. Body, mind and voice are declared to consist of material substance: material substance, again, is a mass of subtlemost particles of material substances (paramanu dravyanam pindhah). (161) Body, voice and mind, all three, are other substance, because they consist of material substance. And they are material substance, because they are ascertained to have an existence of characteristic form which is the individual mark of material substance. Now such material substance is an evolution, in the modification of a single mass, of more than one sub-atomic (paramanu) substance: because, despite the plurality of the existences of characteristic form which are the individual marks of the plural sub-atomic (paramanu) substances, in a way they appear as an unity. Now he establishes that the self is not other substance and not what acts upon other substance: 11.70. I am not composed of matter, nor is material substance made by me into a mass. Therefore I am neither the body, nor the maker or active agent (karta) of that body. (162) As to this other substance, called body, comprising the pair, voice and mind, which in this section has been made out as consisting of matter, I am not it, because there is incompatibility in me, not composed of matter, being body, which consists of matter. Nor am I what works the body, whether by way of cause, or by way of agent, or by way of instigation of the agent, or by way of approver of the agent, because it is in every way incompatible that I, not agent of the evolution of plural material substance in its modification as a single mass, should be agent of the body, which consists in an evolution of Page #352 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 326 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES plural material substance in a mcdification as a single mass. Now he averts the doubt how there is evolution of plural substance in a modification as a mass: 11.71. The ultimate atom, itself not possessing spacial units or space-points, having the extent of one spacial unit only, and soundless, experiences, as smooth or rough, the condition of extension over two spacial units and so on. (163) The ultimate atom, since it has not two or more spacial units, is without spacial units; since it has one spacial unit, it is of the extent of one spacial unit only; since it has not itself the particular modification, sound, which consists in plural substance of ultimate atoms, it is soundless. Because, existing without opposition to the four touches, the five tastes, the two smells, and the five colours, it may be either smooth or rough, thence comes its experience, in the form of evolution into the modification “mass,"92 of the condition of extension over two spacial units and so on. Thus, accordingly, smoothness and roughness bring about the condition “mass.” Now he states what-like are that smoothness and roughness of the ultimate atom: II.72. Beginning with extension over) one, the smoothness or roughness of the atom is said to increase, through its evolution, by units, until it experiences the condition of infinite number. (164) The ultimate-atom has evolution, since that, as the innate nature of things, is unescapable. Subject to variation” from time to time in consequence of that evolution,-since the atom is adapted to diverse qualities,--smoothness or roughness results, including distinctions in an unbroken series, which, beginning with one, through addition of unit ends in infinity. Next he here states from what kind of smoothness or roughness the condition of mass arises: II.73. The smooth or rough evolutions of atoms are either even or odd: when exceeding the even by two, they are combined, except at the beginning. 94 (165) The general rule is "combination resulting from smoothness or roughness in excess of the even by two degrees”; because a difference of two in degree of smoothness or roughness is, as cause of evolution, efficient of combination (allowed). The exception is “no combination resulting from smoothness or roughness in the first degree”; because Page #353 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 327 smoothness or roughness in the first degree is, as not a cause of evolution in the thing to be evolved, not efficient of combination (forbidden). Now he discerns the above-stated causality in the case of the “mass” condition of ultimate atoms: II.74. The second degree in respect of smoothness undergoes combination with the smooth of the fourth degree, or with the rough:95 the atom, in the third degree, is combined when associated with the fifth degree. (166) The "mass” condition of ultimate atoms must be recognized as having the above-stated cause; for combination of two atoms of the second and fourth, and of the third and fifth degrees is admitted (Read bandhasya prasiddheh), if they are both smooth, or both rough, or one smooth and the other rough. And it is said: “material-particles are combined smooth with smooth and rough with rough material-particles are combined, smooth and rough, similar and dissimilar in degree.'' There is combination of the smooth with the smooth two degrees higher, of the rough with the rough two degrees higher: there is combination of smooth with rough, in case of odd or even, excepting of the lowest degree."98 Now he discerns that the self is not agent of a material mass: II.75. Aggregates extending over two or more spacial units-fine or gross; having configurations; earth, water, fire and wind-are originated by their own several evolutions. (167) These thus originated aggregates, -extending over two or more spacial units; undergoing varieties of smoothness or roughness in consequence of varying potentialities of occupying space (see n. 33, and in general the Tattva-dipika on PS 93-2 (in the translation the portions numbered H and h]; assuming diverse configurations in consequence of varying potentialities of bearing shapes; subject each to its several potentiality of manifesting or veiling the fourfold set of touch and so on (touch, colour, smell, taste)—come into being merely by their own several evolutions, earth, water, fire, wind. Hence it is discerned that the soul is not agent of the mass (state) of materialparticles, beginning with the double atom and ending with the infinite (read dvyanukadi-anantanta-pudgalanam). Page #354 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 328 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Now he discerns that the self is not conveyor of a material mass: II.76. The universe is in all directions densely packed, as roomfilled, with material bodies, fine and gross, unadaptable and adaptable. (168) Since the universe is of itself in all directions densely packed with material bodies — evolved in fineness and evolved in grossness; in case of not excessive fineness and grossness, possessed of potentiality for evolving as karmic-matter; in case of excessive fineness and grossness, lacking the same; by reason of being qualified by a power of room-filling not impeding one another—therefore it is discerned that the soul is not conveyor of a material mass. Now he discerns that the self is not agent of the karma-condition of material masses: II.77. Aggregates adaptable to karma-condition, when they meet with a soul's evolution, attain the state of karman; but they are not made to evolve by the soul. (169) Since, in dependence upon an exterior means, namely the mere evolution of a soul, located in the same spot, material aggregates, being themselves equipped with a potentiality of evolving in the karmacondition” even without a soul to evolve them, evolve of themselves in the karma-state, therefore it is discerned that the soul is not agent of the karma-condition of material masses. Now he discerns that the self is not maker of the body consisting of material substance evolved in the karma-condition: II.78. Such and such material aggregates, having attained a karma condition, give rise, further, to the soul's bodies, in its transitions to other bodies. (170) Whatever material aggregates, merely on the occasion of a soul's evolution, evolve of themselves in karma-condition, the same, in dependence upon the soul's transition to another body in the course of its beginningless, continuous, activity, themselves give rise to bodies. Hence it is discerned that the soul is not the maker of the body, which consists of material substance evolved in karma-condition. Now he discerns that the self is not body: II.79. The physical, the plastic, the magnetic (electric), the emanatory and the karmana bodies all consist of material substance. (171) Since the physical (audarika), the plastic (vaikriyika), the emanatory Page #355 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 329 (aharaka), the magnetic (taijas) and the karmana bodies all consist of material substance, therefore it is discerned that the soul is not body. Now he states what then is the soul's special, unshared, characteristic which effects its discrimination from all other substance, body and so on: II.80. Know the soul to be tasteless, colourless, odourless, without the manifest touch quality (avyakta here = asparsha), with its quality of sentiency or consciousness, soundless, without apprehension by a mark, without any defined configuration. (172) Since it is the self's proper nature to be without the qualities of taste, colour and odour, to be without manifestation of the touch quality, to be without modification as sound, and in consequence of this to be unapprehensible by a mark, also to be without any configuration, it has for the effecting of its discrimination from material substance tastelessness, colourlessness, odourlessness, unmanifestedness, soundlessness, inapprehensibility by a mark, nonconfiguration. Also its having consciousness for quality effects its discrimination from all non-soul substance, whether material or nonmaterial. And this of itself, since, as inhering only in its own substance, soul, it carries with it its character as having a particular nature, effects the discrimination from the remaining other substances. Whereas the expression without apprehension by a mark is used where “not apprehendible by a mark” might have been used, that is for the purpose of conceiving more meanings. Thus: (1) understanding “that whose apprehension is not when it is apprehensive by marks, i.e. by sense-organs,” we conceive its consisting of supra-sensual knowledge; (2) understanding “that whereof there is not apprehension, as apprehendible by marks, i.e. sense-organs," we conceive its not being object of sense-perception; (3) understanding “that whereof there is not apprehension through a mark within reach of the senses, as of fire through smoke,” we conceive its not being subject of inference implying sense perception; (4) understanding that whereof there is not apprehension by others merely through a mark," we conceive its not being merely a thing inferred; (5) understanding that whose apprehension (insert grahanam) of others is not merely through a mark,” we conceive its not being merely an inferer (i.e. the soul is not an agent of inference only, but also of perception); (6) Page #356 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 330 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES understanding "that whose apprehension is by its own nature not through a mark," we conceive its being a direct knower (i.e. it has paramarthika-pratyaksha, Outl. p. 113): (7) understanding that where of the apprehension, i.e. its basis as a knowable object, is not through a mark, i.e. its characteristic termed psychic-attention,” we conceive its not being knowledge with external things for basis (the self is really of only the nature of knowing); (8) understanding "that whose apprehension, i.e. self-appropriation,100 is not of a mark, i.e. the characteristic termed psychic-attention,” we conceive its being nonextrinsic knowledge; (9) understanding "that whereof the apprehension, i.e. the appropriation by another, is not of a mark, i.e. of the characteristic termed psychic-attention,” we conceive its being knowledge which cannot be taken away (read yasyeti aharyajnanatvasya); (10) understanding "that in the mark whereof, i.e. in the characteristic termed psychic-attention, there is not interference, like eclipse in the sun,” we conceive its innate nature as pure psychic-attention; (11) understanding that which has not apprehension, i.e. appropriation of material karman, through its mark, i.e. its characteristic termed psychic-attention,” we conceive its freedom from coalescence of substantial karman; (12) understanding that which has not apprehension, i.e. enjoyment of objects (read upabhogo), through its mark, i.e. sense-organs," we conceive its not being enjoyer of objects;101 (13) understanding that, the soul, of which there is not apprehension from the 'mark' self, defined (read lakshanasya) as senseorgans, etc. (adi refers to the sexual organs),” we conceive its not being governed by semen and menstruation; (14) understanding that which has not taking of a mark, i.e. a delusive appearance (read mohana for mehana),” we conceive its not being merely a worldly expedient; (15) understanding "that which has no apprehension, i.e. winning of people (Loka-vyapti), by a mark, i.e. delusive appearance,” we conceive its not winning people by appearances, which are the familiar expedients of cheats (kuhuka=kuhaka); (16) understanding that which does not assume marks, i.e. the sensations of female, male and neuter," we conceive its not being female, male or neuter substance; (17) understanding that which does not assume marks, i.e religious badges,” we conceive its not being the external marks of ascetics; (18) understanding "that whose apprehension, i.e. awareness of things, is not a mark, a quality (read lingam guno),” we conceive its being pure Page #357 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 331 substance, untouched by particular quality; (19) understanding that whose apprehension, i.e. particular awareness of things, is not a mark, a quality modification,” we conceive its being pure substance, untouched by particular modification; (20) understanding "that whose apprehension, i.e. general awareness of things, is not a mark, i.e. a cause of recognition,”102 we conceive its being pure modification, untouched by substance. Now, in view of the question "How can there be bondage of the self, since, being incorporeal, it is without smoothness or roughness?," he propounds the prima facie opinion: II.81. The corporeal, having qualities of colour and so on, is bound by mutual forms of touch (viz. smoothness and roughness): how can the self, the opposite thereof, bind material karman? (173) On the part of two corporeal material substances, indeed, since they are associated with qualities, colour and so on, mutual bondage, due to a particular touch, smoothness or roughness as described, is in fact recognized: but on the part of self and karma-matter how is it recognized? Though the karma-matter, as associated with qualities, colour and so on, can have a particular touch, smoothness or roughness as described, yet, since the incorporeal self, as not being associated with qualities, colour and so on, cannot be credited with a particular touch, smoothness or roughness as described, we have inadequacy on the one side. Now he states the approved view that there is bondage of the self, though incorporeal: II.82. Just as, though devoid of colour and so on, it (the self] sees and knows substances having colour, etc. qualities; in this way, understand, it is bound with them. (174) In the same way as, though deprived of colour and so on (the self], it sees and knows coloured substances and their qualities, similarly of course, though deprived of colour and so on, it is bound by karmamaterial, having colour, etc. For otherwise it is impossible to evade the further interrogation “How does it, being incorporeal, see and know the corporeal?” Nor is this made the subject of an example by reason of the difficulty of giving a solution: rather is it by means of an example made plain even down to the boy and the cowherd. Thus: as on the part of a boy or a cowherd, who sees and knows a clay bull or a bull, standing apart from them, there is not union with the bull, Page #358 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 332 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES but the common understanding of an union with the bull is justified by an union with a seeing or knowing which has the form of a bull and which is erected upon a psychic-attention occasioned (nimitta) by a bull standing in the condition of an object, so the self, since, being colourless, it is void of touch, has indeed no union with karmamaterial, but the common understanding of bondage by karma-material is justified by an union with states of passion, dislike and so on, erected upon a psychic-attention occasioned (nimitta) by karmamaterial existing in the condition of taking up the same space (as the parts of the soul). Now he makes known the characteristic nature of subjective bondage (bhava-bandha): 103 II.83. The soul, which is constituted of psychic-attention or function of consciousness, becomes infatuated, or attached, or averse on encountering the various sense objects; so it is bound up with them.104 (175) This self, indeed, is in its entirety, since it consists of discursive (sa-vikalpaka) and intuitive (nir-vikalpaka) mental-distinguishing, composed of psychic-attention. Whatever of it, on meeting with the various distinguishable things, falls into either infatuation or attachment, or aversion, that, since it has its innate nature affected (uparakta) by infatuation, attachment or aversion conditioned by the other”-like a crystal gem which has its innate nature coloured (uparakta) by blueness, yellowness, or redness, conditioned by a blue, yellow, or red accessory—becomes itself bondage, since it is accompanied by their natures. Now he makes known the proof of subjective bondage and the characteristic nature of substantial bondage (dravya-bandha): II.84. With whatever (mental) state a soul sees and knows the objects (of senses) (read vishayam or vishayan) which has come within its ken, thereby it is affected: karman is thereby bound - this is the teaching. (176) With whatever state, in the form of infatuation, of attachment, or of aversion, this self sees and knows the things which, since it consists of mental-distinguishing, definite (sakara) and indefinite (nirakara) 105, fail to be distinguished [by it), by that same it is affected, This affection it is that is subjective bondage, corresponding to smoothness and roughness. Then again there through material karman is bound: so Page #359 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 333 we have here substantial bondage conditioned by subjective bondage. Now he makes known the characteristic nature of bondage of matter, soul, and the two together: 11.85. Bondage of material things is through their touches, of soul through attachment and so on: mutual interpenetration is said to be [bondage) of matter and soul (together). (177) The evolution of karmans into union through particular touches, smoothness or roughness, is bondage of matter only. The evolution of the soul into union with conditioned modifications, infatuation, attachment, aversion, is bondage of soul only. The mutual penetration, on the other hand, of soul and karma-matter, which is better described as merely occasion of their mutual evolutions, is the bondage between the two. Now he revives the fact that substantial (material) bondage is caused by subjective bondage: II.86. The self has spacial units (space-points): into those spacial units enter material aggregates according to their suitability (cf. gathas, PS 168-169): they stay and go; or they are bound. (178) This self, as having innumerable spacial units as many as the world space, has spacial units (cf. Tattva-dipika on PS 136). So, according as in those spacial units is its vibration, dependent upon the atomgroups (vargana) of body, voice and mind, aggregates of karma-material having of themselves similar vibration enter and stay in them. If the soul is in a subjective state in the form of infatuation, attachment, or aversion, it is also bound. Hence it is discerned that subjective bondage is cause of substantial (material) bondage of karman (dravya bandh). Now he proves that subjective bondage, which is simply an evolution into attachment, is, as being cause of substantial material bondage of karman (dravya bandh), the veritable (nishchaya] bondage: II.87. Attached, the self binds karman; when it is devoid of attachment, it is liberated from karmans. This, be assured, in verity sums up the bondage of souls. (179) Since only when evolved into attachment is the self] bound by the fresh karman, and not when evolved into detachment; since from the fresh karman it is not released when evolved into attachment, but only when evolved into detachment; since, when evolved into attachment, it is bound by (any) new material karman which even Page #360 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 334 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES comes into contact with it and is not released by the old, long familiar; whereas when evolved into detachment, it is released by any fresh material karman which comes into contact with it and also by the old, long familiar and is not bound; therefore it is discerned that, as being the thing most really effective of substantial bondage, evolution into attachment is the veritable bondage. Now he reveals the fact that evolution is qualified by attachment, which is the thing most really effective of substantial (material) bondage; also the qualification: II.88. From evolution comes bondage; evolution is attended by attachment, aversion and infatuation. Infatuation and aversion are evil (inauspicious): attachment is good (auspicious) or evil. (180) Substantial bondage comes from evolution qualified: and the being qualified is by way of being composed of attachment, aversion and infatuation. It admits of duality according to the goodness or evilness therein: through being composed of infatuation or aversion it is evil; through being composed of attachment it is both good and evil, because attachment has a double character according as it includes sanity (visuddhi) or morbidity (sanklesha). Now, metonymically substituting effect for cause, he illustrates the qualification of the qualified evolution and the non-qualified evolution: II.89. Good evolution in regard to other things is termed merit, bad is termed sin: evolution not entering into other things is in [due] time cause of evanescence (destruction) of misery. (181) Evolution, indeed, is of two kinds, proceeding in other substance or concerned with own substance. Of these, that proceeding in other substance is, as being affected by the other, qualified evolution; that proceeding in own substance is, as not affected by the other, nonqualified evolution. Among these, qualified evolution is said to have two qualifications, good evolution and evil evolution. Of these, good evolution, as being cause of binding of meritorious matter, is merit; evil evolution, as being cause of binding of sinful matter, is sin. Of pure evolution, on the other hand, since, as being pure, it is one, there are no special forms. Being, in course of time, 106 cause of evanescence of karma-material, which is cause of samsara misery, it is liberation, consisting in evanescence of karma-material, which is cause of samsara misery. Now, with a view to the soul's activity and abstention in regard to Page #361 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 335 own and other substance (respectively), he exhibits the distinction of own and other: II.90. The classes of souls (jivas), earth-bodied, etc. and the mobile, are said to be other immobile like (anya) than the sessential nature of] soul, and the soul is also (essentially) other (anya) than they. (182) The six classes of souls, earthen and so on, admitted with distinction of mobile and immobile, are, due to being (combined with) as being (only) unconsciousness, other than the soul, and the soul also, as being conscious, is other than they. Here, the six classes of souls are substance other than the self (atmanah): the self (atma) alone is own substance (sva-dravyam). Now he discerns knowledge and non-knowledge of the distinction of own and other as occasioning the soul's activity in regard to own and other substance: 11.91. Whoso does not in this manner know the other (para) and the self, according to their characteristic natures, makes for himself through infatuation the conviction (of other being self and belonging to self, such as] “I am this," and "this is mine." (183) Whoso does not in this manner, through the respectively invariable characteristic natures as conscious and unconscious, see the distinction of soul and matter as own and other, he only, and no other, has through infatuation the conviction of other substance being self and belonging to self, “I, am this” and “this is mine." Therefore what occasions the soul's activity in regard to other substance is merely the absence of clear distinction of its own and the other; and consequently (samarthyat) what occasions activity in regard to own substance is the negation thereof. Now he describes what is the self's karman (act): II.92. Working out its own inner nature, the self is indeed the agent of its owr. state; but of all states composed of material substance it is not the agent. (184) The self is indeed agent of its own state; for that is its own property, since that must necessarily be effected by the self, as it possesses potentiality of so becoming. And, independently effecting this, it must necessarily be the agent thereof; and, being effected by the self, its own state, being that which it has to attain, must be result (karman, its accusative). Thus the karman of the self is its (the self's] own Page #362 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 336 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES evolution: the self does not bring about states of matter; for these are properties of the other, since they are not effectible by the self, as it has no potentiality of so becoming. Not effecting them, it cannot be agent of them; and, not being effected by self, they cannot be its karman. Thus evolution of matter is not act (karman) of the self. Now he rebuts a doubt as to how evolution of matter can fail to be karman of the self: 11.93. Although existing at all times in the midst of matter, the soul, in fact, does not grasp, does not release, and is not the agent of material karman. (185) Assuredly evolution of matter is not karman (effect) of the self, since this is exempt from appropriation or surrender of other substance. For whatever is perceived to be cause of evolution in another thing is not (insert na) perceived to be exempt from appropriation and surrender thereof : as in the case of fire in regard to a mass of iron. But the self, although existing in identical space, is in fact exempt from appropriation and surrender of other substance: hence it cannot be cause of the evolution of material components into the state of karman. Now he describes how, accordingly, there is appropriation or surrender of the self by material karmans. 11.94. He, being at present in this transmigratory condition) the agent of his own evolution, constituted of its own substance, is at times appropriated [i.e. bound up with) and released by karman-dusts. (186) This self, though exempt from appropiration and release of other substance, now, in the transmigrant state, exercising agency only in regard to his own substantive evolution,---for which the evolutions of other substance serve only as occasioning causes [i.e. the supportive or auxiliary factor (nimitta)—is, so long only, appropriated, by way of a particular kind of interpenetration, by the dusts of matter, which, merely using the occasion (nimitta) of his own self-evolution, assumes evolution into karman, and sometimes he is released [by them). Now he describes how produced is the variety of material karmans. II.95. When the self, associated with attachment and aversion, evolves into good and evil, karma-dust, in the state or form of ‘knowledge-obscuring' and so on, enters into it. (187/1) Assuredly, at the time of the self's evolving into good and evil, Page #363 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 337 there exists independently a variegated evolution of karma-matter; just as at the time of evolution of a new cloud's water into conjunction with the earth there exists a variegated evolution of other matter. Thus: just as, when the water of a new cloud evolves into conjunction with the earth, then other material components independently evolve in variegated states as green-swards, mushrooms, cochineal insects, so, when this self, under the sway of attachment or aversion, evolves into a good or evil state, then other karmic-material-components, entering it through its vibratory activity, evolve independently in variegated states, "knowledge-obscuring" and so on. Hence the variety of karmans is produced by their innate nature, and not produced by the self. Now he states that the self alone is bondage: II.96. The self, which has spacial units (space-points), when stained with deluded view, attachment and aversion, is, at that time embraced by karma-dust, described as bondage in the scripture. (188) Just as in the world a single garment, having spacial units, is, through being stained with lodhra and so on, observed to be dyed with colour of madder and so on, so the self also, having spacial units, is, at time, through being stained with infatuation, attachment and aversion, to be regarded as a single bondage, embraced by karmadusts: for the thing contemplated by strict verity [internal selfreferential viewpoint] (nishchaya naya) is the pure substance. Now he exhibits the absence of contradiction between internal selfreferential viewpoint [strict verity, Faddegon] (nishchaya naya) and external other-referential standpoint [common acceptance, Faddegon] (vyavahara naya): II.97. This [in brief] is the summary account of the bondage of souls, described Arahantas to the yatis as strict verity (nishchaya naya) [i.e. from the internal self-referential point of view]; common acceptance (vyavahara-naya) [i.e. from the external, other-referential standpoint] it is expressed differently. (189) Only evolution into attachment is karman of the self: It is a duality of merit and sin. That the self is agent only of evolution into attachment and so on and appropriator and renouncer of that only is the view of nishchaya naya, which consists in describing the pure substance. But that which says that "the evolution of matter is the self's karman107, and that is a duality of merit and sin: the self is agent of the evolution of matter and appropriator and renouncer thereof" is the view of Page #364 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 338 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES vyavahara naya, which consists in describing non-pure substance. Both these two are correct, since substance is conceived in both forms, as pure and as not pure. However, in this place the view of nishchaya naya is adopted, as being the most effective: for, as emphasizing the purity of the thing in view, viz. substance in its purity, the view of nishchaya naya is the most effective means of accomplishing the task (sadhaktam), not the view of vyavahara naya, which emphasizes the impure. Now he states that from the point of view of the impure we get only an impure self: II.98. But whoso does not abandon the notion of mineness, such as "I am this", "this is mine," in regard to body and wealth forsakes the state of sramana and takes a wrong path. (190) The self, in fact, which, regardless of and being non-relative (nirpeksha) the view of nishchaya [pure] naya, consisting in description of [undefined, transcendental] pure substance, and infatuated with the view of vyavahara naya, consisting in the description of impure substance, does not abandon the notion of mineness in regard to body, wealth and so on, which are other substance, thinking them to belong to the self, "I am this," "this is mine," leaves afar the path of sramanahood, which has the form of evolution into the pure self, and takes actually a wrong path, in the form of evolution into impure self. Hence it is discerned that through the point of view of the impure we get only an impure self. Now he discerns that from the point of view of the pure we get simply the pure self: II.99. Whoso contemplates thus, "I do not belong to other: others do not belong to me: I am only something of the knowing nature alone," that self in its contemplation is a contemplator of the [real] 8 (191) self, 108 Whoso, in fact, being neutral in the sense of having no opposition109 in regard to the view of vyavahara naya,-which consists in discerning impure substance and is active only upon its own objects, and having cast away infatuation by means of the view of nishchaya [pure] naya, which consists in discerning pure substance,-has dissipated any connection of mutual ownness and ownership between self and other, thinking, "I do not belong to others: others do not belong to me," and, conceiving that "I am one [alone],1 pure 110 Page #365 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 339 knowledge," lets go the non-self and, taking on the self as self, turns away from other substance and confines his thought to the single point, the self, such an one assuredly, confining his thought one-pointedly, will in that moment of confining his thought one-pointedly be pure self. Hence it is discerned that only from the point of view of the pure do we get the pure self. Now he teaches that on ground of being eternal (dhruvatva) only pure self should be resorted to: the II.100. Thus I deem the self as pure because it is knowledge and intuition, a great thing, supra-sensual, supreme reality (mahartha), eternal (dhruva), stable [immobile, Faddegon] (achala), without prop or support. (192) The self, in fact, is pure and only the pure self is eternal (dhruva) existent (sat) and without a cause, it is without beginning or end and since it is self-established; nothing else is so. And purity belongs to the self, since through discrimination from other substance and through non-discrimination from its own properties it is an unity (ekatva). And this [unity] is because of consisting of knowledge and intuition, because of supra-sensual, supreme reality, because of being stable, and because of being without prop. As to these, it has unity because, bearing in itself knowledge and being of itself intuition, it is absolutely discriminated from other substance and undiscriminated from its own properties; likewise it has unity because, transcending the several senses, which grasp each its restricted quality, touch, taste, smell, colour, and also the mode of sound, and being itself one supreme reality apprehending all the qualities, touch, taste, smell, colour and also the mode of sound, it is discriminated from other substance, consisting in the sense-organs, and not discriminated from its own property, consisting in apprehension of touch, etc.: likewise it has unity because, being stable through taking and leaving the discernible modifications in their process of instantaneous evanescence, it is discriminated from substance consisting in the discernible modifications, and not discriminated fror.. its own property, consisting in discerning the presentations thereof; likewise it has unity, because, being without prop, as not being propped upon discernible substance in its perpetual process, it is discriminated from discernible "other" substance and not discriminated from its own property, consisting in discerning the presentations thereof. Thus the self is pure, because Page #366 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 340 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES the view of the pure, which is simply consciousness, discerns only what is no more than that, and it alone, because of its being eternal (dhruvatva), is to be taken to: what of other unstable things, which correspond to the numerous shadows of way-side trees coming in contact with the limbs of the traveller? Now he teaches that on ground of unsteadfastness nothing other than the self is to be resorted to: II.101. Neither bodies nor possessions, neither pleasure nor pain, neither enemies nor friends are steadfast or eternal (dhruva) for the soul; the self, which is constituted of psychic-attention, is steadfast or eternal. (193) Nothing else whatever is steadfast or eternal (dhruva) for the soul, because it has beginning and end, inasmuch as something impermanent (asat) has produced it and because it is brought into being by another thing; for everything (with the exception of self] results in impurity, since it is not distinct from the other” substance and is distinct from the self's own properties, which are infected by the “other”. The self alone, which has psychic-attention for self, is steadfast and pure. Therefore I do not resort to the unsteadfast, impermanent body, etc., although they are resorted to; but I resort to the pure self, which is eternal (dhruva). Now as regards the question "what results from this resorting (upalambha) to the pure self?” he explains: II.102. He who, having thus discerned the pure self, contemplates on the supreme reality of that self, whether he is a householder or an ascetic,"11 destroys the evil knot of infatuation. (194) He who in the manner described approaches the pure steadfast (dhruva) self attains, through his activity in regard to it, pureness of self. Being then the supreme reality of self and nothing else than consciousness with unlimited energy (shakti), he attains contemplation, which is characterized as deep, attentive thoughtfulness. Then, since in one activley occupied with formed thought (sa-sakara) there is an arising of an attentive thoughtfulness without deviation, he attains the unfastening of the coil-knot (granthi) of infatuation, bound very tightly throughout his transmigration. Thus a breaking of the knot of infatuation is the fruit of restoring to the pure self. Now as regards the question "what happens from the breaking (bheda) of the knot of infatuation?" he explains: Page #367 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 341 II.103. He who, having destroyed the knot of infatuation and having made an end to attachement and aversion, abides in the state of a shraman, counting pleasure and pain as the same, acquires imperishable happiness. (195) From the destruction of the knot of infatuation ensues the destruction of attachment and aversion, whereof that is the root. Thence follows an abiding in the state of a shraman, characterized as the perfect equanimity (madhyastha) of one who counts pleasure and pain as the same. Thence follows attainment of imperishable happinss, characterized as absence of perturbation. Thus imperishable happiness is the fruit of the breaking of the knot of infatuation. Now he certifies that contemplation (dhyana) characterized as deep, attentive thoughtfulness, does not lead to impurity of self: 11.104. Whoso, having destroyed the stains of infatuation and being detached from sense objects, restrains his mind and abides in his innate nature, becomes a contemplator of the self. (196) To the self whose stains of infatuation are destroyed belongs detachment from sense-objects, because it abstains from activity towards the “other” (substance), whereof that (infatuation) is the root. Then comes restraint (nirodha) of the internal-sense, which has nothing else for refuge because there is no other substance which could be its resting-place (adhikarana); like a flying bird for which there is only one bark in mid-ocean. Thereupon, through the disappearance of flightiness, whereof that (not restrained internal-sense) is the root, comes steadfastness in his innate nature, which is unlimited innate consciousness. And that, because of being an unperturbed, deeply attentive, thoughtfulness, proceeding (pravrtta) in its own nature, is entitled “contemplation.” Hence contemplation, as being an abiding in one's inborn nature, is the self, since it is not anything other than the self. Now he propounds the question what the possessor of complete knowledge (sakala-jnani), who has attained the pure self, contemplates: 11.105. What does the shraman, who has annihilated the dense destructive karman and directly knows the reality of all existences and has reached the limit of the knowable, contemplate, free from doubt? (197) . The ordinary man is seen to contemplate an object of which, — because he is full of longings (trshna), while there exist in him Page #368 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 342 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES infatuation and hindrance of the energy of knowledge, and because he has no immediate knowledge and no well-defined object,- he is desirous, curious and in doubt. But the revered Omniscient does not feel desire, curiosity or doubt, because he has eradicated all longings, while there exists for him no infatuation, or hindrances to the energy of knowledge, inasmuch as he has destroyed the dense destructive karman, and because the truth of all existences is immediately perceptible to him and the limit of the knowbale attained. How then can there be to him an object (artha) of desire, curiosity or doubt? In these circumstances what does he contemplate? Now he propunds the answer: the possessor of complete knowledge, who has attained (read upalabdha-shuddhatma) the pure seif, contemplates this: 11.106. Set free from all afflictions and hindrances, rich with complete happiness and knowledge in all his faculties, elevated above the sense-organs, he without sense-activities (aksha) contemplates supreme happiness. (198) This self, as soon as-in consequence of the absence of senseactivities, which are abodes of hindrance to innate happiness and knowledge and abodes of such happiness and knowledge as do not extend in all directions and do not comprise the whole soul-it is itself, without sense-organs, immediately, being elevated above others and the sense-organs, it becomes free from all afflictions, because it has untroubled innate happiness and knowledge, and rich with complete happiness and knowledge in all its faculties, because it is full of such happiness and knowledge as extend in all directions and comprise the whole soul. And in this state, though every desire, wish for knowledge and doubt are absent, it contemplates the highest happiness, unprecedented and characterized as absence of perturbation: that is to say, it abides as simply a deeply attentive consciousness, accompanied by absence of perturbation. And such a state is, in fact, attainment of perfection, whose essence is innate knowledge and bliss. Now he determines that this itself is the path of liberation, characterized as attainment of the pure self: 11.107. Thus, my homage to those, who following the path [of liberation) have attained the state of the Jinas, "12 the best of Jinas, 113 the shramanas, and liberated souls (siddhas). And homage to that path of nirvana (199) Page #369 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE PRINCIPLE OF KNOWLEDGE 343 Since all those, the spiritual guides (tirtha-kara), who are for the last time embodied, and the aspirants to liberation, not for the last time embodied, have beem sanctified by following a path towards liberation proceeding in just the manner described and characterized as a striving for the truth of the pure self, and since there has been no other way, therefore it is determined that there is only this one road to liberation and no second. And enough of elaboration! To those who strive towards the truth of the pure self, and to that Path of Liberation which consists in the striving towards the truth of pure self, while the difference between the object of adoration and the adorer has rot yet been superseded, be Homage then in non-essentials (noagama) and in heart. The path of liberation has been determined; the due action is (to be) carried out. Now, carrying out the former pledge contained in the words “I depend on the tranquillity” etc. (PS 5), he sets forth this striving towards the pure self, which striving is the path of liberation: II.108. Therefore, having in this way conceived the self as essentially of knowing nature (jnayak), I relinquish the notion of “mineness," adopting the idea of non-attachment or negation of "mineness.” (200/1) This I, qualified (adhikarin) for liberation, by surrender of the idea of “mine” and adoption of the idea of negation of “mineness," preceded by acquaintance with the truth of the self as essentially something-that-knows,-strives with all its might towards the pure self, since it has no other task. Thus: I now am essentially of knowing nature (jnayaka), and, as only jnayaka, I have with everything a connection characterized as that of naturally knowable and knower, not any other connection, such as that of possession and possessor. For me, therefore, there is in respect of nothing as being “mine,” in respect of everything a negation of “mineness.” The pure self, thenwhich, since the knowing capacity has the nature of realizing all knowables, in one moment intuits, -as it were carved in relief, engraven, implanted, pinned down, hobbled down, actually present, mirrored, – the whole mass of things, deep, of unfathomable, nature, a mountain of variegated modifications, successive, infinite, past, present and future -and which, while assuining uniformity, because of impossibility of discrimination due to the inevitability of the relation of knowable and knower, yet never abandons uniformity in virtue of Page #370 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 344 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES its essence as a knower of infinite natural potency and in that same permanence persists everlastingly, though through infatuation otherwise regarded, -to that pure self, as it really is, I having eradicated infatuation, adhere without the least wavering. Towards this self, which, in consequence of in disinclination to weaknesses, -by reason of being actively occupied in perfect knowledge having its root in purity of conviction, -is, although a practising saint (sadhu), yet already perfected (siddha), and also towards similar supreme selves, may there spontaneously arise a perpetual mental adoration, characterized as a sole intentness114 upon them. “Thus, having rightly penetrated the Jaina doctrine, the expositor of the truth of knowable, the bounteous Absolute in the form of speech, we abide perpetually rapt in the one-pointed attitude (vritti) which is nothing but the pure self-substance."115 (PS Kalash 10) “Making truly everything to the utmost limit a knowable, making the knowable, with its differences superseded, a knowledge and making that knowledge, though seemingly different from self, into self, the self shines forth, having straightway attained the Absolute.” (PS Kalash 11) “The conduct follows the substance; the substance follows the conduct; the two are surely sapeksha, i.e. mutually complementary to one another or interdependent. Let him, therefore, who is desirous of liberation climb the path of liberation, whether having envisaged the substance or having envisaged the conduct.” (PS Kalash 12) Here ends The Lamp of Truth, a commentary on Pravachanasara, composed by Amrtachandra Suri, the second sciptural book, entitled The Teaching of the Truth of the Knowable. Page #371 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Book III The Conduct Page #372 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Book III The Conduct NOTE: III.1, III.2, etc. denote Gatha (verse) No. 1, 2, etc. of Book III, while Gatha Nos. 201, 202, etc. at the end of translation denote consecutive numbering of gathas starting from Book 1, which tallies with the gatha numbering of the original Prakrit text given at the end of this edition and most editions of the work in Hindi. Now begins the Supplement expository of the Conduct, containing an examination of conduct for others. “With attainment of the substance comes attainment of the conduct; with attainment of the conduct, attainment of the substance”made aware of this, let others, who have not yet desisted from (sinful] action (karman), follow a conduct not repugnant to the substance. (PS Kalash 13) In this way he stimulates others to observe the conduct, i.e. as described in gathas 201-203: CONDUCT INCLUDING NEGLIENCE (VERSE 201-231) III.1. Thus having bowed before the Siddhas, the great Jinas, and the shramanas, one should take refuge in the state of shramana, if one wishes liberation from misery. (201) Just as my own self, desirous of liberation from misery, in gathas 4 and 5 paid veneration, in the form of prostration and salutation, to the Arhats, Siddhas, Acharyas, Upadhyayas and Sadhus, and after this has for itself adopted the state of a shramana, which, consisting mainly in purifying intuition and knowledge, bears the name of equanimity (samya) and includes the state of well-being conceived in the two intervening (the first two books), books of our treatise, so the selves Page #373 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 347 of others also, if desirous of liberation from misery, should likewise adopt the same. Of the path of its adoption, as experienced, we here stand forth as guides. Now he teaches what anyone desirous of becoming a shramana does first: III.2. Having said farewell to his kindred; being released by his family, wife and sons; having applied himself to the practice of knowledge, intuition, conduct, austerity and energy (virya)."16 (202) Now he who wishes to become a shramana begins by saying farewell to his kindred, effects his release from parents, wife and sons, and applies himself to the practice of knowledge, intuition, conduct, austerity and energy. Thus he bids farewell to his relatives in these terms: “O selves who abide in the kindred of this person's body, this person's self belongs in no way to you; of this be assured. He has said farewell to you. This self, wherein the light of knowledge has burst forth, seeks the self, the self's primordial kinsman. . "O self of the father of this man's body, O self of the mother of this man's body, the self of this man has not been procreated by you; of this be you assured. Therefore do you release this self. This self, wherein the light of knowledge has burst forth, seeks the self, the self's primordial parent. "O self of the wife (ramani) of this man's body, you do not impassion (ramayasi) the self of this man: of this be you assured. Therefore release this self. This self, wherein the light of knowledge has burst forth, seeks its own experience (anubhuti), the self's primordial (impassioner) wife. "O self of the son of this man's body, you were not procreated by this man's self: of this be you assured. Therefore release this self. This self, wherein the light of knowledge has burst forth, now seeks the self, the self's primordial son.” In this way, he effects his release from parents, wife and son. "Likewise exercise in knowledge, characterized by — (1) consideration of time (kala); (2) modesty (vinaya); (3) affection for knowledge (upadhana); (4) respect (bahu-mana); (5) non-concealment (anihnava); (6) the meaning (artha); (7) the words (vyanjana); (8) that which combines the last two mentioned (tad-ubhaya-sampanna); you do not belong to the purified self; of this I am assured. Yet I apply Page #374 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 348 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES myself to you, until by your grace it"7 attains the purified self. “O exercise in intuition, characterized by (1) absence of doubt (nishankitatva); (2) absence of desires for anything but self-realization (nihkankshatatva); (3) absence of hatred (of the poor and diseased (nirvichikitsatva); (4) freedom from foolish superstitions (nirmudhadrshtitva); (5) edification (sthitikarana); (6) causation of progress (upavrmhana); (7) tenderness (vatsalya); (8) promulgation of doctrine (prabhavana); you do not belong to the purified self: of this I am assured. Yet I apply my self to you, until by your grace it attains the purified self. “O exercise in conduct, characterized by (1) - (5) the five great vows (mahavrata), causes of striving on the road of liberation; (6) - (8) the three restraints (gupti) of body, mind and speech; (9) - (13) religious observances (samiti), walking carefully so as not to hurt any living being, speaking relevantly, taking only pure food, carefully handling the few things which belong to a shramana, great care as to where to answer the calls of nature; you do not belong to the purified self: of this I am assured. Yet I apply my self to you, until by your grace it attains the purified self. “O exercise in austerity, characterized by (1) fasting; (2) eating less than what one may desire; (3) accepting alms only if a particular thing is fulfilled; (4) renunciation and suppression of taste and tasteful things; (5) sitting and sleeping alone; (6) mortification of the body through refusing it many comforts; (7) penance in expiation of any fault; (8) eager zeal and humility; (9) service and attendance on old, infirm and sick sadhus, (10) reading the scripture; (11) contemplation; and (12) non-attachment to the body; you do not belong to the purified self: of this I am assured. Yet I apply my self to you, until by your grace it attains to the purified self. “O exercise in energy, characterized by not hiding your potency promotive of all the other exercises; you do not belong to the purified self: of this I am assured. Yet I apply my self to you, until by your grace it attains to the purified self.” Thus he applies himself to the practice of knowledge, intuition, conduct, austerity and energy. Now he teaches what like he thereby becomes: III.3. Then before a shramana, a class leader, rich in merits, distinguished by family (kula), form and mature age, and highly Page #375 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 349 approved by (other) shramanas, he makes his bow and, after saying, "accept me,” he receives favour. (203) Then the person desirous of the state of a shramana bows reverentially and receives favour. Thus: Approaching one who, through shramana-hood, which consists in a self which has practised and caused (others) to practise all the renunciations and activities both, is a shramana: who, through skill in practising and causing (others) to practise such shramana-hood, is rich in merits; who, through being fit to be honoured without hesitation by all people of the world and through being free from inherited defects such as usury, '18 etc. is of distinguished family: who, because an exterior clear colour (shuddha-rupa) is indicative of interior of pure colour, is of distinguished colour; who through freedom from all infirmity of mind due to infancy or old age, and through having a mind dissociated from perversion by the extravagancies of youth, is distinguished by mature age; through being by preference sought by all who long for liberation, since he has annihilated all human weaknesses in the sphere of practising and causing to be practised the above-defined shramana-hood, is highly approved by shramanas, who is a ganin (i.e. a class-leader), a teacher who succeeds in effecting the comprehension of the truth of the pure self-approaching such a teacher with the words “Favour me by promoting my understanding of the truth of the pure self,” he bows before him. Being by him furnished with the objects of his request in the words “Yes, here is for you understanding of the truth of pure self," he receives favour. Now he teaches what like he further becomes: III.4. “I do not belong to others, and others do not belong to me; nothing whatever belongs to me”-firm in this conviction, conqueror of his senses, he (shramana) adopts jadha jada-ruva in Pk. yathajatarupa in Sanskrit), i.e. natural rupa (character) of a new born child. (204) Further the person desirous of the state of shramana adopts his natural form. Thus: “In no respect do I belong to others nor are others anything to me, because in reality all substances are devoid of all connections with other substances; therefore in this world, which consists of the six substances, nothing else than myself belongs to me.” Thus convinced in his mind and conqueror of his senses, through conquest of his senses and quasi-senses (noindriya), which are relations Page #376 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 350 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES of possessor and possession between themselves and other substances, he indeed adopts his natural rupa (character), inasmuch as he adopts the pure rupa (nature) of the self-substance as it originally is." Now of this adopting the natural rupa, which condition had until then been absolutely unattained, because of never having been practised during the whole precedent samsara, he mentions a number of characteristics, external and internal, which make evident the success which is being attained by the skill of his new practice: III.5. The (external) characteristic of a shramana is (1) the possession of rupa (form) as it is by birth, (2) the extraction of hair and beard, (3) purity (of not being attached to things), (4) the absence of himsa (the injuring of living beings, etc.), (5) and devoid of decoration of body. (apratikarma, or aparikarma, see also PS 224 and 228). (205) III.6. A (further) characteristic (of shraman), as described by Jina (the conquerors of internal enemies), is (1) absence of infatuation and sins pertaining to incidental activities, (2) being endowed with purity of psychic-attention (upayoga) and of the threefold activity (of body, speech and mind, yoga), (3) and independent of “the other,” which puts a stop to further births." (206) In the self which has begun by itself, in the way described by us, to adopt a form as it is by original nature, there is an absence of states such as infatuation, attachment and aversion, causes of the possession of rupa different from that of original nature; in consequence of this non-existence, then, there belong to him who abides in such a state: (1) possession of a rupa as it was by original nature; (2) extraction of hair and beard; (3) purity; (4) absence of deeds such as the injuring of living beings; 120 (5) not decorating the body due respectively to negation of (1) wearing garments and adornment, (2) keeping hair and moustache, (3) possessing anything (sakimchanatva), (4) being engaged in blamable activity (yoga), (5) paying attention (samskara) to the body. This is the external mark. Likewise, in consequence of the non-existence of states such as infatuation, attachment and aversion, causes of the possession of a rupa different from that of original nature,-which rupa is now expelled by the rupa of original nature, there belong to him who abides in such a condition: (1) freedom from infatuation and sins pertaining to incidental activities; (2) possession of purity of psychic-attention and Page #377 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 351 (threefold) activity; (3) independence of “the other” due (respectively) to the negation of (1) the evolution of the consequences of the notion “mine”; (2) the possession of impurity of psychic-attention infected by good (shubha) and evil (ashubha) and the like (threefold) activity following thereupon; (3) dependence on other substances. This is the internal mark. Next, in the words, "by taking these two marks (Verses 205 and 206) and doing so and so he becomes a shramana", indicating the identity of subject of the verb “becomes”121 and all the other actions (previously mentioned) of taking leave of kindred, etc., he teaches that so much suffices (iyata) for attainment of the state of shramanas. III.7. Having adopted this sign or mark at the hands of his superior teacher, after reverencing him, heard what he should do, together with the vows, applying himself thereto, he becomes a shramana. (207) Next, wishing to become a shramana, he (1) adopts the two characteristics, (2) reverences the teacher, (3) hears the vows and tasks, (4) applies himself, and by so doing becomes a shramana, possessed of all requirements of the shramana-state. Thus, (1) Having by the act of acceptance honoured this external and internal characteristics, which lead to the adopting the forin of original nature, and which are a gift,-as being customarily given, originally by the guru, the supreme Lord, the Arhat, but at the moment by the initiation-teacher, as demonstrating the procedure of acceptance, - he identifies himself therewith. (2) Next, having by prostration honoured the original, the following and the subsequent gurus, who, by the forgetting all distinction between self and other, not distinguishing between the adorable, adorer and adoration, successively involving each other, have given their all, he identifies himself with adoration, praise (stuti), and homage (vandana) 2nd and 3rd essential daily duties (avashyaka). (3) Then, knowing by study of the scriptures (svadhyaya, the fifth avashyaka), i.e. by hearing the one great vow defined as renunciation (pratyakhyana) ( in the list of the avashyakas) of every blamable activity relating to mind, speech and body (yoga)—that the self evolves into the equanimous state of samaya (jiva or self), on knowing the essential nature of soul, ascends to the samayika (first avashyaka). (4) Then, knowing the nature of soul as different from karmas in all three times (past, present and future) on hearing about repentance Page #378 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 352 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES of past misdeeds (pratikraman), confession of one's faults in the present (alochana) and resolve not to repeat the blamable activity in future (pratyakhyana) through the scriptures ascends the state of consciousness different from the activities related to body, speech and mind (4th avashyava). (5) Then, continually basing himself without distraction on the one characteristic of own nature (svarupa), which possesses the rupa (form, character) of original nature, and having given up attachment to the body (kayotsarga, 6th avashyaka), as abode of every blamable activity, he applies himself. And, having applied himself in this way and adopting in all cases equal vision or view of equanamity (samadrashtitva) by regarding all things alike, he becomes really a shramana. Now he teaches that even a shramana habituated to uninterrupted equanimity (samayika) requires sometimes correction of negligences (chedopasthapana): III.8. (Five) vows (vrata), (five-fold) religious observances or selfregulations (samiti), restraint of five senses (indriya-rodha), pulling out the hair (loch), the daily duties (avashyaka) (six in number), unclothed state of nakedness or scantily clothed (achailakya), not bathing (asnana), sleeping on the ground (kshiti-shayana), not brushing the teeth (a-danta-dhavana), taking food in a standing position (sthitibhojana), one meal a day (eka-bhakta). (208) III.9. These (twenty-eight) are the primary or fundamental qualities"22 (mula-guna) of shramanas, prescribed by the best of Jinas. A shramana remiss in one of these becomes a corrector of negligence (chedopasthapaka). (209) As being specialized forms of the one great vow defined as renunciation (pratyakhyana) of every blamable activity (yoga), abstinence from hurting (any living being), from falsity (in speech, thought and deed), from theft, from unchastity, from worldly concerns, this fivefold vow, and in attendance thereupon the five-fold religious observances or self-regulations, the five-fold restraints of the senses, pulling out of the hair with one's own hands, the six daily duties, achailakya, not bathing, sleeping on the ground, not brushing the teeth, taking food in a standing position, one meal a day-are the fundamental qualities of a shramana, since they are branches of the indispensable samayika Page #379 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 353 (Tattvarthadhigama Sutra, IX. 18, samayika-samyama as first kind of samyama) self-restraint. When in respect to these the shramana is remiss because, while established in the indispensable samayika self-restraint, he has not practised the branches, then, reflecting that “for one who desires simply gold sometimes an earring, a bracelet, a ring and so forth are good: he cannot on all occasions have (merely) gold,” he corrects himself by one of the branches and so is a corrector of negligences. Now by giving information concerning the different kinds (vikalpa) of teachers (acharya), he shows that, like the giver of ordination, the corrector of negligences is another person (para): III.10. In the adoption of the marks the giver of ordination is called guris the other shramana who give advice as to correction (upasthapaka) of the faults are niryapakas. (210) Since that teacher who, at the time of the adoption of the marks, effects ordination by teaching indispensable self-restraints is the guru, and, since, on the other hand, the teacher who later by expounding the self-restraint of correction of negligences (chedopasthapana)123 in regard to the branches (vikalpa) corrects in respect of negligences, and also the teacher who, when a negligence exists, corrects by teaching the way of repairing (pratisamdhana) the omission, is a niryapaka, therefore the corrector of negligences is another. Now he teaches the way of repairing (pratisamdhana) a neglected self-restraint: III.11. When a shramana commits a negligence in a bodily activity earnestly undertaken, then an action, combined with self-reflection and confession of fault (alochana) is prescribed for him. (211) III.12. When a shramana practised negligence (of mental intent), then he must approach a shramana expert in the doctrine of the Jina, and after self-reflection confess (alochana) his fault before him and do what is advised. (212) There are two kinds of negligences in self-restraint, external and internal. That which relates only to bodily action is external; that which relates to psychic-attention is internal. If in the course of an earnestly undertaken bodily activity of a shramana properly intent there somehow occurs an external negligence, then, since it is altogether clear of internal negligence, the reparation is by an action, accompanied by reflection. But, when the same person, inasmuch as the negligence Page #380 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 354 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES relates to intent, has been intent upon a patent negligence, then reparation is made by resorting to a shramanal24 expert in the rules of conduct as prescribed by the Jina, and further by reflection and by the procedure advised by him. Now he teaches that inclinations towards other substances, as occasioning negligences in the state of a shramana, should be rejected: III.13. In the teacher's abode (adhivasa) or in solitude (vivashc),125 let the shramana who has become free from negligences in regard to the shramana-state live (viharatu), ever avoiding (pariharamana) 126 attachments. (213) All inclinations towards other substances are, as infecting the psychic-attention, occasions of negligences in the shramana-state, which is psychic-attention free from infection; simply from absence thereof (of those inclinations) comes shramana-hood void of negligences. Her ce in an abode constantly appropriated (adhikrtya) in his own mind to himself, or in a dwelling distinguished (vishishta) for its gurus, let this shramana who has become free from negligences in regard to the shramana-state abide, always rejecting inclinations to other substances. Now he teaches that inclination towards one's own substance is to be cultivated, as occasioning completeness of the shramana-state: III.14. The shramana who moves about ever attached to knowledge, with faith in the forefront, and is earnest in regard to the fundamental qualities (mula-guna)127 has complete shramanahood. (214) For inclination towards one's own substance, being purificatory of the psychic-attention, of itself occasions completeness of the shramana-state, which is purified psychic-attention. Therefore, earnest in regard to the fundamental qualities, he must live ever attached to knowledge, intuition, etc.: that is to say, he must be simply pure existence, attached to the pure self-substance, which has for essence knowledge and intuition. Now he teaches that even a slight (sukshma) 128 inclination towards other things, even such as is natural in ascetics, must be rejected, as occasioning negligence in the shramana-state: III.15. A shramana does not enterain any desire or attachment to food or fasting, lodging or wandering (vihara), anything of worldly concern (upadhi),129 for another shramana or useless and idle gossip (vikatha). 130 (215) Page #381 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 355 For food merely taken as a means of sustaining the body, which is an auxiliary cause of the modification called the shramana-state; for fasting, which, without contravening such a sustaining of the body, takes place conformably to the sutra ordinance of a passionless and still repose of the pure self-substance; for a lodging, such as a cave in a high mountain, frequented in order to secure a passionless and calm internal substance; for the business of wandering, undertaken in order to find means for sustaining the body as above mentioned; for any upadhi (anything that complies with one's needs), which is limited to the body merely and, as being an auxiliary means to the modification called the shramana-state, is not prohibited; for a shramana, familiar to him in one way or another, merely in the mutual relation of one who gives and one who receives enlightenment; for talk (vikathayam), in which a portion of the wall-of-consciousness (bhitti) is stained by contact with sparkle of word particles, and which is opposed to the pure self-substance,-even for these things an inclination must be rejected, so that the wall of consciousness is no more painted with these fancies (vikalpa). Now he informs us, what is a negligence (chheda): III.16. Heedless!31 action in lying, sitting, standing, going, etc., is considered to be at all times continual hurt (himsa) 132 to the shramana-state. (216) A negligence is an impure (ashuddha) psychic-attention; for it "breaks,” “destroys,” the shramana-state, which consists of pure psychic-attention. Negligence is thus itself hurt (himsa). Therefore heedless action on the part of the shramana in lying, sitting, standing, going, etc., which is necessarily accompanied by impure psychicattention, is for him a hurt, at all times in continuous progress and in no way different from negligence. Now he teaches two kinds of negligence, as being internal or external: III.17. Let the creature die or live, on the part of the careless one the act of hurting is certain: by the mere fact of hurt he who is careful in his observances incurs no bondage. (217/1) Impure psychic-attention is internal negligence; the taking of another's life is external. Whether the taking of another being's life occurs or does not occur, to the actual impure psychic-attention, proved by the careless conduct, which does not occur without it, the nature of hurting certainly belongs: and to the non-existence of impure Page #382 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 356 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES psychic-attention (read asadbhavasya), proved by the careful conduct, which occurs without it, the nature of hurting certainly does not belong, as is shown by the fact that the taking of another's life does not involve bondage : therefore internal negligence is the more serious, and not the external. Even so, the external should be recognized, simply as being an occasion for the internal negligence. Now he teaches that internal negligence must in any case be rejected: III.18. A shramana of careless conduct in regard to the six bodies 133 is esteemed to be hurting them; but, if he always behaves carefully, then, like a lotus in water, he is un-assoiled. (218) Since the existence of impure psychic-attention, proved by careless behaviour, which does not occur without it, is hurtful, inasmuch as bondage is known to result from the cause of taking the life of the six classes of bodies; and since non-existence of impure psychicattention, proved by careful behaviour, which occurs without it, is non-hurtful,-for, inasmuch as it has not the slightest bondage resulting from the “other,” it is known to be like a lotus luxuriating (durlalita) in the water, without assoil-for these reasons internal negligence, which has the form of impure psychic-attention, must be rejected in all cases where external negligence, in the form of taking another being's life, which is merely occasion of internal negligence, is entirely rejected. Now he teaches that similarly appropriation (upadhi), since it is exclusively an internal negligence, should be rejected: III.19. Bondage may arise or not arise when, in case of a bodily action, a living being is killed: but from appropriation or possessiveness (the Tatparya-vrtti paraphrases upadhi by parigraha) bondage certainly results; therefore shramanas have abandoned it entirely. (219) Whereas in the taking of another being's life through a bodily action the negligence-quality is held to be variable,-because its character as bondage is variable according to the presence or absence of impure psychic-attention, with appropriation the case is different. Its negligence-quality is invariable, because its character as bondage is invariable owing to the invariable presence of impure psychicattention, which is proved by its non-occurrence without the same. Therefore the holy Arhats, the supreme shramanas, have themselves Page #383 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 357 abandoned all upadhi (external possessions as well as internal parigraha of attachment, aversion and passions). Accordingly others also should from the first reject it, like internal negligence, because it does not occur without the same. "Hereby, if a man reflects upon it, is said all that needs to be said. For the unreflecting, surely, the net of delusion is hard to escape even with the greatest expenditure of words.” (PS Kalash 14) Now he teaches that rejection of appropriation is in fact rejection of internal negligence: III.20. Without the absolute renunciation (tyaga) 134 of worldly concerns, devoid of all consideration, regard or expection of any sort (nirvekkho in Pk., nirpeksha in Sk.), there does not take place purification (visuddhi) of mental states (aasaya in Pk., aashaya in Sk.) and when the mind is not purified, how can there be annihilation of karman? (220/1) Given the existence of connection with an external (negligence), and given rejection of internal (negligence) having the form of impure psychic-attention, as of impurity of rice-grains when husks are present, we do not find only the fundamental pure psychic-attention. Therefore rejection of appropriation, ordained in view of a purpose, namely rejection of an internal negligence, namely impure psychic-attention, is in fact rejection of internal negligence. Now, enlarging upon appropriation, he teaches that it is invariably internal negligence: III.21. How can he (who is favourably disposed towards parigraha) be free from infatuation, incidental sins inevitable in worldly activities (arambha) 3 and lack of self-restraint (samyama)? And how one, who is attached to or engrossed in other substance, can realize the real nature of self? (221) Since, given appropriation, there unavoidably results infatuation, characterized as an evolution of the idea of mine, worldly undertakings, characterized as an evolution through a series of acts having that for object, and lack of self-restraint, characterized as an evolution destructive of the character of pure self, and since one associated with appropriation, being fond of other “substance," does not attain the pure self, we determine that appropriation is invariably internal negligence. The purport hereof is thit, having determined the nature of appropriation to be such, we Page #384 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 358 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES should entirely forgo it. Now he teaches an exception, to the effect that for some person in some circumstances at some time in some way some appropriation is in fact not to be rejected: III.22. That wherethrough negligence does not attach to the user either in taking or in leaving it [things], the shramana who has considered time and place may use it. (222) That every appropriation must be rejected, since the self-substance is without any second, material, substance, is the main rule. But here we have an exception, that by virtue of particular time and place some [appropriations] are not rejected. For, when a shramana who has undertaken a rejection of all appropriations cannot, although desirous of attaining the highest self-restraint in indifference, succeed in this, because his energies have failed owing to particular time and place, then, taking to a diminished self-restraint, he has recourse to appropriations, merely as external means. And the appropriation so resorted to is not only not a negligence through being an appropriation; on the contrary, it is a rejection of a negligence. A negligence is that which does not occur without impure psychic-attention; but this, accepted in order to avoid a negligence in the matter of taking and leaving, e.g. of taking food and voiding of excrements (nirhara), which are means for the life of the body,-itself required as an auxiliary means for the modification called the shramana-state,-is in every respect a rejection of negligence, since it does not occur without pure psychic attention. Now he teaches the characteristic nature of an appropriation which is (rightly) not rejected: III.23. An appropriation which is (really) not objectionable and is not desired by people who lack self-restraint, and which does not beget infatuation, etc., a shramana should accept, but sparingly. (223) That appropriation which is altogether unobjectionable, because it does not lead to bondage; which is not desired by people without self-restraint, because it is unusual except in the case of self-restraint; which does not beget infatuation, etc., because it takes place without an evolution such as attachment, is not rejected. Therefore an appropriation of a nature as described may be accepted, but no other, however small, having a nature different from that described. Page #385 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 359 Now he teaches that the real duty (dharma) is the main rule, and not the exception: III.24. "Why anything136 at all?" one should reason that when the slightest thought "even to his body?", 137 on the part of him who dsires no rebirth, is considered attachment-thus have the best of Jinas extolled inattention (towards the body) (nih-pratikarma). (224/1) Even in regard to the body,-so absolutely adopted and not an object of rejection, inasmuch as it is an auxiliary cause of the modification called the shramana-state,-the holy divine Arhats have extolled inattention, "Being other substance, this acquisition,138 far from deserving favour, is an object of indifference." Then in connection therewith why should one who has a taste for the realization of the perception of the truth of pure self admit the other, residual, miserable, not agreed, acquisitions? This is the evident intention (read akutam or akutih) of those (Arhats). Therefore it is determined that the "main rule" is the real Duty, and not the exception. The meaning here is that we must cling to the extreme nirgrantha condition; for it is the real Duty (vastudharma). Now he teaches which are the different exceptions: III.25. As instrumental on the path of the Jinas is mentioned the mark, i.e. the form as it is by birth; so also are prescribed the word of the guru, propriety of conduct (vinaya) and the study of the sutras. (225) Whatever not-rejected appropriation is here excepted is in all cases such as is instrumental, as rendering service by being an auxiliary cause of the modification called the shramana-state; but no other object. Different kinds thereof are: the material components of the body, which make up the external mark, inasmuch as they possess the native colour which corresponds with the natural colour, free form anything adventitious; the mental word-components of the saint's teaching in illuminating the truth concerning the self, when heard as pronounced by the gurus who are giving instruction at the time; the material sutra-components, being sounds which are means to scripture-knowledge, which, when studied, is perpetually instructive and able to illuminate the beginningless and endless truth of the pure self; Page #386 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 360 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES the material-components of the mind (chitta), which affect the modification in intuition and so on, revealing the truth of the pure self, and, in the so-modified person, the will for a disciplined condition. The purport here is that, like the body, even speech and mind are not the essence of reality (vastu-dharma). Now he teaches the procedure of maintaining the not-rejected appropriation which is confined to the body: III.26. A shramana is indifferent to this world (i.e has no desires in this world) and has no expectations in regard to the other [i.e. next world), is self-controlled in food and wandering (yukta-aharavihara)l"9 free from passions (kashaya). (226/1) Being free from passions, since his innate nature is completely separate from the ripening of all karmic matter, because evolved through the truth of uniform pure self without beginning or end; being indifferent to this world, since, although at the time still belonging to mankind, he stands far aloof from all human business; being without inclination for the other world, since he is empty of tonging (trshna) to experience future states, such as that of an immortal, etc., the shramana must be self-controlled in food and wandering, since he feeds and moves his body as a means for grasping the truth of the pure self, like a lamp filled and carried round as a means for perceiving an object to be examined. . The purport here is that, since he is free from passions, therefore he does not, through attachment to his present body or attachment to a heavenly body, live without self-control in respect of food and wandering, and he is self-controlled in food and wandering merely for the purpose of maintaining the modification, called the shramanastate, which leads to the comprehension of the truth of the pure self. Now he teaches that one who controls himself in food and wandering is (as good as) actually without food and wandering: III.27. He whose self is not-desirous of food, 140 is indeed austerity; and the shramanas who go and accept food, which is not the object of desire, are also considered abstainers from food. (2271 Since in essence he is abstinent from food (anashana) and since the alms are devoid of the fault of desire (eshana-dosha),141 the selfcontrolled in food is in verity actually foodless. Page #387 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 361 Thus, if a man is at all times conscious only of the self, which is exempt from the taking of any material sustenance, his innate nature is in itself foodless, inasmuch as it is void of all longing for food. This, namely, is his abstinence from food (anashana), his austerity; for the internal is of more importance (than the external). Those who with this in view realize a nature in itself without food and, in order to preclude that (food), live by such, other, alms as are free from fault of desire (eshana), are, although taking food, really not taking food and are really abstainers from food, since, by reason of their self-control in food, every inclination based on their innate nature or the nature of other substance is absent. Likewise, it is to be understood, although not stated, that he who is self-controlled in wandering, is really without wandering, since his innate nature is in itself without wandering and since his wandering is purified by religious observances (samiti). Now, in view of the question “how is self-control in food secured?,” he teaches: III.28. The shramana, possessing only a body and not attending !42 to that body, which he deems not his (i.e. has no sense of mineness in that), controls it by austerity, manifesting the energy (shakti) of his self. (228) Since a shramana, although possessing only a body,--for he does not forcibly reject the appropriation consisting of his mere body, an auxiliary means for the evolution called the shramana-state,—yet omits every care (samskara) for it having taken to heart the meaning of the Highest Lord explained in a former sutra, “Why anything?" and so forth (224-1), and, thinking that “this (body) is not mine; so it deserves not favour, but indifference,” pays no attention to it, for this reason, since he takes no improper food which would presuppose the notion of mine, control in diet may be duly his. And, since, manifesting the full energies of his self, he with every effort keeps that body controlled by asceticism, characterized by an innate mature free from food (anasana), as described in the last preceding sutra, for this reason, his diet being that of one actually engaged in yoga, as he is without the loss of yoga, which consists in the proceeding of taking the food (to himself], control in diet may be duly his. Now he teaches fully the characteristic nature of controlled or proper diet (yukta-ahara): Page #388 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 362 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES III.29. (The proper food consists of) a meal once a day; not filling the stomach; taken as given; collected by begging; in the day-time; without respect to taste; neither honey nor meat.143 (229/1) Food taken once a day is controlled (yukta) food, since so much suffices to sustain the body, which is an auxiliary means to the modification called the shramana-state. But food taken more than once is not controlled, since, being a habit due to attachment to the body, it is made into flagrant occasion for hurt; nor is it that of a selfcontrolled person, since it is habit due to attachment to the body. Only food which does not fill the stomach is controlled food, since only by this is self-control (yoga) 144 not violated. But food which satisfies the stomach is not controlled, since, as violating self-control, it is to a certain extent an occasion of hurt; nor is it that of a self-controlled person, since it violates self-control. Only food taken as given is controlled food, since only such food is free from attachment, characterized as a particular liking. But food not taken as given is not controlled, since, being a habit due to attachment, defined as a particular liking, it is made a flagrant occasion for hurt: nor is it that of a self-controlled person, since it is a habit due to attachment, characterized as a particular liking. Only food collected by begging is controlled food, since that only is independent of effort. But food not collected by begging is not controlled, since it is clearly an occasion of hurt, as presupposing an effort: nor is it that of a self-controlled person, since internal impurity is manifested by such a food habit. Only food eaten in the day-time is controlled food, since only then can it be properly inspected. But food which is taken not in the daytime is not controlled, since, not being properly inspected, it is an occasion of unavoidable hurt: nor is it that of a self-controlled person, since internal impurity is manifested by such a food habit. Only food without respect to taste is controlled food, since only this is graced with internal purity. But food which has respect to taste is not controlled, since in consequence of internal impurity it is made a flagrant occasion of hurt: nor is it that of a self-controlled person, since it is a habit of internal impurity. Only food not containing honey or meat is controlled food, since such food is no occasion of hurt. But food containing honey or meat is not controlled, since it is an occasion of hurt: nor is it that of a Page #389 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK II: THE CONDUCT 363 self-controlled person, since internal impurity is manifested by such a food habit. Here containing of honey and meat implies also (upalakshana) any (other) occasion of hurt: hence only food which is free from all occasion of hurt is controlled food. Now he teaches the proper adjustment of conduct, in which main rule (utsarga) and exception (apavada) harmonize: III.30. Boy or old man or tired or sick, let him follow a conduct appropriate to him in such a way that no fundamental negligence (mula-cheda) takes place. (230) The main rule is that even by a boy, an old man, one tired or sick a conduct very rigorous and appropriate to one who practises self-restraint must be maintained in such a way that (read na yatha syat) there is no neglect of self-restraint (samyama), which is fundamental importance as a means towards the reality of pure self. The exception is that by a boy, an old man, one tired or sick, a conduct mild and appropriate to a boy or an old man, one tired or sick, must be maintained in such a way that there is no neglect of the body, which is of fundamental importance as a means to the reality (tattva) of the pure self. The main rule as affected by the exception is that a boy, an old man, one tired or sick, while maintaining a conduct very rigorous and appropriate to one who practises self-restraint, in such a way that there is no neglect of self-restraint, which is of fundamental importance, as a means towards the reality of the pure self, should maintain a conduct mild and appropriate to a boy, an old man, one tired or sick, in such a way that there is no neglect of the body, which is of fundamental importance as a means towards the self-restraint which is a means to the reality of the pure self. The exception, as affected by the main rule, is that a boy, an old man, one tired or sick, while maintaining a conduct mild and appropriate to a boy, an old man, one tired or sick, in such a way that there is no neglect of the body, which is of fundamental importance as a means to self-restraint, which is a means towards the reality of the pure self, should maintain a conduct very rigorous and appropriate to one practising self-restraint, in such a way that there is no neglect of self-restraint, which is of fundamental importance as a means to the reality of the pure self. Thus, in any case, by harmonizing main rule and abrogative rule Page #390 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 364 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES a proper adjustment of conduct must be effected. Now he teaches a misadjustment of conduct through conflict (virodha) between main rule and exception: III.31. If a shramana with awareness of time and place, his tiredness (i.e. capacity for physical labour] forbearance and of upadhi [i.e. bodily condition), acts in regard to food and wandering, then he incurs a minor shortcoming (lepa).145 (231) Here the cause of exhaustion and sickness is fasting (upavasa); the upadhi is the body, the abode of youth and old age. Therefore the boy, the old man, the tired and sick are here brought in One who, though aware of place and time, proceeds in regard to food and wandering in accordance with his state of boyhood, old age, fatigue or sickness, does by acting on the line of mild conduct commit a minor shortcoming; therefore the main rule is preferable. He who, though aware of place and time, proceeds in regard to food and wandering in accordance with his state of boyhood, old age, fatigue or sickness, commits by acting on the line of full-grown (vrddha) conduct only a minor shortcoming; therefore the exception is preferable. He who, though aware of place and time, through fear of minor shortcoming does not proceed in regard to food and wandering in accordance with his state of boyhood, old age, fatigue or sickness and, by his adherence to very hard (atikarkasha) conduct, causes his body out of due course to fail (read patayatah), and then reaches heaven with his whole accumulation of the nectar of self-restraint lost, because his auserity has no opportunity, incurs an irreparable major shortcoming. For this reason the main rule, applied without regard to the exception, is far from superior. He who, though aware of place and time, in disregard of a minor short-coming proceeds arbitrarily in food and wandering out of regard for his state of boyhood, old age, fatigue or sickness, and by his adherence to mild conduct destroys his self-restraint, and becomes on a level with persons lacking self-restraint, because at the moment his austerity has no opportunity, incurs an irreparable major shortcoming. For this reason the exception, applied without regard to the main rule, is far from superior. Therefore in every way a misadjustment in conduct through clashing of the main rule and the exception must be rejected, and for Page #391 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 365 that purpose the syad-vada, 146 in its developed form with main rule and exception in mutual harmony, should be adhered to in every case. “Thus let the self-restrained person (yati), practising in accordance with the main rule and exception a conduct found beneficial by men of old times, who were full of special care, and gradually, after having proceeded through several distinct roles or stages, attaining a repose without compare, take his stand entirely upon his own substance, showing itself as a special and general form consciousness.” (PS Kalash 15). Here ends the discussion of CONDUCT Now begins the discussion of the path of liberation, otherwise called the state of the shramanas and characterized as mentalconcentration (eikagrya). Here he first sets to work upon the Scripture (agama), which is the chief means thereto: THE PATH OF LIBERATION (VERSES 232-244) III.32. He, who has reached mental concentration is shramana; mental concentration belongs to him who has certainty about objects: certainty arises from the Scriptures; therefore to be busy (chesta) with (the study of] the Scriptures is of primary importance. (232) Now the shramana can only be one who has mental-concentration: mental-concentration belongs to him only who has certainty about objects: and this certainty about objects comes only from the Scripture. Therefore occupation with the Scripture is the main thing, and there is no other way. For neither can objects be ascertained without the Scripture, since only this possesses an internal depth, wellfounded on a correct ascertainment of the whole multitude of objects, appearing with three characteristics147 in threefold time: nor could mental-concentration be attained without certainty concerning objects, since in one who had no certainty about objects there would be constant distraction, sometimes through excessive eagerness, when, confused in mind by the wish to ascertain, he wavers in all directions; sometimes through unrest, exploding every moment, when, enslaved by the desire to do something and seeking to create everything himself, he evolves through all kinds of occupations: sometimes through extreme capriciousness, when, filled with desire to enjoy and assuming everything to be for his enjoyment, he is in a mental-state stained with the faults (doshas) of attachment and aversion, and, involved in Page #392 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 366 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES duality by the division of things desirable and undesirable, changes his condition with every fresh object, so that, unable to arrive at certainty, he does not see the holy self without action or enjoyment, which, although exhausting everything simultaneously, is, as not being everything, one. Nor could the shramana-state be attained without mentalconcentration, since the shramana-state, which consists in applying oneself to the reality of pure self, cannot exist in one who, without mental-concentration, beholds that “surely a many is here," under the influence of such a presentation judges that “surely a many is here,” and, filled with this experience and always acting with a mind distracted by such mental distractions (vikalpa) about each thing that “surely a many is here,” in such a pitiable condition lacks mentalconcentration upon the reality of pure self, in the form of vision, knowledge and activity proceeding through evolution into enlightened (samyak) view, knowledge and conduct, which have for characteristic natures the presentation, the realization and the activity of the one self. Therefore, for the attainment of the shramana-state, otherwise called the path of liberation, one desirous of liberation must, in any case, be deeply versed in the Holy Word, explored by the venerable omniscient Arhat, with its distinctive banner of many-sidedness (allusion to the anekanta-vada = syad-vada). Now he proves that destruction of karmic matter, called liberation, is not possible for anyone lacking the understanding of the Scripture: III.33. A shramana who lacks the understanding of Scriptures knows not the self (or) 148 the other.” Not knowing the reality of things, how can he living on alms destroy the karmas? (233) Now without the Scripture there could not be knowledge of the “other” self (paratman) or knowledge of the highest self (paramatman). Neither could one devoid of the knowledge of the other self, or devoid of the knowledge of the highest self, destroy the objective or physical and subjective or psychic karma (dravya-bhava-karma) of infatuation, etc., or the karman which consists in the perversion of knowledge. To explain: One without Scripture,-who, in regard to this world, defiled with the pollution of great infatuation moving with the flow of the river of beginning and endless existences, has his discrimination inundated, as if he were drunk or insane, and who, though observing Page #393 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 367 with a not discriminative (avivikta) light of knowledge, has not in regard to substances such as the body, ascertained as the place of each particular self, or in regard to psychical states such as infatuation, attachment and aversion, commingled with his psychic-attention, his own experience (anubhava) of the self, based on the instruction of the Scripture, which gives certainty about the self and the other (sva and para at the beginning of the commentary),-could not attain the knowledge “this is the other, this is the self." Likewise also, one straining himself through having taken as object of knowledge the universe with its unfathomably deep nature—a mass of diverse modifications, manifested in the series of three timescould not, without his own experience of the self, based on the instruction of the Scripture, which gives certainty about this highest self, attain the knowledge of the one highest self, which has knowledge for nature. Likewise again, one lacking the knowledge of the other self, and of the highest self, who imagines an oneness with body, etc., originated by objective karman, and with the psychical states such as infatuation, attachment and aversion, based on the body, etc., is, through failure to discriminate between that which destroys and that which should be destroyed, unable to attain to destruction of objective and subjective karman of infatuation, etc. Likewise also-since without a basis in the highest self his worldlyexperience, whilst, revolving with uncontrollable revolution since ever there was samsara, evolves through ups and downs with every single thing, because it is based on the knowable,-he could not attain the destruction of the karmans which consist in the perversions of knowledge. Therefore those who are desirous of destroying karman must in any case study the Scripture. Now he teaches that the Scripture, alone is the eye of those who are on the path to liberation: III.34. The saint (sadhu) has the Scripture for eye; all creatures have their sense-organs for eyes; the Devas have eyes which see the remote (avadhi); but the liberated-souls (siddhas) have eyes which see in every respect. (234) Now only the venerable liberated souls, because they consist of pure knowledge, have eyes which see everywhere. All other beings, Page #394 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 368 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES because their perception is bound to corporeal (murta) substances, have sense-organs for eyes. The Devas, because they apprehend corporeal substances characterized by fineness (sukshamatva), have eyes which see the remote; and so they too, because, seeing only coloured substance, they are not distinguished from beings with sense-organs as eyes, have sense-organs for eyes. So then for all these beings moving in samsara and being themselves on the knowable, because they are maimed by infatuation, there could be no possession of eyes seeing everywhere, which is obtainable by realization of the reality of pure self, whereupon depends the basing one's self on knowledge. So, in order to obtain this, the venerable shramans take the Scripture for eye; and, although, by reason of the mutual blending of the knowable and the knowledge, discrimination between them is impossible, yet, having effected a separation of the self and the other, they break through the great infatuation, and, having reached the highest self, they stand based on knowledge. Therefore those desirous of liberation should see everything with the eye of the Scripture. Now he explains how with the eye of the Scripture everything is seen: III.35. All objects together with their various qualities and modifications are established [known] by the Scripture; seeing [i.e. comprehending) by Scripture, the shramanas know them all. (235) Now through the Scripture all substances are trustworthily known (pramiyante); for all the substances are free from contradiction by any argumentation. And they are known as characterized (vishishta) by their various qualities and modifications; for the Scripture, as it consists of the many-sided-view (anekanta), which penetrates the several properties simultaneously or successively arising, can possess the character of a trustworthy means of knowledge. Therefore, all objects are established by the Scripture. And, evolving by way of becoming the psychic-attention of study-knowledge (shruta-jnana), which consists in the many-sided-view (anekanta), pervading all substance, characterized by their various qualities and modifications, they become of themselves knowable to the shramanas. Therefore to those who have the eye of Scripture nothing can be imperceptible. Now he shows that the road to liberation is nothing but the simultaneity of Scripture-knowledge, the consequent conviction Page #395 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 369 (shraddhan) in the principles or reality of things (tattva) and categories (artha) and the self-restraint resulting from both of them: III.36. He, who does not view reality of things, preceded by knowledge of Scripture, has not self-restraint; thus says the sutra. Without self-restraint how can one be a shramana? (236) To one who is destitute of conviction, preceded by Scripture(knowledge), which has the quodammodo-theory (syad-vada) for emblem, and characterized as conviction in the principles and categories; who, because he does not possess discrimination between self and other, is assured of identity with the passions (kashaya) and the body; who in consequence of not restraining his longing for senseobjects is a destroyer of the six kinds of soul-bodies; who, because he is without quietism (nivrtti) in any direction, is active (pravrtti) in every direction; also because he does not possess the knowledge of the highest-self nor is engaged in mental-concentration on the truth of self, which has the form of knowledge, whereas his worldly-opining (inapti) invades without barrier (nir-argala) the circle of the knowableto such a one even self-restraint is unattainable. And for one who has not attained self-restraint there can be no shramana-state, otherwise called the path of liberation, whereof the nature is a convinced mental-concentration. Hence the path of liberation can be nothing but a simultaneity of Scripture-knowledge, conviction in the principles and categories and self-restraint. Now he dispels (the idea) that non-simultaneity of Scriptureknowledge, of conviction in the principles and categories and of selfrestraint could be the path of liberation: III.37. One does not attain liberation by means of Scriptureknowledge, if he is not convinced of the nature of reality of things (arthas); and one convinced of the nature of reality of things also does not attain liberation (nirvana) if he is lacking self-restraint. (237) One does not attain perfection through knowledge produced by Scriptures, but destitute of faith (i.e. conviction with regard to the nature of reality of things]; or through faith combined with that knowledge, but devoid of self-restraint. To explain: If a man, although clearly, with the help of the Scripture, reasoning out all the categories, yet does not understand (pratyeti) the self, which is one clear appearance-form (akara) of knowledge, combined with the appearance-form of the knowable in Page #396 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 370 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES all the categories, then, not experiencing (un-anubhavan) the self as described, because he is devoid of faith in the self as described, how can he immersed as he is in the knowable and infatuated as to knowledge, become a knower? and for one who does not know what can the Scripture, though illumining the knowable, effect? Therefore through Scripture-knowledge, void of faith, there is no attainment. Moreover, if a man, although believing in the self and experiencing it as one clear appearance-form combined with the appearance-form of the knowable in all the categories, does not live with it restrained within itself, then, because in his very self there abides a state of consciousness which capriciously moves to and fro between the substances owing to beginningless latent impressions (vasana) of infatuation, attachment and aversion, and because there does not exist in him a state of consciousness which is consolidated in this one truth (principle, tattva), free from latent impressions and agitation, how can lie be self-restrained? And for one without self-restraint what can belief, which consists in apprehension (pratiti) of the truth (reality) of the self as described, or knowledge, which consists in experiencing (anubhuti) of the reality of the self as described, have any effect? Therefore from belief or knowledge, devoid of self-restraint, there is no attainment of liberation; hence (the idea] that non-simultaneity of Scripture-knowledge, conviction in the principles and categories, and self-restraint could be the path of liberation is refuted. Now he makes clear that, even with simultaneity of Scriptureknowledge, conviction in the principles and categories, and selfrestraints, the most effective means towards the path of liberation is knowledge of the self: III.38. That karman which one without knowledge destroys in hundreds of thousands of crores of existences (lives), a knower (jnani) possessing threefold restraint (gupti) (of mind, speech and body] destroys in a mere breath. (238) That karman which, as it ripens in a series of stages, beginning with the manifoldness of childish pains, the man without knowledge, — evolving through the transitory psychical states of pleasure, pain, etc., in consequence of his acceptance of attachment and aversion,—with difficulty escapes in hundreds of thousands of crores of existences, because it again repairs its continuity, that karman, brought to ripeness by a vigorous effort-because, possessing the quality of a knower, Page #397 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 371 characterized by experience of the self's pure knowledge nature, obtained by the exceeding benefit of a simultaneity of (1) Scriptureknowledge, having for emblem the quodammodo-theory (syadvada), (2) conviction in the principles and categories (tattvartha shraddham), and (3) self-restraint, he possesses the three restraints, which function in refraining from (uparama) bodily, vocal and mental karman,-he who by repelling attachment and aversion has cast far away all weakness such as pleasure, pain and so forth, easily in the space of a mere breath brings to nought without renewal of its continuity. Therefore we must agree that knowledge of the self, given a simultaneity of Scriptureknowledge, faith in the principles and categories, and self-restraint (read samyatatvanam), is the most effective means to the path of liberation. Now he teaches that for one who lacks knowledge of the self simultaneity of the knowledge of the complete Scriptures, faith in the principles and categories, and self-restraint is ineffective: III.39. But, if anyone has delusion (murcha) [i.e. attachment or mental clinging) in regard to the body, etc., even to the extent of an ultimate atom, he does not attain perfection (siddhi), though knowing the Scriptures completely. (239/1) If anyone, because the whole substance of the Scripture is to him a myrobalan in the hand, knows the self, which knows the whole mass of substances, characterized by their appropriate modifications and in their past, present and future existences, has faith and practises self-restraint, yet at some time, despite a simultaneity of Scriptureknowledge, faith in the principles and categories and self-restraint, - in consequence of being slightly defiled with infatuation,-does not make his self evolve in an uninfected psychic-attention (because infected by delusion of body and so on) and so experience the self as having knowledge for self, he does not reach perfection (sidhyati), since he is not released from karmic matter, which is pinned down, as it were, by a pin, by even that spot of impurity of infatuation. Therefore even a simultaneity of Scripture-knowledge, faith in the principles and categories and self-restraint, when destitute of knowledge of the self, is ineffective. Now he establishes a simultaneity of self-knowledge with simultaneity of Scripture-knowledge, faith in principles and categories, and self-restraint: Page #398 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 372 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES III.40. That shramana who practises the five self-regulations (samiti) and the three restraints gupti), controls his five senses, has conquered the passions (kashaya) and is fully endowed with intuition and knowledge, is called self-restrained. (240) He who through Scripture-knowledge, which has the many-sidedview as emblem, believes in the self and experiences the self as having its one clear appearance-form (akara) of knowledge combined with appearance-forms of the knowable in all the categories; who wishes to abide always in the self alone; who has made the vessel of the body a means of self-restraint carried out by a positive-behaviour (pravrtti) controlled by the fivefold set of samitis, who has gradually allayed (samuparata) (referring to the guptis) the activity (vyapara) of body, voice and mind by keeping the five senses controlled and checked; who has ascertained that the cause which makes the activity (urtti) of consciousness hover over strange substances is--although become entirely one with the self, in consequence of mutual penetration, different from it by distinction in innate nature; and who, by himself, like a skilful wrestler, tightly squeezing and squeezing the group of the passions, makes them give up life, that man, being also void of all “other” substances, is patently self-restrained, because the activity (urtti) of his consciousness is eternally unaffected owing to the ascertainment of the reality (tattva) of self, which in innate nature is simply pure conviction (drshi) (drashti] and knowledge (jnapti). In him alone is attained a simultaneity of self-knowledge with a simultaneity of Scripture-knowledge, faith in the principles and categories, and self-restraint: Now he teaches what is the characteristic of one who has become self-controlled through a simultaneity of self-knowledge with a simultaneity of Scripture-knowledge, conviction in the principles and categories and self-restraint: III.41. Considering the groups of enemies and friends as the same, pleasure and pain as the same, praise and blame as the same, clay and gold as the same, the shramana,149 moreover, considers life and death as the same. (241) Self-restraint (samyama) is conduct accompanied by enlightened (samyak) intuition and knowledge. Conduct is dharma; dharma is equanimity; equanimity is a state-of-evolution of the self devoid of infatuation (moha) and perturbation or mental agitation (kshobha). Page #399 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 373 Therefore equanimity is a characteristic of the self-restrained. So in regard to the two groups, enemies and friends, pleasure and pain, praise and blame, clay and gold, life and death, he is the same (samah). Whoso,-being free from the infatuation, “this one is strange to me, this one belongs to me; this is a joy, this is a torment; this is an elevation to me, this is a humiliation; this man is useless to me and this thing is helpful; this means a maintaining of myself, and that is a complete destruction”– has not in regard to anything the duality of attachment and aversion; who continually experiences the self as having for nature pure faith and knowledge; who, having comprehended enemies and friends, pleasure and pain, praise and blame, clay and gold, life and death indistinguishably, merely as knowables, constantly abides in the self, which has knowledge for self, truly possesses equanimity in every regard. That equanimity must be designated as a characteristic of him who is self-restrained, who has brought to perfection a simultaneity of selfknowledge with a simultaneity of Scripture-knowledge, conviction in the principles and categories and self-restraint. Now he shows this self-restraint having a simultaneity of selfknowledge with a simultaneity of Scripture-knowledge, conviction in the principles and categories, and self-restraini to be identical with the path of liberation, otherwise called the shramana-state, characterized as mental-concentration: 111.42. He who is intent on the triad, world-view, knowledge and conduct together, is held to be in a state of mental-concentration; his shramana-hood is complete. (242) When (1) through the modification of enlightened vision (samyagdarshan), characterized as comprehension (pratiti) of the principles (tattva) of knowable and knower as it is (read jneya-jnatr-tattva-tathapratiti-lakshanena), (2) through the modification of knowledge, characterized as experience (anubhuti) of the principles of knowable and knower as it is, (3) through the modification of conduct, characterized as abiding in the truth of seer and knower, which is effected by abstinence from any other action on the part of the knowable and the knower,-through these three modifications simultaneously the self,–by reason of intense mutual-interpenetration, manifested in a relation of thing enjoyed (bhavya) and enjoyer Page #400 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 374 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES (bhavaka)-evolves through a part and whole relation and possesses a state of self-restraint together with a repose in itself; then, although there is an experiencing of a one consisting of a many,-as in the case of panak (a drink mixture),–we must, by reason of the rejection of all other substances, recognize the path of liberation, otherwise called shramana-hood, characterized as mental-concentration. According to the external, other-referential (practical, Faddegon) point of view (vyavahara-naya), which, since it involves differentiation (bheda), considers chiefly the modes, the statement is that “enlightened view, knowledge, and conduct are the path of liberation.” According to the internal, self-referential (theoretical, Faddegon] point of view (nishchaya-naya), which, since it consists in an identity (abheda), considers chiefly the substance, it is that “mentalconcentration is the path of liberation." According to trustworthy proof (pramana) it is that “both are so," since everything consists in difference and identity. “Thus that path of liberation, which, according to the attitude of the conceiver, becomes plural, though one, and so exhibits triple characterization and again oneness,-that path, stable, with existence dependent upon the purport of seer and knower (drashtr-jnatr), let men take by storm, in order that they may shortly storm an incomparable splendour of flashing thought.” (PS Kalash 16) Now he refutes this idea that non-mental-concentration is the path of liberation: III.43. If a shramana, being ignorant about the nature of reality of things, is infatuated through addiction to the “other” substance, and feels attachment or aversion, then he is bound with various karmas. (243) Whoso does not with simple concentration (ekam agram) realize the self, which has knowledge for self, necessarily addicts himself to the “other” substance, that is, the knowable. And, being addicted thereto and fallen away from the knowledge of the self, which has knowledge for self, he is himself without knowledge and either becomes infatuate or feels attachment or aversion; and, being so, he becomes bound and not released. Therefore, non-mental-concentration could not be the path of liberation. Now determining that mental-concentration is the path of liberation, he summarizes: Page #401 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 375 III.44. If a shramana is not infatuated with reference to objects, and does not feel attachment, nor is subject to aversion (dvesham), then inevitably he destroys the various karmas. (244) Whoso with single concentration realizes the self, which has knowledge for self, does not addict himself to the other” substance, that is, the knowable. Not being addicted thereto, not fallen away from the knowledge of the self, which has knowledge for self, he stands fast himself as knowledge, and neither is infatuated, nor feels attachment or aversion; and, being so, he becomes released and not bound. Therefore it may be proved that only mental-concentration is the path of liberation. Thus ends the exposition of the THE PATH OF LIBERATION. Now begins the exposition of good pyshcic attention. Here it is stated that those who possess good psychic attention are also shramanas: GOOD (SHUBHA) PSYCHIC ATTENTION (VERSES 245-270) III.45. In the Jain scriptures (samaye), shramanas are those endowed with pure psychic-attention and with good psychic attention. Amongst them, those with pure psychic-attention are free from karmic inflow (asrava); the others are subject to karmic inflow. (245) Those who, though pledged to shramana-hood, are, through survival of a small portion of the passions, unable to ascend to the stage of pure psychic-attention, consisting in an actualization (urtti) of the principle of the self, which has for nature quite pure convictions (drshi) and understanding (jnapti), both active (pravrtta) in renunciation (nivrtti) of all “other” substance—would they, being in the proximity or neighbourhood (upakantha) thereof, with their energies blunted (kunthikrta) by the passions and with their internal organ excessively full of longings (utkanthula), be shramanas or not? As to this a statement is given. In the first place, good psychic-attention may coinhere with righteousness (dharma), since we have had (PS 11) the description “self evolved through righteousness.” Therefore, those who possess good psychic-attention would, by reason of the existence of righteousness in them, be shramanas. But they are not on a level (sama-kastha) with chose who possess pure psychic-attention, since those who possess pure psychic-attention, Page #402 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 376 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES having thrown off all passions, are without karmic inflow. The others on the contrary, having a particte of passion undispersed, are subject to inflow. For this very reason they may not be coordinated with the possessors of pure psychic-attention, but are also considered as shraman. Now he sets forth the definition of a shramana with good psychicattention: III.46. If in the conduct of a shramana there is found devotion to Arhats, etc. and disinterested affection (vatsalya) for all who have applied themselves to the sacred writings (pravachana), then that conduct is said to be of good psychic-attention. (246) He who, given the state of shramana, which consists in abandonment (sanyasa) of every attachment, is himself, through the influence of a particle of passion, unable to abide exclusively in the actualization of the pure self, yet is inspired by devotion and love for others, Arhats, etc. abiding exclusively in the actualization of the pure self, who, having applied themselves to the sacred writings, expound the exclusive abiding in the actualization of the pure self, would,inasmuch as his actualization of the pure self is only so far commingled with activity towards the “other” substance, stimulated by a slight attachment,-exhibit a conduct of good psychic-attention. Therefore the characteristic of shramana of good psychic-attention is a conduct conjoined with affection (anuraga) for the pure self. Now he exhibits the action of shramanas having good psychicattention: III.47. Respectful behaviour to shramanas, by rising in welcome and attendance upon them (when they go), combined with reverence (vandana) and homage (namaskara) and the removal of their fatigue, are not censurable in a conduct of affection. (247) On the part of the persons of good psychic-attention, their conduct being conjoined with affection for the pure self, the proceeding of respectful behaviour, i.e. praise, homage, rising in welcome and attendance upon departure, towards shramanas, who have reached the actualization of the pure self, and the proceeding of removing their fatigue, with the aim of conserving the actualization of the pure self, would not be a fault. Now he demonstrates that actions of this kind are proper only for those persons who apply themselves to good psychic-attention: Page #403 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 377 III.48. Instruction in vision and knowledge, receiving pupils and rearing of them and instruction in the worship of the best of Jinas are the conduct of those who have attachment [i.e. those with good psychic-attention]. (248) The proceeding of instructing in intuition and knowledge, which proceeding implies a wish to show kindness, the proceeding of receiving pupils and the proceeding of rearing them and the proceeding of instructing them in the worship of the best of Jinas are only for those who have good psychic-attention, and not for those who have pure psychic-attention. Now he determines that all (such) proceedings belong only to those who have good psychic-attention: III.49. Whoso constantly renders help to the fourfold150 community (sangha) of shramanas without doing hurt to (living) bodies is eminent among those who possess affection (of good psychicattention). (249) Any proceeding in assistance of the fourfold community of shramanas, with the purpose of conserving their actualization of the pure self, and unaccompanied by doing hurt to the six (kinds of living) bodies, --seeing that there is a pledge of self-restraint (samyama),—is merely for those who have good psychic-attention, since it is mainly inspired by attachment, and never for those who have pure psychicattention. Now he forbids interference of active-behaviour with self-restraint: III.50. If in an effort to render service and help with humility and respect (to sadhus, vaiyavrtya) he does hurt to [living] bodies, then he is not a shramana, but a householder (agarin): that should be the duty (dharma) of lay-followers (shravaka). (250) Whoso, by his activity in administering with a view to conserving the actualization of the pure self, injures his own self-restraint, falls away from the shramana-state, inasmuch as he enters upon the duty of the householder (grahstha). Therefore every activity whatever must in any case be performed without detriment to self-restraint, since even in case of active behaviour the object is self-restraint. Now he exhibits a distinction in active behaviour according to its object (vishaya): III.51. Even though there should result a small stain, yet a layman or an ascetic, who are the followers of Jina, should through Page #404 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 378 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES compassion render disinterested aid (nirvekkham in Pk. or nirpeksha in Sk.) [i.e. without any consideration or expectation of any kind) to all. (251) An activity characterized as rendering aid to others and due to compassion-in the case of the followers of Jina whose minds are purified by unalloyed kindness and who, inasmuch as their activity is directed toward pure knowledge and conviction, follow a stricter or freer line of life-is, even if bringing a small stain, unforbidden, inasmuch as it has regard to nothing but the attainment of the pure self. But activity is not forbidden under every circumstance and in every respect, on the ground of bringing (only) a small stain; for then there is nothing to prove that through such activity there is a conserving of another's and one's own actualization of the pure self. Now he exhibits a distinction in active behaviour according to time: III.52. Having seen a shramana overcome by disease, hunger, thirst or exhaustion, a sadhu (noble person) should render service and help with all his power. (252) When to a shramana who has reached the actualization of the pure self there befalls some trouble which might cause the loss thereof, that is the time for the person of good psychic-attention to endeavour (pravratti) to counteract with all his power. But any other time is merely one for desisting (nivratti) from such activity with a view to his own attainment of the actualization of the pure self. Now he exhibits a distinction, with its occasion, in the active behaviour of discourse with people of the world (read pravrtteh sanhmitta): III.53. Neither may one, in the case of (persons who apply themselves to) good psychic-attention, blame discourse with worldly people, if with a view to render service and help (vaiyavrtya) to infirm, venerable (guru), young or old shramanas. (253) Discourse with people devoid of the actualization of the pure self is approved, if it is exclusively with the purpose of ministering to infirm, venerable, young or old shramanas who have reached the actualization of the pure-self; but not with another purpose. Now he exhibits a distinction in good psychic-attention, as secondary (gauna) and primary (mukhya): III.54. This conduct or activity of excellent attachment (prashasta raga) is observed by shramanas, while it is said to be primary for Page #405 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 379 lay-followers (grahstha); by this highest happiness is (gradually) attained (by lay followers). (254) Thus has been described good psychic-attention, having the form of excellent conduct on the part of persons possessing inclination (anuraga) towards the pure self. Taking place by reason of the existence of a small amount of passion in those who have chosen complete abstention (virati) which reveals the pure self, this on the part of shramanas is secondary, because it is accompanied by attachment, which is repugnant to the actualization of the pure self. But on the part of lay-followers, although it takes place in consequence of the existence of attachment,-inasmuch as, through lack of complete abstinence, they are without revelation of the pure self (read shuddhatmano'nubhavat, in agreement with the simile arkatejasa iva),-it is primary, since, like fuel experiencing the sun's heat through the intermediacy of the crystal, they experience the pure self in conjunction with attachment; and it gradually (kramtah) brings about the highest happiness of nirvana. Now he proves that according to variant occasions (karanavaiparitya) good psychic-attention has variant effects (phalavaiparitya): III.55. Excellent attachment brings variant fruits according to the particularity of its objects (vastu); as, at the time of harvest, do germs (seeds) fallen in different kinds of soil. (255) Just as from similar germs (seeds) there is variance of produce due to variance of soil, so from similar psychic-attention, characterized as excellent attachment, there is variance of fruit, due to variance of receptacle (patra),131 since different occasions lead to different effects. Now he exemplifies the variance (vaiparitya) in occasions and variance in results: III.56. One who finds satisfaction (rati) in vows (vrata), observances (niyama), study (adhyayana), contemplation (dhyana) and liberality or charity (dana) with reference to objects (objective deeds, vastu) ordained for those who have not yet reached enlightened wisdom (chadmastha) does not obtain liberation from rebirth; he obtains a state characterized by pleasure (sata). (256) The results of good psychic-attention, applied to objects set forth by the Enlightened Lord, is attainment of liberation from rebirth, preceded by accumulation of merit. -- Page #406 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 380 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES There is, however, a difference in the result, due to variance of occasion. Here the variance of occasion is the objects set forth by those who have not yet reached enlightened wisdom. As regards these, the variant result of good psychic-attention applied to satisfaction with vows, observances, study, contemplation and liberality is the attainment of mere "outcast” (apasada) merit, without liberation from rebirth; it is the state of a high Deva or man. He explains in full the variance of occasion and the variance of result: III.57. Service, kindness or charity, bestowed on persons who do not know the transcendental (paramartha) nature of reality and in whom indulgence in sense objects and passions predominate, result (in a rebirth) among low levels of gods (devas) or men. (257) The objects set forth by persons who have not yet reached enlightened knowledge being the variance of occasion, and the persons being those who do not know the highest aim and exceed in passion for sense objects,-inasmuch as they are devoid of clear discrimination of the pure self and have not attained actualization of the pure self,– the attainment of mere "outcast" merit by service, help or gift to these, inspired by good psychic-attention, is the variance of fruit; it is rebirth among low Devas and men. Now he enforces the belief that from a variance (vaiparitya) of occasion a non-variant fruit does not arise: III.58. Since indulgence in sense objects and passions are said in the sacred texts to be sin, how should men addicted thereto become saviours [i.e. be able to liberate themselves and help others to liberate themselves from the mundane existence, i.e. samsara)? (258) Now passions for sense objects are sin; the men also who have them are sinful; those also who are fond of such men become sinful, inasmuch as they have affection for sinners. Therefore, having passions for sense objects and depending upon the merits of those who are attached to them, how can they be fit to save others from samsara? Therefore from them a non-variant fruit could not arise. Now he proves that an occasion which gives rise to a non-variant result is non-variant: III.59. A man in whom there is cessation from sin, who possesses equanimity towards all righteous (dharmika) persons and strives for Page #407 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 381 the totality of meritorious qualities has entitlement for following the right path (for guna-samididovasevi probably one should read gunasamidadovasevi). (259) The shramana who, through cessation from sin, neutrality (madhyastha) towards all righteous persons, and striving for the totality of meritorious qualities, has for portion the right path, consisting in mental-concentration, which results from evolution through a simultaneity of enlightened view, knowledge and conduct, must, since he is an abode of liberation and merit, be regraded as a non-variant occasion bringing about a non-variant result (read aviparita-phalakaranam). Now he expounds a non-variant occasion which gives rise to a non-variant result: III.60. Those who are devoid of evil psychic-attention and have pure psychic-attention or good psychic-attention are saviours of men: he who is devoted to them, receives what is excellent (merit). (260) Shramanas, characterized as above, who through annihilation of infatuation, aversion and disapproved (aprashasta) attachment, are free from evil psychic-attention-being sometimes, through stoppage of every arising of passions (kashaya), possessed of pure psychic-attention and, sometimes, through ripening of excellent attachment, possessed of good psychic-attention, are, through being themselves abodes of liberation, saviours of men; and others who manifest excellent feelings of devotion to them become partakers of merits. Now in a pair of sutras, he indicates that the practice of reverence towards the non-variant occasion, which occasions a non-variant fruit, should be carried out in general and particular: III.61. Having perceived a fit object (vastu) as described (say venerable saints), one should proceed with acts such as rising in welcome: then according to qualities distinction should be made this is the teaching. (261) With reference to a fit-object (vastu), such as we have described as a cause of purification of the self, it is not forbidden to shramanas to introduce an intensification of quality into their activity in action agreeable thereto. III.62. Rising in welcome, hospitable reception, reverence, nourishing, respectful attention, folding of hands and prostration are said to be due in this life to superiors in meritorious qualities. (262) Page #408 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 382 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Such forms of behaviour as rising in welcome, hospitable reception, reverence, nourishing, respectful attention, folding of hands and prostration, when shown to shramanas who in meritorious qualities are superior to oneself, are not prohibited. Now he probihits all forms of (such) behaviour towards pseudoshramanas (shramanabhasa): III.63. (Only) shramanas skilled in the interpretation of the sutras and rich in self-control, austerities and knowledge, should be honoured by (other) shramanas with rising in welcome, reverence and prostration. (263) Only in the case of shramanas possessing self-control, austerities, and knowledge of their own essence, inspired by familiarity with the sutras and their meaning, are proceedings such as rising in welcome unforbidden. In the case of others, pseudo-shramanas, they are forbidden. Now he teaches what sort of person is a pseudo-shramana: II.64. Although endowed with self-control, austerities and knowledge of the sutras, if one is not convinced of the (nine) categories (arthas) taught by the Jina, primarily the self, he is considered to be no shramana. (264) Though knowing the sacred tradition, self-controlled and persistent in austerities, one who does not believe in the teaching of the Jina, which is full of categories not other (than he proclaimed), is entire, and,-inasmuch as by one's own self as knowable (everything) is exhausted-contains the self as its most important constituent, is a pseudo-shramana. Now he shows that want of respect towards an equal (sama) 152 in shramana-hood leads to utter ruin: III.65. He who on seeing a shramana abiding by the injunctions of the scripture reviles him from hatred and does not show respect to him in actions is a man of ruined conduct. (265) The conduct of a man who from hatred reviles a shramana faithful to the doctrine and in actions does not show respect to him is ruined, consequence of being infected with the passion of hatred. in Now he shows how utter ruin befalls the man who treats his superior in shramana-hood as an inferior: III.66. If one inferior in merits expects reverence from another who is superior in merits, thinking "I am also a shramana," he Page #409 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 383 wanders for ever in samsara. (266) If one who himself possesses lower qualities, thinking from pride “I also am a shramana,” expects reverence from others who are superior in merit, then, may be, owing to pride in his shramana-hood he wanders for ever in samsara. Now he shows that utter ruin befalls the man superior in shramanahood who treats his inferior as an equal: III.67 If the superior in merits as regards shramana-hood show in their actions (respect) to those inferior in merits, they are imbued with delusion and debased conduct. (267) Those who, themselves superior in merits, show in their actions (respect) to others inferior in merits, fall from (right) conduct, are perverted through infatuation. . Now he shows that association with those who are not good (asat) is forbidden: III.68. If a man who possesses sure knowledge of the words and meanings of the sutras, whose passions are subsided (read shamita in the Sanskrit paraphrase) and who excels in austerities does not give up company with worldly people, then he is not self-controlled (samyata). (268/1) Seeing that even one exceedingly self-controlled through possessing (1) a sure (nishchita) knowledge of the words and meanings of the sutras-through the method of internal, self-referential point of view (strict-examination, Faddegon) (nishchaya-naya) applied to (a) the complete Holy Word, having the existent for characteristic and expounding the world-totality (vishva), and (b) its complete import, having the existent for characteristic, and (c) the whole knowing reality, having the existent for characteristic and simultaneously pervading as the basis the knowable forms of both, and (2) the quelling of his passions through his psychic-attention being free from inclination and (3) superiority in austerities because of motionless psychic-attention repeatedly practised, would through attachment to worldly people lose self-control, like water in contact with the god-ofseven-rays (fire),-some change is unavoidable, therefore attachment to such people is in any case to be prohibited. Now he adds a definition of worldly people: III.69. If one who has left the world for the state-without-bonds (nirgrantha) still engages in mundane concerns, he is called a worldly Page #410 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 384 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES man, though equipped with self-control and austerities. (269) Even one who through professed entrance into the sublime statewithout-bonds (nairgranthya) has borne a great weight of self-control and austerities, if through gross infatuation he becomes slack in the business of pure thought and, tossed to and fro by human affairs, does not abstain from mundane acts, is called a worldly man. Now he shows that association with good (sat) people should be practised: III.70. Therefore, [in this state-without-bonds 153] a shramana should always dwell with a shramana who is either equal in merit or superior in merits, if he wishes liberation from misery. (270) Since, as it is the nature of the self to evolve, even a self-controlled man does lose his self-control by associating with worldly people, — some changes being unavoidable, as in the case of water in contact with fire, therefore a shramana who seeks liberation from misery should always dwell with another shramana equal or superior in merits. Thus by association with one of equal merits he preserves his merit, like cold water placed in the corner of a cold room, and by association with one superior in merits (read gunadhika-sangat instead of gunasamgat) he increases his merit, like cold water mixed with still colder snow and hail. “Thus let the monk (yati) who first has recourse to an active behaviour (pravrtti) based on good psychic-attention, and gradually (kramatah) by his facility in proper self-control advances to complete abstinence (nivrtti), experience an absolutely everlasting state, consisting in knowledge and bliss and bringing the delight of having easily mastered the (reality of the) whole outspread mass of things." (PS Kalash 17) Here ends the exposition of GOOD PSYCHIC-ATTENTION. Now (the five gathas called) the Five Jewels (pancharatna): "Crest-ornament of this book, illuminating briefly in every part the doctrine of the Holy Arhat in its unique way, expounding (read vyakurvaj) the states of samsara and liberation, with their divergent paths, may the flawless Five Jewels be now triumphant with these [last] five sutras (gathas).” (PS Kalash 18) Now he reveals the Reality of Transmigration-Principle (Samsaratattva): Page #411 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 385 THE FIVE JEWELS (VERSES 271-275) III.71. Those who in (comprehending) the scripture grasp the reality of things not as they are, being convinced (in their mistaken way) that "so and so are reality," wander through all later time (in the transmigratory existence), which brings them an endless fullness of karmic fruit. (271) Those who, from their own lack of discrimination, conceive objects wrongly and, forming for themselves the conviction "thus is the truth," are for ever ignorant,-inasmuch as their minds are soiled with the continually accumulating dirt of great infatuation-these, although adhering to the doctrine, are only pseudo-shramana, because they have not attained to shramana-hood in the real sense; and with mental-moods (vrtti) unsettled by their gyrations through other births during an infinite time, terrible through its huge mountain of enjoyment of endless karmic fruit, they are to be understood as the transmigrationTruth (tattva). Now he reveals the Reality of Liberation-Principle (Moksha-tattva): III.72. He who is free from improper (a-yatha) conduct, who has convictions concerning nature of the reality of things (padartha) as they are (yatha), whose self is in repose (nishchitah prashantatma), and whose shramana-hood is consummated, does not live long in this unfruitful (a-phale) here [in this transmigratory existence]. (272) He whose self, through habituation to the light of the lamp of spotless discrimination, which is, as it were, the crest jewel of the three worlds, is in constant repose (upashanta) and in its own being unmoved by longing,-which is at rest by his ascertained-knowledge of the categories as they are-and who, always acting with reference to his one characteristic-nature, is free from improper conduct and always a knower, is indeed a shramana of consummate shramana-hood; no more essaying the pitiable condition of an animate creature,inasmuch as the fruit of all previous karman has been easily brushed aside and no fresh fruit of karman is brought to development,-and with his mental-mood, through absence of any transition to a second state, established in its pure innate nature, is to be understood as the Liberation-Truth. Now he reveals the Principle/Reality of the Means of the Liberation [moksha-tattva-sadhana-tattva]: III.73. Those who properly understand the reality of things or Page #412 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 386 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES the categories, who have given up external and internal appropriation (upadhi), and who are not attached to sense-objects, are designated pure (suddha). (273) Those venerable men who are passionately fond of learning in regard to the true characteristic nature of the complete principles (tattva) of knower and knowable, considered according to the manysided doctrine (anekanta-kalita); whose self-principle (atma-tattva) possesses a characteristic nature distinguished by a thoughtfulness of unlimited energy welling up within, and purified of adherence to any external or internal attachment;-and who,-inasmuch as the mood of their internal-principle (antas-tattva) is safeguarded (gupta), as if in deep sleep, by its characteristic nature,-experience no attachment whatever to objects,-these venerable men, possessing all forms of greatness (anubhava) and being pure, manifesting heroism by the bold determination wherewith they break open the huge portals of karman, closed throughout the [beginningless) samsara, should be understood as the reality of the means of the Liberation-Truth. Now he extols the Principle/Reality of the Means of the LiberationTruth as the centre of all desires (sarva-manoratha-sthana): III.74. To the pure, it is said, belongs shramana-hood; to the pure belong intuition and knowledge; the pure attains liberation (nirvana); He alone is a perfect soul (siddha). Homage to him! (274) Shramana-hood, which is the manifest road to liberation and is characterized as mental-concentration occupied with a simultaneity of enlightened view (samyag-darshan), knowledge and conduct, belongs to the pure alone. Conviction and knowledge, which consist in the perceiving and conceiving of all generalities (samanya) and particularities (vishesha), i.e. the infinite constancies of things commingled with all their past, present and future divergencies, belong to the pure alone. Nirvana, whose divine innate nature is stamped with inborn knowledge and bliss, revealing themselves without hindrance (read nihpratigha-vijrmbhita, with insertion of the syllable gha), belongs to the pure alone. The venerable perfect one, deep through acquisition of the nature of the self, which self abides peacefully as if chiselled in its condition of the highest bliss, is alone pure. Enough of expatiation! To the pure Truth of the means to the Page #413 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BOOK III: THE CONDUCT 387 Liberation-Truth, to that centre of all desires, be paid sincere homage, wherefrom all separation of self and other has disappeared, because the relation between worshipper and worshipped has developed as mutual relation of part and whole. Now, furnishing the disciple with the fruit of the treatise, he completes the work: III.75. He who, practising the conduct of a householder or the homeless [properly], understands this scripture acquires in a short time the essence (sara) of the [Divine Discourse(s) or] the Scripture (Pavayana in Pk., Pravachana in Sk.). (275) Disciples who-inasmuch as they are intent in a mental-mood settled in its characteristic-form of well purified knowledge and intuition-are equipped with the stricter or freer form of conduct, and who, themselves realizing the true nature of the self by means of a realization preceded by psychic-attention upon Scripture-knowledgecondensing the extensive mass of all topics of the text-books,understand this doctrine (read shasanam etad budhyate), take hold of the never before realized self, which is the essence of (Divine) discourses or scriptures and which is persisting throughout the endless stream of the three times, and being the best among all the substances, realizes the existent reality (bhutartha) (which exists in all living beings in all stages of life's journey), the intuitive divine knowledge and bliss, i.e. the supreme reality of self (bhagwant atma). Here ends in The Lamp of Truth (Tattva-dipika), a commentary on The Essence of the Divine Discourse/Scripture, composed by Amrtachandra Suri, the third scriptural book, entitled Supplement Expository of the Conduct. Page #414 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Gathas given only in Tatparya-vriti of Jayasena 19/1. Souls who believe in the best (pure self] among all things and who is respected by the foremost of Devas (gods) and Asuras (demons), have their miseries brought to nought. 52/2. To him the world, combining (sambandha) the kings of Devas, Asuras and men, pays devoted homage always: and so do I. 68/2. He who has splendour, vision, knowledge, supernatural powers (riddhi), bliss, likewise “sovereignty” [affluence] (aishvarya), and majesty (mahatmya), of the lordship of the three worlds, is Arhat. 68/3. To that perfect [liberated) soul (Siddha), exceeding in goodqualities, who has transcended the dignity of kings of Devas and men and is not tied to rebirth, I again make prostration. 79/2. The purified (self), perfected in austerities and self-restraint, showing the way to heaven and liberation, and extolled by the kings of Devas and Asuras, stands at the summit of the world. 79/3. Men who adore the Deva of Devas, the guru of the three worlds, the foremost among the best of saints, attain never-waning happiness. 82/2. Men pure in conviction, pre-eminent in knowledge and standing firm in (right) conduct complete, deserve respectful adoration (puja), hospitality (sat-kara) and offering (dana); homage to them! 92/2. Whoso at the sight of such a person is pleased and, having risen in welcome, shows Him honour by praise, homage, etc., derives merit therefrom. 92/3. Men or animals, having thereby obtained the Deva or human state (gati), have their wishes always fulfilled in respect of powers (vibhava) [Vibhava= vibhuti (superhuman power)] and sovereignty (affluence] (aishvarya). Page #415 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ GATHAS GIVEN ONLY IN TATPARYA-VRITI OF JAYASENA 389 93/1. Therefore, having paid homage to Him (the worthy Lord) and continually fixing my mind on Him, I will concisely state the way to full certitude of the supreme reality. 135/2. Five of these substances-time being excluded-are called existence-aggregates (asti-kaya): aggregates, again, are accumulations of infinitesimal particles or space-points (pradesha). 146/2. The vitalities (prana) are ten: five sense-organs: three vital force (bala) of mind, speech and body; further, there is the vitality of inspiration and expiration [i.e. respiration); together with the vitality of life duration (ayuh). 187/2. Through pureness (Visohi (instrumental), explained in the Tatparya-vrtti. as "a purification consisting in a strong attachment to righteousness”) (good thought-activity) comes a vehement or intense fruition (anubhaga) of good kinds of karman, in the case of affliction or morbidity (samklesha) (Tatparya-vrtti, samklesha, here= tivrasamklesha), (intense fruition) of evil kinds of karman; but in the (contrary or opposite case fruition of all kinds of karman is milder. 200/2. To the liberated soul (Siddha) and saintly, purified in conviction, having the psychic-attention of enlightened (samyag) knowledge, and enjoying happiness without hindrance or afflictions, my homage and again homage! 217/2. When the foot of (a saint or monk) who observes the iryasamiti (the religious observance in walking with the eyes carefully directed 3'/, yards ahead) has been raised for movement, although, coming in contact therewith, a small living being is hurt or killed, 217/3. Yet not the slightest bondage from this cause is taught in Scripture, just as clinging to objects (parigraha) is regarded according (as it is due to the attachment, etc. mental state of the nature of infatuation (murchha), not in physical acquisition of external objects. 220/2. If he accepts a piece of cloth or has a bowl-thus it is said in the sutra here—how has he given up dependence (alamba) on exterior things? or how is he free from worldly undertakings? 220/3. Indeed, should he take a piece of cloth, or a pot, or alms bowl, or anything else, there is injury (arambha) to life (prana, i.e. lives of others or his own spiritual life) and a distraction in his mind. 220/4. He takes, shakes, washes and dries his bowl, or piece of cloth, carefully depositing them in the sun, and feels fear or guards them from others (thereby giving up contemplation on his pure self). Page #416 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 390 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 224/2. The law preached by the Lord of shramanas has no regard to this world or the following. How then could there be in this law a separate linga [According to the Tatparya-vrtti. this gatha contains a purva-paksha (opponent's view). Linga is explained as savarana-chihnam, or concealed token consisting of clothing) for women? 224/3. Decidedly no attrinment of [liberation] (siddhi) by women in their present existence is agreed. Therefore for women there is a separate linga (The second gatha contains the parihara (refutation). Linga is explained as pravarana-sahitam chihnam, a token provided with an upper garment.) suitable to their case. 224/4. The mental-mood (vrtti) of women consists by nature in heedlessness (pramaad); and so they are called “women” (pramada): therefore these pramadis are described as full of heedlessness. 224/5. Infatuation, aversion, fear, disgust and various kinds of deceit (maya) are unavoidable in the minds of women: for them, therefore, there is no nirvana (liberation in that very birth]. 224/6. In the world of living beings no woman is free from even one of those (faults or shortcomings); nor is their body well covered: therefore they wear a covering. 224/7. There is necessarily found in them melting of (sexual urge in] the mind, unsteadiness, the menstrual loss of blood and sudden origination of tiny men (subtle human organisms]. [These “tiny men,” says the Tatparya-vrtti are not seen even by subtle perception (sukshmalabdhi-aparyapta).] 224/8. In the womb, between the breasts, in the navel and loins or armpit this subtle origination (of human organisims) is said to take place. How could they be fit for self-control? 224/9. Although she is pure in conviction and even occupied with the study of the sutras (Suttajjhayanena, paraphrased in the Tatparyavrtti by ekadashanga-sutradhyayanena, “the reading of the eleven Angas and the Sutras”: Outline of Jainism by J.L. Jaini p. 135, etc.) or practises a severe course of conduct, for a woman no falling-away or shedding of (complete) karmic-matter (nirjara) is preached (prescribed). 224/10. Therefore a corresponding external-token (consisting of clothing) is prescribed for them by the Jinas. The nuns (shramani), distinguished by family (kula), appearance (rupa) and time of life, i.e. age (vayas), follow such and such a rule of conduct (samachara). Page #417 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ GATHAS GIVEN ONLY IN TATPARYA-VRITI OF JAYASENA 391 224/11. Any one of the three castes (Brahmana, Kshatriya, Vaishya) who has a sound body, is of an age capable of austerities, has a good countenance and is free from blame, is fit to receive the token-of-anascetic (linga) [a capable shudra, etc. also). 224/12. The loss of the three jewels is what the best of Jinas designate a deficiency (bhanga): by deficiencies in other respects one is disqualified for (voluntary) fasting unto death (sallekhana) (a practise indulged in case of incurable disease and impending unavoidable death). 226/2. Through the four (passions) (anger, pride, deceit and greed], [four kinds of] idle talk about women, food, thieves and politics), the (five] objects of the senses, and when pre-occupied with affection and sleep (drowsiness), a shramana becomes guilty of the fifteen kinds of] heedlessness (pramada). 229/2. In pieces of meat, cooked, raw and being cooked, there takes place a continuous origination of very smallest living beings (nigoda) of the same kind. 22913. He who eats or touches a cooked or raw piece of meat kills a mass of many kotis (ten millions) of souls [beings). 229/4. A morsel (of food) which, although not forbidden (apratikrushta), has been in one's hand, should not be given to another; if given, it is not fit for eating, or the eater becomes liable to repentance (pratikrushta). 239/2. Renunciation, abstinence from worldly undertaking (leading to sin), indifference to sense-objects and annihilation of the passions are called self-restraint; especially in the state of a religious mendicant (pravrajya). 268/2. He who, seeing one thirsty, hungry or pained (miserable], is pained in mind and through pity assists him is “compassion." Page #418 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Appendix Concerning 47 Points of View regarding the Self What is this self? and how is it approached? As to this question, what has been stated is here restated. In the first place, the self is one substance having endless properties, pervaded by the generality of consciousness”; because it is trustworthy known by self-experience (svanu-bhava), preceded by the valid-knowledge characterized as the scripture-knowledge pervaded by the infinitely-many points of view (naya), which in their turn pervade the infinitely numerous properties (dharma). 1. According to the method of substance”, (dravya-naya) it is only consciousness, like a simple piece of cloth. 2. According to the method of modification” (paryaya-naya) it is simply intuition, knowledge, etc., like the threads (constituting the cloth). 3. According to the method of considering (things) as existent (astitva-naya)”154 it is, as having its own (a) substance, (b) place, (c) time and (d) character, something possessing existence (astitvavat): like an arrow (a) consisting of iron, (b) placed in the interspace of string and bow, (c) in the condition of insertion and (d) directed at the mark. (Similarly, the self consists of consciousness-as-such with respect to its own substances; it is placed in the physical universe with respect to its own place; it is having the form or mode existing in the present time with repect to its own time; and it is something of the nature of knowing things with respect to its own character). 4. According to the method of non-existence” (nastitva-naya) it is, with reference to (a) another substance, (b) its place, (c) its time, and (d) its character, something that possesses non-existence; like the Page #419 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ APPENDIX 393 arrow of a previous time, (a) not consisting of iron 155, (b) not placed in the interspace of string and bow, (c) not in the condition of insertion and (d) not directed at the mark. 5. According to the method of combining existence and nonexistence” (astitva-nastitva-naya) it is successively, with reference to its own and the other (a) substance, (b) place, (c) time, and (d) character, something that possesses and does not possess existence; like the arrow (and that] of a previous time, which (a) consisted of iron and thereafter no more consists of iron, (b) is placed in the interspace of string and bow and thereafter is not placed in the interspace of string and bow, (c) is in the condition of insertion and then not in the condition of insertion, and (d) is directed at the mark and then is not directed at the mark. 6. According to the method of inexpressible” (avaktavya-naya) it is, with simultaneous reference (a) to its own and other substance, (b) its (own and the strange) place, (c) time, and (d) character, something which cannot be described; like the arrow (and that) of a previous time, which (a) consists and does not consist of iron, (b) is placed and is not placed in the interspace of string and bow, (c) is and is not in the condition of insertion, and (d) is directed and is not directed at the mark. . 7. According to astitva-avaktavya-naya it is, with reference to (a) its own substance, (b) place, (c) time, and (d) character with simultaneous reference, (a) to its own and the other substance, (b) (its own and the strange) place, (c) time, and (d) character, something which possesses existence, but cannot be expressed; like the arrow (and that] of a previous time, which (a) consists of iron, (b) is placed in the interspace of string and bow, (c) is in the condition of insertion, and (d) is directed at the mark, and which, moreover, (a) consists and does not consist of iron, (b) is placed and is not placed in the interspace of string and bow, (c) is and is not in the condition of insertion, and (d) is directed and is not directed at the mark. 8. According to nastitva-avaktavya-naya it is, with reference to (a) another substance, (b) a strange place, (c) time, and (d) character and with simultaneous reference to (a) its own and the other substance, (b) (its own and the strange) place, (c) time, and (d) character, something which does not possess existence and cannot be described; like the arrow (and that] of a previous time, which (a) does not consist Page #420 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 394 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES of iron, (b) is not placed in the interspace of string and bow, (c) is not in the condition of insertion, and (d) is not directed at the mark, and which, moreover, (a) consists and does not consist of iron, (b) is placed and is not placed in the interspace of string and bow, (c) is and is not in the condition of insertion, and (d) is directed and is not directed at the mark. 9. According to astitva-nastitva-avaktavya-naya it is, with reference to (a) its own substance, (b) place, (c) time, and (d) character with reference to (a) the other substance, (b) strange place, (c) time, and (d) character, and with simultaneous reference to (a) its own and the other substance, (b) (its own and the strange) place, (c) time, and (d) character, something which possesses existence, does not possess existence and cannot be described; like the arrow [and that] of a previous time, which (a) consists of iron, (b) is placed in the interspace of string and bow, (c) is in the condition of insertion, and (d) is directed at the mark, and which, moreover, (a) does not consist of iron, (b) is not placed in the interspace of string and bow, (c) is not in the condition of insertion, and (d) is not directed at the mark, and which, finally, (a) consists and does not consist of iron, (b) is placed and is not placed in the interspace of string and bow, (c) is and is not in the condition of insertion, and (d) is directed and is not directed at the mark. 10. According to "the method of alternation" [or alternate thought constructions] (vikalpa-naya) it is something with alternative forms; like the single person who is child, youth and old man. "156 11. According to "the method of non-alternation" (a-vikalpa-naya) it is something without alternative forms; like the single person simply. 12. According to the "method of name" (nama-naya) it is something which is connected with the sacred word (sabda-brahman); like a thing itself. 13. According to "the method of representation of one thing by another" (sthapana-naya) it is something which rests on all its materialsubstances; like corporeality. 14. According to "the method of substance" (dravya-naya) it is something which exhibits itself in past and future modifications; like a shramana as a king and a boy as a merchant. 15. According to "the method of present state or condition" (bhavanaya) it is something which shows itself in the modification of a certain Page #421 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ APPENDIX 395 moment; like a woman who is acting as a man. 16. According to "the method of generality" (samanya-naya) it is something which pervades (vyapin); like the string which binds together the necklace. 17. According to "the method of particularisation" (vishesha-naya) it is something which does not pervade; like one pearl of that necklace. 18. According to "the method of the permanence" (nitya-naya) it is something which persists (in something else); like a [continually] dancing youth (read natad-yuvavad). 19. According to "the method of the non-permanence" (a-nityanaya) it is something which does not persist (in something else); like (the two roles) Rama and Ravana. 20. According to "the method of the omnipresence" (sarvagatanaya) it is something which is everywhere; like an eye with eyelids open. 21. According to "the method of the non-omnipresence" (asarvagata-naya) it is something which abides in itself; like an eye with eyelids closed. 22. According to "the method of the vacuous" (shunya-naya) it is something which appears as its self alone; like an empty house. 23. According to "the method of the non-vacuous" (a-shunya-naya) it is something which appears as non-vacuous (with a content); like a ship loaded with passengers. 24. According to "the method of the unity [or non-duality] of knowledge and knowable" (jnana-jneya-advaita-naya) it is one thing; like fire, when evolved through a great mass of fuel. 25. According to "the method of the duality of knowledge and knowable" (jnana-jneya-dvaita-naya) it is several things; like a looking glass in combination with the images of other things. 26. According to "the method of the determinism" (or necessary, niyati-naya) it is something which appears as having a determined nature; like fire, which possesses heat as a determination. 27. According to "the method of the contingent" (aniyati-naya) it is something which appears as having a contingent nature; like water, which possesses heat not determined by necessity. 28. According to "the method of nature" (svabhava-naya) it is something for which manipulation is superfluous; like a thorn, which is sharp [by nature] without being sharpened. Page #422 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 396 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 29. According to the method of non-nature” (a-svabhava-naya) it is something for which manipulation is necessary; like an arrow, which is sharp after having been whetted by the ironsmith. 30. According to the method of (proper) time” (kala-naya) it has its effectuation dependent on the (proper) moment; like the mango fruit, which ripens in accord with summer days. 31. According to the method of not (proper) time” (a-kala-naya) it has its effectuation not dependent on a (proper) moment; like the mango fruit, brought to ripeness by artificial heat. 32. According to the method of human effort” (purushkara-naya) it has its effectuation brought about by effort; like those who maintain human effort in the case of the madhu-kukkuti (fruit of the citrontree) obtained by human effort. 33. According to the method of fortuitnusness” (daiva-naya) it has its effectuation not brought about by effort; like those who maintain the fortuitousness of the ruby found in the citron-tree without "human effort.” 34. According to the method of Providence” (ishvara-naya) it is something which enjoys in dependence on something else; like a traveller's child forcibly suckled by a nurse. 35. According to the method of denying Providence" (un-ishvaranaya) it is something which enjoys independently; like a lion tearing antelopes at will. 36. According to the method of the thing with quality" (guni-naya) it is something that receives a quality; like a boy educated by a teacher. 37. According to the method of the thing without quality” (a-guninaya) it is something that is merely a witness; like the spectator of the boy educated by the teacher.. 38. According to the method of the agent” (kartr-naya) it is something which is the agent of such evolutions as dye-stain by the dyer. 39. According to “the method of the non-agent” (a-kartr-naya) it is something which is merely a witness; like a spectator of the dyer engaged upon his work. 40. According to the method of the experiencer” (bhoktr-naya) it is something which experiences pleasure, pain, etc.; like a sick person who enjoys agreeable and disagreeable food. 41. According to the method of the non-experiencer” (a-bhoktr Page #423 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ APPENDIX 397 naya) it is something which is mere witness; like the physician's servant who is a spectator of the illness of the experiencer of agreeable and disagreeable food. 42. According to "the method of action” (kriya-naya) it has its effectuation brought about principally by setting to work; like the blind man who obtained a treasure (read -nidhanandhavad) by means of an eye which started seeing as a result of getting rid of blood defect in his head when broken against a pillar. 43. According to the method of knowledge” (jnana-naya) it has its effectuation brought about principally by discrimination; like the house-corner merchant who for a handful of peas bought a magic jewel. 44. According to the external other-referential point of view” (the method of common sense, Faddegon] (vyavahara-naya) it is that which undergoes the duality of bondage and liberation; like an atom connected with another ultimate atom, which either binds it or lets it loose [i.e. the self undergoes bondage with the material karman and liberates it therefrom). 45. According to the internal, self-referential point of view” (the method of verification, Faddegon] (nishchaya-naya) it is that which does not undergo the duality of bondage and liberation; like an atom which evolves through the qualities of smoothness (or adhesiveness, snigdhatva) and roughness (rukshatva), qualities which are suitable for bondage or liberation of whatever is simply bound or liberated (i.e. the self itself undergoes bondage and liberates it through its own attachment, etc. psychic dispositions or absence thereof). 46. According to “the method of the impure” (a-shuddha-naya) it is something having a nature provided with qualifications (upadhi); like earth specialized as pot or dish. 47. According to “the method of the pure” (shuddha-naya) it is something having a nature free from upadhi; like earth in itself (kevala). With reference to this it has been said: "There are as many points of view, standpoints or expositions of methods (naya) as there are modes of speech or statements of speakers, and there are as many para-samayas (other modes of speech or expositions of methods as there are standpoins." These para-samayas (other modes of speech, expositions of methods or Page #424 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 398 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES standpoints) are definitely wrong, incorrect, false and faulty (michham in Prakrit, mithya in Sanskrit), when they make absolute assertion that their own particular exposition, or description of a thing, which is partially correct, is in every way, in every respect, entirely, completely (savvaha in Prakrit or sarvatha in Sanskrit) true or perfect. However, the statements, or expositions of methods that are qualified by the word “from a particular point of view,” or “in a certain context” (kahanchi in Prakrit or kathanchit in Sanskrit) are spoken from a relative point of view [i.e. do not refute the possibility of other alternative aspects or viewpoints being correct from their own particular perspective), as in Jainism (in accordance with the syadavada method of conditional predication, which is complementary to nayavada, the Doctrine of standpoints), “are faultless or right (samyak) in their own respective spheres."? Thus, described by way of innumerable views severally, each embracing innumerable attributes, the self-substance has a single-view essence, as set forth, because, like the ocean, wherein are commingled the white and blue masses of Ganges and Yamuna water, it is a single subject, pervading a single attribute of a non-variegated (a-mechaka) nature, since it is impossible in it to discriminate the innumerable attributes, as merely contradicting each other. But, described by way of final truth (valid knowledge, praman), characterized as the single Scripture-knowledge, pervaded simultaneously by innumerable “views," each embracing innumerable attributes, it has a “many-view” essence, as set forth, because, like the single ocean consisting of a gathering of the water-floods of all rivers, it is a single subject, pervaded by innumerable attributes of variegated nature, since it is impossible to discriminate the innumerable attributes as distinct realities. “If with the multitude of nayas dominated by the lotus (lustre) of the word "quodammodo" [syatkara) men behold, then also with final truth (valid knowledge, praman) they behold within them the substance of their own self, with its endless series of properties manifest, as nothing but pure consciousness.” (PS Kalash 19) Thus is expounded THE SOUL-SUBSTANCE. Now the detail of its attainment is expounded: Now this self, perpetually disturbed in its very self, like the ocean, through the moods of its very self, agitated by experiencing states of infatuation, occasioned by beginningless material karman; Page #425 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ APPENDIX 399 revolving through particular cognitions in endless successions; making friendships with particular external things, made knowable by being occasions of cognitions; exclusively turned outwards through weakening of the discriminative insight of the self; and following after the duality of attachment and aversion, leading to further accumulation of material karman, is very far indeed from the attainment of itself. But when this same, its whole knowledge-side provoked to action by the aggressive karman-side, accomplishes in regard to the beginningless material karman, first, a knowledge of the distinction of the destroyed and the destroyer, and then a distinction (of itself), and, with its mental-moods calmed in the majesty of its exclusive selfexperience, abides absolutely undisturbed, like the ocean, in itself, and, pervading simultaneously all particular cognitions, no more changes, since for that there is no room, then it continues no more its friendship with particular external things, made knowable by being occasions of particular cognitions. Then, exclusively directed inwards through well-established discriminative insight of the self; and far from following after the duality of attachment and aversion, leading to accumulation of material matter; it attains its holy self, never before realized and having for nature unparalleled knowledge and bliss! May the world too reach the supreme self, having for self knowledge and bliss! On this subject there is the verse: “The Truth, deep sunk in the river of the Absolute State [omniscience state) moves along with its great flood of the ambrosia of bliss and having for its glorious face the great consciousness capable of beholding the universe, may the peoples, thanks to the doctrine of the Jina, which has for emblem the word 'Quodammodò' (syatkara), attain, brilliant, their own, illuminated by the rays of the choice, genuine Jewels, and that what is worth realizing.” (PS Kalash 20) “Let the folk (men) not leap in the delusion that all universe is expoundable, and therewith the self, and that Amrtachandra Suri is the expositor in his garland of flower words to expound them. Let them leap now unperturbed, with a measure of purified enlightenment, Page #426 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 400 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES having obtained, by the power of knowledge of the 'Quodammodo doctrine (syadvada), this its own true nature eternal in every Self." (PS Kalash 21) "All that truth, high and low, which has here in no low tones been proclaimed, was once in [has been consummated in) consciousness (chit), like the oblation in the [sacrificial] fire (read bhutkalpam). May consciousness experience it to the full, since here is only consciousness and nothing else; the one supreme reality is consciousness.” (PS Kalash 22) Here ends the commentary, The Lamp of Truth. NOTE 1. The translation of the two quotations in the Prakrit language, as given byBarend Faddegon (given below) is not at all proper and is, in fact, very damaging to Jainism. It appears to be based on his ignorance of Prakrit and failure on his part to understand the correct meanings of words “para-samaya”, “savvaha” and “kahanchiť and their significance in properly understanding the Jaina Doctrines, particularly Syadvada. Faddegon's translation of the two quotations (cited from Gommatsara Karmakanda, verses 894-895) is given below: "So many speakers, so many expositions of methods (naya): so many expositions of methods, so many heterodox systems.” "The word of the heterodox systems is, in whatever way stated, false; but the word of the Jainas is, however stated (from any point of view), perfect (samyak)." Page #427 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Notes 1 The idea of the genitive case is not considered as karaka. The second interpretation of svayambhu does not seem to refer to grammatical notions. la The word karaka (relation expressed by a grammatical case; 2. factor) is ambiguous according to the two interpretations given of the word svayambhu. 1b Four means and four results are mentioned in this passage. Means: (1) lack of knowledge and vision due to combined supression and annihilation of obscuring karman, (2) annihilation of antaraya karman, (3) of avarniya karman, and (4) of mohaniya karman. Results: (1) independence with regard to sense organs, (2) sublime energy, (3) absolute knowledge and intuition, and (4) the distinction between the self and the other; the realization of bliss. lc If the reading is not corrupt, anyonya-vrtti must have two different meanings at the end of the two sentences. Or should we for the second anyonya-vrtti read mitho-vrtti? 2 The author denies prapya-karita, "activity subsequent to approach.” 3 In a wider sense of the word "cause” the substance is the cause of its qualities; the object the cause of its appearance. Read in the first occurrence pratibimbi in place of pratibimba. 4 The sounds consist, according to the Jainas, of a sound-matter. 5 A similar condemnation of too complicated supposition is found in the scholastic writings of Brahmanism. 6 i.e. the immediate impression which makes us believe in a duality of soul and objective world is not merely illusionary, but indeed trustworthy. 7 Sensorial-knowledge is (according to older Jainism) indirect-knowledge a-pratyaksha 8 Upadesha, "the pointing out," here=shabda Or should we read upashlesha, "contact? Page #428 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 402 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 9 10 11 . 12 Actions of the soul cause the assimilation or “binding” (bandha) of fresh karmic matter in the karmic body which envelops the soul. This karman, thus bound, is for a longer or shorter time in a latent condition (satta); every moment when the soul is in action some of this collected karman is used and is then said to be in a “rising condition” (udaya); but simultaneously and in consequence fresh karman is bound (H.V. Glasenapp, Der Jainismus eine indische Erlosungsreligion nach der Quellen dargestellt von Helmuth v. Glasenapp (Berlin 1925), p. 42), (if the soul evolves into attachment, aversion, etc. psychic states (SS 132-136 JS).] “Dushta."- Infatuation (moha), attachment (raga), and “shortcoming" (dosha), i.e. aversion (dvesha), form together mohaniya-karman. With this triple division compare the more intricate classification of mohaniyakarman in J.L. Jaini, Outline of Jainism, Indore: J.L. Jaini Trust, (1979), p. 32. ajavamjavabhava-svabhavatah. The expression ajavamjava (= that which is quick up to quickness itself = javaj javatara = that which is quicker than quick), used as paraphrase for samsara, recurs in the commentary on PS 88. kshayopashamavastha. The “mechanics” of karmic matter is treated in several dogmas of Jainism. (a) In the theory of the seven padarthas (Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 37) it is taught that the soul by its wrong belief, etc., attracts karman, which flows into the soul (asrava), and thus karman and the soul bind each other (bandha). Thus, when the soul acts, fresh karman is bound and karman previously collected is enjoyed and used (vipaka-nirjara). When, however, the soul raises itself and finds the truth preached by the Jina, it will succeed in checking (samvara) the inflow of fresh karman, and even in destroying latent karman (a-vipaka-nirjara). In the first case a deed is accompanied by enjoyment and destruction of old karman, (or) by the binding of fresh karman; in the second case a deed will tend not only to the destruction of the karman used at that moment, but also to the annihilation of still resting karman. (b) In the theory of bandha, udaya and satta (H.V. Glasenapp, n. 9, p. 42) bandha denotes the bondage of karman which penetrates into the soul in its present (vartamana) state in consequence of its passionate actions or even of actions in general. Satta means the latent state of previously collected (samchita) karman. Udaya demotes the “realization” (prarambha) of this latent karman and the formation, due to this, of external circumstances and internal properties which determine the souls experience and character during its life; a part of this karman which is Page #429 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ NOTES 403 thus realized wears off naturally (vipaka-nirjara). (c) In the theory of the five bhavas (psychical states, H.V. Glasenapp, p. 52; cf. J.L. Jaini, Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 50) we meet with the terms upashama (i.e. the subsidence of karman), kshaya (i.e. the annihilation of karman) and kshayopashamika-bhava (i.e. the partial annihilation and the partial subsidence of obscuring matter. 13 Cf. Outline of Jainism, n.10 p. 113, paramarthika-pratyaksha. 14 The immateriality of the soul does not exclude its extension in space; but its infinitesimal particles are exclusively called pradeshas, never anus (atoms). 15 The three forces (bala) or powers (virya) are body, mind and speech. Their use is called yoga. Outline of Jainism, n. 10, p. 82, no. 4; Glasenapp, n. 9, p. 57. 16 Kakakshitara, the crow's eye-pupil, here metaphorically used for the eyeball. Crows are popularly supposed to have only one eye, which, as occasion requires, moves from the cavity on one side into that on the other. Jacobi, Handful of Popular Maxims, I, p. 18. 17 Pravachana-sara. ghadi khayam jada, i.e. ghatikarmani kshayam jatani. The expression, grammatically incorrect and due to contamination, is rightly paraphrased in the Tatparya-vrtti as kshayam gatani. 18 Bhavya and abhavya, qualified and not qualified refer to those who have the capacity for liberation from samsara and those who do not have that capacity; V. Glasenapp, n. 9, p. 79. 19 “Fire at the end of time,” i.e. the fire which consumes the world. 20 The general duties mentioned in this gatha are cognate with the voluntary vows of the layman; Outline of Jainism, n. 10, p. 69. Compare puja (veneration) with samayika (first shiksha-vrata, or third pratima), dana (charity) with atithi-samvibhaga (third shiksha-vrata), upavasa (fasting) with posadha (second shiksha-vrata or fourth pratima). 21 The substance-here, the soul-is considered to be the cause of its properties. 22 Samayika, referring to the doctrine (equanimous] (samaya), devotional; cf. samayika (as a noun), worship; Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 69. 23 Cf. the theory of the Vaisheshikas. holding that elementary states of conscience last one moment (kshana). antardhana and antarhita, in the text, do not correspond in meaning. 25 Vasana: cf. the meaning of this term in Buddhistic philosophy. 26 According to the Jaina system of ethics, the stages towards perfection are, 1. the absence of wrong belief (mithyatva), 2. the absence of incontinence (avirati), 3. the absence of heedlessness (pramada), 4. the Page #430 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 404 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES absence of the passions (kashayas), 5. the cessation of all activity (yoga) of mind, body and speech. Cf. Outline of Jainism, n. 10, p. 94; Glasenapp, n. 9, p. 81. 27. The strange substance, or other substance, is all that which is not the soul; strange qualities are qualities belonging to the strange substances. 28 There is reference to the secondary meaning, “butting," of parinata. One interpretation as per Amrtachandra's comments of karunabhavo is karunya bhava, the feeling of compassion. The Tatparya-vrtti adds a second interpretation, according to which karunabhava would mean karunaya abhavah, i.e. absence of compassion. (For a detailed discussion on this, see my Introduction). 30 The genitive budhyamanasya is not to be constructed with niyamat, but with kshiyate as a dative-like genitive: “the accumulation of infatuation comes to an end for him," etc. Compare the genitives in the commentary, where, however the noun niyamat is lacking. 31 There is much ambiguity in regard to the word “para-samayd”, which is often explained as “mithyadrashti”, i.e. one having deluded view in regard to the reality of things or as “heretic”. 32 The commentary on gatha 93/2, offers many difficulties. It consists of two parts. The second of them is supposed to be an explanation of the first, but is really a little altered repetition. As to the subdivisions of the first portion I wish to observe: Ad la. The term padartha is identical with artha, occurring in PS 87 and there defined as including substances, qualities and modifications. The crosswise-generality (vistara-samanya) and lengthwise-generality (ayata-samanya) are called in the Tatparya-vrtti, respectively transversegenerality (tiryak-samanya) and vertical-generality (urdhvata-samanya); the last-mentioned term occurs in the Tattva-dipika on PS 10. According to the Tatparya-vrtti the urdhvata-samanya refers to the features remaining the same in a substance during its successive evolutions; thus a man remains in a certain sense the same man during his youth, manhood and old age; the tiryak-samanya refers to the features common to the specimens of one genus Thus the first sentence of the passage means our "notions of substances, qualities and modifications," or, shortly, the objects (padarthas) find their basis in the substance; for the substance is not only identical with itself, but is also “the self” of qualities and modifications, according to gatha PS 87. Our notions of substances, again, are due to the fact that there is a similarity in one substance between the successive states, and a similarity between substances mutually Page #431 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ NOTES 405 Ad 1b. Compared with the substances as their abode, the qualities and modifications are particularities. The qualities represent coexistent relations; modifications represent successive relations. Ad lc. The svabhava-guna-paryayas relate to the density of all substances: thus even of such substances as soul and space. The vibhavaguna-paryayas are partly changes of physical or sensorial qualities, such as changes of colour, and partly physical qualities in their successive states, such as cognitions. 33 The six sthanas or aggregation-states are enumerated in Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 21, not the two sthanas mentioned ibid., p. 33. Or are the six dimensions meant? 34 Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 86, no. 16, “set of central attributes which sustain the others”. (Agurulaghutva is that quality or property of substances which maintains them as they are and prevents them from being converted into other things). 35 Or should we translate, "of the latter,” and “which latter collection bears, "? cf. Tattva-dipika on PS 10. 36 For an illustration how the degree of sthulatva or sukshmatva varies with the number of pradeshas, see Glasenapp, n. 9, p. 39. 37 By these particular or typical qualities are defined respectively space, dharma, adharma, time, matter, soul. Consciousness is enumerated under the general qualities as well. We may summarize the Jaina doctrine of categories in the following tabular form: Objects (padarthas) contain 1. substances; these are collections of lengthwise and crosswise generalities: they possess existence, divided into two kinds; they possess qualities and modifications. 2. qualities, divided into a. general qualities : existence, oneness, etc.; b. special qualities, characterizing the six dravyas. 3. modifications, divided into a. substantial modifications, a. homogeneous, b. heterogenous; b. qualitative modifications, a. connected with the fineness and grossness of substances, b. the rest 39 Whilst here existence is said to be the innate nature of the substance, it is taught in PS 97 that existence is-sarva-gata, omnipresent, or belonging to everything (i.e. belongs to all things), and is a lakshanam vividhalakshananam, common characteristic of that which for the rest shows Page #432 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 406 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES the greatest variety of characterization. This variation in expression has led the commentator to think that the author distinguished existence-in-reference-to-the-substance or existenceof-characteristic-nature from existence-in-general. (see the beginning of the comments on PS 95). In the same way the Vaisheshika system distinguishes existence in the arthas (substance, quality and action) from existence as positive being and opposed to negation. 40 In trying to find my way in this syntactical labyrinth I have taken pitadigunaih kundaladi-paryayais cha as an instrumentalis causae; and have construed anupalabhyamanaih with these nouns, in spite of the strange word-order. 41 The passage is directed against the Vaisheshika system, whose darshan is even quoted. Now we find in one of the oldest texts of this philosophy, Prashastapada's Bhashya, the notion yuta-siddhi or ayuta-siddhi mentioned in three passages (Dvivedin's edition, pp. 14, 141 and 152). The theory of this notion given there is not so clear as one would desire, since samavaya is defined by the notion a-yuta-siddhi, and yuta-siddhi with the help of samavaya. Yuta-siddhi, namely, is 1. the independent possession of movement of two, or one of two eternal things; thus a moving atom is yuta-siddha in comparision with another atom of physical space; and 2. the relation of samavaya, in the case of transient substances; thus a stick and (the body of) the bearer of the stick are yuta-siddha, since they are both transient and inhere in separate groups of atoms. On the other hand, samavaya exists between objects which are not yutasiddha and one of which is the recipients (adhara), whilst the other is the recipiendum (adheya.); thus there is samavaya between the aggregate and its portions, the quality and the substance, the genus called substance (dravyatua) and the particular substance, existence and the thing-existent. 42 The formulation of this alternative reminds us of the Buddhist kshanabhanga-vada in the form in which it was accepted by the Yogachara. 43 The reader will be interested and surprised, when comparing the premises and conclusions given here and in the comments on PS 100. But, besides the inconsistency or capriciousness of argumentation, we must notice that the present passage attacks the Madhyamikas, according to which sect sunyata ("emptiness," "precipice") means the extreme confusion and logical anarchy to which all phenomena, physical and psychical, are subject; and kshanikatva or kshana-bhanga the momentary duration and therefore unsteadiness of everything. Cf. Madhava-Acharya's chapter on Buddhism in his Sarva-darshan-sangraha. Page #433 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ NOTES 407 44 Tatparya-vrtti: the "extension" of the quality "existence" over substance, quality and modification (satta-gunasya dravya-guna-paryayeshu vistarah). 45 The reasoning given in the following passage may be described as an argumentatio ad absurdum, or rather ad absurdissimum; for the premise is shown to lead to two dogmas upheld by the abhorred Madhyamikas, the sunyata-vada and the apoha-vada. The sunyata-vada taught the "nothingness," "absence," shallowness, contradictoriness of everything; the apoha-vada upheld the impossibility even of defining. For genera do not exist in nature, or even in our mind. If you will define a cow, you may say that it is not a horse, not an elephant, in short not a non-cow; but really you do not get further by that. Brahmanic philosophers exerted themselves to show the contradictoriness of this theory of "definition by means of negation"; but certainly the Madhyamikas themselves must have been quite conscious of this nature of their apoha-vada. They intended to show the impossibility of defining; for their mysticism consisted just in their deep feeling of the helplessness of the human intellect before the enigma of existence. 46 Svarupa-kartr-karanadhikarana: cf. Tattva-dipika, PS 96, where a dvanda, formed of the three last members, occurs. 47 Bhanga, in the term saptabhangi, does not mean "paralogism," which rendering was given by Cowell, but "turn," or varied form (of idea or expression). The word syat [Faddegon's translation "may be" is not correct; syat means "in a certain context," in a certain sense, in some respect or from a particular point of view], in each bhanga, may be paraphrased "the proposition holds true, provided you take it in the right sense, in the correct proportion, namely, with other notions." 48 According to the context this must mean two of these three possibilities combined, 1 with 2, 1 with 3, 2 with 3. 49 i.e. the three possibilities combined. 50 Parama-dravya-paramatman- its quality, namely -parama-dharma. 51 Outline of Jainism, n. 10, p. 32. In the significance of nama-karman in early Indian philosophy we have to recognize a remote influence of "primitive thought," according to which the name is a quality of the thing. So in Jainism the nama-karman of a thing has become its central quality, around which the other qualities are grouped as specifications or effects. 52 The explanation of the first and second meaning of karman "responsible deed," and "karmic matter" bases itself on the use of the word karman for "direct grammatical object", cf. Tattva-dipika, on PS 16. Page #434 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 408 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 53 In Brahmanic philosophy purva-paksha = the view of the opponent; and uttara = the orthodox view. —54 In the compound dravya-karman, dravya means “material substance.” Cf. the three meanings of karman, distinguished by the Tattva-dipika, on PS 117. 55 Kartr, agent, is the grammatical subject of a verb; karman, matter, or deed, the grammatical object; cf. Tattva-dipika, on PS 16. 56 With reference to these three sides of psychical life, intellect, will and emotion, pleasure and pain, we may notice (cf. here note 10) that avarana- and darshan-mohaniya-karman belong to the province of intellect, antaraya- and charitra-mohaniya-karman to the sphere of will and emotion, whilst vedaniya-karman represents the feelings of pleasure (sata) and pain (asata), and the rest of aghatiya-karman the objective conditions of these. Hasya (frivolity), shoka (sorrow) and the other akashaya-[no-kashaya] karmans presuppose a voluntary indulgence in the sentiments and are in this respect distinguished from sata- and asata karman. 57 Kriya, in kriya-bhava, means “movement”; cf. the term karman in the Vaisheshika system. 58 Parinama in the Prakrit text seems to be an ablative and is explained as such in the commentary. Thus the Sanskritization of the gathas should run, parinamaj jayante. The Tatparya-vrtti reads the text as uppada-tthidibhanga...parinamado jayadi, which gives a correct meter, but offends against grammar. Parinama, in general = “evolution,” “evolution-stage," "change," i.e. "existence with its threefold aspect during a moment's duration (Pravachana-sara, 99), is used here in the specialized signification of "qualitative change.” 59 The term tad-bhava has two significations in our text, (1) the “being that” = “identity” (Pravachana-sara, 106-108), opposite to a-tad-bhava = anyatva; (2) "qualitative” or “distinctive being” (Tattva-dipika, on 149), opposite to kriya-bhava. The second line of the gatha begins thus, te tad-bhava, visittha; this is interpreted in the commentary first as te 'tad-bhava-vishishtah (cf. R. Pischel, Grammatik der Prakrit-Sprachen, 1900, p.175) and then as te tad-bhava, whilst a-tad-bhava is taken as anyatva and tad-bhava as distinctive being! 60 Puggalassa suhumado (i.e. sukshmat; Tattva-dipika, less correctly, sukshmatvat, Tatparya-vrtti, paramanu-lakshana-sukshma-svarupadeh. While the Jainas thus hold that sound is a substance and that matter in general possesses in its fine form the four qualities, colour, taste, smell, Page #435 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ NOTES 409 and touch, all Brahmanic systems agree in taking sound for a quality; further the Vaisheshika-system teaches the accumulation-theory: the elements possess successively one quality more than the precedent one; and the Samkhya-darshan accepts the tan-matra-theory, holding that every element in its fine form only possesses one quality. 61 Jaini, Outline of Jainism, n. 10, p. 90, no. 30, "the conditions when some particles (pradeshas) of the soul expand and go out of the body and then come back to it, as in the case of the aharaka-body." 62 This seems to be in conflict with the fact that the material-atoms can be not only asamkhyeya, but also ananta. But we must remember that the Jaina system does not teach the impenetrability of matter; thus one infinitesimal-particle of space (akasha-pradesha) can hold an innumerable (asamkhyeya) or even endless (ananta) number of material-atoms (pudgalaparamanus). Cf. Tattva-dipika on PS 139, second paragraph. 63 The Sanskrit text of the gatha offers here a very strange anacolouthon, dharma-dharmabhyam atato lokah sheshau pratitya kalo, it is explained in the commentary, as if there kalena cha were read. By a simple emendation we can avoid this irregularity in the Prakrit text, namely by changing dhammadhammehi adado logo...kalo into dhammadhamme hi adade (nom. pl.) loge (locat, sing.)...kalo. The asyndeton here is hard, but not inconsistent with the style of the gathas. 64 One would have expected "the remaining five substances”. 65 In other words, there are innumerable time-streams in the world, which are situated in the infinitesimal-spacial-units of the souls and the material atoms. These time-streams exist without any adhesion (bandha) or commingling (samparka) with one another. They all have the same properties: their modifications are samayas (moments), nimishas (time required for raising the eyelids), etc. One such time-stream covers one pradesha and is therefore called a time-atom (kalanu). Thus a samaya is the shortest time-duration; a kalanu is one time-stream, considered in its spacial extension. 66 For the theory of cohesion cf. Tattvarthadhigama Sutra, V. 32-36. 67 Since there is no cohesion between the kalanus, it is rather surprising to find time mentioned in this context. 68 Substance, i.e. one soul-particle or one material-atom. Cf above, note 4. 69 Which powder, that is on the box being opened, perfumes the whole room. 70 Pradeshodbhava is an inadequate expression of the author's intended thought, viz. pradeshatvodbhava. Cf. the last sentence of the commentary on the gatha. Page #436 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 410 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 71 In the text tasthushah pradeshamatrasya must not be constructed with the immediately following genitive paramanos, but with tasya (= samayasya) at the beginning of the clause (after yatas). 72. Here samaya means time; dravya-samaya thus = beginningless and endless time. In the immediately following sentence, however, samaya again means “moment." 73 Perhaps the drift of the argumentation comes to this: a moment is the duration in which an ultimate atom penetrates a space-particle, but the atom does not reach first one and then another portion of the spaceparticle, from which a division of the time-moment would ensue; but the space-particle is indivisible. 74 These time-atoms exist locally next to one another, and consequently with every such atom lying in its line of movement the atom would come in contact. 75 Thus one infinitesimal-particle of space can hold an endless number of material-atoms. 76 In other words, the syad-vada or anekanta-vada holds true in the case of space too; it is one and many according to our point of view. In the following the commentator attacks a one-sided view. 77 In the following argumentation we must take notice that the word "spot” (kshetra) has a vague meaning ; it depends on us what extent and limits we shall give to such a kshetra. “The two fingers are in one spot,” “they are in two spots," both answers are possible. For the rest the author thinks that the problem gives rise to the following division: I. The fingers are in one spot. A. This spot is one continuous substance with identical parts. B. It is one continuous substance with distinguishable parts. II. The fingers are in more than one spot. A. These spots form several not-continuous substances. B. These spots form one continuous substance The alternatives I B and II B are accepted, as being the same as the Jaina doctrine on this point. 78 Cf. the similar expressions urdhvata-samanya, and ayata-samanya, Tattva dipika, PS 10, 93/2 (see also note 32). 79 Cf. Tattva-dipika on PS 80, where the substance is called the identity; and the modifications the divergences (vyatireka) in the identity. 80 According to the commentaries on PS 142 and 143, time (kala or samaya) is a substance (dravya), because the moment (samaya) as its modification possesses existence, or occurrence (urtti), i.e. the three aspects (kotis), origination, annihilation, and permanence, or the synthesis of Page #437 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ NOTES 411 origination and annihilation. Time is a substance, but not an asti-kaya, i.e. "something extensivelyexistent,” or “something that, itself permanent like the atom, builds up by aggregation the transitory objects.” Time is a substance, because it is that which is common to the successive moments, which is their identity (anvaya); and since in the moments changing substances possess origination, annihilation and permanence, the moments themselves, and indirectly time, may be said to possess existence and its three aspects. 81 In the commentary the singular pradesha is often given in the meaning of pradeshatva, i.e. “possession of one or more pradeshas”. 82 In the Tatparya-vrtti nadum is explained as jnatum sakyate, and padesha mettam is taken as beginning the main clause. 83 tattvatah, Tatparya-vrtti: padarthatah, considered as an object. 84 We can distinguish in the commentary the following parts: A. Thesis. Existence or occurrence without pradesha cannot belong to time, and still less can time be occurrence itself. [Note: in Jainism a substance is in a certain sense identical with its qualities; existence is considered as a quality of things; thus in general a substance is identical with its) existence.) B. First part of the argumentation. Time cannot be the occurrence itself, for the occurrence must rest on something which possesses the occurrence. And if we suppose that time were identical with the occurrence, then oneness of origination, annihilation, and permanence would be impossible. C. Argument for the conclusion, drawn at the end of B. If the unity of originations and annihilation, with reference to a substance, were to consist in an uninterrupted series of origination and annihilation, without something in its modifications subject to these aspects, then the Buddhistic theory of momentariness, kshana-bhanga-horrible dictu! would hold true. Time, therefore, consists of (one or more) pradeshas. D. Second part of the argumentation. Should time consist of many pradeshas, then (as we must read between the lines) the only supposition, allowed, would be that it consists of an innumerable number of pradeshas, equal to the space of the universe. But this is excluded, because the moment could not come into existence. E. Final conclusion (or the return to thesis). Time consists of one pradesha and, as such, according to the gatha it possesses existence. Had it not possessed even one pradesha, it would not have existed. 85 Read ana-prana-prano in agreement with the Prakrit text. The pranas are given in the karman-classification of Jainism as bala or virya (the fifth Page #438 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 412 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES antaraya-karman), indriyani (belonging to the group of nama-karman, sub-division pinda-prakrtis), ayuh-karman, and ucchuasa-karman (one of the apinda-prakrtis of nama-karman). Cf. the table of karmans in Outline of Jainism n.10, after P. 36. 86 In general Indian philosophy (cf. note 10) ignorance, attachment and aversion are the roots of the misery of existence. Ignorance forms the intellectual, attachment and aversion the emotional, side of this evil. 87 Dravya-prana may be compared with "dravya-karman". For bhavakarman, see Tattva-dipika on PS 122. Para = the other = all that is not oneself; thus all corporeal substances, but also other souls. However, as we may interpret our author, by our hatred we may, or may not, cause injury to the other souls, in any case we injure ourselves. 88 Pudgala-or paudgalika-karman is synonymous with dravya-karman. 89 The Tatparya-vrtti understands acharyas, upadhyayas, and sadhus. 90 On darshan-mohaniya and charitra-mohaniya, see Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 32; on kshayopashama state and udaya state, see supra note 12 "the mechanics of karman." 91 As a rule we find in Jain works eight kinds of touch, viz. (1) light (laghu), (2) heavy (guru), (3) soft (mrdu), (4) hard (khara), (5) smooth, or sticky like oil (snigdha), (6) rough, or dry like ashes (ruksha), (7) cold (shita), (8) hot (ushna). Perhaps the four kinds mentioned in the text are the four pairs of opposites laghu-guru, mrdu-khara, etc. Or perhaps we may suppose an older doctrine; cf. the Vaisheshika system, which maintains three kinds of touch. 92 According to the text the ultimate atoms can evolve (parinato-bhavati— Tatparya-vrtti) through different qualities, losing some and gaining others. Thus, acquiring either sneha or rukshatva, they are capable of forming aggregates. In the Vaisheshika system, as expounded by Prashastapada, the ultimate atoms may likewise change in quality; but their aggregation as double, triple, etc. atoms is due either to the apeksha-buddhi of God or to the adrshta of souls: cf. the translator's work. The Vaisheshika System, 147 and PP. 165-8. P. 93 Thus according to the number of atoms in the aggregate the degree of smoothness or roughness in each atom seems to change. very 94 This theory of the cohesion and adhesion of material substances is not clear. We may make the following observations: The word sama has in the two lines of the gatha different meanings. In the first line it means "even." This interpretation is supported by the Tatparya-vrtti, "even" is the term for [atom] evolved into the second degree (dvi-shakti), fourth degree, sixth degree, etc.; 'odd' is the term for [atom] evolved into the Page #439 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ NOTES 413 third degree, fifth degree, seventh degree, etc." This explanation is in accordance with the Prakrit trishtubh quoted in the Tattva-dipika on PS 166. Further, we must observe that the Prakrit lacks a Dual; according to the sense the clause samado duradhiga jadi bajjhante should have been Sanskritized as samato dryadhikau yadi badhyete, "when two [atoms] differ [in degree] by two from equal[ity], then they are bound." A more logical expression would have been "when of two atoms one is two degrees higher than the other, etc." The two atoms, differing by two in degree are called "the level" (sama) and "the higher" (adhika). Cf. Tattvarthadhigama-sutra, v. 36. The expression adi-parihina is satisfactorily explained by the Tattvadipika in the following gatha. In general it is clear that the pudgala-bandha theory of the Jainas is only partly based on observation, and more on fancy. A similar remark holds good of the try-anuka theory of the Vaisheshikas; see the translator's work, The Vaisheshikas System, p. 368. Comparing with European notions, we may say that the bandha between ruksha and ruksha is the cohesion and adhesion between solid substances (e.g. between the particles of a stone, between chalk and blackboard); the bandha between snigdha and snigdha the cohesion in a fluid; the bandha between snigdha and ruksha the adhesion between a solid and a fluid substance, e.g. the cohesion in a solution. The theory of the degrees seems to have originated in speculation: its main thesis is that only when the exponents of the degrees of roughness or smoothness differ by two can two atoms "attract" each other and thus cause evolution (parinamika, Tattvarthadhigama-sutra, v. 36) in one another. Finally, it deserves to be noticed that this theory of material cohesion or adhesion is given principally as an introduction to the exposition of "bondage" between soul and matter (gathas, 172-189). 95 i.e. the rough of the fourth degree. Similarly, the rough of the second degree combines with the fourth degree of either kind. 96 As a technical term, rupin is explained in the Gommata-sara Jiva-kanda, v. 614:"From the point of view of an atom with two degrees of smoothness an atom with two degrees of roughness is similar (rupi); and an atom with one, three and other degrees is dissimilar (a-rupi). The same applies to rough also." 97 The Prakrit of this tristubh verse differs from that of the gathas, e.g. it has the form durahia in place of the duradhiga of the Pravachana-sara. Page #440 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 414 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 98 Jahanna-vajje. Vajje developed out of Sanskrit varjam (“with exception of”), perhaps under influence of krte (“for the sake of”). 99 Glasenapp, n.9, p. 39, “die Menge der pradeshas des karman." Shakti yogin corresponds to yogya in the gatha. 100 Aharati has here the same meaning as in aharaka-jnana (Outline of Jainism, n. 10, p. 44); the idea is that the self always possesses potentially pure psychic-attention. 101 Para. 13-15 are far from clear and seem to have suffered several corruptions. So I have been reduced to making a series of conjectures. 102 According to (PS 110) and (PS 111) the soul is a substance untouched by qualities and modifications; according to (PS 112) a modification untouched by substance. Here again we have an example of the Jaina syadvada, anekanta-vada. (In these paras, the “pure” substance is to be understood in the sense of karma-nirpeksha parinamika bhava, see J.P. Jain, “Introduction” on the nature of the self ir this volume.] 103 Cf. the terms bhava-karman and dravya-karman, n. 87. 104 Tatparya-vrtti, taih sambaddho bhavati, “is combined with them.” 105 These two terms are equivalent to sa-vikalpaka and nir-vikalpaka (or the scripture). 106 Samaye is alternately rendered “in the doctrine or in the scripture”. 107 Ambiguous: karmic matter belonging to the soul, or deed done by the soul. In the opinion of Barend Faddegon, to say “the evolution of matter is the self's karman” (PS 189 AC) is “ambiguous” because he thinks that how can “karmic matter be said to belong to the soul or deed done by the soul”. This frank expression of doubt on his part is due to the fact that he does not seem to understand the Jaina concept of the nimitta karana and the role played by it in the doctrine of karma and mindbody interaction as also the intracacies of external, other-referential vyavayara naya and internal, self-referential standpoint (nishchaya-naya). In Jainism, the self's psychic states of attachment, etc. act as the supportive factor or auxiliary cause (nimitta karana) in the evolution of matter into material karman, that there is a difference between matter and material karman. Karmic matter is matter that has the capacity to evolve into material karman, but it cannot evolve into material karman unless psychic states act as nimitta karana thereof. It is for this reason that the evolution of matter is said to be the "self's karman" from external, other-referentia vyavahara point of view (naya). For a detailed discussion in this regard, see Jagdish Prasad Jain, Samaysara of Kundakunda (New Delhi, forthcoming), chapter on Karta-Karma. 108 According to the Prakrit text appanám havadi jhada, a reading warranted Page #441 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ NOTES 415 by the metre. But the Tattva-dipika translates atma bhavati dhyata, "he becomes the self, a contemplator. 109 Cf. the introduction to PS 189, nishchaya-vyavaharavirodham darshayati. 110 ekam. The gatha has jnanam aham ekko. 111 The Sanskrit paraphrase of the gatha in some books gives sakaranakarah (with form or formless); the original Prakrit gatha of Kundakunda, as also Tatparya-vrtti of Javasena mentions a second interpretation, namely as sagaranagarah (“while having home-life, or has given this up”). 112 Tatparya-vrtti: anagara-kevalinah, the homeless possessors of perfect knowledge. 113 Tatparya-vrtti: na kevalam jina jinendras cha tirthakara-parama-devah, “not merely Jinas, but Kings of Jinas, highest Gods who are Spiritual Guides." 114 Read parayanatva in place of parayanatattva. 115 This and the following paragraph have in the original the form of Shalini verses ; the third verse is a Vasanta-tilaka. 116 Cf. Outline of Jainism, n. 10, p. 133, where the five acharas are called, "qualities of the acharyas." 117 It-the purified soul just mentioned=the speaker himself. 118 Krorya, 'cruelty'? 119 In the original of the gathas neuter adjectives are used for abstract nouns. As concerns the interpretation, I have followed the Tattva-dipika, in the Tatparya-vrtti the second characteristic is divided into five kinds, (1-3), as in the Tattva Dipika, (4) the cause of liberation, (5) the obedience to the Jaina doctrine. 120 i.e. deeds prohibited by the maha-vratas. 121 Read kriyayah in agreement with kriyanam, which follows. 122 Cf. Outline of Jainism n.10, p. 133, subheading. V, the moral qualities of the sadhu (saints): the two lists coincide completely. 123 Tattvarthadhigama Sutra, III. 18, chedopasthapya, as the second kind of self-restraint. 124 Read shramanashrayalochana. 125 In the Tarparya-vrtti we meet with two interpretations of adhivasa, “living in the house of the teacher who is placed over (adhi-krta) one” and “staying in the pure self.” Vivasa is explained there as "a dwelling left (vi-rahita) by one's gurus.” According to the Tattva-dipika one should render adhivasa by “abiding in the self,” and vivasa by "a dwelling characterized (vishishta) by the presence of gurus.” 126 Tattvarthadhigama Sutra, IX. 18, parihara-vishuddhi, as the third kind of self-restraint. Page #442 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 416 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 127 Enumerated in PS 208. 128 Tattvarthadhigama Sutra, IX. 18, sukshma-samparaya as the fourth kind of samyama. 129 Tyaga is renunciation of all worldly concerns (parigraha), i.e. of possessions; vyutsarga is abandonment of all that may become seductive (upadhi), specially that which is required for the welfare of the body. Thus, tyaga and vyutsarga, parigraha and upadhi are nearly identical. On parigrahatyaga, cf. Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 133, 5th mahavrata; Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 132, the 8th of the ten dharmas, Outline of Jainism n.10, pp. 69-70, the 5th, 6th, 8th-11th of the pratimas. On vyutsarga, utsarga or kayotsarga cf. Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 97, the 5th of the samitis, Outline of Jainism, n. 10,p. 132, the 11th of tapamsi; Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 133, the 6th of the avashyakas. 130 Cf. Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 94, the four first forms of pramada. 131 Prakrit text, apayatta, Tattva-dipika, aprayata, Tatparya-vrtti. aprayatna (correct). 132 The usual and primary meaning of himsa is the destroying of any kind of life. Here the word receives a wider signification: and thus the ahimsavrata refers more to the intention (bhava-himsa) and obtains at the same time a formal strictness. 133 i.e. the bodies of the six kinds of souls; the five sthavaras and the trasa kind, Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 8. 134 On tyaga and upadhi cf. note 129, and on the “mechanics” of karman matter, note 12. 135 Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 70 the 8th of pratimas. 136 Both commentaries, with the same mistake, read kim kimchanam iti. 137 Dehe vi samgatti, Tattva-dipika, atha dehepi samga iti, Tatparya-vrtti, aho dehopi samga iti ("Ah ! the body too is an attachment”). 138 Cf. above, note 129. 139 Vihara, “wandering undertaken in order to find the means for sustaining the body," Tattva-dipika, on PS 215. The ascetic ethics of the Jinas attaches importance to the limitation of our bodily movements; cf. the dig-virati-guna-vrata and the deshavakashika-sikshavrata, both optional duties of the lay-follower (Bhandarkar, 2nd Report, pp. 114 and 115). 140 Prakrit, jassa anesanam appa, “whose self is non-desire.” Tattva-dipika, yasyaneshana atma, “whose self is without desire." 141 Or “fault against the eshana-samiti," Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 134. 142 Deha rahita-parikarma, e.g. he does not bathe, or brush his teeth, Pravachanasara, 208. 143 Ekabhakta: see list of mula-gunas, Pravachanasara, 208; aprati Page #443 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ NOTES 417 purnodara=anavapta, 2nd tapas, Outline of Jainism n. 10, p. 131 ; diva, na madhumansah, Outline of Jainism, n.10, , p. 68, dharmas of the pakshika-shravaka; rasa-parityaga, 4th tapas, Outline of Jainism, n. 10, p. 131, etc. The noun bhakta is made masculine in the Sanskrit paraphrase and commentary. 144 Yoga has a meaning cognate with that of the participle yukta, and cannot be translated in this passage by “activity of mind, body, or speech.” 145 The gatha is a conclusion to the passage beginning with PS 222. For time and place, cf. PS 222; for upadhi, PS 223 etc., for shrama and kshama, PS 230. 146 The theory of holding that a statement is possibly, i.e. under restrictions, true; cf. above, note 47. 147 Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 111. 148 The text of the gatha, appanam param, is explained in the Tatparya vrtti as an asyndeton: the Tattva-dipika accepts two interpretations. 149 The Prakrit form samana presents a favourite similarity in sound to sama. 150 I am inclined to interpret "the fourfold multitude of shramans” as referring to the Arhats, Siddhas, Ganadharas and Sadhus mentioned in Pravachanasara, 4. The benefiting, then, must be understood as practical assistance, partly as adoration. The Tarparya-vrtti, however, cites the four following classes: (1) Rshis, who possess miraculous power (rddhi) or absolute knowledge; (2) munis, who possess avadhi, manah-paryaya-or kevalaknowledge (Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 59); (3) yatis, who mount the ascending stages (shreni) of the upashamaka and kshapaka state (Glasenapp), n.9, p. 85); (4) sadhus in general. Bhandarkar, second report, p. 100, takes chaturvarnasya shramana-samghasya as asyndeton of two nouns, the first of which he explains by the four classes of shravakas, shravikas, yatis (“ascetics”) and aryas (aryikas). 151 The value of deeds depends on the choice of "authority," i.e. adviser, and on the choice of the “person to be benefited” by the deed. Patra seems to be ambiguous. (Patra is one who receives benefit.] 152 The word "sama" is the antithesis to adhika and adhara in the following gatha (PS 266). 153 Tanhi refers to the noun niggantham=nirgrantha=nairgranthya in the preceding gatha. Jayasena explains tanhi as locative (adhikarana), governed by adhivasadu, and the accusative (karma) samanam as a grammatical attribute (lakshana) to this tanhi. In other words, the verb allows two constructions, which are here contaminated. 154 The sections 3-9 give an exposition of the sapta-bhangi-naya. 155 The example is not quite clear. Must we think of an arrow in general, or Page #444 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 418 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES of two arrows, one of iron and the other of another material, whilst the second replaces the first? Or of one arrow made from two materials? 156 For the sections 12-15, see Outline of Jainism, n.10, p. 47. Page #445 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ श्री कुन्दकुन्दाइरियको पवयणसारो ज्ञानतत्त्व--प्रज्ञापन एस सुरासुरमसिदहिवं घोरघाइकम्ममलं । पणमामि यसमारणं तिस्थं धम्मस्स कतारं ।।१।। सेसे पुस तिथपरे ससम्बसिद्ध विमुखसम्भावे । समणे य खापदंससवारिसतबबोरिमापारे ॥२॥ ते ते सम्वे समझ समगं पत्तेगमेव परोग। वामि प पट्टते मरहते माणुसे खेने ॥३॥ किच्या परहंता सिद्धाणं तह समो मलहरागं । सम्झावयवणाणं साहणं व सम्बेसि ॥४॥ सेसि विमुखवंसरागारणपहाणासमं समासेन्ज । उपसंपयामि सम्म जत्तो निम्बारपसंपत्ती ॥५॥ संपज्जाविरिणवारणं देवासुरमणपरायविहवेहि । जोवस्स परित्ताको समसारणम्पहाणाको ॥६॥ चारित्रं खलु धम्मो धम्मो जो सो समो ति निहितो । मोहल्लोहविहीणो परिणामो अपणो हु समो ।।७।। परिमदि जेण दम्ब तकालं तम्मयं हि पन्जत । सम्हा पम्मपरिणको मावा धम्मो मुऐपन्यो ।।। जीवो परिसमदि मदा मुहेस प्रमुहेण वा मुहो महो । मुखए ता सुद्धो हदि हि परिणामसम्भावो ॥६॥ गस्थि विणा परिणाम प्रत्यो प्रत्थं विणेह परिणामो । दय्वगुणपन्जयस्पो अस्थो अस्थित्तरिणबत्तो ॥१०॥ Page #446 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 420 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES धम्मेण परिसबप्पा मापा गदि मुनसंपयोग हो । पाववि सिल्वाणसुहं सुहोबलुतो व सम्ममुहं ।।११।। पसुहोदपेण मावा कुणरो तिरियो भवीय ऐरइयो । दुक्खसहस्सेहिं सदा मभिदुदो भनि मतं ॥१२॥ प्रासयमावसमुत्थं विसयातीवं अगोषममणतं । अम्बुधिष्णं च सुहं मुर बमोगपसिवाणं ॥१३॥ सुनिस्विपयस्वमुत्तो संजमतवसंजुदो विगहरागो। समरणो सममुहदुक्यो भगियो सुद्धोवनोगो ति ॥१४॥ उपयोगविसुद्धो जो विगदावरसंतरायमोहरमो। नवो सयमेवावा मावि परं ऐषभूवारणं ॥१५॥ तह सो लाइसहावो सम्बार सबलोगपविहितो। मूदो सयमेवाना हबवि सर्वभु ति रिपट्ठिो ॥१६॥ भंगविहसोय भवो संभवपरिस्जिदो विलासोहि । वियदि तस्लेव पुरलो हिदिसंभवरणाससमवायो ॥१७॥ उप्पादो य विणासो बिनदि सास अनावस्स । परमाएल दु फेवि भट्टो खनु होवि सम्मू ॥१८॥ तं समरिष्टुं हुं अमरासुरप्पहाणेहि । जे सहति गोवा सि दुसाणि सोति ॥१८-१॥ पक्लीगधाविकम्मो प्रगतवरवीरिषो पहियतेखो। गायो प्रतिविमो सोसासं सोपपरिणदि ॥१६-२॥ सो मा पुस दुरसं केवलगाणिस्त एस्थि देहगई । जन्हा अदिवियर्स भाई जम्हा तं गेयं ॥२०॥ परिणमदो खतु खाएं पञ्चामा सम्भवम्बपण्णाया । सो व ते विजारादि उम्गहपुमाहि किरियाहि ॥२१॥ Page #447 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PRAKRIT TEXT 421 रात्यि परोक्तं किचि वि समेत सम्यक्त्रगुरणसमिद्धस्स । अक्लातीदस्स सदा सयमेव हि पाएगजावस्स ||२२|| प्रादा लागवमाखं खायं यष्पमासमुद्दि | संयं लोयासोयं तम्हा लाएं प सच्चयं ॥ २३॥ खासाम्पमा समाया हा हबदि जस्सेह तस्स सो मादा । होणो वा ग्रहिस्रो वा गालावी हर्बाद धूवमेव || २४|| होणों जदि सो मादा तष्णागमवेदसं स जानादि । अहिम्रो वा सालादो भागेग विजा कह लावि ||२५|| युगलं सम्यगयो जिरकसह सधेदि य तग्मया जगदि श्रट्टा । वामपादों य बिजो विसयादो तस्स ते भगिदा ॥२६॥ सालं अप्प ति मदं बट्टदि गाणं विरपा र पप्पालं । तन्हा सास ग्रप्या झप्पा गाणं व प्रणं वा ॥२७॥ खाली गासहायो घट्टा संगप्पा हि लाखिस्स । दवाणि ब चक्लूर्ण शेरगोन्तु बट्ट ति ॥ २६ ॥ स पबिट्टो साबिट्टो खासी रोयेसु दयमिव चन्तु । नारादि वस्सदि खिययं प्रक्लातीवो जगमसेसं ||२६|| रणमिह इंबली बुद्धज्झसियं जहा सभासाए । अभिभूव तं पिबुद्ध वट्टदि तह शाखमट्ट सु ॥३०॥ अवि ते ग संति भट्टा खाले बाणं ण होदि सम्यगर्थ । सम्बयं वा ना कहं रह गाराद्विया भट्ठा ॥ ३१ ॥ तेव्हविरशेव ग मुंचवि ख परं परिरणमदि केवली भगवं । पेच्छदि समंतो सो जागरि सव्वं खिरवसेसं ॥३२॥ जो हि सुदेण विजानदि सप्पानं जाणनं सहावेग । तं सुयकेनलिमिसिणो भनंति लोगप्पीबयरा ॥ ३३ ॥ Page #448 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES सुसं. जिरणोवविटुं पोग्गलदव्यप्पाहि बयणेहि । तं जागणा हि रणार्ग सुत्तस्स य जाणणा भणिया ॥३४॥ जो जाणदि सो गाणं ण हवदि गाणेण जाणगो प्रादा। पाएं परिणदि सयं अट्ठा गाणट्ठिया सव्वे ॥३५॥ तम्हा गाणं जीवो ऐयं बव्वं तिहा समक्खादं । दध्वं ति पुणो मादा परं च परिणामसंबद्धं ॥३६॥ तत्कालिगेव सब्वे सदसन्मूदा हि पज्जया तासि । वट्ट ते ते गाणे विसेसदो दग्वजादीणं ॥३७॥ जे ऐव हि संजाया जे खलु भट्ठा भवीय पज्जाया। ते होंति प्रसन्मूदा पज्जाया गाणपच्चक्खा ॥३॥ जदि पच्चक्खमजादं पज्जायं पलयिदं च गाणस्स । ण हवदि वा तं गाणं दिव्वं ति हि के परवेति ॥३६॥ प्रत्थं प्रक्चरिणवदिवं ईहापुव्वेहि जे विजाणंति । तेसिं परोक्खमूदं पादुमसक्कं ति पम्परां ॥४०॥ अपदेसं सपदेस मुत्तममुत्तं च पज्जयमजावं । पलयं गदं च जाणदित गाणदिदियं भरिणयं ॥४१॥ परिणमदि गेयमढेरणादा जदि गेव खाइर्ग तस्स । णागं ति तं जिगिंदा खवयंतं कम्ममेवुत्ता ॥४२॥ उदयगदा कम्मंसा जिरणवरवसहेहि रिणयविणा भणिया। तेसु विमूढो रत्तो दृट्ठो वाबंधमणुभवदि ॥४३॥ ठागगिसेजविहारा धम्मुवदेसो य णियदयो तेसि । परहंतागं काले मायाचारो ब्व इत्थीणं ॥४४॥ पुण्यफला प्ररहता तेसि किरिया पुणो हि प्रोदइया। मोहदिहिं विरहिवा तम्हा सा खाइग ति मदा ॥४५॥ Page #449 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PRAKRIT TEXT 423 जादि सो सुहो व अनुहो गहववि मादा सयं सहावेस । संसारो वि . बिजदि सम्बेसि मोबकायागं ॥४६॥ चंतकालियमिवरं जाणवि चुगवं समतयो मन्वं । प्रत्यं विचितविसमं तं गाणे खाइयं मणियं ॥४७॥ जो विचार बुगवं मत्थे तिक्कालिगे तिहषगये। गाई तस्स ग सक्कं सपज्जयं बन्यमेगं वा ॥४॥ एवं पसंतपक्जयमेषमणतारिण बमजावाणि । गविजागदि अदि सुगनं किष सो सम्माणि जागादि ॥४॥ उम्पन्बरि जदि गाणं कमसो प्र? पाच गाणिस्स । तं व हदि रिमन्त्रण बाइगं गेव समगदं ॥५०॥ तिकालसिञ्चधिसमं सपलं सस्वस्थसंभवं चित। जुगवं वारसद बोण्हं अहो हि माणस माहप्पं ॥५१॥ मावि परिणमरिण गेहवि उप्पयादि व तेसु प्रदुमु । जाणवि से प्राधा प्रबंधगो तेग पगतो ॥५२-१॥ तस्स पमाई लोगो देवासुरमा परापसंबयो । भत्तो करोदि गिच्च उपनुत्तो तं तहा बि पहं ॥५२-२॥ अस्थि प्रमुत्त मुत्त अदिरिया इंदियं च प्रत्येसु । गाणे च तहा सोक्लं जं तेनु परं चतं गेयं ॥५३॥ बं पेच्छदो प्रमुत्तं मुत्तेसु प्रदिवियं च पच्छणं । सयलं सगं .इबरं तं जाणे हदि पञ्चाक् ॥५४॥ बोबो सयं प्रसुत्तो मुतिगो सेग मुत्तिणा मुस। मोगेहिता जोग्यं जागदि वा तेग बाणादि ॥५५॥ फासो रसोय गंधो बन्यो सद्दो य पुग्गला होति । प्रस्ताएं ते असा जुगवं ते व गेहंति ॥५॥ Page #450 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 424 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES पर हवं ते मात्रा व सहावो ति अप्पणो प्रणिवा । उबल तेहि कधं पच्चयं अपणो होदि ।।७।। गे परदो विण्णाणं तं तु परोक्न ति भणिदमदुसु । जदि केबलेण गावं हवि हि जीवेण पञ्चपलं ॥५॥ जावं सब समतं गाणमणस्पवित्व विमलं । रहिदं तु प्रोग्गहादिहिं मुहं ति एगतियं मणि ।।५।। ज केवलं ति गाणं से सोख परिणमंच सो चेव । खेदो तस्स ग भणिवो लम्हा घादी खयं जारा ॥६॥ गाणं अत्यंतगर्ग लोयालोएसु विस्यमा विट्टी । गगुमागदं सम्बं ९ पुष गं तु से लडं ॥१॥ जो सदहति सोक्स सुहेसु परमं ति बिगदादी । मुरिलग से प्रभव्या भव्वा वा तं पहिच्छति ॥१२॥ मनुप्रासुरामरिता पहिरा दियहि सहजेहि । प्रसहता तं दुक्खं रमति विसएमु रम्मसु ।।६३॥ जेसि बिसयेमु रखी तेसि दुक्म वियाग सम्भावं । नातं न हि सम्भावं वागारो गस्थि विसयत्वं ॥१४॥ पम्या इ8 वियसे फासेहि समस्सिदे सहायेण । परिणममाणो अप्पा सयमेव मुहंग हदि देहो ॥६॥ एगतेण हि बेहो सुहंग हिस्स फुरि सग्गे गा। विसमवसेण दु सोक्वं दक्खं वा हदि सयमादा ॥६६॥ तिमिरहरा जइ गिट्टी अणस्स बोबेण गरिम कायध्वं । तह सौरवं सयमावा विसया कि तस्थ कुवंति ॥६७।। सपमेव जहाविषयी तेजो उन्हो घ देवता गभसि । सिद्धो बि तहा गाणं मुहं च लोगे तहा देयो ॥६८-१॥ Page #451 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PRAKRIT TEXT 425 तेजो रिट्ठी गागं हो सो तहेब सिरियं । तिवणपहागरामं माहम्पं बस्स सो परिहो ॥६-२॥ तं गुगको अधिपदर प्रविधि मणवदेवपरिभाव । अपुणभावगिवर पणमामि पुगो पुगो सिद्ध ॥६८-३॥ देवादिगुरुपूजाम र दामम्मि वा मुसीलेषु । उपवासाविसु स्तो सुहोवमोगप्पमो मप्पा ॥६६॥ बुत्तो सुहेग मारा तिरियो वा मागतो व योगा। मूरो ताबदि कालं मादि सुहं इंदियं विविहं ॥७॥ सोमवं महाबसि गरिष सुराणं पि सिडमुबोसे । है बेहदण्टा रमति विसएसु रम्मेसु ॥७॥ परणारयतिरिपरा भगति जवि देहसंभवं बुक । किह सो महो व अनुहो उबमोगो हरि जीवाणे ॥७२॥ कुतिसारहवाकषरा सुहोवमोक्ष्यहि भोगेहि । देहावीणं विद्धि करति महिना वाभिरवा ॥७३॥ बदि संति हि पुष्पाणिय परिणामसमुग्भवाणि विविहागि । गणपति विसपतहं पोषागं देवता ।।४॥ से पुरा उहिष्ण तहा दुहिता सम्हाहि विसयसोक्सासि । इच्छति अनुभवति य पामरण दुस्ससंतसा ।।७।। सपरं बापासहिवं विच्छिणे बंधकारणं विलम। जं दियेहि ल ब लोखं दुस्समेव तहा ।।७।। स हि मण्णादि यो एवं स्थि विसेसो ति पुरसपावाणं । हिरि घोरमपारं संसारं मोहसंचालो ।।७।। एवं विविक्त्यो नो बम्बेसु रागमेवि सं था। उबमोविसुबो सो नदि बेहुम्भवं तु ॥७॥ Page #452 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 426 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES चता पावारंभं समुट्ठियो वा सुहम्मि चरियन्हि । रंग जहदि आदि मोहावी व लहदि सो अपगं सुद्ध ॥७६ / १ ॥ तव संजमप्यसिद्धो सुद्रो सम्गापवग्ग मग्ग करो । अमरासुरिवमहिशे देवो सो लोयसिहरत्यो ॥७६ / २ || तं देवदेवदेवं जदिवरवसहं गुरु तिलोयस्स | परणमंति जे मणस्सा से सोक्खं प्रक्वं प्रक्यं जंति ॥७२ / ३ ॥ जो जादि अरहंतं बध्यत्तगुरु सपज्जय तेहि । सो जारादि प्रप्पा मोहो खलु जादि तस्स लयं ॥ ६० ॥ जीवो बचगदमोहो उवलो तरचमप्पस्यो सम्मं । जहदि जबि रामदोले सो अप्पाणं लहवि सुद्धं ॥ ६१॥ सब्बे वि य अरहंता तेरण विधाणेण सविदकम्मंसा । fever auladi fखावा ते रामो तेसि ||६२/१॥ सरगसुद्धा पुरिसा लालवहारणा सम्मग्वरिवत्या । पूजासककाररिहा दारणस्य य हि ते रामो तेसि ||८२ / २|| roatfare मूढो भावो जीवस्य हवदि मोहो ति । सुम्भवि तेजुच्छष्णो पप्पा रागं व बोसं वा ॥८३॥ मोहेस व रामेण व बोसेल व परिणदत्त जीवस्य । जापदि विविहो बंधो तम्हा ते संखबइदम्बा ||८४|| अट्ट प्रजयागहणं करुणाभावो य तिरिएमएसु । बिसएसु य प्यसंगो मोहस्सेदारिण लिंगा ॥६५॥ frer सत्थादो श्रट्ट पक्चक्खादीहि बुझदो लिपमा । खोयदि मोहोवचयो तम्हा सत्यं समभिवव्वं ॥ ८६ ॥ दण्ारिण गुरुणा तेसि पज्जाया घट्टसण्या भशिया । तेसु गुखपज्जयारां श्रप्पा जब ति उवदेशो ॥ ८७॥ Page #453 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PRAKRIT TEXT 427 जो मोहरागयोसे रिणहरणदि उवलम्भ जोण्हमुवदेसं । सो मन्वदक्खमोक्खं पावदि अचिरेण कालेण ||८|| पाणप्पगमप्पागं परं च दवतरणाहिसंबद्ध । जादि दि रिपच्छयदो जो सो मोहम्बयं पुरवि ।।८।। तम्हा निरणमग्गादो गुणेहि पादं परं च दव्येसु । अभिगच्छदु गिम्मोहं इच्छदि जदि अप्पयो प्रप्पा ॥१०॥ सत्तासंबद्ध सविसेस जो हि व सामणे । सद्दहदि ण सो समगो तत्तो धम्मो ण संभवदि ।।१।। जो बिहदमोहविट्ठी आगमकुसलो विरागचरियम्हि । प्रगटियो महप्पा धम्मो ति विसेसिदो समगो ॥२१॥ जो तं दिट्ठा तुट्ठो अम्भुट्टित्ता करेवि सक्कारं । बदंणरसमसणाविहि तत्तो धम्ममादिदि ।।६२/२॥ सेण परावतिरिच्या देवि वा माणुस गदि पप्पा । विहविस्सरियेहि सदा संपुण्समगोरहा होंति ॥६२।३।। ज्ञेयतत्त्व-प्रज्ञापन तम्हा सस्स णमाई किच्चा णिच्वं पितम्मरणा होज्ज । बोच्यामि संगहादो परमविरिणच्छयाधिगमं ।।१३।१।। प्रत्थो खानु बच्वमग्रो दश्वाणि गुणप्पगाणि भगिवाणि । तेहि पुणो पज्जाया पज्जयमूढा हि परसमया ॥३२॥ जो पजयेसु गिरदा जोवा परसइग ति णिहिट्ठा। प्रादसहायम्मि ठिदा ते सगसमया मुणेदवा ॥१४॥ अपरिच्चत्तसहावेणुपाद ग्वयधुवत्तसंबद्ध । गुणवं च सपज्जायं जंत ववं ति बुच्चति ॥५॥ Page #454 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 428 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES सम्भावो हि सहावो पुणेहि सह पम्मएहि चित्तहिं । समरस सम्वकाल उप्पारम्बयधुवत्तेहि ॥६॥ इह विविहलबलगावं लवलगमेमं सदित्ति सम्वगयं । उक्सिदा खनु धम्म जिगवरवसहेण पगतं ।।७।। व सहावसिद्ध सदिति जिणा तस्वदो समक्खावा । सितष प्रागमदो णेच्छदि जो सो हि परसममो ।। सवष्टियं सहावे व मस्स जो हि परिणामो । प्रत्येसु सो महायो लिदिसंभवगाससंबद्धो ॥६॥ प भवो भंगविहीको भंगोवा सस्थि संभवकिहोगी। उम्पारोवि में भंगो ग विगा योग्रेग अरषेण ।।१०।। उप्पाइटुिरिभंगा वियते परजएसु पनाया। बव्वं हि संति गिय तम्हा द हदि सम्वं ॥१०॥ समवेर खलु रवं संभवठिदिगामणिबहि । एक्कम्मि व समये सम्हा वर्ष खतिवयं ॥१२॥ पादुम्भववि व अन्गो पन्जाभो पज्जो वर्वाद प्रन्यो। बध्वस्स तं पिवम् पेव पगढुंग उप्पण्यं ॥१०॥ परिणमदि सयं दवं गुणदो य गुणंतरं सहविसिष्टुं । तम्हा गुणपम्जाया भषिया पुरण वश्यमेव ति ॥१४॥ ण हववि अदि सह प्रसव हदि तं कहं दग्वं । हदि पुणो अगं वा तम्हा दब्वं सयं सत्ता ॥१०।। पविभत्तादेसत्तं पुषत्तमिति सासणं हि बीरस्स ।। मणतमत्ताभावो रथ तम्भवं होवि कथमेगं ॥१०६।। सदग्छ सच्च गुरखो सन्वय पनमोति विस्थारो। जो खलु तस्म प्रभावो सो सवभावो प्रतम्भावो ॥१०७।। Page #455 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PRAKRIT TEXT 429 अंग संग मुखो बोवि गणो सो गतवमस्यायो । एसोहि असम्भाबो गेव प्रभाषो ति विहिवो ॥१०॥ जो खलु बम्बसहावो परिणामो सो गुणो सबिसिष्टो । सदविदं सहाये रंब ति जिलोबदेतोयं ।।१०।। पन्थि पुरणो तियकोई पन्चामोतीहवा विणा । वसं पुरण भावो तम्हा स स सत्ता ॥११०॥ एवंविहं सहावे वं मत्वपम्जयत्यहि । सबसम्भावणिवा पावुभावं समा लमहि ॥१११॥ जोगे भवं भविस्सवि रोमरोबा परो भवीय पुरषो । कि इन्वतं पन्हषि स जहं बदि प्रसो कहं हदि ॥११२॥ मगुवो प हबपि देवो देवो गामानुसो व सिद्धो वा । एवं महोम्नमालो प्रणासभा कषं महवि ।।११३॥ रबदिएण सम्बं नवं तं पञ्चदिए पुणो। हदि य असमरापणं तबकाले तम्मयत्तानो ॥११४॥ अत्पित्तिय स्थितिय हवि भक्तमिति पुरखो । पम्बायेण दु केस वि तदुभयमबिटुमणं वा ॥११॥ एसो ति रास्थि कोई पत्षि किरिया सहावारणमता। करिया हि त्यि प्रफला धम्मो अदि शिकतो परमो ॥११॥ कम्मं पामसमा समावमय अपणो महास। अभिभूय एरं तिरियं मेरइयं वा मुरं कुवि ।।११७॥ परगारयतिरियसुरा जीवा सल शामकम्मणिवत्ता । ण हि ते सद्धसहावा परिणममाणा सकम्माणि ॥११।। जायद मेव रण नरसहि लगभंगलमुग्भवे न कोई। जो हि भवो सो बिलम्रो संभवविलय तिते गामा ||११६॥ Page #456 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 430 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES तम्हा दुपस्थि कोई सहामसमष्ट्रिोति संसारे । संसारो पुरण किरिया संसरमासस्स बम्बस्स ।।१२०॥ पावा कम्मलिमसो परिणाम सहवि कम्मसंजुत्तं । तत्तो सिलिसदि कम्मं सम्हा कम्मं तु परिणामो ॥१२।। परिलामो सयमा सा पुष किरिय ति होदि जीवमया । किरिया कम्म तिमदा तम्हा कम्मरस स दुकत्ता ॥१२२॥ परिणमदि चेस्साए मावा पुरण बेदरणा तिधाभिमदा । सा पुरा जागे कम्मे फलम्मि वा कम्मखो भरिपदा ॥१२३।। खाएं प्रदवियप्पो कम्मं जोवेरा जं समारद्ध। तमणेगविषं भणिवं फलं ति सोक्खं , बुक्खं वा ॥१२४॥ अप्पा परिखामप्पा परिणामो मागकम्मफलभावी। तम्हा गार्ग कम्म कलं च पादा मुवयो ।।१२।। कत्ता करण कम्मं फलं प्रपति णिज्यिको समगो । परिणदि गेब मज्ज गदि अप्पाणं लहदि मुझ ॥१२६॥ व जीवमजोबं जोबो पुस चेरणोवनोगमायो । पोग्गलदमयमुहं प्रवेद हदि य प्रजोवं ।।१२७॥ पोग्गसजीवरिणबद्धो धमाधम्मस्थिकायकालढो। वट्टवि भागासे जो लोगो सो समकाले दु॥१२८।। उप्पावदिदिभमा पोग्गलजीवप्पगस्स लोगस्स । परिणामा जायसे संघाबादो व मेवादो ॥१२६।। लिगेहि जेहि वर्ष जीबमजीवं च हदि विष्णादं । तेऽतम्भावविसिट्ठा मुत्तामुत्ता मुसा ऐया ॥१३०॥ मुसा इंदियगेम्झा पोग्गलम्बप्पणा मगेगविधा। एन्वाणममुत्ताणं गुणा प्रमुत्ता मणेदना ।।१३१॥ Page #457 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PRAKRIT TEXT वरसगंधफासा विज्जते पुगलस्स सुमादो । पुढबीपरियंसस्स य सद्दी सो पोग्गलो चित्तो ॥ १३२ ॥ श्रागासस्तवगाहो धम्मद्दव्यस्स गमहेबुतं । पम्मेदre वस्स दु गुणों पुरणो ठारणकार गदा ।। १३३ ।। कालस्स बट्टगा से गुरगोबधोगो ति अप्पणी भरियो । गेया संखेबाबो गुला हि मुत्तिप्पही गाणं ।। १३४ । । जुगलं ।। जीवा पोग्गलकाया धम्माधम्मा पुग्यो य भागासं । सपदेसेहि प्रसंखा रत्थि पवेस ति कालस्स ।। १३५१ ।। एवारिण पंचदध्वारिण उज्झियकालं तु अस्थिकाय ति । भन्ते काया पुण बहुपदेसारण पथयतं ।। १३५ / २ ।। लोगालोगेसु रामो धम्माधम्मेहि प्राववो लोगो । ऐसे पत्र कालो जोवा पुरण पोग्ला सेसा ।। १३६ ।। जय ते गभप्पदेसा लघष्पदेसा हवंति सेसारणं । अपदेसो परमाणु तेरा पवेसुग्भवो भरिलो ।। १३७ ।। समग्रो व अम्पदेसो पवेसमेतस्स दम्यावस्स । विददो सो बट्टदि पवेल मागासवत्स ।। १३८ ॥ विददो तं देतं तस्सम समग्रो तदो परो पुग्यो । को सो कालो समझो उप्परपद्ध सी ॥१३६॥ श्रागासमणुरिट्टि आगासपदे सपा भरिणवं । सम्बेसि च प्रपूर्ण सक्कदि तं देदुमवगासं ।। १४० ।। एक्को व दुगे बहुगा संखातोदा तो अनंता य । वाणं च पवेसा संति हि समय त्ति कालस्स ॥ १४१ ॥ उत्पादो पद्ध सो विज्जदि अदि जस्स एमसमयम्हि । समयस्त सो वि समग्र सभावसमवद्वियों हवदि ।। १४२ ।। एगम्हि संति समये संभवठिदि सामसािवा कट्टा | समयस्स सकालं एस हि कालणसं भावे ।। १४३ ।। 431 Page #458 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 432 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES जस ण संति परेसा पोसमेत बतबदो सा। सुन बाग तमत्वं मत्वंतरमूरमात्वीवो ॥१४॥ सपनेसेहि समग्गो लोगों बहिरिणद्वियोरिणच्चो । जो तं मागवि जीवो पागचक्लेग संबडो ॥१४॥ इंदियपागोब तथा बलपाणोतह याउपागोय। माणप्पागप्पागो बोवाणं होति पागा ते ॥१४६/१॥ पंचविवियपागा मगणिकायाय तिणि बलपागा। मागप्पागप्पाणो पाउपपाणेग होति बसपागा ॥१४६२॥ पारसंहिचहि जीवविधीवत्सविमोहिमोवियोपुव्वं । सो नीवो पागा पुण पोग्गलयब्यहि सिब्बत्ता ॥१७॥ जीबो पागणिबडो बढो मोहादिएहि कम्मेहि । उवभंग कम्मफल बन्मादि अमोहि कम्मेहिं ।।१४।। पाणावा जोबो मोहमोसेहि कुसारि जीवाणं । यदि सो हवि हि षो सासावरणाविकम्मेहि ।।१४६।। पापा कम्ममलिमसो घरेदिपारणे पुणोतुनो अन्ये । नवर्याद जाब मतिं देहपधाणेसु विसपेतु ॥१५०॥ मो रियारिविनई भवीय उवयोगमष्पगं भादि । कम्मेहि सोग रंगदि किह तं पाणा अणुचरति ॥१५॥ अस्थित्तचिस्स हि त्यस्तत्वंतरम्हि संभूयो। प्रत्यो पलामो सो संगणालिपमेदेहि ।।१५२।। गरणारयतिरियसुरा संतागादोहि मगहा जाता। पस्यावा जीवाणं उत्यारिहि गामकम्मरस ॥१५३॥ तं सम्भावगिवई बम्बसहा तिहा समक्खा । जागरिलो सवियप्पं ग मुहरि सो माधिम्हि ॥१४॥ प्रप्पा उपयोगप्पा उबमोगो गागवंसर्ग भगिनो। सो वि सुहो अहो वा उवनोपो अप्पणो हरि ॥१५॥ Page #459 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PRAKRIT TEXT जबयोगी अदि हि सुहो पुष्णं जीवत्स संचय जादि । असुहो व सब पार्श्व तेसिमभावे न चयमत्थ ।। १५६ ।। पेच्छदि सिद्ध सहेव अणगारे । जो आणावि जिगिदे उपयोगो सो सुहो तस्स ॥१५७॥ नीवेतु सानुकंपो विसयकसायोगादो दुस्सु विबुच्चितयुगो खुदो । उम्पो उमगणपरो उपग्रोगो मस्स सो प्रसुहो ।। १५६ || असुहोबभोगरहियो सुहोवतो ग मलदवियम्हि । होन्यं मज्जत्थोऽहं खा सप्पगमध्यगं माए ॥१५६॥ साहं देहो र मरणो प वेब बारी स कारणं तेसि । कत्ता स्व ण कारविदा प्रणुमंता चैव कतीलं ॥ १६०॥ बेहो व मरणो वासी पोलर स्वप्पा ति शिहिड्डा । पोष्णलवणं हि पुलो पिठो परमाणुवध्यालं ।। १६१।। साहं योग्यसमो हा से मया पोग्ला या पिटं । लम्हा हि रस देहोऽहं कत्ता वा तस्स देहस्स ।। १६२ ॥ अपवेशी परमाणु पर्वसमेत्तो द सबमतो भो । सिद्धो वा सुक्सो वा दुपदेसाबित्तमनुभवति ॥ १६३ ॥ एगुत्तरमेगावी मनुस्स सिद्धत्तणं च सुस्वतं । परिणामादो भलिदं नाव असंततमनुभवदि ।। १६४ ।। सिद्धा मा सुक्खा वा पशुपरिखामा सभा व बिसमा वा । समयो दुहाधिगा अनि बक्झन्ति हि प्राविपरिहीया ।। १६५ ।। सिद्धतले बुनुलो चणसिद्धं स बंधमभवदि । क्लेव वा तिगुरियो अनुवभवि पंचगुणतो ॥१६६॥ पसादी लंबा सुरुमा वा बादरा ससंठाला । पुढविचलते वाऊ सगपरिलामेहि जायन्ते ।। १६७।। 433 Page #460 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 434 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES मोगाउगाखिचिदो पुग्गलकाहिं सम्बदो लोगो । सुहुमेहि पावरेहि य अप्पासोग्गेहि जोग्गेहि ॥१६॥ कम्मत्तगपायोग्गा संघा बोवस्स परिणई पप्पा । गन्यति सम्मभावं ण हि ते जोवेरा परिणमिया ॥१६६।। ते ते कम्मतगा पोग्गलकाया पुसो वि जीवस्त । संजायते हा देहतरसंकमं पप्पा ॥१७॥ पोरालियो य देहो बेडम्पिमो य तेजसियो । प्राहारय कम्माप्रो पोग्गलबप्पमासम्बे ॥११॥ परसमस्वमगंधं अबतं बरखागुनमसई। भास पलिपगहणं जीवसिदिसंठालं ॥१२॥ मुत्तो सवारिमुखो बम्मादि फाहिमपनमहि । तभिवरीदो अप्पा बझदि किष पोग्गलं कम्मं ॥१३॥ हवाविरहि रहिवो पेयदि बाणावि रुखमादीणि । सपालि गुरणे यजमा तहबंधो तेष बाबीहि ॥१४॥ उपयोगमप्रो जीवो मुग्भवि रवि वा परस्सेदि । पपा विविध विसये जो हि पुषोतेहि सो बन्धो ॥१७॥ भाग्रेस ओख जीवोपेन्द्रवि जाणादि प्राग बिसये। रम्मदि तेणेव पुरणो बन्झदि कम्मति उपदेशो ॥१७॥ फासेहि पोग्यलाएं बंधो जीवस्य रागमारीहिं । अण्णोणमवगाहो पुग्गलजीवप्पगो भरिणो ॥१७॥ सपदेशो सो मापा तेस पदेसेलु पोग्गता काया। पविसंति जहाजोगं चिट्ठति हि जति सम्झति ।।१७।। रत्तो पनि कम्म मुच्चादि कम्मेहि रागरहिदप्पा । एसो बंधसमासो जोबासं जाण सिन्जयहो ॥१७॥ Page #461 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PRAKRIT TEXT परिणामादो बंधो परिणामो रागदोसमो हनुयो । असुहो मोर पढोसो सुहो व असुहो हवदि रागो ।। १६० ।। सुहपरिणामो पुर्ण अहो पावं लि भरिदमसु । परिणामो पन्नगदो दुक्खक्ायकारणं समये ।। १८१ ।। भरिया पुढविष्यमुहा जीवणिकायाच बावरा य तसा । अण्णाते जोवादो जोवो वि य तेहिंदो प्रग्लो ।। १८२ ॥ जो गवि जादि एवं परमप्पानं सहावमासेन्ज । कोरदि अवसानं ग्रहं ममेदं ति मोहावो ॥ १८३॥ कुब्वं सभावमादा हवदि हि कत्ता सगस्त भावस्स । पोग्गलदम्बमयाखं ग दु कत्ता सध्वभावाणं ।। १६४ ।। गेहदि मे रंग मुचदि करेदि न हि पोग्गलागि कम्माणि । जीबो पोम्नलमज्भे वट्टावि सभ्वकालेसु ।। १६५ ।। स इदारिंग करता सं सगपरिरणामस्स दब्बजावस्स । प्रावीयदे कदाई विमुञ्चदे कम्मधूलीहि ॥ १८६॥ परिणमदि अदा अप्पा सुहम्हि सुहम्हि रारादोस हुदो । तं पविसदि कम्मरयं खालावरणाविभावेहिं ।। १८७/१।। सुपयडी विसोही तिब्वो असहाण संकिलेसम्म । विवरीदों द जहरगो प्रणुभागो सध्यपडी ।। १८७ / २ || दु सपवेसो सो अप्पा कसायियो कम्मरएहि सिलिट्टो बंधो सि एसो बंधससासों जोवारणं णिच्छयेण निहिट्टो । प्ररहतेहि जदीणं ववहारो प्रणहा मलिदो ॥१८६॥ मोहरागदो सेहि । परुविदो समये ।। १८८ ॥ ण चर्यादि जो वु मर्मात ग्रहं ममेदं ति बेहदविणेसु । सो सामण्णं चत्ता पडिवण्णो होदि उम्मगं ॥। १६० ।। 435 Page #462 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 436 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES साहं होमि परेति च मे परे संति नाणमहक्को । दि भावि भाणे सो अपांगं हदि झा ॥१९॥ एवं गाणप्पाणं सगभूदं प्रतिनियमहत्थं । भुवमयसमणालयं मम्णेऽहं प्रप्पगं सुद्धं ॥१२॥ बेहा वादविसावा सहसा वाव समितमणा । गोवस्त ग संति धुवा धुवोवप्रोगप्पगो अप्पा ॥१६॥ जो एवं जाणित्ता मादि परं अप्पगं विसुरप्पा । सागारोऽसमारो औषि , सो मोहडागठि ।।१४।। जो बिहबमोहमंठी रागपदोसे अबीय सामणे । होज्वं समहसुक्खो सो सो प्रालयं लहहि ॥१६५।। बोलविबमोहकलुसो विसयविरतो मसो सिभिसा । समबदियो सहाये सो अप्पागं हवि भावा ॥१६॥ खिहायसवापिकम्मो पचास सम्वभावतन्याहू । गयंतगयो समसो मावि कम९ प्रसंदेहो ॥१७॥ सम्यागाविजुत्तो समतसम्बनसोक्सणारगड्ढो । भूदो पाखातीरो भावि प्रणखो परं सोवळ ॥१९८|| एवं जिणा जिरिणवा सिया मगं समुट्टिवा समणा । जावा समोत्थ तेति तरस य विवागमगस्त ॥१६॥ तम्हा तह जापिता अप्पागं जाणगं समावेग । परिवम्मामि मत्ति उद्वितो जिम्ममाप्तम्हि ॥२००/१।। दसणसंसुदागं समभणाणोवनोमवृत्ताम् । मन्बावापरदा पमो समो सिद्धसाहूर्ण ॥२००२॥ Page #463 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PRAKRIT TEXT 437 चरणानुयोगसूचक चूलिका एवं पमिय सिद्ध निणपरसहे पुरखो पुगो समथे। पतिवज्जबु सामरणं अदि इच्छदि दुक्सपरिमोक्वं ।।२०१॥ प्रापिच्छ संवर्ग विमोचिदो गुरुकलतपुत्तेहि । प्रासिम्ब गाणबंसलवरिसतबबीरियापारं ॥२०२।। समसं गणि मुखद कुलरुषवयोविसिमिद्वारं । समहि तं पि पलदो परिच्छ मवेवि प्रणुगहिदो ॥२०॥ गाहं होमि परेसिभ मे परे सस्थि मज्झमिह किचि । इदि पिन्छियो जिदिदो बादो अपबादरुवपरो ।।२०४।। अपनादस्वजा उत्पाडिसकेसमंसुगं सर्व। रहिवं हिसावीरो अप्परिकम्मं हवि लिंग ॥२०॥ मुच्छारंभबिलुतं तं उवजोगजोमसुद्धीहि । लिग्गं रग परावेवं प्रणम्भवकारणं जेन्हं ॥२०६।। मादाय तं पि लिगं गुरुणा परमेण तं बमंसित्ता। सोच्या सव किरियं उदिदों होवि सो समरखो ॥२०७॥ बदसनिदिवियरोधो सोचावस्सयमचेलमन्हाएं। सिदिसयरामवंतवमं सिविभोयणमेगभत्तं च ।।२०।। एदे खलु मूलगुणा समसाणं बिगबरेहि पन्यता। तेस पमत्तो समगो बोटावगो होरि ॥२०॥ लिगम्हणे तेसिं गुरु ति पबजज्बदायगो होदि । खेदेसूवट्ठवगा सेसा गिजायगा समएा ।।२१०॥ पयदम्हि समारवं छेदो समयस्स कायोटुम्हि । गापि जवि तस्स पुणो पालोयगपुब्विया किरिया ॥२१॥ Page #464 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 438 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES बेपत्तो समणो समचं वबहारिगं जिनमदम्हि । प्रासेन्यालोचिता उवरिष्टुं तेण कायव्यं ॥२१२॥ अधिवासे विचासे केवविहरणो भवीय सामन्ये । समणो विहरतु गिवं परिहरमाणो गिषाणि ॥२१३॥ चरविरिणबद्धोणिसमसो गाम्हि दंससमुहम्हि । पपदो मूलमुरणेसु य जो सो परिपुष्पसामणो ॥२१४।। भत्ते वा खमणे वा मावस वा पुरषो बिहारे वा। उधिहिया लिवर दिसमणम्हि विकम्हि ॥२१॥ अपपता वा चरिया सयणासठासचंकमादीसु । समएस्स सम्बकाले हिसा सा संतपि ति मदा ॥२१६॥ मरदुव बियप जोबो प्रयदराचारस्स गिन्धिदा हिंसा । पयवस्स परिष बंधो हिंसामेत्तेख समिबस्स ॥२१७/१।। उन्चालिम्हि पाय हरियासमिबस्स सिम्पमस्याए। माबाघेल कुलिगं मरिन सं जोगमासेम्म ।।२१७/२।। रणहितस्स तष्पिमित्तोबंधोमुहमोय रेसिदो समये । मुच्छा परिम्गहो चिप प्रभयपमालदो विट्ठो ॥२१७/३॥ प्रयदाचारोसमखोलासुविकायेसु बमकरोतिमदो। परवि व जदि पिच कमलं व जले पिकवलेवो ॥२१॥ हदिवस हबदिबंधो मम्हि जीवेष कायचेम्हि । बंधो धुवमुवधीदो इदि समणा घडिया सव्वं ॥२१६॥ रण हि पिरवेक्सो चागो वहदि मिक्लुस्स प्रासयविसुद्धी । भविसुदस्स प चित्ते कह न कम्पक्समो विहिलो ।।२२०/१॥ गेहदि यसखा भाषपस्थिति भणिमिह सत्ते। अदि सो चत्तालंबो हवि कहं या प्रणारंभो ॥२२०२।। Page #465 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PRAKRIT TEXT चिसम्म ।।२२०.३॥ areers दुद्दियभायणमच गेहदि निपदं । विश्जदि पाणारंभी विक्लेवो तस्स does frers धोबड सोसेइ जदं तु प्रादवे खिता । पतं व बेलवंडं विमेदि परदो य पालयदि ||२२०/४ || किष तम्हि णत्यि मुच्छा प्रारंभी या प्रसंजमो तस्स । तथ परदम्बम्मि रदो कथमध्यार्ण पसाधयदि ।।२२१।। छेदो जेम ण विज्जयि गहनविसग्मेसु सेवमाणस्स । समणो तेणिह वट्टदु कालं खेतं वियागिता ।।।२२२ ॥ अप्पडकुट्ठ उर्वाध प्रपत्थणिज्जं प्रसंज्जवजखहि । मुच्छादिजगणार हिदं गेह समणो जदि वि श्रव्यं ॥ २२३ ॥ किं किंच ति तक्कं प्रणव्भवकामिणोध देहे वि । संग ति farafer अपकिम्मत्तमुद्दिा ||२२४/१ ॥ पेच्छदि न हि इह लोगं परं च समणिददेसिदो धम्मो । धम्महि तरह कम्हा वियप्पियं निगमिव ॥ २२४२॥ निच्छदो इत्थीरां सिद्धि हि ते जन्मणा दिट्ठा । तम्हा तप्प डरुवं विद्यप्पियं पडीपमादमइया एवासि वित्ति भासित्रा सम्हा ताम्रो पमदा पमादबहुला ति संति धवं पमदान चित्ते बित्ता माया सिगमित्यो ।। २२४. ३ || मोहपदोसा भयं तम्हा तासि ण ण विणा बट्टदि णारी एबकं वा तेसु जोवलोयन्हि । पमदा । णिहिट्टा ।।२२४/४ ।। विज्जदि सहसा तासु श्र उप्पादो सिगम्हि य इत्यो थरलंतर भणिदो मुहमुत्पादी तासि कह दुर्गुछा य । निव्वाणं ।। २२४५ ।। न हि संउडं च गतं तम्हा तासि व संवरणं ।। २२४/६ ।। funeral तासि सिथिल्लं अत्तवं च पकडल | सुहममप्राणं ।। २२४७।। णाहिकक्वपदेसेसु । संजमो होवि ।। २२४६ ।। 439 Page #466 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 440 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES जहि दसणेल सुंदा मुत्तम्भयरणेण चाबि संजुत्ता। घोरं चरविवरिप इरिथस्सल रिणज्जरा भगिना ॥२२॥ तम्हा तं परि लिगं तासि जिणेहि पिदि। कुलल्ववमोजुत्ता समसीमो तत्समाचारा ॥२२॥१०॥ बणेसु तीतु एक्को कल्लाजंगो तबोसहो वयसा । सुमुहो कुन्छारहिदो लिमगहणे हबदि जोग्गो ॥२२॥११॥ जो रयणतयणासो सो भंगो जिगवरोहि गिट्टिो। सेसं भंगेण पुले गो होदि सल्लेहनापरिहो ॥२२४/१२।। उबपरणं विण मग्गे सिमंजहजादस्वामिविभाग। गुरुवयणं पि य विमो सुस्तम्भयणं यणिविट्ठ ।।२२।। इह लोग गिरावेरखो अप्परिबको परम्मि लोम्हि । चुत्ताहारविहारो रहिदकसानो हवे समगो ॥२२६।। अस्स परोसरममप्पातं पितबो सप्पडिग्छगा समरगा । अयं भिक्खमणेससमय ते समषा पसाहारा ॥२२७/।। कोहाविएहि पाहि वि विकहाहि सहिहियागमहि । सममो हदि पमतो उबबुतो गेहगिहाहि ।।२२७/२।। केबलदेहो समनो मेहे ग मत्ति रहिवपरिकम्मो । भानुत्तो तं तबसा पनिगृहिय अपणो सति ॥२२॥ एक्कं बलु तं भरा अपरिपुष्पोबरं बहाल । चरण भिक्खेरण दिवा ण रसावेक्वं ए मधुमंसं ॥२२६/१।। परकम् प्र प्रामेसु प्रविपन्चमाणासु मंसपेसीसु । संतत्तियमुक्वायो सम्बादीसं णिगोदाएं ॥२२॥ जो पक्कमपक्कं वा पेसो मंसस्स खादि फासरि वा। सो किल णिहदि पि जीवाणमणेगकोडीसं ॥२२९/३॥ प्रापडिकुटुं पि पारितगयं गेव देयमण्णास । दत्ता भोत्तमनोग्गं भुत्तो वा होरि पबिछुट्टो ॥२२६/४॥ Page #467 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 441 PRAKRIT TEXT बातो वा बुडो वा समभिहलोषापुरषो गिलागोवा। परियं चर सबोग्ग मूलन्देको बास हवति ॥२३०॥ माहारे ब बिहारे देसं कालं समं समं उषि । बारिणता हे समसो बट्टदि अदि अप्पलेबी सो ॥२३॥ एपग्गगयो समगो एयग्गं गिन्छिवस्स प्रत्येमु । पिच्छितो मागमवो पागमचेटा तो जेद्वा ॥२३२॥ भाममहोपो समतो सेवामार्ग परं बियाणादि । पविजाणंतो प्रत्ये सवेदिकम्माणि किष भिक्खू ॥२३॥ मागमवासू साहू इंदियचणि सबभूवाणि । देवा य. प्रोहिया सिता पुरण सव्वदो बाबू ॥२३४॥ सम्बे भागमसिहा प्रत्वा गुरुपरमपहिं विहि । भाति मागमेख हि पेन्धित्ता से विते समगा ।।२।। प्रागमपुब्या विट्ठी व भवति बस्सेह संगमो तस्स । पत्थीदि भगति सुसं पसंनदो होदि किष समरणो ॥२६॥ पहिपागमेण सिम्मानिसहहएं अविविवि प्रत्येसु। सहहमाणो प्रत्ये प्रसंगदो बा - बिम्बारि ॥२३॥ मसापी कम्मं मवेवि भवसयसहस्सकोडीहि । तं पाणी तिहि गुत्तो बवि नस्सासमेसेस ॥२३॥ परमाणुपमारणं वा मुच्या हारिएसु नस्स पुगो । विम्वविमति सो सिरिस सहविसबानमधरो वि॥२२६/१॥ जागो य प्रारंभो विसविरागो सामो कसाया। सो संबमोरि भरिगो पबचाए बिसेसेण ॥२३६२।। पंचसमिसे तिगुत्तो पंवेदियसंबुडो विवकमायो । बसणणाएसमग्मो समसो सो संजबो मरिणदो ॥२४॥ समसत बंधुवागो समनुहदुस्लो पसंससिक्समो । समलोदकंचरणो पुष बीविषमरणे समो समणो ॥२४१।। Page #468 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 442 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES सरगाणारचरिते तीस जुगवं समुहिबो जो दु । एयग्गगदो सि मदो सामणं तस्स परिपुष्णं ॥ २४२ ॥ मुज्झदि वा रज्जदि या दुस्सदि या दव्वमण्यणमासेज्ज । नदि समरणो प्रणाली बदि कम्मे हि विविहेहि ॥ २४३ ॥ प्रट्ठेसु जो ण मुज्झदि सा हि रज्जदि रोग बोसमुवयादि । समणो जदि सो रियई खबेदि कम्माणि विविहाणि ॥ २४४ ॥ समरगा सुद्ध वनुत्ता सुहोबत्ता य होंति समयन्हि । तेसु वि सुद्ध वजुता भरणासवा सासवा सेसा ॥ २४५ ॥ अरहंतादिसु भती बदलवा पचयणाभिजुरो । विज्जवि जवि सामले सा सुहकुत्ता भवे बरिया ||२४६ ॥ बंदल मंसणेह सम्भारमानुगमरणपश्विती । समरस समावयो न खिबिदा रामचरियम्हि ॥२४७॥ दंसरगरणानुवबेसो सिल्सम्हलं च पोसणं तेसि । खरिया हि सरागाणं निलिम्पूजोवदेसो य ॥ २४६ ॥ उबकुलवि जो विच्विं चातुव्वणस्स समरणसंघस्स । कार्याविराधरणरहिदं सो बि सरागप्पपानो से ॥ २४६ ॥ जबि कुर्गादि कायखेदं वेज्जावच्चत्वमुज्जदो समयो । व हवदि हर्षादि प्रगारी धम्मो सो सावयास से ।। २५० ।। जोन्हाणं गिरबेक्यं सागारपगारचरियताणं । अणुकंपयोवयारं कुब्बर लेवो यदि वि भ्रप्पो ॥ २५१ ॥ रोगेण वा छुपाए तहाए वा समेस वा रूढं । विट्ठा समरणं साहू परिवज्जडु श्रादसत्तीए ।। २५२ ।। बेाच्चरिणमितं गिलाणगुनबालबुड्ढसमरणारणं । लोगिगजरगसंभाला ग सिविदा वा सुहोवख़ुदा ।। २५३ ।। एसा पसत्यदा समरणारणं वा पुमो घरत्यागं । चरिया परेति भखिदा ताएव परं लहवि सोक्लं ।। २५४।। Page #469 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PRAKRIT TEXT 443 रागो पसस्थभूदो वल्पविसेसेण फलरि विवरीदं । पाणाभूमिगदागिह बीजाणिव सम्सकालम्हि ।।२५५॥ बहुमत्यविहिदवत्थुसु परिणयमन्मयलझागदागरदो।। ए लहवि अपुरणम्भावं भावं सारपगं लहदि ॥२५॥ प्रविविवपरमत्थेमु य विसयकसायाधिमे परिसेसु । बुई कर बदतं फलादि देवेसु मणुवेसु ॥२५७।। अदि ते विसयकसाया पावति परुविधा व सत्येसु । किह ते तप्पडिबडा पुरिसा रिसत्यारणा होति ॥२५॥ उपरखपायो पुरिसो समभावो पम्मिगेसु सम्बेसु । गुगसमिवियोवसेवी हवि स भागी सुमम्गस ॥२५॥ अमुभोवयोगरहिदा सब बधुत्ता सुहोवजुत्ता वा। खित्यारपंति लोगं तेसु पसत्वं लहरि भत्तो ।।२६०।। विट्ठा पगई बस् अभट्ठाणम्पपासकिरियाहि । बट्टा तदो गुणादो बिसेसिबम्बो ति सबदेसो ॥२६१॥ अग्भटाणं गहणं उवासणं पोसणं बसपकारं। मंडलिकरणं पणमं भरिणवमिह मुखाधिगाणं हि ॥२६२।। अभट्ट या समसा मुत्तस्यक्तिारबा उवासेया। संजमतवसापड्ढा परिणववरणीया हि समहि ॥२६॥ ण हदि समरणो ति मयो संजमतवसुत्तसंपत्तो वि । दि सहवि स प्रस्थे मारपधागे जिससावे ।।२६।। प्रववददि सासरणत्वं समर्श विद्वा पदोसदो जो हि । किरियासु खाणुमम्मावि हदि हिसो एदुचारितो ॥२६॥ गुगबोधिगस्स विलयं परिच्छगो जो विहोमि समतो ति । होज्वं गुणाघरो जरि सो होवि पतसंसारी ॥२६६॥ Page #470 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 444 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES अधिगगुणा सामग्णे बदति गुणावरहि किरिया । अवि ते मिच्छ वधुत्ता हवंति पानवारिसा ॥२७॥ गिन्धिरसुत्तत्थपदो समिदकसामोतबोधिगो चापि । लोगिगजलसंसागराचविचार संजदोपरि ।।२६८/१॥ तिसि भुक्ति वा दुहिक बलू गमो हि दुहिवमलो। परिवरित किवया सस्सेसा होरि अनुकंपा ॥२६॥२॥ लिगंभो पनाको बट्टवि अवि पहिगेहि कम्महि । सो लोगिगो ति भणिदो संघमतवसंपत्तो वि॥२६६।। सम्हा समं गणावो समणो समणं गुणेहि मा पहियं । प्रषिवसवु तम्हि खिचं इन्धविनविदुक्सपरिमोपलं ॥२०॥ प्रजधागहिवत्या एवं तन ति सिथिदा समये । मज्यतफलसमिदं भर्मति से तो परं कालं ॥२७॥ अवषाचारविनुत्तो बवत्वपदसिछिदो पसंसप्ता। मफले चिरं स जीववि वह सो संपुण्यसामलो ।।२७२॥ सम्म विविवपदत्वा चत्ता उहि बहित्यमम्मत्वं । विसयेसु पावसत्ता ते सुद्धा ति गिट्ठा ॥२७॥ सुखस्स प सामनं भलिवं सुखस्स ससं पाएं। सुखस्स व सिम्बाएं सो चिय सिद्धो समो तस्स ।।२७४।। सुरभादि साससमेयं साधारणगारबरियवा बुतो। जो सो पश्यणसारं सहरा कालेख पप्पोरि ॥२७॥ प्रति प्रवचनसार [पमनगमारो] Page #471 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Glossary of Jaina Technical Terms The English equivalent of words used in this work, given below in Sanskrit, may not always necessarily and exclusively have the same meaning in all contexts or indicate the same Jaina term. The references are to consecutive numbering of verses (gathas). The additional (extra) verses in the text, given only in Jayasena's commentary, are marked with an asterisk (*). Sk. stands for Sanskrit and Pk. stands for Prakrit. Ajiva Non-life or the insentient principle; nature of 127. Adharma The principle of stationariness or the fulcrum of rest; property of 133. Anagara An ascetic, or homeless 194. Anyatva Non-identity; defined 106. Appadikammam Non-attention towards the body 205, 224/1, also 228. Appadikutha Non forbidden by the sacred text 223, *229/4. Abhavya A non-liberable being; nature of 62. Amurta Incorporeal, Non-concrete; defined 131; see guna. Arahanta One who is worthy of worship, Tirthankara, nature of the (Sk. Arhat) activities of 44-45; glories of *68/2. Artha An existential entity; some characteristics of 10; defined 87; 93/2, agama as the proof of 235. Avagraha Apprenhension of an object, outlinear grasp 21, 59. Avadhi Clairvoyance; 234 Ashubhopayoga Inauspicious psychic-attention or manifestation of consciousness; fruit of 12; demerit caused by 156; characteristics of 158; karmic influx in 245. Page #472 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 446 Astikaya Akasha Agam Atman Arambha Alochana Avashyaka Asrava Ahara Aharaka (- sharira) Indriya Iha Utpada-vyaya Upadhi Upayoga THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Existence-aggregate or magnitude, a technical name given to five substances, time being excepted; five kinds of and defined *135/2. Space, also sky; the property of 133; space-points of 135/1; two kinds of 136. The Jaina scripture; importance of the study of 232; karman destroyed by the study of 233; monks see through 234; self-control obtained from 236. The self; coextensive with knowledge, neither less nor more 23-24, 36; identity with knowledge 27; the happiness itself 67; contact and relation of karma with 121-122; the relation of three kinds of chetana with 125; agency, etc. in 126; property of 134; nature of 155; independence of 160; body not identical with 162; real nature of 192; external things and relations different from 193; see also jiva and chetana. Preliminary sin; all those activities which involve some slight harm to living beings *220/3. Report of defaults 211-212. Essential duty 208. The influx of karmas, causes of 245. Food, etc.; nature of monk's 229/1, *229/4; reasons for abstaining from non-vegetarian *229/2-3. The emanatory or translocational body 171. The sense organ or the sense; simultaneous comprehension impossible for 56; not a part of the soul's nature 57; sense-perception not pratyaksha 57; nature of the happiness from 76. Specific enquiry, discrimination 40. Origination, destruction or annihilation and permanence dhrauvya or stability; refer to modifications leaving arthatva 18, 101; interaction of 100; simultaneous presence of (in a substance) 102; relation of origination and destruction 119. The same as parigraha, encumbrances 223. Psychic-attention, manifestation or function of consciousness. It is a very mobile term, whose shade of meaning slightly changes according to the context. It Page #473 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ GLOSSARY 447 Audarika (-sharira) Karman Kaya Karmana (-sharira) Kala Kalanu Kevala-jnana is a condition of the soul which is an embodiment of consciousness; three kinds of 9; two channels of 155. The physical body 171. Karma, a subtle type of matter which inflows into the soul, when the latter is disturbed by passional vibrations etc.; ghati-k. destroyed by Mahavira 1; ghati-k. destroyed in shuddhopayoga 15; nature of and soul's contact and relation with 121-122; soul bound by 148; harm to vitalities as the cause of jnanavaraniyak. etc. 149; vitalities are further incurred due to 150; a way of escaping from 151; transformation of material aggregates into 169; body of 171; illustration of the bondage of 174; possibility of the destruction of 220, 233, 244; causes of 243; nama-k. the states of existence fashioned by 117, 118. 153. Body, an embodied being; six kinds of 218. The karmic body 171. Time; property of 134; infinitesimal-spacial-units or space-points denied in the case of 135/1. The ultimate unit of time 143. Omniscience; equated with happiness 19, 60; its direct comprehension without sensorial stages 21; the manner of its vision 29; as a reflector of present and absent modifications 37; scope of the comprehension of 41,48; its ability to know all substances with all their modifications 49; simultaneous comprehension of 50; glory of 51; pratyakshatva of 54. The omniscient; his exemption from physical feeling 20; no indirect perception in his case 22; the mode of his vision and comprehension 29; his immunity from disturbances when seeing and knowing 32; his immunity from bondage 52. Knowledge which originates after the destruction of armas; defined 42, 47. An apostle, the direct disciple of Tirthankara, but sometimes equated with acharya, who is at the head of an ascetic group 4. Quality; modifications associated with 93/2; substance is the substratum of 110; murta and amurta distinction Kevalin Kshayika-jnana Ganadhara Guna Page #474 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ • 448 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Charitra Chetana Chadmastha Cheda Jiva of 130. Conduct, equated with dharma and sama 7. Sentiency or consciousness; definition of and three kinds cf 123-124; see also atman and jiva. One who has not attained omniscience; fruit of following 256. Default (in the practice of primary virtues); and Chedopasthapaka is that monk who stands in need of re-establishment in the correct behaviour after he has committed a default 209; antidotal procedure against 211-212; guarding against 213, 222. Soul or the sentient principle; non-concrete or incorporeal nature of 55; as one that develops happiness 65-66; its difference and non-difference in different births explained 112-113; nature of 127; space-points of 135/1; as a knower endowed with four life-essentials or vitalities 145; incurrance of karmas by 148; modifications of 153; descriptions of 172; illustration of the karmic bondage of 174, 176; bondage resulting from the passional vibrations of 175-176; embodiment distinct from 182; conditions of material substances not caused by 184; discussion about the reception of karmas by 115; see also atman and chetana. Knowledge coextensive with the self and the objects of knowledge 23; all-pervasiveness of 23; the self identical with 27; its relation with jneya indicated with an illustration 28; its enlightenment of objects illustrated 30; equated with the understanding of the sacred text 34; equated with the knower 35; equated with the soul 36; two kinds of 53; its being pratyaksha 54; pratyaksha-, and paroksha-distinguished and defined 58; karmas instantaneously destroyed through 238. The object(s) of knowledge; coextensive with knowledge 23; scope of 23; reflected in and grasped completely by Jina 29; its relation with jnana illustrated 28. Penance, austerity; in the form of fast 227. The magnetic (electric) body 171. Jnana Jneya Tapas Taijasika (-sharira) Page #475 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ GLOSSARY 449 Trasa (-kaya) Movable body (or being) that possesses more than one sense 182. Deva A god, a resident of heavens; nature of his happiness 71, 73-75. Dravya Substance; defined 49, 95; infinite number of and infinite modifications of 49; as made up of qualities 93/2; nature of 96; differentia of 97-98; origination etc., associated with the condition of 99; origination etc. intimately and simultaneously united with 102; existential character of and immunity from modificational disturbance 103; its relation with qualities and modifications 104; satta as the characteristic of 105, 109, 110; positive and negative aspects of 111; two kinds of 127; concrete and nonconcrete qualities of 130; space-points of 141; three fold nature of 154. Dravyarthikal-naya) substantial viewpoint; non-difference established by 114. Dvesha Aversion (Pk. form dosa) 81, 83. 84, 180: see raga (or attachment) with which it is generally coupled. Dharma equated with charitra and sama 7; the soul considered as 8; a designation of shraman 92. Dharma The principle or fulcrum of motion; property of 133; space-points of 135/1. Dhyata A meditator; qualifications of 196. Niryapaka An ascetic who establishes a defaulter-monk in the correct behaviour; defined 210. Nirvana Nirvana or liberation; a way of attaining 6: salutation to the path of 199; in the same birth women cannot attain *224/3-10, infatuation as a hindrance to 239; attainment of 259-260. Pancha-parameshthin The five dignitaries; enumerated and saluted 4. Paramanu A primary or subtle-most atom; a measure of spacepoint 137; nature of and the aggregates formed by 163; process, with illustration, of aggregates formed by 164-166. Para-samaya Those who do not understand the reality of the self and are affected or conditioned by "the other”; defined 93/2, 94, 98. Page #476 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 450 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Parigraha Paryaya Paryayarthika Papa Punya Pudgala Prthaktva Pradesha Attachment for paraphernalia (parigraha); defined *217/3; bondage caused by 219; self-realisation endangered by 221; hindrances due to *220/2-4, 239; acceptable type of 223, 225; see also mamatva. Modification; subjected to origination and destruction 18, modifications of all substances, both present and absent, reflected in knowledge 37; absent paryaya defined 38; qualities associated with 93/2; a substance endowed with 101; substance as the substratum of 110; as the ground of seven-fold predication 115; defined 152; illustrated 153. Modificational viewpoint; difference established by (-naya) 114. Demerit; defined 181, 258; see also punya. Merit; and papa 77; defined 181. Matter; its qualities 56, 132; sound as a form of 132; space-points of 135/1; forms and constituents of 161; the physical world full with bodies of 168; bodies formed by 170; kinds of bodies formed by 171. Separateness; defined 106. Space-points; predicated of different substances 135/ 1;defined and its scope 140. A lady; why a woman is called *22414. The Divine Discourse or the essence of the scripture(s) 275. A preceptor who initiates a monk in the order; defined 210. Life-essentials or vitalities; four kinds of 146/1; Ten further subdivisions of *146/2; material nature of 147; karmic bondage consequent on the harm unto 149. Bondage of karmas, its possibility 84; of soul and matter illustrated 173-174, 177, 178; the doctrine of 179; discussed in detail 187/1, 188-189; himsa as a cause of 217. A liberable being; nature of 62. Sense of ownership, notion of mineness; mundane circuit caused by 150; renunciation of 190-191, 200/ 1, 215; not even for body 228. Pramada Pravachanasara Pravrajya-dayaka Prana Bandha Bhavya Mamatva Page #477 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ GLOSSARY 451 Murccha Murta Mulaguna Moksha Moha Raga Linga Loka Vardhamana Infatuation, excessive attachment 239; see also parigraha. Concrete or corporeal; defined 131; see also guna. Primary virtue; twentyeight enumerated 208-209. Liberation, see Nirvana. Delusion or Infatuation; destruction of 80, 86, 88-89, 194; defined 83; as a cause of bondage 84; characteristics of 85. Attachment; as a hindrance to the realisation of spiritual purity 81; as a source of infatuation 83; as a cause of bondage 84, 179, two kinds of 180; illustration of the fruit of 255; see also dvesha with which it is generally coupled. Emblem (viz the ascetic emblem); description and two kinds of 205-206; that prescribed for women *224/ 2, etc. Physical world 128; =akasha physical space; origination etc., in 129; constituents of 135/1. Vardhamana alias Mahavira, the last Tirthankara of the Jainas; he attained liberation in 527 B.C.; saluted along with previous and contemporary Tirthankaras 1-3. Unhealthy gossip; four kinds of 215. The objects of pleasure; as the source of misery 64. (Pk. Veuvviya) (-sharira); The plastic or transformatory body 171. Vow 208. Sound; the material nature of 132. Equanimity; defined and equated with dharma and charitra 7. Body; five kinds of 171. The pure and the perfect one; defined 273; attainment of 274. Pure manifestation of consciousness; fruit of 11; nature of happiness in 13; nature of a shroman endowed with 14; omniscience in 15; as a cause of destroying misery 78; absence of karmic influx in 245. Void; defined 144. Auspicious manifestation of consciousness; fruit of 11, Vikatha Vishaya Vaikriyika Vrata Shabda Sama Sharira Shuddha Shuddhopayoga Shunya Shubhopayoga Page #478 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 452 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Shraddhan Shraman 70; characteristics of 69, 157, 246; merit caused by 156; karmic influx in 245; activities sanctioned for a monk with 247-248. Conviction, faith; importance of 237; as a necessary qualification of a shraman 264. A saint, an ascetic; his qualifications 91-92, 226; dharma as a designation of 92; procedure, etc. to be observed at the time of the initiation of 202, 207; reflection and appearance of 204; his caution against cheda 213; commission of himsa by 216; careful activities prescribed for 218; responsibility of himsa on *217/23; foodlessness of 227; how least karma is incurred by 231; definition of a self-controlled monk 240-242; destruction of karmas by 244; activities allowed for a shraman of shubhopayoga 247-249; mutual help among 252; the occasion when contact with commoners not forbidden for 253; formalities to be observed by 261263; faith to be possessed by 264; malice and vanity leading to the fall of 265-266; his mistake in cooperating with a lower shraman 267; selection of a colleague by 220; attainments of perfect shraman 272. A nun *224/10. Shraman-hood; misery destroyed by the adoption of 201; preliminary rites at the time of adopting 202; the preceptor, etc. from whom to adopt 203; description of the emblem of 205-206; definition of the perfect type of 214; the fruit of the perfect type of 272. A householder or a layman 250. A scriptural omniscient; defined 33. Attachment or association; defined 224. Existence; scope of 107, satta- 110. The doctrine of seven-fold predication, quodammodo, stated 115. Moment or instant, an unit of time which is coordinated with an atom of matter and a point of space; defined 138; origination, etc. in 139; initial nature of 142. Scripture; para- and svaka-defined 94, 98. Shramani Shramanya Shravaka Shruta-kevalin Sanga Sat Saptabhangi Samaya Samaya Page #479 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ GLOSSARY Samiti Sallekhana Samyam Samsara Sagara Siddha Siddhi Sukha Sutra Skandha Stri (-moksha) Sthavara (-kaya) Syadvada Svayambhu Himsa Carefulness 208. Voluntary fasting unto death *224/12. Self-control or discipline; defined *239/2. Transmigratory existence, defined 120. 453 A householder 194; duty of 250; the highest duty of 254; see also shravaka. A liberated soul; an embodiment of absolute happiness and omniscience, and also a Divinity 68/1; salutation to *68/3. see Nirvana. Happiness; in shubhopayoga 11; in shuddhopayoga 13; equated with omniscience 19; of an omniscient 20; two kinds of 53; absolute happiness defined and equated with omniscience 59; happiness of senses is misery 76; absolute happiness as an object of meditation 198. The sacred text; its constitution and equation with knowledge 34. An aggregate; formation of 166-167. Liberation of women; discussed *224/3-10. Immovable being, i.e. those that possess only the sense of touch; they are five: earth, water, fire, air-bodied and vegetation or plants. 182. see saptabhangi. The self-existent; definition of 16; as a collocation of origination, destruction and permanence 17. Harm unto beings; shraman's commission of 216; bondage due to 217. Page #480 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Name Index Adi Shankracharya, 14 Advaita Vedanta, 20, 32 Ahimsa Mandir, 6 Akalanka Deva, 39-40, 74-78, 85, 140, : 143, 154 Amitgati, 144 Amrtachandra, 2-4, 6-9, 13-14, 20, 29, 31-32, 34, 39, 42, 48-52, 54, 57, 62, 68, 73, 88-89, 91, 93, 98, 107110, 113, 117, 119-122, 135, 137, 139, 141, 148-151, 154-157, 160161, 166-169, 171-172, 185, 188, 191 n. 8, 203, 207, 399 Ashoka, Emperor, 159 Deleu, 35, 43-45 Denecke, W., 191 n. 9 Descartes, Rene, 145 Deva, Yogendu, 17 Devadutta, 233 Divakar, Siddhasen, 192 n. 9 Dundas, Paul, 165-166 Einstein, Albert, 53 Faddegon, Barend, 36, 49, 98, 149, 207, 286-287, 337, 400 n. 1 Frauwallner, Erich, 35 Barnett, L.D., 206 Bhandarkar, R.G., 1 Bharill, H.C., 4, 60, 89, 92-93, 96, 166, 169, 179-188 Bhattacharya, H.M., 117, 124, 134, 190 Bronkhorst, J., 152-153, 176-177 Buddha, Lord, 65 Buehler, G., 205 Gandhi, M.K., 111-112 Gautam Gandhara, 1 Gazzaniga, 46 Ghoshal, S.C., 206 Glasenapp, Helmuth von, 206 Hacker, Andrew, 52 Hemaraja, 203 Hitler, Adolf, 112 Chakravarti, A., 35-36 Chalmers, David, 145 Chandra, K.R., 44 Colebrook, Claire, 206 Jacobi, H., 35, 42 Jain, Hem Chand, 177 Jain, Jagdish Prasad, 110 Jain, Rajkrishna, 6 Jain, S.A., 35 Dalia Lama, 47, 100 Page #481 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ NAME INDEX 455 Mimansaka, 125 Moreleau-Ponty, Maurice, 122 Nagel, Thomas, 145-146 Nemichandra, 206 Nyayavijaya, Muni, 155 Jain, Veer Sagar, 183 Jain, Vijay K., 37 Jaini, J.L., 35-36, 38, 207, 390 Jaini, P.S., 35 James, William, 145 Jayasena, 2-8, 29, 31-32, 64, 87, 90.99, 107, 113, 117, 121, 139, 149, 161, 169, 181-182, 186, 188, 203-204 Jinabhadra, Acharya, 155 Jinasena, Acharya, 72 Jnanasagar, Acharya, 108 Johnson, W.J. 35, 42-44, 148, 152, 155 157, 163, 165 Obama, B.H., 112 Padmaprabhadeva, 139 Patanjali, 14, 100, 174 Polyani, Michael, 122 Pujyapada, Acharya, 39, 73-74, 78, 99, 144, 152-153 Rajchandra, Srimad, 111 Rao, K. Ramakrishna, 174 Kabat-Zinn, Jon, 46 Kanaknandi, 72 Kanji Svami, 32, 47, 93-95, 114-115, 133-135, 166, 178, 186-187 Kanjipanthi, 4, 32, 47-48, 60, 81-82, 89-93, 95-96, 114-115, 117, 133135, 154, 166, 174, 176-177, 179 180, 183, 187 Kendall, Donald, 185 Krishnamurti, J., 115 Kundakunda, Acharya, 1-2, 4-7, 9-10, 17, 29, 32-33, 35-37, 42-43, 45, 4749, 51-56, 60-64, 66, 68, 70, 79, 81, 84, 87, 90-91, 93, 96, 98, 101, 111, 115-117, 119-124, 126-129, 133-135, 137, 146-151, 154, 158, 160-165, 166, 171, 176-182, 184- 190, 191 n. 9, 193 n. 9, 203, 205206 Sadasukh, Pandit, 66 Samantabhadra, 60, 65, 102, 105-106, 141, 144, 165, 184 Sankhya, 20, 32 Schubring, W., 44 Searle, John, 145 Shakespeare, 99 Shankara, 18, 180 Shastri, I.C., 37, 119, 121-123 Shitalaprasada, Brahmachari, 207 Shri Ara Jina, 106 Shri Shanti Jina, 106 Suparshva, Lord, 10 Tatia, Nathmal, 35, 124 Thomas, F.W., 35, 42 Todarmal, Pandit, 81-84, 92, 168 Tolle, Eckhart, 46 Leibniz, G.W. von, 145 Lincoln, Abraham, 101 Machiavelli, N., 52-53 Mahaprajna, Acharya, 162 Mahavira, Lord, 1, 44, 105, 151, 156, 158, 217, 286 Malebranche, Nicholas, 145 Marcel, Gabriel, 122 Matilal, B.K., 134 Umasvati, 43, 127, 148, 152, 206 Umaswami, see Umasvati Upadhye, A.N., 5-9, 98, 117, 149, 155, 191 n. 8, 208 Velmans, Max, 145 Vidyananda, 37, 75, 78, 105 Page #482 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 456 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Williams, R., 153 Vidyananda, Muni, 152 Vidyasagar, Acharya, 60, 92 Vijayaraghavan, K., 100-101 - Vikramaditya, King, 192 n. 9 Voltaire, 79 - Yashovijaya, 122-123 Yativarashabha, Acharya, 72 Zhaveri, J.S., 37 Zydenbos, Robert J., 152 Warren, Herbert, 207 Page #483 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Title Index Gita, 13-14, 17-18,116, 188 Gommatsara Jivakanda, 38, 206-207 Gommatsara Karmakanda, 400 Harmless Souls, 165 Abhidhana-rajendra, 206 Acharanga Sutra, 42, 156 Adipuranam, 72 Antagada-dasao and Anuttarovavaiyadsao, The, 206 Apta Mimamsa, 77-78, 144 Ashta Pahuda, 5, 64-65, 98 Ashtashati, 78 Ashtavakra Gita, 56 Atmabodha, 14 Ishtopadesh, 78 Jai Dhavala, 71-73, 94-95, 99, 102-103, 150 Jaina Epistemology, 121 Karttikeyanupreksha, 19 Kashaya-Pahuda, 71, 94 Kritikarma-shastra, 218 Baras Anuvekkha, 1, 66 Bhagavati Sutra, 37, 43, 105, 148, 152, 156 Bhagavdagita, 14, 17, Bhava Pahuda, 64-65, 85, 98 Bible, 100-101 Bodh Pahuda, 5, 98 Laghiyastriya, 140, 172 Maransamadhi, 80 Mokshmarg Prakashak, 81-85 Merchant of Venice, 99 Moksha-prabhrta (pahuda), 78, 203 Mulachara, 79 Charitra Pahuda, 5, 65 Collected Works of Mahatma Gandhi, 122 Dasaveyaliya Sutra, 42, 155 Dharmaratna Prakarana, 104 Dhavala, 99, 103 Dhyanshatak, 103 Dravya Sangraha, 79, 123 Nishithachurni, 68 Niyamasara, 1, 16, 67, 116, 119, 121, 139, 158, 164, 166, 173, 178-179, 184, 186-187 Nyayakhanda Khadyatika, 123 Epigraphia Indica, 205 Fundamentals of Jainism, 110 Oghaniryukti, 155 Page #484 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 458 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES Out of My Later Years, 53 Outline of Jainism, 390 Sheel-prabhrta (Pahuda), 65, 98, 204 Studies in Jaina Philosophy, 35 Sutra-prabhrta (Suttapahuda), 5, 207 Suyagadamga, 42 Svayambhu Stotra, 10, 60, 102, 106, 141 Svopajna Bhasya, 152, 154 Panchasangraha, 76 Panchastikayasara, 1, 6, 20, 31, 35, 42, 69,71,98, 127, 141, 167, 172, 177 Paramatma-Prakash, 17, 116 Power of Now, 46 Prabhratas, 203 Prashamratiprakaran, 127 Pravachanasara, 1-2, 4-6, 9, 12-13, 19, 24-27, 29, 31-34, 36, 39, 42, 4750, 55-57, 59-64,68, 87-88, 91, 9495, 97-99, 106-108,111, 113, 115117, 119, 121, 126, 131, 136-138, 146-149, 153-154, 156-160, 163164, 166, 169-173, 177, 179, 181182, 184, 186-187, 203-205, 207, 216, 302 Purusharthasiddhyupaya, 88, 109, 168, 207 Tattparya-vrtti, 3, 203, 207, 356, 388 390 Tattva-dipika, 203, 242, 262, 278, 289, 292, 314, 317, 327, 333, 387 Tattvartha (Tattvarthadhigama) Sutra, 35, 37,43, 73-74, 88, 93, 102, 133, 148, 151-154, 185-187, 353 Tattvarthadhigma Bhashya, 152, 206 Tattvarthavartika (Rajavartika), 40, 74, 143 Thanang, 148, 152, 156 Uttaradhyayana churni, 80 Uttaradhyayana Niryukti, 105 Uttaaradhyayana (Sutra), 37, 42-43, 69, 148, 156, 159 Uttaradhyayana vritti, 104 1491 Ratnakaranda Shravakachara, 65, 126, 165 Rayana-sara, 203 Rishibhashitani, 68 Vihayapannatti, 43-45 Visheshavashyakabhashya, 155 Vivekchudamani, 18-19 Samansuttam, 12 Samayasara, 1, 6-7, 9, 25, 32-34,47,55, 67-68, 74, 87, 93, 119, 126, 130, 136, 150, 164, 172 Sarvarthasiddhi, 74, 99, 152-155 Yoga Sutra, 14, 174 Yogasara-Prabhrata, 22, 144 Yuktyanushashan, 105 Page #485 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Word Index aashaya, 357 aayatan, 57 abhavya, 249 abheda, 130, 172, 248, 374 abhibhuya, 119 abhinna, 132 abhipata, 250 abhipraya, 73, 125, 140, 172 a-bhoktr-naya, 396-397 abhyantar, 178 abhyudaya, 11 ab-jyotir, 308 abuddhi-purvak, 45 achailakya, 157,352 achal, 30 achala, 339 acharyas, 60, 108, 217-218, 346, 353 achela, 156 achetan, 26-27, 228, 304 achetanatvat, 24, 27 adarsha, 122 adhah pravrtakarana, 72 adhara, 298 adharma, 40, 89, 103, 113, 150, 263, 304, 308-311, 314 adharma leshyas, 68 adhikara, 222 adhikarana, 341 adhikaranatva, 224 adhikaras, 2 adhikarin, 343 adhikrtya, 354 adhivasa, 354 adhyasa, 118 adhyavasana, 150 adhyavasana bhavas, 50-51, 174 adhyayana, 379 agam, 134, 365 agarin, 377 aghati karmas, 214 a-guni-naya, 396 a-gurulaghutva, 272 aham ekko khalu suddho, 29, 31 aham, 25, 30 ahankara, 51, 89, 107, 136, 271, 329 ahankarika, 89, 256 ahetuka, 30 ahimsa, 106, 110, 151 aikibhuta, 123 aikya, 123 aishvarya, 388 aiyatta, 31 ajiva, 29, 31, 224 ajnana, 151 ajugavam, 209 a-kala-naya, 396 akalushata, 70 akanksha, 232 akara, 45, 228, 234, 301, 369, 372 akarta, 115, 177 Page #486 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 460 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES akartratva, 115, 177 a-kartr-naya, 396 akkhaya, 44 akramya, 236 aksha, 245, 342 akutam, 359 akutih, 359 alamba, 381, 389 alambante, 282 alochana, 158, 164, 352-353 aloka, 304, 310 a-mechaka, 398 amoda, 251 amsha (ansha), 131, 313 amurta, 22, 141, 143, 244, 306 amurta eva, 144 amurtika, 143 anadyantah, 30, 34 anagara, 45 anagara-uvaoga, 44 anagarovautta, 44-45 anakara-jnana, 206 anakulatva, 301 anantanubhandi kashaya, 97 ananya, 131 ananya parinama, 96 anapayitvam, 225 an-apoha, 289 anasana, 360-361 anatamatva, 118 anatma-bhuta, 40-41 anatmamatmopacarat, 118 anekant, 107, 121, 140, 151, 205, 217, 229, 258, 366, 368 anekanta-kalita, 386 anekanta-tattva, 386 angadadi-paryaya-api, 291 angara, 163 anihnava, 347 anishta phala, 75, 166 a-nitya-naya, 395 aniyati-naya, 395 antahkarana, 118 antahkarana jada, 118 antaraya, 223 antaraya karman, 213, 226 antarhita, 258 antas tattva, 130, 386 anubhaga, 381, 389 anubhava, 68, 73, 90, 367, 386 anubhuti, 4, 347, 370 anugrhitam, 273 anukampa, 70, 79, 92, 95, 98-99, 101 102, 105, 107 anukrmavishai, 84 anumantavyah, 141 anupalambha, 246 anuraga, 256, 263, 376, 379 anushthana, 104 anuvratas, 164 anuvrtti, 320 anvaya, 257, 281, 290-291, 305, 319 anvyayi 39 anya, 24, 26-27, 288, 335 anya nirpeksha, 22, 29 anyatva, 26, 132, 286, 288, 293 anyonya-vritti, 231 apadanatva, 224 apakara, 76 aparamarthika, 249 aparikarma, 350 aparinama, 134 aparinami, 124, 133, 177 aparinami chaitanya tattva, 134-135 aparityakta, 134 apasada, 380 apavada, 363 apeksha, 115 a-phale, 385 api, 75 apoha, 288-289 appa, 38 appa divo bhava, 116 appa divvena jaladi, 116 appa so paramappa, 116 a-pradesha, 310, 317 apramatta, 23, 155 aprashasta, 55, 59, 68, 381 Page #487 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ WORD INDEX 461 aprashasta dhyana, 68 aprashasta raga, 48 aprathak, 132 aprathaktva, 211 apratikrushta, 391 Arahanta, 58, 125, 138, 160-161, 337 arambha, 155, 173, 357, 381, 389 aranala, 251 aravinda, 251 Arhat, 4, 167, 217-218, 238-239, 257, 260, 323, 351, 356, 359, 366, 376, 384, 388 arihanta, 6, 10, 257 arjavavastha, 118 arkatejasa iva, 379 arpita anarpita, 141 arta, 64, 68, 71, 77 arta dhyana, 78 artha, 116, 220-221, 228, 261, 278, 282, 287, 312, 316, 320, 342, 347, 369, 382 artham antarena, 324 aryante, 261 asadbhavasya 356 asamanjatiya, 25 asamanjatiya paryaya, 28 asambandha, 22 asamkhyeya, 207,309 a-samyag-avabodha, 247... asamyam, 173 asan, 293 asana-nipata, 250 a-sarvagata-naya, 395 a-sat-utpada, 290 asata, 114, 223, 340 asatkaryavada, 129 ashraya, 52, 68, 90, 131 ashubha, 21, 39-40, 47-48, 50-52, 54 60, 62-64, 66-71, 73-76, 78-83, 86, 88-91, 94, 136, 153-154, 168, 179, 220-221, 322) 351 ashubha bhava, 73 - ashubha bhavna parihar, 67 ashubha karma, 66 ashubha parinama, 40, 69, 72 ashubha upayoga, 47-48, 56-57, 68, 87, 208, 222 ashubha yoga, 66, 77 a-shuddha naya, 397 ashuddha, 28, 47, 91, 355 ashuddhi, 92 a-shunya-naya, 395 asnana, 352 asparsha, 329 asrava, 73-74, 78, 80, 93, 96, 132, 161 asrava bhava, 174 asrayabhuta, 261 asthani, 281 asti-kaya, 389 astitva, 220, 274, 289, 316 astita-avaktavya-naya, 393 astitva-nastitva-avaktavya-naya, 394 astitva-nastitva-naya, 393 astitva naya, 392 astitva-samanya, 272 astittvavat, 392 asuras, 388 a-svabhava-naya, 396 a-tad-bhava, 132, 286-287, 306 ati sarvatra varjayeta, 160 atikarkasha, 364 atindriya-jnana, 210 atma, 27, 38-39, 41, 76, 79, 133, 137, 143, 155, 168, 179, 318, 335 atma-bhuta, 40-41 atma chintan, 76 atma dharma, 89 atma dhyana, 96 atma dravya, 24, 125 cima shuddhi, 67 atma-svabhava, 151, 172 atma-tattva, 386 atma-trptam, 264 atma-vishuddhi, 72, 77 atma-vyavahara, 271 atmajnana, 96, 117 atman, 22, 130, 169, 205, 209, 245, 272, 283 - Page #488 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 462 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES ayata-anaikya, 269 ayatana, 254 ayata-samanya, 268 ayata-vishesha, 269 a-yatha, 385 ayati, 222 ayuh, 389 a-yuta-siddhatva, 278 atmanah, 335 atmanam, 25 atmanam aparinaman dahana iva, 241 atmanam atmaneva uddhareta, 116 atyanta heya, 45, 52, 55 atyanta vibhakta, 39 audarika, 328 audasinya, 271 audayika, 22-23, 58, 136, 141, 239 audayika bhava, 23, 102, 136 audayika karman, 58, 239 aupshamika, 23, 33 avabodha, 234, 246 avachchanna, 259 avadhi, 206, 272, 367 avagraha, 206, 227, 247-248, 308, 313 avaktavya-naya, 393 avarana, 226-227, 237 avaraniya, 223 avasara, 279 avashyaka, 157, 351-352 avastha, 118 avatishthate, 21 avatthiya, 44 avaya, 209, 227 a-vibhaga, 314 avibhakta Pradesh, 132 avidya, 118 a-vikalpa-naya, 394 avinabhava, 128-131, 165, 280 avinabhavi, 71 avinabhavin, 230 avinabhuta, 282 aviparita-phala-karanam, 381 avirati, 37, 51, 97, 174 avirodha, 113 avishuddha, 33 avivikta, 367 a-vrtta, 230 avvayaya, 44 avyatiriktabhava, 130 aya, 15 aya-bhavenam, 43 ayata, 205 badha, 319 bahiratma, 108 bahittham majjhattham, 155 bahu punya rashau, 106 bahu-mana, 347 bahya, 178 bahya sadhanadi hi, 84 bahya tapa, 157 bala, 245, 318-319, 389 balah, 151 baliyan, 147 bandha, 93, 311 bandha marg, 52, 68, 90 bandhasya prasiddheh, 327 bhagwant atma, 387 bhakti, 84 bhanga, 391 Bharat-kshetra, 218 bhattarakas, 217 bhav dharan, 319 bhava, 28, 44, 58, 64, 70, 79, 91, 138, 141, 144, 174, 204, 220, 227, 258 259, 290, 297, 301, 317 bhava bandha, 137, 147, 332 bhava karma, 174 bhava-karman, 300 bhava prana, 26 bhavaka, 374 bhavana, 224 bhavana-saushthava, 223 bhava-naya, 394 bhavani, 281 bhava-prana, 320 bhavaprana Jharnat, 20 bhavya, 373 Page #489 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ WORD INDEX 463 bheda, 172, 264, 272, 278, 340 bhed-abhyasa, 16 bhed-vigyan, 24 bhinna, 27, 132, 314 bhinna sattayen, 133, 135 bhinna svabhavat, 123 bhitti, 355 bhoga-nimittam, 61,85 bhokta, 36, 115, 143 bhoktr-naya, 396 bhumika, 103, 107,259 bhutarth, 34, 387 bhuti, 234 bhutkalpam, 400 buddhi, 124 buddhi-purvak, 45 chitra, 307 chitta, 33, 360 chitta bhitti, 51, 248 chitta bhumi, 89 chitta prasad, 69 chitta vrtti, 169 chitta-kshana, 281 chittaprasadnam, 100 chittasya kshobha, 70 chittavrtti nirodha, 14 chadmastha, 250, 379 chaitanya, 18-19, 38, 136, 143, 232, 239 chaitanya anuvidhayi, 63 chaitanya anuvidhayi parinama, 39 chaitanya svabhava, 27 chaitanya vicar, 58 chaitanya-samanya-mahiman, 241 chanyah, 298 charana-tattva, 2 charitra, 12, 31, 36, 47, 79, 114, 166, 172, 178, 221 charitra-moha, 107, 113 charitra mohaniya karman, 97, 220 cheda, 20 chedopasthapaka, 352-353 chesta, 365 chetaka-svabhava, 232 chetana, 20-21, 26, 35-38, 40, 42, 124 125, 131, 135, 211, 296, 300, 304 chetana upayogamaya, 20 chetanatva, 27,230 chetayita, 38 chheda, 355 chid-vivartana, 258 chinmatra, 22, 29-30, 35 chit, 400 chit shakti matra, 22 daiva-naya, 396 dana, 61, 84, 90, 95, 102, 105, 379, 388 danshan mulo dhammo, 19 darshan, 2, 21, 36, 38, 42-45, 47, 114, 172, 174, 206, 212, 217, 226 darshanavaraniya karma, 213 darshan-moha, 113 darshan-mohaniya karman, 97, 220 daya, 95, 104-105-106, 108 daya dharma ka mool hai, 19 daya visudhho dhammo, 98 daya-dama-tyaga-samadhi, 105 dayamurti, 106 deshana, 95 deshana labdhi, 95 devas, 109,321,323-324, 368, 380, 388 dhammam bhoga nimittam, 154 dhammas, 13 dharanant dharmah, 18 dharma, 11, 13, 19, 31, 35, 41, 51, 54, 56, 61-64, 66, 69-70, 74, 84, 89, 91,95, 98, 103-104, 106-107, 113, 131, 153, 159-169, 171, 178, 209, 217, 219-22, 229, 253, 256, 263264, 276, 282, 295-296, 304-305, 308-311, 314, 359, 372, 375, 392 dharma anuraga, 87 dharma dhyana, 68, 71, 78, 103 dharma sadbhavat, 63 dharmatma, 63 dharmika, 57, 380 dhrauvya, 20, 128, 132, 205, 221 dhrauvyena, 225 Page #490 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 464 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES dvesham, 375 dvyanukadi-anantanta-pudgalanam, 327 eikagrya, 365 ek matra karana, 4 eka-bhokta, 352 ekagratah, 172 ekam agram, 374 ekantah, 144, 229 ekantena, 168 ekasmin chaiva samaye, 127 ekatva, 28, 30, 41, 144, 150, 339 eshana, 157, 361 eshana-dosha, 157, 360 eshana-samiti, 157 eva, 27, 33, 49, 76, 89, 131, 136, 151 evam, 49,61 dhruva, 30-31, 58, 127, 129, 134, 339 dhruvatva, 339-340 dhyan aur samadhi, 106 dhyana, 61, 71, 77-78, 341, 379 divya, 236 dosha, 169, 365 dosha-vinigraham, 106 drashta, 115, 234 drashta jnata, 82 drashti, 164, 248, 372 drashtr-jnatr, 172, 374 dravati, 128 dravya, 20, 23, 26, 127, 129-130, 132, 134-135, 147, 174, 21, 268 dravja bandh, 332-333 dravya bhava, 128, 224 dravya himsa, 150 dravya karma, 63, 174 dravya naya, 392, 394 dravya paryaya, 131,269 dravja pranas, 20, 24, 26-27, 150, 319 dravya sat lakshanam, 127-128 dravya vishesh, 2 dravya-bhava karman, 169, 366 dravyagatah svabhavah, 102, 141, 146 dravya-jata, 312 druvya-karman, 300 dravya-kshetra-kala-bhava, 242 dravyam, 304 dravyam guna paryayashrayam, 131 dravyantara, 33 dravyarthikena, 293 dravya-samaya, 313 dravyatva, 128-130, 272, 283, 290, 292, 298 dravyatva-guna, 285 duhkhankura, 255 dukhit mana, 101 dukkha, 150 dura-bhavya, 250 durlalita, 283, 305, 356 dvaita, 13,52 dvandas, 13 dvesh, 11, 47, 69, 88, 97, 103, 114, 173 gana, 294 Gandharas, 218 ganin, 349 ganyamanasya, 311 gati, 41, 75, 129, 134, 320, 388 gauna, 92, 141, 378 ghana, 226 ghatia, 6 ghatia karman, 116 ghee, 58 grahstha, 377, 379 grabya, 139, 236 granthi, 13, 223, 340 guna, 128, 130, 205, 211, 221 guna paryaya, 129-131,285 gunadhika-samgat, 384 gunantara, 131 guna-paryaya, 269 guna-samga, 384 guna-samidadovasevi, 381 gunasthan, 8 guni-naya, 396 gupta, 386 gupti, 12, 67, 69, 92, 158-159, 164, 168, 170-171, 178, 348, 370, 372 guru, 87, 351, 354, 378 Page #491 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ WORD INDEX 465 hetu, 75-76, 90, 227 heya, 47-48, 52, 56, 73, 81, 90, 96, 105, 166 himsa, 8, 110, 148, 150-151, 153, 155, 165, 204, 351, 355 bri, 105 ichchha, 107 iha, 206, 209, 227, 236 ihedam, 278 indirya-rodha, 352 indraneel ratna, 119 indriya-rodha, 157 indriya vishaya, 75 irya-samiti, 381,389 ishta, 75 ishta anishta, 169 ishta phala, 166 ishvara-naya, 396 itara-samagrim, 245 itarearashraya, 299 ityadivat prapashyatah, 278 iyata, 351 iyrati, 261 jiva guna, 22, 35, 38, 42 jiva niyaka, 24-28, 41 jiva samasa, 41 jiva sthana, 25 jiva svabhava, 27 jiva tattva, 24-27, 123 jiva vishesh, 29 jivad-avastha, 250 jivadavasthendriyah, 251 jivasya svakasya bhavah, 136 jivatma, 125 jivatva, 24, 41, 134, 318, 320 jivayoh, 150 jnana, 2, 21, 36, 42-45, 47, 114, 125, 172, 206, 212 jnana chetna, 36 jnana-ineya-advaita-naya, 395 jnana-jneya-dvaita-naya, 395 jnana-naya, 397 jnana-tattva, 2 jnanavaraniya, 240 jnanavaraniya karma, 213 jnani, 102, 115, 170, 370 jnapti, 243, 245, 369, 372, 375 jnata, 36, 115 inayak bhava, 33-34 inayak svabhava, 33 jnayak-shuddha, 173 jnayaka, 33, 124, 232-233, 343 jneya, 115, 127 jneya jnayak, 33 jneja-jnatr-tattva-tatha-pratiti-lakshanena, 373 jneyatam apanna, 302 jneya-tattva, 2 jo janadi so nanam, 124 jugupsa, 105 jyotis, 297 jada, 118 jadhajadaruva, 157 jaghanya, 76 jaghanya parinama, 72 japa, 220 jati, 75 Jina, 15, 106-107, 116, 172, 228, 237 238, 242, 253, 260-263, 176-277, 288-289, 323, 342, 346, 353-354, 359, 377-378, 382, 390 Jinendra, 261 jiva, 20, 22-28, 31, 33, 35, 37-38, 41- 44, 52, 55, 68-70, 91, 95, 99, 103, 114, 122-123, 129-131, 134-135, 141, 143-144, 147-150, 175, 177, 205, 211, 297, 309-310, 318-319, 335, 351 jiva dravya, 2, 22, 24-25, 37, 43, 104 kadapi, 115 kala, 347 kula-naya, 396 kala-padartha, 312 kalanu, 309-310, 312, 316 Page #492 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 466 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES kalushata, 70-71, 92 kapatheenata, 105 kapot, 69 karakas, 52, 68, 75, 89, 100, 116, 136, 169, 224 karakatva, 224 karana, 227 karanasamagri, 118 karanavaiparitya, 379 karma, 14-16, 18, 31, 33-35, 40, 42, 45, 50-51, 56, 58, 61, 63-68, 71-73, 76, 78, 80-81, 83, 87, 93, 96-97, 102103, 115-116, 125-126, 135-137, 139, 141-142, 144, 146, 153, 156, 169, 174, 179, 204-205, 209-210, 212-213, 337, 351, 374-375 karma-bhava, 142 karma chetana, 36 karma krta, 23, 141 karma santati, 175 karma-kshaya-nimmitam, 61 karman, 4, 6, 21-23, 25, 27, 40, 44, 47, 49, 58, 81, 85, 90, 135-136, 138139, 141-143, 147-148, 150, 169, 174-177, 180, 209, 211, 213, 217, 223-226, 237-240, 242-243, 248, 250, 296-297, 299, 301, 306, 319321, 323, 328-330, 333-337, 341- 342, 357, 370-371, 385, 386, 398 399 karma-nirpeksha, 22-23, 33-35, 44, 58, 137 karmaodaya, 136 karma-parinameneyrati, 261 karma-phala, 300, 319 karmaphala chetana, 36 karma-rahita, 31, 33-34, 44, 179 karmatva, 224 karma-udaya, 136 karma-upadhi, 23,59 karma-yoga, 105 karmodaya, 135 karta, 36, 115, 135, 138-139, 142, 147, 177, 325 kartratva, 142 kartr-naya, 396 kartrtva, 224 karuna, 97-99, 102-103, 105, 107, 110 111, 114 karuna bhava, 99 karunabhavo, 97-98, 108, 111, 113, karuna buddhya, 108 karunaya abhava, 113 karya, 73, 77 kashaya, 12, 48, 51, 59-60, 87, 109, 159, 164, 171, 219, 226, 360, 369, 381 kashaya mandata, 93 katham na, 231 kathanchit, 62, 143, 398, 400 n. 1 kaya cheshta, 160 kayotsarga, 352 kevala, 29-30, 34, 205, 226, 232, 246, 320-321, 324, 397 kevala-jiva, 246 kevala-jnana, 226, 246, 248 kevala-jnanin, 232 kevali, 4, 6 kevalin, 226, 232-233 kheda, 101-102, 248 khela, 321 khyati, 106 khyati puja laabha, 64 klesha, 95 klesha kalpana, 34, 124, 234 koti, 319 koti-dvaya, 284 krama baddha paryaya, 117, 177-178 kramabhavi-vishesha, 221 kramaparinameneyratah, 261 kramashah, 63 kramatah, 52, 55, 58, 63, 84, 87, 90, 94, 154, 167, 177, 379, 384 kripa, 101 kriya, 178, 299-300 kriya-bhava, 305 kriya-naya, 397 krta-krtya, 177 kshana, 282-283 Page #493 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ WORD INDEX kshana-bhanga, 282, 317 kshanikatva, 283 kshapak shreni, 72 kshaya, 33 kshayika, 23, 58, 237, 239-240, 243 kshayika-jnana, 210 kshayiki, 136, 239 kshayopashamika, 23, 33, 58 kshetra, 313 kshiti-shayana, 352 kshobha, 11-12, 13, 18, 66, 164, 170 171, 219, 259 kula, 348, 390 kundalavastha, 118 kunthikrta, 375 labha vancha rahitam, 106 Lajja, 105 lakshana, 35, 37 Lakshanasya, 330 lakshaya, 61 Lakshyate, 273 lepa, 364 leshya, 68-69, 71 linga, 260, 306, 308, 390-391 loch, 352 lodhra, 337 loka, 304, 310 lokottara, 227 mada, 51, 89 madhyastha, 15-16, 85, 217, 341, 381 maha-moha, 246 mahartha, 30, 339 mahatmya, 388 mahavrata, 164, 348 maîtri, 105 mamakara, 136, 271 mamatva, 107, 114, 155 mamedam, 25 manah-paryaya, 206 manda kashaya, 91 manda udaya, 70 mangala, 86 manogupti, 67 manushya-kshetra, 218 manushya-vyavahara, 271 marg, 168 mata, 9, 238 maya, 9-10, 238 mayacharo, 9 metta, 103 mithya, 130, 398 mithya charitra, 37 mithya darshan, 37, 97, 99. 174, mithyadrashti, 92, 108 mithyatva, 37, 51, 92, 96-97, 114-115, 174 moha, 4, 11, 12-13, 31, 47, 49, 69, 8889, 96-99, 103, 105, 107-108, 111,113-114, 125, 143, 147, 159, 164, 171, 173, 180-181, 259, 372 moha sanchhanna, 49 467 mohadi, 169 mohana, 330 mohaniya karman, 136, 213, 226 moksha, 11, 23, 57-58, 60, 72, 82, 85, 92, 107, 136, 162, 174, 179 moksha-hetu, 85 moksha marg, 68, 71, 90, 130, 167 moksharthi, 27 moksha-tattva, 385 moksha-tattva-sadhana-tattva, 385 moodh, 268 mool sadhan, 277 mrgatrashna, 50 muchyate, 146 mudha, 259 mudha mati, 51, 89 mudra, 106 mukhya, 141, 169, 378 mukura, 121 mula, 104 mula-cheda, 363 mula-guna, 157, 160, 164, 352, 354 mula-karana, 296 mum, 13 muni, 204 Page #494 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 468 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES murchcha, 107, 15, 160, 371, 381, 389 murta, 137, 237, 244, 306, 368 murta-amurta, 306 murtani, 244 murtimana, 143 na yatha syat, 363 naimittika, 229 nairgranthya, 384 nama karman, 24-27, 252, 296-297, 321 nama-naya, 394 namaskara, 376 naraka, 321 nasha, 205 nastitva-avaktavya-naya, 393 nastitva-naya, 392 natad-yuvavad, 395 nava tattva, 29 naya, 172, 204-205, 303, 392, 397-398 naya paksha, 34 nayavada, 398 nayo jnatur abhiprayo, 140 nibandhana, 304-305 nidan, 51, 89, 237, 256 nidhanandhavad, 397 nigoda, 82, 92 nigraha, 79 nihkankshatatva, 348 nihpratigha-vijrmbhita, 386 nih-pratikarma, 359 nikhata, 242 mimitta, 23, 65, 75-77, 82, 113-115, 137-142, 144-145, 154-155, 296, 305, 319, 332, 336 nimitta karana, 63, 138, 144-145, 169, 174 nimitta karta, 142 nirakara, 332 nir-argla, 369 nirdayata, 108 nirdosh, 30 nirgrantha, 204, 359, 383 nirahara, 358 nirjara, 66-67, 72, 94, 104, 125, 390 nirmal 30 nirmam, 29 nirmudhadrshtitva, 348 nicodha, 66, 73, 341 nirpeksha, 31, 33, 64, 106-107, 115, 162, 338, 357, 378 niruradhi, 21-22, 34, 142 nirvana, 11, 47, 52, 55, 60-62, 65-66, 85, 90, 162, 167, 169, 174, 218219, 263-264, 342, 369, 379, 386, 390 nirvichikitsatva, 348 nir-vikalpaka, 332 nirvikara shuddha chaitanya dhartiti dharmah, 31 nir-vishesham, 22 nirurttasti, 296 nirurtti, 105, 177 niryapaka, 353 niryapakas, 353 nishankitatva, 348 nishchaya, 67, 117, 119, 121, 167-168, 178, 224, 229, 257, 333, 338 nishchaya charitra, 66, 86, 164, 166-167, 179 nishchaya dharma, 104 nishchaya-jivatva, 318 nishchaya moksha marg, 168 nishchaya naya, 20, 28, 81, 101, 113, 133, 138-140, 142-143, 146-147, 150, 169, 337-338, 383, 397 nishchayabhashi, 82 nishchayabhashi mithyadrasthi, 81 nishchayatah, 146 nishchayena bandha, 146 nishchinomi, 263 nishchita, 383 nishchitah prashantatma, 385 nishkriya, 23 nishpanna-nishpattimat, 278 nitya, 128, 134 nitya shuddha chit-ananda, 133 nityam, 128 nityatva, 307 Page #495 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ WORD INDEX 469 nivishta, 313 niurtti, 369, 375, 378, 384 niyam, 16, 61, 158, 379 noagama, 343 noindriya, 349 no-karman, 22, 306 nyaya, 228 paccakkham vinnanam, 209 padartha, 93, 169, 173, 179, 222, 248, 263, 268-269, 312, 385 padma, 69 pakshatikranta, 34 panak, 172, 374 panch parameshthi, 59 panchagga guna, 22 pancharatna, 384 panditya pradarshan, 6 papa, 74-80, 85, 88-90, 92-93, 103, 153, 179, 256, 323 papa karma, 88 papa rupa, 68 papamaya, 67 papasrava, 71 para, 13, 21, 25, 39-40, 47-52, 54-55, 57, 59, 62, 66-69, 72-73, 102, 152, 224, 243, 246, 262, 335, 353 para-daya, 102 para dravya, 27, 133 para nimitta, 147 parahita-parasukha-kamana, 103 para-jiva, 150 para-samaya, 268, 270, 271, 277, 279, 397, 400 n. 1 para-samaya pravrtti, 167 para-samayikas, 270 param, 107 param atman, 169 param Brahma, 106 param dharma, 106 param samadhi, 16 param saukhyam, 126 paramanu, 325 paramanu dravyanam pindhah, 325 paramartha, 15, 34, 50, 61,85, 108, 114, 246, 248, 256, 299, 380 paramartha bhava, 85, 111 paramartha khalu samayah (paramartha khalu samao), 15 pramarthena, 229 paramarthika, 248 Paramatma, 31-33, 116, 179, 366 parameshvaras, 217 parampara se, 71 paramparaya, 64, 90, 169, 231 param-upeksha samyamvipreet, 113 paraspara sapeksha, 140 paratman, 169 paricchindatah, 261 parichcheda, 227 parichchitti, 227 parigraha, 155, 157, 162, 173, 357, 381, 389 parihara, 390 pariharamana, 354 parinama, 11, 18, 20-21, 34, 36-37, 58, 72-73, 76, 78, 91, 118-119, 124, 127-128, 134, 219, 312 parinama vishuddhi, 150 parinamansheeh 44, 135 parinamayanti, 248 parinami, 20, 44, 118, 124, 128, 134 135 prinami bhava, 134 parinami nitya, 20, 124, 128, 132 parinamika, 143 parinamika bhava, 22-23, 26, 31, 34, 44, 85, 137, 142 parispandan, 305 parmartha, 89 parmarthatah, 254 parokkham, 209 paroksha, 206, 209 paroksa-jnana, 250 parokshatva, 245 paropakara, 107 paryaya, 22, 26, 28, 43-44, 47-54, 58, 67, 127-135, 172, 205, 211 Page #496 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 470 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES paryayarthikena, 293 paryayatva 272 paryaye, 298 paryushan, 178 patayatah, 364 patra, 379 paudgalika, 209 paudgalika-karman, 150, 320 pavitra, 30 pavitti, 66 phala, 75, 221 phalavaiparitya, 379 picumanda, 297 pishacha, 253 pita, 243 prabhavana, 348 prabhu, 45, 143 pradesha, 44, 120, 207, 230, 237, 245, 274, 279, 309-310, 314-318, 389 pradeshika, 278 pradhan bhuta, 76 pradur-bhava, 292 prajna, 65-66 prakrti, 76, 124 prakrti-bhuta, 301 pramad, 108, 148, 150, 258, 390-391 pramadcharya, 71 pramadis, 390 pramana, 172, 374 pramatta, 23 prameshthins, 217-218 pramiyante, 368 prana, 123, 146, 150-152, 206, 318-319, 381, 389 pranamanı, 217 pranati, 218 prani, 150 prapta, 296 prapyate, 299-301 prasham bhava, 70, 92-93, 99, 159 prashamsukha, 127 prashanta atma, 159 prashasta dhyana, 68 prashasta, 52, 57-59, 68-69, 71, 73, 80 prashasta raga, 47-48, 55, 57,59,62,68, 70, 80, 82, 87, 90, 92, 94-95, 105, 107, 113-114, 126, 154, 378 pratapati, 223 prathak, 290 prthakatva, 26, 89, 120, 132, 230, 254, 263, 286 pratibhasa-maya, 241 pratikraman, 164, 178, 352 pratikrushta, 391 pratipadam, 293 pratisamdhana, 353 pratishedha, 295 pratisiddha, 139 pratiti, 4, 370, 372 pratyakhyana, 164, 351-352 pratyaksha, 206, 236, 244-245 pratyaya, 97, 169, 270 pravaha, 279-280 pravarana-sahitam chihnam, 390 pravrajya, 391 pravitta, 341, 375 pravrtteh sa-nimitta, 378 pravrtti, 105, 177, 369, 372, 378, 384 prayashchitta, 178 prayojanavana, 64,87 pudgala, 24-25, 123, 205, 211-212, 238, 246 pudgala-dravya, 306 pudgala karman, 85 pudgala-prana, 320 puja, 106, 388 punya, 21, 39-40, 51, 55-59, 61-62, 66 70, 69-70, 72-80, 82, 85-90, 9293, 95, 101, 103-106, 111, 114, 153-154, 179-180, 238, 256, 323 punya bandha, 65, 71 punya karma, 72, 95 punyamaya, 67 purna paramatma, 133 purushartha, 59,75 purushkara-naya, 396 purva-paksha, 298, 390 Page #497 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ WORD INDEX quodammodo, 204, 233, 264, 294-295, 369, 371, 398-400 raga, 11, 57, 97, 103, 107, 114, 219 ragadi bhava, 133 raagadi samasta vibhava rahitam, 29, 31 ramani, 347 ramayasi, 347 ramya, 126, 250 rati, 250, 379 ratto bandhadi kammam, 137 raudra, 68, 77 raudra dhyana, 78, 103 riddhi, 388 ruche, 259 ruchita, 259 ruksha, 311-312 rukshatva, 397 rupa, 251, 349-350, 390 rupena, 294 sad-avishishta, 289 sadbhava, 167, 290, 301, 321 sadhak, 73 sadhaktam, 138, 147, 302 sadhan, 30, 61, 72, 74, 80, 95-96, 133, 154, 167, 178-179, 277 sadhu (sahu), 106, 158-159, 163, 165, 217-218, 323-324, 344, 367, 377378 sadrashya-astitva, 272, 274, 276 sad-utpada, 292 sagara 163 sagara-uvaoga, 44 sagarovautta, 44 sahabhavi, 129-130 sahabhavi-vishesha, 221 sahaja, 126, 224, 247, 250 sahakara, 285 sahavarti, 129-130 sakal charitra, 111 sakala-jnanni, 341 sakara, 332 sakimchanatva, 350 sakshat, 231 sakshat-karana, 232 sakshi, 118 sakshi bhava, 115 sallekhana, 110, 391 sama, 11-12, 14-15, 158, 163, 171, 174, 219, 382 samaamah khalu dharma, 19 samabhava, 12, 14, samachara, 390 sama-darshan, 16 sama-darshinah, 17 samadhi, 16, 65 samadhi-marana, 110 samadrashtitva, 352 samah, 372 samaiyam, 12 sama-kastha, 375 samana, 12, 54, 157-161, 163-165, 171, 173 samanya, 205, 293, 386 samanya-guna, 272 samanya-lakshana, 277 samanya-naya, 394 samaraddham, 212 samarthyat, 335 samasanna-bhavya, 250 samastatma-pradeshan, 248 samata, 17, 163 samata rahitasya, 16 samatva, 14, 18 471 samavaya, 125, 225 samavetam, 127 samaya, 12, 15, 257, 283, 289, 308, 310, 312-316, 351 samaya-padartha, 319 samaya pratibaddha, 15 samayaye samano hoi, 159 samayika, 12-13, 351-353 samayika-samyama, 353 sambandha, 388 sambhava, 205, sambhavana, 238 sambhavita, 239 Page #498 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 472 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES sambhuti, 239 samchetana, 232 samharani, 281 samiti, 12, 61, 92, 157-158, 164-165, 168, 171, 178, 348, 352, 361, 372 sammaditthi, 16 sammam, 16 samo, 11-12, 158 sampradanatva, 224 samsara, 2, 17, 23, 51-52, 102, 130, 136 137, 167, 180, 213, 216, 222-223, 239, 256, 262, 264, 299, 334, 350, 367-368, 380, 383-384, 386, samsara avastha, 20 samsara-tattva, 384 samskara, 174, 247, 260, 350, 361 samsthana, 321 samudaya, 131, 268, 282 samudghata, 122-123, 309 samuparata, 372 samvara, 66-67, 72-74, 88, 94, 104, 125 samvarta, 310 samvatsari pratikraman, 178 samvedana, 120, 122, 229, 231, 260 samvedan-sheeh 99, 102 samvedya, 231 samvega, 70, 92, 99 samvid, 234, 281 samvritti, 36, 304 samya, 11, 17-18, 66, 171, 218, 346 samyak, 70, 130, 171, 372, 389, 398 samyak-darshan, 4, 24, 70, 81, 92, 99, 218, 372, 386 samyak-drashti, 4 samyak-jnana, 218 samyak-shraddhan, 4 samyaktva, 79, 90, 99, 103 samyam, 51, 74, 96, 105, 153, 155, 159, 168, 170-171, 173, 178-179, 222, 357, 363, 372, 377 samyat, 171, 383 samyatatvanam, 371 sangha, 377 sanklesh, 21, 39, 48, 54-55, 57, 59, 62, 76-78, 88, 91, 95, 111, 154, 323, 334, 381, 389 santhara, 110 sanyasa, 376 sanyat, 158-159, 164 saparahidam, 98 sa-pratipaksha, 128, 139 sapta-bhang, 205 sapta-bhangi, 294 sara, 256 sarva, 155 sarvagata-naya, 395 sarvajna, 116-117, sarvajnata, 116 sarva-manoratha-sthana, 386 sarvatha, 55, 80, 398 sarvatha kshanik, 128 sarvatha nitya, 128 sarvatra sambhavam, 243 sa-sakara, 340 sat, 30, 127, 278, 281, 289, 339, 384 sat avasthitam, 131 sat dravya lakshanam, 128 sata, 223, 379 sata-vedaniya karma, 102 sata-vedaniya, 255 sat-kara, 388 satkaryavada, 129 satta, 220, 278, 292 sattatmana, 278 sat-utpada, 290 saukhjam, 107 savadya-lesho, 106 sa-vikalpaka, 332 savvaha, 400 n. 1 seva, 105 shabda-brahman, 264, 394 Shakras, 254 shakti, 51, 221, 290, 307, 314-315, 340, 361 shakti tapas tyaga, 160 shama, 11-12, 14, 158-159, 163, 171 shamit, 159, 383 shasanam etad budhyate, 387 Page #499 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ WORD INDEX sheel, 65-66 shraddhan, 24, 369 shraman, 12, 19, 63, 106-107, 126, 149, 156-158, 160-163, 170-173, 217, 222-223, 263-264, 302, 341-342, 346-349, 350-354, 350-354, 356, 358, 360-361, 364-365, 368, 372, 374-379, 381-382, 384-385, 390391, 394 shramanabhasa, 382 shramana-hood, 161, 338, 354, 372-373, 383, 385-386 shramana-state, 149, 354-355, 358-359, 362, 366, 369, 372 shramani, 390 shramanya, 171, 263 shravaka, 377 shruta-jnana, 368 shruta-jnanin, 232 shruta-kevalin, 232-233 Shrutaskandha, 2 shruti, 206 shubha, 2, 19, 21, 39-40, 47-48, 52-61, 63-64, 66-73, 76, 78-79, 81-84, 8691, 93-96, 98, 103-104, 111, 114, 125, 136-137, 154, 161, 168, 180, 220, 253, 322, 351, 375 shubha bhava, 65, 73, 80, 94, 105, 111 shubha karma, 76, 80, 85 shubha parinama, 40, 69, 73, 76, 93 shubha upayoga, 2, 8, 48, 59-60, 62-63, 68, 82-83, 87-88, 98-99, 161, 174, 177, 208-209 shuddha, 8, 18, 29-30, 32-34, 39,47, 54, 57-58, 60, 62-64, 70-73, 75, 79, 8182, 84, 91-92, 94, 96, 220, 223, 382, 386 shuddha atma, 96, 179 shuddha atma tattva, 160 shuddha chit svarupe charanam, 31 shuddha naya, 397 shuddha parinama, 73 shuddha-rupa, 349 shuddha upayoga, 2, 19, 34, 48, 51, 66, 68, 79, 81, 83, 89, 103, 179, 209 shuddhata, 72, 79 shuddhatmano'nubhavat, 379 saddhatmano vipreet, 89 shudra, 391 shukla, 69 shukla dhyana, 78 shukla leshya, 69 shunya, 221 shunya-naya, 395 shunyata, 282, 288-289 Siddha, 210-211, 213-214, 217-218, 252, 277, 323-324, 342, 344, 346, 367, 381, 386, 388-389 siddha-chaitanya-samanya, 245 siddhanta, 251 siddha-samaan, 168 siddha-siddhimat, 277-278 siddhi, 170, 274, 371, 390 siddhyati, 371 slesha, 298 smrti, 206 Snigdha, 311-312 Snigdhatva, 397 sparsha, 250 sphurjaj-jyotih, 265 sthana, 279 sthapana-naya, 394 sthavara, 223 sthiti, 205 sthitikarana, 348 sthula, 237, 245, 270 stuti, 351 sukha, 209 sukshamatva, 368 sukshma, 245, 315, 354 sukshma-labdhi-aparyapta, 390 sumarga, 162 su-shila, 154, 253 473 sutra, 222, 233, 355, 361, 383 sutraka, 280 suvarnatva, 288 sva, 102, 152, 169, 262 svabhava, 19, 25, 33, 68, 89-90, 95, 99, Page #500 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 474 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES 126, 134, 136-137, 269, 272 svabhava bhedatparatvena, 123 svabhava-naya, 395 svabhava paryaya, 28 svabhava, samaavasthit, 17 svabhavam asadya, 25 svabhavana, 103 svabhavika, 21-22, 237 svada, 251 svadhyaya, 157,351 sva-dravya, 24, 27-28 sva-dravyam, 335 sva-himsa, 153 sva-kartratva, 115 svaka-samayas, 271 svakasya bhavasya, 135 sva-lakshan, 120, 230 svanimitta, 147 svanubhava, 241, 392 svapara, 226 sva-para anugraha heto, 102 sva-para dhukha nivrtti, 102 sva-para hita, 102 sva-para pratyaya, 269 svara, 251 svarupa, 228, 237, 352 svarupa-astitva, 272, 274 svarupe charanam, 31 sva-samaya, 130, 270-272 sva-samchetyamana, 232 svastitva, 236 svatah siddha, 263 svatattva, 37, 44, 121, 229 svatman avasthanam, 78 svayam, 57, 224 svayam parasya, 57 svayambhu, 116, 213, 224 svayameva, 116 syadavada, 151, 204-205, 213, 233, 264, 276, 365-366, 369, 371, 398, 400, 400 n. 1 syat, 143 syatkara, 398-399 tad bhavavyayam nityam, 128 tad-abhava, 128, 287-289, 305-306 tadbhavah parinamah, 128 tad-bhavat, 287 tad-ubhaya-sampanna, 347 taijas, 329 tankotkirna, 296 tanmaya, 18 tapa, 51, 62, 84-85, 96, 157, 173, 178 179, 222 tapasya 156 taporuchi, 76 taratamya, 269 tathavidha, 272 tattva, 139, 169, 232, 265, 268, 288, 302, 363, 369-370, 372, 382, 385 386 tattvartha shraddham, 371 teevra kashaya, 91 teevra udaya, 70 tejo, 69 tena, 288 tirtha-nayakas, 218 Tirthankara, 72, 217-218, 238 tiryag, 292 titiksha, 105 traikalika bhava parinata, 128 traikalika svabhava, 18-19 trasa, 223 trashna, 95, 127 trikali, 133-134 trikali dhruva, 135 tri-koti, 289, 292 trshna, 341 tulya-kalam, 240 tuna, 129 tyaga, 357 udaya, 11, 16, 49, 63, 80, 87, 135, 143, 220, 321, 323 un-anubhavan, 370 un-anya, 292 un-anya-bhava, 292 un-anyatva, 293 Page #501 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ WORD INDEX 475 utkanthula, 375 utpada, 205, 221 utpad vyaya, 128 utpadyavasthaya, 283 utpanna, 312 uttam sukha, 85, 126 uttara-paksha, 298 uvaoga, 43-44 uvautta, 45 un-ishvara-naya, 396 upabhogo, 330 upachaar, 169, 299 upadana, 169, 259 upadana karana, 144-145, 174 upadana karta, 142 upadesha, 99, 237 upadeya, 31, 47-48, 59, 73, 82, 87, 166 upadhana, 347 upadhi, 155, 160, 162, 173, 233, 250, 296, 354, 356-357, 364, 382, 386, 397 upadhyayas, 217-218, 346 upadyate, 278 upakantha, 375 upakara, 76, 106-107 upalabdha-shuddhatma, 342 upalabdhi, 247 upalabhya, 245 upalabhyata, 245 upalakshana, 363 upalambha, 258, 340 upalambhaka, 245 uparaga, 302 uparakta, 51, 89, 137, 256, 332 uparaktatva, 320 uparama, 371 uparanjaka, 136, 239 upashama, 59, 70, 226 upashanta, 385 upasthapaka, 353 upavasa, 364 upavrmbana, 348 upayoga, 18-21, 23-24, 28, 30, 35-42, 44-47, 53, 61-63, 81-82, 84, 8688, 91-92, 123-130, 125-137, 154, 165, 177, 179, 204, 209, 212, 218, 221, 304, 322, 350 upayoga visheshitah, 38 upayogatma, 39 upayukta, 45 upayunjams tishthami, 324 urdhva, 205 urdhvata-samanya, 221 vaibhava, 51, 89 vaichitrya, 240, 307, 328 vaikriyika-sharira, 251 vaiparitya, 380 vaishamya, 240 vaisheshikas, 125 vaiyyavrttya, 105, 107, 377-378 vandana, 217-218, 351, 376 vartana, 305, 308 vartate, 312 vasana, 370 vastu, 220, 234, 279, 283, 285, 379, 381 vastu-dharma, 359-360 vastu-simanta, 279 vastu svabhavat dharma, 11, 18-19, 31 vastu svabhavo dharma, 107 vata, 251 vatsalya, 348, 376 vayas, 390 vedaniya 114 vedaniya karman, 114, 223 veetraga 69 veetraga bhavarupa, 166 veetraga charitra, 166 veetragatva, 168 veetragi, 106 vibhaga, 301, 319 vibhakt, 150 vibhava, 133, 219, 269, 274, 388 vibhava paryaya, 28 vibhuti, 388 Videha-country, 218 vidhana, 222 vidhayika, 287 Page #502 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 476 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES -- vidhi, 295 vidhyatam vikirati, 257 vidya-dama-daya-param, 106 vihara, 158, 354 viharatu, 354 vikalpa, 42, 223, 300-301, 321, 353, 366 vikalpa-naya, 394 vikar, 41, 130, 136 vikara, 263, 302 vikara-shaman, 12 vikatha, 158, 354 vikathayam,355 vikrti-bhuta, 301 vinaya, 347, 359 vipaka, 175, 223 viplavate, 282 vipratishedha, 294-295 virati, 379 viriya, 43 viriyam, 43 virodha, 139, 364 viruddh karya, 62 virupa, 237 virya, 209, 217, 225, 347 vishaya, 51, 87, 116, 228-229, 236, 377 vishaya kashaya, 55 vishaya trashna, 50, 56, 89, 254 vishayam, 332 vishayi, 236 vishesha, 52, 256, 293, 303, 386 vishesha-guna, 230, 272 vishesha-lakshana, 277, 304 vishesha-naya, 394 visheshana, 257, 262, 287 visheshas, 241 vishishta, 313, 354, 368 vishishta punya bandha, 169 vishkambha, 279 vishuddha, 12, 31, 33, 76, 79, 179 vishuddha atma, 60 vishuddhi, 11, 21, 23, 33, 39, 48, 51-52, 54-55, 57-60, 62, 70, 72, 74-80, 8485, 87-88, 90-96, 153-154, 167, 323, 334 vishva, 383 visohi, 389 vistara, 287,310 vistara-vishesha, 268 vivartana, 296 vivasha, 354 viveka, 262 viviktatva, 231 viviktva eva, 232 vrddha, 364 vrata, 61, 67, 90, 157, 165, 168, 178, 379 vritti, 222, 230, 274, 279-280, 289, 292, 302, 344, 372, 385 urttimat, 315 vyakta, 308 vyakti, 304, 307, 319 vyakurva, 384 vyanjana, 347 vyanjita-nityatvo, 313 vyapara, 372 vyapin, 394 vyapta, 283 vyatipata, 279, 281-282, 290, 292, 305, 319 vyavaccheda, 304 vyavahara, 66-67, 84, 86-87, 117, 119, 138, 164, 167-168, 178-179, 229, 318, 320 vyavahara charitra, 79, 104, 164-167, 179 vyavahara dharma, 67, 84 vyavahara moksha marg, 71, 167-168 vyavahara naya, 20, 25, 28-29, 42, 64, 70, 92, 113-114, 138-140, 142143, 146-147, 168-169, 337-338, 374, 397 vyaya, 205, 221 yadi, 56 yat sakalam, 244 yatha, 385 yatha jata rupa, 157 yathajatarupa, 349 yathavasthita, 18 Page #503 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ WORD INDEX yati, 337, 365 yeyam atmanah, 320 yoga, 14, 97, 121, 174, 231, 233, 257, 350-352, 361-362 yugapat, 172, 239 yogins, 217 yogya, 245 yukta, 362 yukta-ahara, 361 yukta ahara vihara, 156, 160, 360 yukti, 253 yuta-siddhatva, 278 yuta-siddhatvasyadarshanat, 278 477 Page #504 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Subject Index Advaita Vedanta, 8, 118-119, 124, 132 ahimsa, concept of, 148-149 ashubha (evil) psychic attention, 222 in Tattvartha Sutra, 102-103 Jayasena commentary on, 113-114 Pujyapada on, 99 conduct, 156-161, 346-365 and negligence in, 155, 157, 160 criticism of Johnson, 164-166, 172 consciousness, three aspects of, 36 bhava and dravya-pranas, 26-29 bondage mechanism of, 135-138, 141 bondage and liberation mechanism of, 213-214 Buddhism, 46-47, 119, 156, 159, 176 dharma definition of, 18-19 nature of, 19-20 equanimity, 158-159 and self-restraint, 13-14 Bhagvadagita on, 14 characteristics of, 16-18 concept of, 11-13, 16-18 five jewels, 385-387 chetana and upayoga are not the same, 37-39 compassion Amrtachandra on, 107-108 and infatuation, 103-104 and non-violence, 104-107 circumstances in which it could be deluding, 108-113 controversy regarding, 103-104 different from infatuation, 103-104 different works and people on, 97 103 distorted views of Kanjipanthi on, 114-116 example of Lincoln, 101 in Ashta Pahuda, 98 in Dhavala, 99 in Niyamsara, 98-99 in Panchastikayasara, 101-102 good (shubha) psychic-attention exposition of, 168, 253-265 Jayasena commentaries, motivations behind, 8-9 faulty explanation of pure, 31-32 recension, additional verses, 3-9 jiνα and pudgala, 211-213 Page #505 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ SUBJECT INDEX 479 five psychic dispositions of, 43-44 jiva nikaya, 24-26 Jiva substance distinctive featurs of, 318-344 joy, exposition of, 126-127, 244-253 practice in Egypt, 109 misperceptions and distortions of Kanjipanthi regarding shubha and ashubha 90-97 misperceptions of Kanjipanthi concern ing substance and mode, 139 misplaced criticisms of Kundakunda by I.C. Shastri, 124 mithyatva cause of karmic bondage, 182-183 moha and compassion, 97 characteristics of, 97 moral virtues, dual role of, 153-155 morality, and spirituality, 85-86 mulganas (primary qualities), 157-158 Kanjipanthi and mistaken concept of inactive self, 177-185 mistakenly equate shubha and ashubha, 48-54 karuna (mercy or kindness) see compassion karunabhavo in PS 85 controversy regarding, 103-104 feeling of compassion or absence thereof, 103 knowable exposition of, 127-129 principle of, 211 knowledge exposition of, 117-118, 122, 226 244 principle of, 209-210 relation between soul and, 129 Kundakunda his works, 1-2 misplaced criticisms by Shastri, 119-124 се nishchaya and vyavahara points of view, 138-141, 145 nishchaya and yavahara charitra (conduct), 166-169 non-violence concept of, 148-149 greater emphasis on psychic dispo sitions, 149-151 internal and external aspects of, 146-148, 152 Tattvartha Sutra on, 151-153 old scriptures problems in translation of, 9-10 omniscience, concept of, 116-117, 148 liberation, path of, 171-174, 365-375 distortion by Kanjipanthi, 174-175 faulty view of Bronkhorst, 175-177 samvara and nirjara are essential, 184-185 149 material karman and psychic states, 141-145 mercy killing or euthanasia, 108-109 Jaina concept of sallekhana, santhara or samadhi-maran is different. from, 109 legalized in Netherlands and Ohio state of USA. 109 parinamika bhava, 22-24 Pravachanasara additional verses in Jayasena's re cension, 3-9 benedictory verses, 217-219 conduct in, 156-161, 346-365 -- significant concepts in, 10-15 two recensions, 2-3 verses given only in Jayasena's re censions, 388-391 Page #506 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 480 psychic attention, 222-226, 253265 psychic dispositions, 149-151, 156 psycho-physical parallelism, 145-146, 151 pure nature of soul, 29-31 Jayasena's faulty explanation of, 3132 pure psychic-attention, 222-226 Kanji's distortion of, 186-189 samana, meaning of, 162-164 samayika, 14-16 Samkhya, 8, 122, 124, 176 Samkhya yoga, 124, 156 self, 47 and its states-of-evolution, 219-222 active and evolvent aspect of, 189 191 nature of, 20-22, 29-31 points of view regarding, 392-400 Yogasara-prabhrat on, 22 self-restraint, 159-161, 171 shubha dual role of, 80-81, 88-90 misperceptions of Kanjipanthi re garding, 90-97 overall appraisal of, 86-88 preferable to ashubha, 54-62 shubha and ashubha in other Jain texts, 71-80 in other works of Kundakunda, 6469 in Panchastikayasara, 69-71 THE ESSENCE OF JAINA SCRIPTURES mistaken view of Kanjipanthi, 4854 shubha psychic attention, 375-384 shuddha and shubha upayoga, 62-64 soul and knowledge, 118-119 evolvent nature of, 44-46 Jaina concept of, 124-125 meaning of pure nature of, 33-35 nature of, 20-22 pure nature of, 29-31 relation to knowledge, 129 transcendental nature of, 15-16 substance, 268-318 definition of, 129-133 misperceptions of Kanjipanthi con cerning substance and mode, 133135 substance in general, 268-303 substance in particular, 304-318 svayambhu (self-sufficient), concept of, 116 Tatparya-vriti, gathas only in, 388-391 upayoga, 35-37 Akalanka's definition of, 40-42 its importance compared with mindfulness in Buddhism, 46-47 other translations of, 36-37 rarity of the concept in Shvetambara texts, 42-43 three kinds of, 39-40, 208-209 Page #507 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Jagdish Prasad Jain is Founder of Jain Mission and Editor of Jain Agam. He was formerly Diplomat/Adviser, Indian Mission to the United Nations, New York; Deputy Director, Ministry of External Affairs, Government of India; and Professor, Jawaharlal Nehru University. New Delhi. He has devoted himself to the study of Jainism for over two decades. He has published numerous articles in national and international journals and has lectured extensively in India and the United States, including Conventions of the Federation of Jain Associations in North America (JAINA) and Jain Center of Northern California. Dr Jain has published nearly a dozen books, including Fundamentals of Jainism (2005), which was adjudged the best book on Jain religion and philosophy in January 2004 in an all-India competition. His other publications include Salvation through Self-Discipline: Niyamsara of Kundakunda (2005), Spiritual Insights: Ishtopadesh and Samadhi Shatak by Pujyapada (editor, 2000), Spiritual Enlightenment: Paramatma Prakash by Yogindu Deva (editor, 2000), and The Enlightened Vision of the Self: Svarupa Sambodhana of Akalanka (editor, 2005). ISBN 978-81-7479-163-4 Price: 1500.00 Page #508 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ ISBN 978-81-7479-163-4 Kaveri Books 4832/24, Ansari Road, Darya Ganj, New Delhi - 110002 (India) Ph.: +91-11-23288140, 23245799 E-mail: kaveribooks@vsnl.com, kaveribooks@gmail.com Website: www.kaveribooks.com TEHNO 9117881741791634|| Price: *1500.00 Jacket design: Sparsh Communications