Book Title: Central Philosophy of Jainism Anekanta Vada
Author(s): Bimal Krishna Matilal, Nagin J Shah, Dalsukh Malvania
Publisher: L D Indology Ahmedabad
Catalog link: https://jainqq.org/explore/001129/1

JAIN EDUCATION INTERNATIONAL FOR PRIVATE AND PERSONAL USE ONLY
Page #1 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE CENTRAL PHILOSOPHY OF JAINISM (ANEKANTA-VADA) L. D. SERIES 79 GENERAL EDITORS DALSUKH MALVANIA NAGIN J. SHAH BY BIMAL KRISHNA MATILAI UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO CANADA une L.D. INSTITUTE OF INDOLOGY AHMEDABAD 380 009 mahamadAbA CRUSH Page #2 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE CENTRAL PHILOSOPHY OF JAINISM (ANEKANTA-VADA) L. D. SERIES 79 BY GENERAL EDITORS DALSUKH MALVANIA NAGIN J. SHAH BIMAL KRISHNA MATILAL UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO CANADA 3) L.D. INSTITUTE L.D. INSTITUTE OF INDOLOGY AHMEDABAD 380009 CRORA Page #3 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ FIRST EDITION March, 1981 Printed by Creative Printers Pvt. Limited, Shree Industrial Mills Estate, Ahmedabad-380 021 and Published by Nagin J. Shah Director L. D. Institute of Indology Ahmedabad-380009 Page #4 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ FOREWORD The L. D. Institute of Indology has great pleasure in publishing Dr. B. K. Matilal's lectures on Anekantavada delivered in the L. D. Lecture Series in 1975. He is right in regarding anekantavada as the central philosophy of Jainism. Anekantavada means 'the doctrine of non-onesidedness', it is a philosophy of synthesis of opposite viewpoints in philosophy. This type of synthesis always presents some problems. Jaina philosophers knew this and to resolve them they developed a philosophic methodology which consists of nayavada (the doctrine of standpoints) and Syadvada or Saptabhangi (the sevenfold predication). The learned Doctor lucidly explains anekantavada and its methodology. He identifies anekantavada with a subvariety of vibhajyavada. His elucidation of Buddha's Middle Way as 'exclusive' middle while that of Mahavira's anekanta as 'inclusive' middle is interesting. He demonstrates how anekantavada resolves the paradox of causality, viz. satkaryavadaasatkaryavada and vivartavada-ksanabhangavada. His observations on Jaina nayas in the light of Madhyamika dialectic are really illuminating. He expounds the theory of Dravya, Guna and Paryaya under the section entitled 'Existence and Substance'. While discussing the doctrine of Sevenfold Predication, he clearly points out its similarity and dissimilarity with Sanjaya's fivefold formula, Ajivaka's 'three-termed' doctrine (trairasika) and the Madhyamika tetralemma (catuskoti). Having given an account of the traditional objections against this doctrine of Sevenfold Predication, he answers the objections and logically defends the Jaina position. I am grateful to Dr. B. K. Matilal for his lectures which he prepared at our instance. They are published here in book-form. The book is divided into fifteen sections instead of three lectures. I crave the induIgence of the scholars for the delay in printing. I have no doubt that the students, teachers and others interested in Indian philosophy in general and Jaina philosophy in particular will find this book interesting and of genuine help in understanding central philosophy of Jainism. L. D. Institute of Indology, Ahmedabad-380 009. 15, February, 1981 Nagin J. Shah Director Page #5 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Page #6 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PREFACE Jainism is an old religion of India. It is one of the few ancient religions of India, which is still very much alive. Several salient features of Indian culture such as vegetarianism, non-violence, tolerance and non-aggression, can be traced back many Jaina sources. It is, however, a pity that Jainism has not aroused as much interest outside India as Buddhism and Hinduism. In the field of philosophy, Jainism has added a new dimension by propounding the doctrine of 'non-onesided nature' (anekanta-vada) of reality. This book undertakes to convey a precise understanding of the central philosophy of Jainism. I am very grateful to the Trustee and the Director of L. D. Institute of Indology, Ahmedabad, for the honour they did me in inviting me to deliver a course of lectures on Jaina philosophy in the summer of 1975. This book is a slightly modified version of the lectures I delivered at the L. D. Institute of Indology. I wish to take this opportunity to thank my wife, Karabi, and my former student, Dr. J. L. Shaw of Victoria University of Wellington, both of whom helped me in preparing the manuscript. Toronto, Canada. Bimal Krishna Matilal Page #7 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Page #8 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CONTENTS I Introduction II Vibhajya-vada as a philosophic method III The Middle-Way and the "Non-onesided" way IV Anekanta : A development from the Vibhajya method V Different senses of Anekanta VI Anekanta as a resolution of the paradox of Causality VII The Jaina nayas and the Madhyamika dialectic VIII Substance and quality : Two main standpoints IX Existence and Substance X The seven standpoints XI Historical background of the Jaina dialectic XII The meaning of SYAT XIII Explanation of the seven predicates XIV Traditional objections XV In defence of the Jaina position Footnotes Appendix Bibliographical References Page #9 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Errata Page Line Read For anekanta principle anakanta principal Page #10 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INTRODUCTION The central philosophy of Jainism is anekanta-vada. It is a philosophy of Non-radicalism. It is, in fact, a unique contribution of the followers of Mahavira to the philosophic tradition of India. Literally, the term "anekanta-vada" means 'the theory of non-onesidedness' or, to be more specific, 'the theory of the many-sided nature of reality'. A serious study of the Jaina doctrine reveals that it is a philosophy of synthesis - a synthesized presentation of different metaphysical or ontological theories of ancient India. A synthesis of the opposite viewpoints in philosophy always presents some problems. Jaina philosophers were well aware of such problems. And in order to resolve them, they developed a philosophic methodology that was unique to Jainism. This methodology, which will be my chief concern in this essay, consists of the dual doctrine of the Jainas ; naya-vada (the doctrine of standpoints) and Syad-vada or sapta-bhangi (the sevenfold predication). The Jaina anekanta-vada is as important a doctrine as the Sunya-vada or the 'Emptiness' doctrine of the Madhyamikas. These two philosophic doctrines are also comparable in many ways. The 'Emptiness' doctrine has, however, been a much-discussed topic in recent times, but, unfortunately, the Anekanta doctrine has remained more or less obscure to modern minds. It will certainly be philosophically fruitful to explore this area of Indian philosophy. Just as the Madhyamika philosophers utilized the methodology of the catuskoti 'four-fold alternative' in order to vindicate the 'Emptiness' philosophy, the Jainas used their methods of 'standpoints' (nayas) and seven-fold predication in order to defend their Anekanta philosophy. I shall try to show here along with my interpretation of the Jaina view that the seven-fold predication of the Jainas is neither more nor less mind-boggling than the Madhyamika doctrine of the four-fold alternatives. My exposition will be based mostly on the available Sanskrit materials on Jaina philosophy. But in reconstructing the history of the Anekanta-vada I will take occasional help from the canonical literature of Jainism as well as Buddhism. It may be noted also that the all-round development of the Anekanta philosophy took place in the history when Sanskrit came to be used by the Jaina writers. The Anekanta philosophy, Page #11 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Central Philosophy of Jainism being itself a synthetic development, historically presupposes the existence of many rival and well-developed philosophical schools. In fact, the Jaina philosophy unfolded itself in the context of many severe and serious controversies among such schools as the Samkhya, Bauddha, Nyaya, Mimamsa and Vedanta. Panditas Sukhlalji Sanghavi and Bechardasji Doshi, two erudite (modern) scholars of Jainism, have described the situation as follows: ... when (the) Samskrta language found a place in Jaina literature and when along with the language the logical method as well as the philosophical discussion was ushered into Jaina literature, the discussion of this doctrine (anekanta-vada) gathered strength and bulk, the details were then multiplied and rival currents of thoughts, arguments and proofs also found a place, consistent with their original nature in the discussion of this doctrine. 1 The principle of anekanta can be briefly described as the acceptance of the manifoldness of reality. Jaina philosophers claim that no philosophic or metaphysical proposition can be true if it is simply asserted without any condition or limitation. If a proposition is asserted as "x is f" then it becomes ekanta one-sided.' This means that the proposition ascribes unconditionally a predicate-property to the subject and thereby excludes other rival possibilities (contradictory predicates ). For Jainism such an unconditional assertion violates the principle of anekanta. As far as the Jainas are concerned, if a metaphysical proposition violates this principle, it is to be regarded as false. When a proposition is unconditionally asserted, it becomes falsifiable. An unconditionally asserted metaphysical proposition, such as "x is f" ascribes the property "f-ness" to the subject. And it can be falsified when its contradictory "x is not f" is shown to be true. Thus, a metaphysical thesis of a particular school is usually rejected by a rival school which puts forward a (directly or indirectly) contradictory thesis. Jainism says that the lesson to be drawn from such age-old philosophic disputes is the following: Each school asserts its thesis and claims it to be the absolute truth, and thus it does not really wish to understand the point that is being made by the opposite side. The rival schools, by their arguments and counter arguments, only encourage dogmatism and intoleration in philosophy. This, according to the Jainas, is the evil of ekanta 'one-sided' philosophies. But the philosophic propositions of rival schools could be integrated together under the Anekanta system. In other words, these rival propositions can be said to capture the truth when and only when they are asserted with proper Page #12 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction qualifications or conditions. This is what the anekanta doctrine teaches. How can one conditionalize one's philosophic proposition ? Add a "syat" particle to the proposition and you have captured the truth! Mahavira the Jina is usually acclaimed as the original propounder of the anekanta doctrine. But some Jaina scholars of today argue that Jainism as a religion has pre-Vedic origin, and therefore its chief philosophic doctrine, anekanta-vada must have been present in rudimentary form from the very beginning. I shall leave aside the dispute regarding the pre-Vedic origin of Jainism. While Parsvanatha must have appeared before the time of the Buddha, it has been shown by scholars with considerable certainty that Mahavira was a contemporary of the Buddha. It is also clear from the Prakrit and Pali sources that Parsvanatha propounded the four fundamental rules of ethics (such as not to kill, not to steal, not to lie, and not to accumulate possessions and all of these were accepted by both the Buddha and Mahavira ), he did not seem to uphold any philosophical thesis such as the anekanta-vada. Thus, I shall proceed with the hypothesis that the beginnings of the anekanta doctrine are to be traced in the teachings of Mahavira the Jina. Pandit Dalsukhbhai Malvania has shown with considerable care how what was known as the vibhajya-vada in the later part of the sramana movement in India culminated in the anekanta-vada of Mahavira.3 I shall return to this question presently. It is commonly asserted by some modern Jaina scholars that although systematic presentation of the anekanta doctrine was not available in the early texts, certain references, from the Rgveda onwards, to the joint assertion of contradictory propositions in answer to various philosophic questions, prove the presence or persistence of the anekanta doctrine throughout the ages.4 Thus the Nasadiya hymn of the Rgveda,5 and various assertions in the Upanisads such as " it moves, it moves not,"6 and "more subtle than the atom and larger than the ubiquitous,"7 are quoted to show the hoary antiquity of the anekanta-vada. I am a bit hesitant to accept this argument for the simple reason that the special characteristic of the anekanta doctrine will be misunderstood if merely the joint assertion of contradictory predicates about an identical subject be itself taken to be a vindication of anekanta doctrine. Most writers on religious and philosophical mysticism prefer to use contradictory predication as a means to bring about the ineffable character of what they call the ultimate reality.8 But a mystic by asserting the ineffable character of the ultimate reality does not necessarily become an anekanta-vadin 'an upholder of the non-one-sided doctrine of reality. Besides, the Jaina anekanta doctrine developed in the mileau of a multiple of rival currents Page #13 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Central Philosophy of Jainism of thoughts and views. Thus the doctrine presupposed at least the systematic presentation of rival philosophic schools. An additional point regarding the origin of the anekanta-vada may be taken into account here. It is possible that the well-known moral doctrine of Jainism, i.e. ahimsa "non-violence' was partly responsible for the development of the anekanta attitude in Jaina philosophy. Both Pandit Mahendra Kumar Shastri and H. D. Kapadia dealt with this point to some extent. 10 Non-violence was the dominant trend in the whole of the sramana movement against the Brahmanas. The Brahmanas apparently supported violence, i.e., killing of animals, in the name of rituals and religion. Hence in a sramana religion like Buddhism and Jainism, abstention from killing anything (i.e., respect for life ) was the first cardinal virtue to be practised by everybody. In Buddhist scriptures, taking life of others (cf. Pranatipata) has been unequivocally condemned. 11 It is enumerated as the first in the Buddhist list of ten sinful ways of life. 12 The Buddha, however, chose a middle course in the practice of non-violence as a way of life as well as in the practice of asceticism and hardship in life. As regards the eating of meat, there are some dubious references in the Pali scriptures. These references can be interpreted as evidence for proving that the Buddha accepted meat occasionally. The Buddha's own attitude regarding the practice of meat-eating was ambivalent. His policy was, perhaps, what might be called today the line of the least resistance. In the Jivaka-sutta of the Majjhima-Nikaya, the practice of meateating was not itself condemned, but only in so far as the taking of meat was in some way contributory to killing or giving pain. Jivaka was the famous physician of King Bimbisara and Ajatasatru. He told the Buddha that he had heard that many people killed living beings and prepared food for the Buddha. He wanted to know whether it was true. The Buddha replied that meat should not be eaten under three conditions, viz., if it had been seen or heard or suspected that the animal had been killed for the person and the meat was intended for him. The following case was cited as harmless : "Suppose a monk who practices the brahmavihara of love accepts an invitation in a village. Does he think, Verily this householder is providing me with excellent food; may he provide me with excellent food for the future.' ?" "Not so, O honorable one," was the answer. "He eats the food without being fettered and infatuated." Page #14 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction "What do you think, Jivaka ? Does the monk at that time think of injuries to himself, to others, or to both ? " "Certainly not, o honorable one." "Does not a monk at that time take blameless food ?" "Even so, O honorable one." 13 On another occasion, the Buddha took a similar position. When Devadatta wanted to introduce stricter discipline into the Order, he was willing to prohibit altogether meat-eating and fish-eating among the monks. But the Buddha declined and said that acceptance of meat or fish from the householder was blameless under certain conditions. Thus we see that the Buddha prescribed the Madhyama pratipat, the Middle Way, both in philosophy and practical behaviour. Just as his philosophic view was one of avoiding of the evils of the extremes, in practical behaviour (acara) too, he preferred a middle course. Thus, severe self-mortification in which the ascetics of those days used to indulge, was for the Buddha, another name for violence, i.e., violence done to one's own self. Mahavira, on the other hand, was a man of very strict principles. He was never soft on the acara, on austerities, asceticism, and abstentions. He did not regard self-mortification as violence done to the self. Relaxation in the principles of self-control was, for Mahavira, another name for sustaining defeat in the hand of our internal adversaries (such as passion and greed). On the notion of non-violence, however, Mahavira added a new dimension of meaning, as we shall see presently. The Jaina canonical texts emphasize that one should try to think of all the living creatures as equal to one's own self and therefore should not try to harm anybody with the intention of harming. Thus, the Acaranga notes as follows : "All beings are fond of life, they like pleasure, hate pain, avoid decay, wish to live long. To all, life is dear...All breathing, existing, living, sentient creatures should not be slain, nor treated with violence, nor abused, nor tormented, nor driven away. This is the pure, unchangeable, external law, which the clever ones, who understand the world, have declared."14 This should not mean, as it is sometimes misinterpreted, that the killing of any kind is sinful. Rather the doctrine of non-violence dictates that we should live in this world in such a way that we do not have Page #15 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Central Philosophy of Jainism to kill any living being. We should cultivate a feeling of kindness and compassion for all living creatures, and killing, or inflicting pain upon, others will be allowed when and only when it is unavoidable. 15 6 Mahavira carried this concept of non-violence from the domain of practical behaviour to the domain of intellectual and philosophic discussion. Thus the Jaina principle of 'respect for the life of others' gave rise to the principle of respect for the views of others. In fact, the essence of the anekanta doctrine was embodied in this principle of respect for the views of others. Thus Kapadia has noted: "... this doctrine of anekanta-vada helps us in cultivating the attitude of toleration towards the views of our adversaries. It does not stop there but takes us a step forward by making us investigate as to how and why they hold a different view and how the seeming contradictories can be reconciled to evolve harmony. It is thus an attempt towards syncretism."16 The philosophic position of the Jainas in this way found expression in the anekanta doctrine, a doctrine that was characterized by toleration, understanding and respect for the views of others. This is a unique character of Jaina philosophy and religion, which I find most admiring. For, very seldom such a sincere attempt has been made to understand the position of the adversary. Whether the fundamental assumption of ontology (i. e., the thesis that reality is many-sided or things are basically of infinitefold nature) is correct or not, is another matter. But certainly the professed catholicity of the Jaina outlook (an attitude which the early Jesuits shared, perhaps, from a different motivation) can hardly be denied. Page #16 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 11 VIBHAJYA-VADA AS A PHILOSOPHIC METHOD The Buddha was sometimes criticized for having instructed doctrines which were apparently contradictory to each other. But the Buddha, in reply, said to Potthapada that he (the Buddha), contrary to the accusation of his critics, had taught and laid down doctrines (dharmas) which were capable of being asserted categorically (ekamsika pi) as well as he had taught and laid down doctrines which were incapable of being asserted categorically (anekamsika pi).17 The word "anekamsika" was probably another name for anekanta. K. N. Jayatilleke has argued this point quite convincingly.18 If this view is true, then the "anekamsika" method could be taken to be the precursor of the Jaina anekanta doctrine. In another place 19 the Buddha told Manavaka that he was not an ekanta-vadin ( one who holds an extreme view) but a vibhajya-vadin. In the Sutrakrtanga, it is said that Mahavira also followed the method called vibhajya-vada 20 Pandit Malvania has explained how the vibhajyavada was developed by Mahavira into the anekunta-vada.21 Thus we can say that both the anekansika method and the vibhajya method were forerunner of the anekanta-vada. What were the meanings of these two terms: anekamsika and vibhajya-vada? In his dialogue with Potthapada, the Buddha said that he had followed the anekamsika method to answer the so-called "unanswerable questions. These questions were listed in the Anguttara as avyakata "unexplained' questions. 22 The anekamsika method in this context seems to mean an INDIRECT method of answering questions through analysis and clarification of the senses of words contained in those questions. The avyakata "unexplained' or 'unaswered' questions were also called tha paniya questions ( 'questions to be set aside' or 'questions to be rejected') in the Anguttara. But these "unanswered' questions were not regarded by the Buddha as really unanswerable. It would be a wrong interpretation if we believed that the Buddha left these questions entirely unanswered. The Buddha used, in fact, the vibhajya method to give answer to these questions. We can explain the meaning of vibhajya-vada in the following manner. The Buddha did not want to adhere categorically to any extreme viewpoint or theory. He would not answer any metaphysical questions Page #17 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Central Philosophy of Jainism such as one about after-life or about the soul by a direct "Yes" or a direct "No". He would rather try to analyse (cf. vibhaga) the questions and its various presuppositions and distinguish (also vibhaga) between its different interpretations. And following this method of analysis and differentiation, the method of breaking up' (vibhajya) the whole into its component parts, one seeks a satisfactory answer to such avyakata questions. Sometimes such a question may be resolved into a number of separate questions answers to which should be sought separately. (That explains why the Buddha remained silent when a 'compounded' question was put to him directly.) Sometimes, the questions may dissolve itself in the face of an 'analysis' to which it would be subjected. In the latter case, the questions can thus be identified as a pseudo-question. In fact, this latter one was the method the Buddha seemed to have followed in most of his dialogues. But only about the four noble truths, suffering, its origin, its cessation and the way, the Buddha seemed to have made categorical assertions. For according to him, these were the most useful and most pertinent matters for the suffering humanity. If the above is a reasonably clear and correct interpretation of vibhajya-vada, then we can translate it as 'the method of analysis and differentiation'. Another sense, slightly different from the above, is found in the Abhidharmakosa-bhasya. Suppose a question is asked where the subject-term is universally quantified, such as "Are all men good?" or "Do all dharmas exist in relation to past, present and future ?" Here it would be somewhat misleading if we gave a direct answer "Yes" or "No". But using the vibhajya method one could answer "Some are good while others are not" or "Some dharmas exist while others do not." Thus, in the Abhidharmakosa-bhasaya, Vasubandhu says: "Those who say that everything exists, past, present and future, are called the Sarvasti-vadins. But there are those who say that only certain things exist, viz., the present karma as well as the past karma which has not yet given its result, and other things, such as the future karma as well as the past karma which has generated already its result, do not exist. They are called vibhajya-vadins." 23 One may note that while the contradictory of a universal proposition, "Alls is p" is "Some s is not p" (viz., in Aristotle's square of opposition, the contradictory of an A-proposition is an O-proposition 24), the direct negative answer "No" to the question "Is all s p ?" will be at best ambiguous. For, this "No" might be interpreted in ordinary language as a reply that no s is p. Besides, this negative answer does Page #18 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Vibhajyavada not entail "Some s is p" (an I-proposition). Thus we see that the vibhajya method is employed here to derive the correct answer to the question that was posed : "Some are, and some are not." Let us probe further into the nature of the questions that were called avyakata (or avyakrta in Sanskrit). In the Arguttara, the Buddha classified "philosophical" questions under four groups : 1. Questions answerable directly (in the affirmative or in the negative ) : Ekamsavyakaraniya. 2. Questions answerable by analysing and separating: (vibhajya vadena vyakaraniya) 3. Questions answerable by a counter-question: (prati-prasnena vyakaraniya). 4. Questions answerable by silence or questions that should be set aside (sthapaniya) The commentary on the Ariguttara illustrates each of these four kinds of questions. Besides, an identical classification of questions is also found in the Milinda-panha as well as in the Abhidharmakosa-bhasya 25. The set of examples found in different sources vary slightly from each other. K. N. Jayatilleke has discussed these examples culled from different sources, and has concluded that the third variety is only a sub-variety of the second.26 I think this four-fold classification was a later development of the earlier theory of the two varieties of questions which should be answered by two different methods; ekamsa (those answerable directly with Yes or No ), and vibhajya (those answerable by analysis and breaking up'). Thus, in addition to Jayatilleke's surmise I suggest further that even the fourth variety in the above classification (e. g. stha pani ya should be regarded as a sub-variety of the second : vibhajya-vyakaraniya (those answerable by analysis). From the Jaina point of view, this suggestion will be welcome, for we see that Mahavira also tried to answer the so-called avyakata 'not to be answered questions by following a sort of the vibhajya method and thereby laid the foundation of his anekanta method. Even the Buddha was not altogether silent about these question, as we shall see below. Let us follow Vasubandhu's explanation of this four-fold classification of questions--Vasubandhu describes them as follows: * Will all beings die ? This question should be answered directly: "Yes, they will Page #19 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Central Philosophy of Jainism 'Will all beings be born (again)? This question should be answered through separation and analysis: "Those with defilements will be born ( again ), but not those without defilements. Is man superior or inferior ? This question should be countered with a different question With regard to whom are you asking ? If he says, 'Is man superior or inferior to the gods ? then the answer is: 'Man is inferior to gods. If he says, 'Is man superior or inferior to the lower beings ? then the answer is: "Man is superior to the lower beings.' 'Is the being different from the (five ) aggregates, or identical ? This question is to be set aside. For the substance' of the being does not exist, just as the dark or the fair complexion of the son of a barren woman does not exist." Vasubandhu reports that Bhadanta Rama criticized this four-fold classification. He apparently argued as follows: Will everybody be born?' This question can be answered also directly: 'No, not everybody will be born.' If (however) the question is rephrased as "Will those who die be born (again)? one should then answer it by separation and analysis (viz., Some will, but others will not.'). Similarly, the third question according to Rama, can also be answered directly: "Man is both superior and inferior, superior to the lower beings but inferior to the gods.' The situation is similar to the question 'Is a piece of consciousness an effect or a cause ?' The direct answer is: 'It is both, an effect with regard to the preceding consciousness, and a cause with regard to the following.' The fourth type of question, Bhadanta Rama says, was unanswered (avyakata), and hence it should not enter into the discussion where answering or explanation of different types of questions was being considered. 27 Vasubandhu himself disagreed with criticism of Rama. According to Vasubandhu, the questions regarding the conception of the four Noble Truths, suffering, its origin, cessation and the way, as well as regarding the impermanence of rupa etc., can be answered directly and definitely (cf. ekansa-vyakaruna ). The second question can be rephrased as "Will those who die be born again ?' And now this question is answerable only by dividing (vibhajya) the class denoted by the subject-term into two groups: those with defilements, and those without defilements. Thus it is a proper example of the vibhajya method. The third question belongs also to the vibhajya method. For the person who asks this question and expects a direct answer cannot, in fact, receive any direct answer. One Page #20 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Vibhajyavada answers the question by dividing (vibhajya) the predicate-property, or rather by specifying (visisya) further the predicate-property: speaking from the point of view of the gods, man is inferior, but speaking from the point of view of the lower beings, man is superior. Thus, we see that Vasubandhu tacitly assumed the third variety to be a sub-variety of the second: vibhajya-vada. From above we can gather that there were, at least, two sub-varieties of the vibhajya-vada: (1) The first type operates by dividing the subject class into sub-classes; (2) The second one operates by specifying or relativizing the predicate. It seems to me that this second sub-variety of the vibhajya method was adopted chiefly by Mahavira the Jina. And thus, this was developed into the anakanta method. Page #21 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ III THE MIDDLE WAY AND THE NON-ONESIDED' WAY The Majjhimanikaya (Culamalunk ya-sutta) lists the ten avyakata 'not to be answered or explained questions as follows : 1. Is the loka (world, man) eternal ? 2. Is the loka not eternal ? 3. Is it (the loka) finite (with an end) ? 4. Is it not finite ? 5. Is that which is the body the soul ? (Is the soul identical with the body ?) 6. Is the soul different from the body ? 7. Does the Tathagata exist after death? 8. Does he not exist after death? 9. Does he both exist and not exist after death? 10. Does he neither exist nor not exist after death ? Various speculations have been made with regard to these avyakata questions. One explanation is that these questions were irrelevant to the practical teachings of the Buddha, viz., the four noble truths. One can refer to the parable of the man shot with an arrow. When that man is bleeding to death, it is irrelevant, and rather stupid, to ask "Who shot the arrow ?" etc. For the immediate need would be to pull out the arrow and save the man from dying. In another place, the Buddha exposed how utterly senseless was the question about whether the Tathagata exists after death or not. Let me quote the dialogue in full: Majjhimanikaya 11. 22., Vacchagottasutta. "The Buddha: 'There is no need, Vaccha, to be confused, no need to resort to ignorance. This doctrine is, Vaccha, very deep, difficult to fathom, difficult to understand...Let me ask you questions, and you, Vaccha, try to answer as clearly as you can. What do you think of the following, Vaccha: "If a flame burns before you, would you know, that the flame is burning before you?" Page #22 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Middle Way and 'Non-Onesided' Way 13 Vaccha: 'If a flame burns before me, I would know that a flame is burning before me.' B: "Let me ask again, Vaccha. Suppose you are asked, "Depending on what does this flame that burns before you burn?" Being asked in this manner, Vaccha, what would you answer ? V: 'If I am, Gotama, asked, depending on what does this flame that burns before you burn ?" I would answer thus: " The flame that burns before me burns depending upon the straw and the wood (as fuel).' B: "If, Vaccha, the flame before you is extinguished, would you know that the flame before you has been extinguished ?". V: "If, Gotama, the flame before me is extinguished, I would know that the flame before me has been extinguished'. B: If, you, Vaccha, are asked again: "To which direction has the flame, that had been extinguished before you, gone? Has it gone to the east, to the south, to the west or to the north ?" what would you answer ?' V: "It is not, Gotama, a proper question. For, Gotama, the flame that burnt depending (as fuel) on the straw and wood has now been burnt out for it has used up ( exhausted ) that fuel and had not been fed with other fuels'." Vaccha, at this point, seemed to have understood the force of this analogy. The Tathagata exists depending upon various pratyaya-s (conditions ) and when these conditions' exhaust themselves death of the Tathagata arises, and it is foolish to ask where he goes after death or whether he exists after death or not. K. N. Jayatilleke has made alternative conjectures about the interpretation of the avyakata questions. He seems to favour the view that these questions are comparable to the metaphysical questions which the Logical Positivists of the West have described as non-sensical.28 Jayatilleke quoted also from L. Wittgenstein in support of his contention: "Whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent." The positivists, to be sure, described some metaphysical questions as meaningless, for these questions did not seem to have any meaning under the Positivists' theory of meaning. It is fashionable today among comparative philosophers to compare the doctrine of the Buddha ( or Nagarjuna ) with the philosophy of Wittgenstein. I am personally somewhat ambivalent of this Page #23 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 14 The Central Philosophy of Jainism comparison. For, despite the obvious parallelism between some cryptic pronouncements of Wittgenstein and some statements of the Buddha, the latter preached a definite goal-oriented doctrine (the four noble truths ) and a definite way (to achieve the goal of Nirvana ). But it may be difficult to construe Wittgenstein's philosophic motivations to be leading man towards such a goal as Nirvana. The Buddha, for example, was definitely and seriously concerned with the human suffering (duhkha) and the "conditioned-ness' of human existence. Thus, if the metaphysical assumptions, such as that of a soul, create and perpetuate suffering, they, accoring to the Buddha, should better be avoided. But one sees Wittgenstein as one who tried to destroy our intellectual confusion created by our philosophic jargons and metaphysical beliefs. Jayatilleke, however, points out the difference between the Buddha and the Logical Positivists in a different manner (p. 475-6) : "It is necessary, however, to draw a distinction between the solution of the Logical Positivists and that of the Buddhist. The Buddhist while saying that (it) is meaningless to ask whether one exists in, does not exist in, is born in, is not born in, Nirvana, still speaks of such a transcendent state as realizable. The meaninglessness of these questions is thus partly due to the inadequacy of the concepts contained in them to refer to this state......... The transempirical cannot be empirically described or understood but it can be realized and attained." (Italics mine). It is difficult to support the above contention. Jayatilleke seems to be suggesting here, following probably the lead of T.R. V. Murti29, that the Buddha, by not answering the avyakata questions tried to impress upon us about the poverty of our language apparatus as well as the consequent ineffability of the "transcendental truth". The Buddha, in my opinion, was seldom eager to teach his disciple about what was called the transcendental truth. Much less can it be said that he believed in any sort of transcendental truths. There is evidence to show that the Buddha was against the mystical teachings which talked about the highest bliss (ekanta-sukha) and other unverifiable (unspecifiable) pronouncen:ents. We can thus refer to the Janapadakalyani-sutta of the Dighanikaya I.95 : "The Buddha continues : Just as if a man would say, "I desire and am infatuated by the beauty-queen of this land." And people would ask him: "Well, friend, do you know whether this beautyqueen of the land, whom you desire and wish to make love to, is a Ksatriyi by caste, or a Brahmani, or a Vaisyi or a Sudri ?" Page #24 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Middle Way and 'Non-onesided' Way And when so asked he answers: "No". And people would ask him: "Well, friend, do you know what is the name or gotra (family name) of this beauty-queen whom you desire and wish to make love to? Do you know whether she is tall or short or of medium height, whether she is dark or pitch-dark or dark-brown or of brown-yellow complexion (mangura = "golden in colour" T. W.Rhys Davids. In fact mangura refers to a river fish of brown-yellow colour; see concise Pali-English Dictionary: A. P. Buddhadatta Mahathera, Colombo, 1957)? Or, do you know in which village, town or city she dwells ?" 15 And when so asked, he answers, "No". And people say to him, "So then, friend, you do desire and wish to make love to someone whom you do not know, nor have you seen?". And when so asked, he answers, " Yes". Now, what do you think of it, Potthapada ? If this happens, would not the statement of that man be nonsensical (appatihirakata='without good ground." Rhys Davids says "Witless" following Buddhaghosa's interpretation "patibhanavirahitam"; Rhys Davids also suggests "not apposite") ? 'Yes, Sir. If this happens, certainly the statement of that man would be nonsensical.' 'Thus, Potthapada, to all those sramanas and brahmanas, who say, "The soul has perfect happiness and no disease (suffering) after death" I say, "Is it true that you, friends, preach and believe that the person has perfect happiness and no suffering after death?". And when they are so asked, they answer, "Yes." And I ask them again, "Do you, friends, move about (in this world) having known or seen any man perfectly happy ?" And being so asked, they answer, "No." And I ask them, " Again, friends, have you yourselves experienced the perfect bliss for a whole night or for a whole day, or even for half a night or half a day?" And being so asked, they answer, "No." Then I ask them thus, "Do you, friends, know the way or the method by which one is supposed to realize the perfect happiness?" Page #25 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 16 And being so asked, they answer, "No." And I ask them thus, "Have you, friends, heard the voices of those gods who had realized the world of the perfect happiness, saying, 'Be earnest, O men, and make direct efforts towards the realization of the world of the perfect happiness. For we have made similar efforts and have now realized the world of the perfect happiness." And being so asked, they answer, "No." Now, what do you think, Potthapada? If this is so, would not the statement of these sramanas and brahmanas be nonsensical ?" The Central Philosophy of Jainism 'Yes, Sir. If this is so, then certainly the statement of those sramanas and brahmanas would be nonsesnical." I think the above dialogue of the Buddha requires no comment. The point of the simile is quite clear. In any case, the Buddha did not leave the ten so-called avyakata questions altogether unanswered. Jayatilleke, in his eagerness to show parallelism between the Buddha and Wittgenstein (or the Positivists) has unfortunately forgotten that the Buddha did answer all the ten questions with the help of his vibhajya method. The first six questions were rejected by the Buddha (and therefore, one can say that he answered them in the negative, perhaps, with a qualified negation), for they definitely run contrary to his philosophic position, i. e. the Middle Way, madhyama pratipat. Thus, for example, if he accepted that the loka (world ?) is finite he would be accepting the annihilationist's position and if he accepted that the loka is infinite, he would be accepting the eternalist's position. But his philosophic goal was to steer clear of these extremes. For example, let us refer to the following dialogue in the Lokayatikasutta of the Samyuttanikaya XII, 47: 'The Lokayatika brahmana asked the Buddha: "O Gotama, does everything exist? " "Everything exists-this is, O Brahmana, the first Lokayatika view." "Again, Gotama, does nothing exist ?" "Nothing exists-this is, O Brahmana, the second Lokayatika view." "O Gotama, is all one ?" "All is one this is, Brahmana, the third Lokayatika view." 66 Again, O Gotama, is all separate ?" "All is separate this is, O Brahmana, the fourth Lokayatika view. The Tathagata, O Brhamana, teaches his doctrine through the Middle Way (having avoided all extremes), viz., depending upon avidya (misconception) samskara arises, and so on." Page #26 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Middle Way and 'Non-Onesided' Way 17 As regards the fifth and the sixth questions the Buddha gave his answers in the Avijjapaccaya-sutta of the Samyutta-nikaya XII. 135: " If it is accepted that the soul is identical with the body, then there is no use of prescribing the discipline for Brahmacarya (ascetic practices such as control of the mind ). And if it is accepted that the soul is different from the body, then there is no use of prescribing the discipline for brahmacarya ( ascetic practices such as control of the body ). Thus, having given up both the extremes, the Tathagata instructs the doctrine through the Middle Way." As regards the last four questions (seventh through tenth in the above list), the Buddha explained his position in the Aggivacchagottasutta of the Majjhima-nikaya II. 22. I have already cited above the dialogue between Vaccha and the Buddha. I have also explained the point of the analogy of a burning flame and its extinction with the Tathagata and his death. By now it is clear that the Buddha, instead of maintaining complete silence about the so-called avyakata questions, answered them explicity with the help of his vibhajya method. Yasomitra quotes another dialogue of the Buddha in order to illuminate his position on the avyakata questions:30 " Is it true, Gautama, that he who acts enjoys the result (also)?" "This, Brahmana, is unexplained." "Is it true that one acts and another enjoys the result ?" ** This, Brahmana, is unexplained." "You say that it is unexplained when I ask 'Is it true that he who acts also enjoys the result ?' You also say that it is unexplained when I ask 'Is it true that one acts and the other enjoys the result ?' Now, certainly, what is the meaning of your statements ( answers )?" " The statement. He who acts enjoys the result' leads to eternalism. And the statement One acts and the other enjoys the result' leads to annihilationism. Having recognized both these extremes, the Tathagata teaches the doctrine by the Middle Way." The above analysis shows that the Middle Way was similar to the * non-onesided' ( anekanta ) way. For in both cases one is advised to avoid the extremes (anta). But Mahavira was not strictly a follower of the Middle Way. For him, the 'middle' was also an anta, a side, as is evident in the scheme, the left, the right and the middle. Thus from the Jaina point of view the Buddha would still be an ekanta-vadin Page #27 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 18 The Central Philosophy of Jainism although he was a follower of the middle course. With regard to the doctrine of the four Noble Truths and the impermanence of the five personality aggregates, the Buddha held a definite position.31 In other words, with regard to these questions the Buddha was an ekantavadin. Similarly, I think the 'dependent origination theory of causality in Buddhism is asserted to refute the evil of both extremes (another illustration of the middle course): sat-karya (the effect pre-exists) and asatkarya (the effect is newly created). In fact, one can follow the 'middle' course in either of the two ways. First, I can accept the middle course and reject the two extremes (anta). Thus I merely suggest a third alternative which excludes the other alternatives already suggested. Second, I can accept the middle course without necessarily rejecting the two extremes. In this case, my alternative does not exclude completely the other alternatives. I merely expand myself to embrace the two alternatives while myself remaining in the middle. The first 'middle' way is based upon rejection and exclusion, the second upon acceptance and inclusion. We may call the first exclusive' middle, and the second the 'inclusive' middle. The Middle Way of the Buddhist was of the first kind. Mahavira's anekanta-vada ( the non-onesided ' doctrine) was of the second kind. Page #28 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IV ANEKANTA: A DEVELOPMENT FROM THE VIBHAJYA METHOD Mahavira was described in the Sutrakrtanga as a vibhajya-vadin. But he developed the vibhajya method in a different line. It will be instructive to collect from the Bhagavatisutra different references to the so-called avyakata questions (mentioned above) and to see how Mahavira answered them with his vibhajya method. This will reveal that the vibhajya method received a definite form in the hands of Mahavira and was finally transformed into the anekanta-vada of the Jainas. In this matter I follow closely the suggestion of Pandit D. Malvania. 32. The first two avyakata questions were explained by Mahavira in the following manner: Bhagavati. 9.386.33 "Bhikkhu Jamali was asked by Honorable Gotama as follows: 'Is the world eternal or is it non-eternal, Jamali ? Is the soul eternal or is it, Jamali, non-eternal ?' Being asked in this manner Jamali was doubtful and wanted to know but was overwhelmed with confusion. He was unable to speak in reply, and remained silent. When Jamali was thus confused, the Venerable Mahavira told the Bhikkhu Jamali thus: 'I have, Jamali, many disciples who are nirgrantha ('without a stitch') ascetics and not even omniscient, but they are able to tell the answer as much as I can. Otherwise, they would not have spoken to you, as they have in the present case. The world is, Jamali, eternal. It did not cease to exist at any time, it does not cease to exist at any time and it will not cease to exist at any time. It was, it is and it will be. It is constant, permanent, eternal, imperishable, indestructible, always existent. The world is, Jamali, non-eternal. For it becomes progressive (in time-cycle) after being regressive. And it becomes regressive after becoming progressive. The soul (i. e. living being) is, Jamali, eternal. For it did not cease to exist at any time. The soul is, Jamali, non-eternal. For it becomes animal after being a hellish creature, becomes a man after becoming an animal and it becomes a god after being a man." Page #29 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Central Philosophy of Jainism Several points may be noted in this connection. First, Jamali was confused and remained silent in the beginning for the question had several ambiguities. Mahavira boasted that not only he could answer it but also most of his ordinary disciples could. (Was it an oblique reference to the 'silence' of the Buddha when he first tried to avoid answering such questions ?) The questions might have been ambiguous but were not unanswerable. 20 Second, in the first four avyakata questions, the subject was "loka". Since it ambiguously means both 'the world' and 'the person', Mahavira used two separate sets of questions with two different subjects, 'the world' and 'the soul', thus, perhaps foreshadowing the Jaina ontological distinction between the living and the non-living (spirit and matter). Resolution of ambiguities is, as I have already noted, part of the vibhajya method. Third, and this is more important, Mahavira, unlike the Buddha, did not reject both of the seemingly contradictory predicates ('infinite' and 'finite') but rather accepted both of them and avoided the seeming contradiction by showing (or exposing) the different senses in which these predicates could be used, Thus, it could hardly be regarded as an acceptance of a real contradiction. To use the later day philosophic terminology of the Jainas, the world, from the point of view (naya) of continuity, may be called eternal, but from the point of view of change of its states, it is non-eternal. This probably foreshadowed also the Jaina synthesis of the Buddhist doctrine of universal flux with the Vedanta doctrine of the unchanging Brahman. Regarding the third and the fourth avyakata questions, Mahavira had the following to say: Bhagavati 2.1.90 (p. 420) "There has been the following question in your mind, Skandhaka, which you have thought about, considered, deliberated and posed to ask: Is the world finite (with an end), or is it infinite?' This can be explained as follows: I have given instruction about the world, Skandhaka, in four ways: They are: following the point of view of the substance, that of area-measurement, that of time, and that of modifications. "Now, from the point of view of the substance, the world is one, and therefore, finite (i. e. countable in number). From the point of view of its area-measurement, the world is, again, finite (i. e. its numerical calculation is possible), for its length and breadth are each measured as asamkhyata 10,000,0002 yojanas. (This is following Page #30 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Anekanta : A Development From The Vibhajya Method 21 the Jaina mythological account of the universe found in Karmagrantha.) And its circumference is measured again, as asamkhyata 10,000,0002 yojanas. (The latter asaskhyata number must be a greater number than the former.) "From the point of view of time, the world does not have an end (i. e. infinite), for it did not cease to exist at any time, neither does it cease to exist (now), nor will it cease to exist at any time, it was, it is and it will be; it is constant, eternal, permanent, imperishable, indestructible, and always existent. "From the point of view of modifications, the world is infinite (i. e. uncountable in number), for it has limitless modifications of colour, smell, taste and touch, it has limitless modification in the form of configuration, it has limitless forms of being heavy and light, and limitless states of formless modifications (a-guru-laghu-paryaya). "Therefore, Skandhaka, the world is finite from the point of view of its substance, finite (i. e. measureable) from the point of view of its area, (but) infinite from the point of view of time (duration) and also infinite (uncountable) from the point of view of its modifications." Afterwards, the same questions were raised with regards to the soul (jiva). And Mahavira proceeded to solve them as follows : Bhagavati (p.420). "There is another question (in your mind), Skandhaka, viz : is the soul finite or infinite ? This can be explained as follows: A soul is, from the point of view of its substance, finite (countable), for it is countable as one. From the point of view of its area, the soul is, again, finite (i. e. has measurable dimension), for it has (according to the Jaina faith) asamkhyata number of parts, and also occupies an asamkhyata number of space-points. "From the point of view of time the soul has no end (i. e. eternal), for it never ceases to exist and it is there always. From the point of view of its modifications the soul is infinite, for it has infinite modifications of knowledge, infinite modifications of direct insight, infinite modifications of character, infinite modifications of formless quality (a-guru-laghu-paryaya). It has no end. Thus, a soul is finite in number from the point of view of its substance, it is finite (measureable) also from the point of view of its area, but it is infinite (continuous) from the point of view Page #31 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 22 The Central Philosophy of Jainism of time, and infinite (unlimited in number) from the point of view of its modifications." It is clear from the above that when Mahavira tried to answer the so-called avyakata questions through the vibhajya method, he had analysed the different senses of, and thereby clarified the ambiguity contained in, such predicate-expressions, "infinite" and "finite." "Infinite" may mean 'limitless in number or measurement' or 'everlasting.' Similarly, "finite" may mean 'limited in number or measurement' or 'of limited duration.' Notice that all these senses have been taken into account in Mahavira's method of analysis. One can thus agree with the principle of Mahavira without necessarily agreeing with the Jaina mythical account of the universe and man. Notice also that Mahavira's analysis differed from that of the Buddha in that the Buddha maintained his doctrine of the Middle Way by rejecting the two alternative questions, positive and negative, while Mahavira came closer to the anekanta-vada by accepting both alternatives with proper qualifications and conditionalization. To the fifth and the sixth questions, Mahavira gave also positive answers (cf. Bhagavati 13.7.494).34 For the last four questions too, Mahavira's answer would be very definite, for he would say, following the Jaina religious faith, that the Tathagata or the saint exists and reaches the end of the universe after death. The above sketch shows how the vibhajya method in the hands of Mahavira was transformed into the anekanta philosophy of the Jainas. If the vibhajya method is interpreted only as a method of analysis and classification then the Jaina anekanta method may be regarded as the opposite of it, i.e., synthesis. But, in fact, the vibhajya method was a generic name for any non-dogmatic and exploratory approach to philosophic and metaphysical questions. It included both analysis and synthesis, differentiation and integration. Schematically we can represent the difference between analysis and synthesis (involved here) as follows: In reply to the question "Are all A's B's ?" one can say: "Some A's are B's, and some are not". Here we answer by discriminating between the two groups of A's, i.e., the two subclasses of the class denoted by the subject term. This was what the Abhidharmika Buddhist called one kind of the vibhajya method, i.e., analysis. In reply to the question "Is A B ?" one can also say: "It depends." In other words, it is said that A's being B depends upon one's Page #32 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Anekanta : A Development From The Vibhajya Method 23 point of view, and this also implies that A's not being B depends on another point of view. In the second case, we try to synthesize the two sides, positive and negative. Mahavira thus developed a philosophy of synthesis and toleration, which later came to be designated as the anekanta-vada. The Buddha's method was one of withdrawal from philosophic disputes, for he avoided committing himself to any extreme view. But Mahavira's method was one of commitment, for he attempted to understand the points of view of the fighting parties (in a philosophic dispute) so that their dispute could be resolved and reconciled. Thus, the essence of the anekanta-vada lies in exposing and making explicit the standpoints or presuppositions of different philosophical schools. Page #33 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ DIFFERENT SENSES OF ANEKANTA "Sugato yadi sarvajnah kapilo neti ka prama Tav ubhau yadi sarvajnau matabhedah katham tayoh." "If Sugata (the Buddha) is omniscient, how do we know that Kapila is not (also omniscient)? If both of them are omniscient, how is it then that the view of the former differs from the latter ?" This verse quoted in Tattvasangraha (verse 3148) was apparently used to refute the Jaina doctrine of omniscience. But the same statement can be used, perhaps with a shift in the emphasis or intonation, by a Jaina to defend his anekanta doctrine. In fact, the anekanta doctrine can be vindicated if we assume the omniscience of Mahavira. Thus, Samantabhadra has said : 35 "Since the doctrines of all 'non-Jaina' (tirthakrt) philosophers contradict each other, none of them is trustworthy. Who, then, could be the guru 'instructor'?" This also reveals the wonderful power of assimilation of the Jaina doctrine. And thus I have called it a philosophy of synthesis and reconciliation. H. Kapadia analysed "anekanta-vada" as an+eka+anta +vada ("notone-a side (an end) - a statement"). He explained the meaning as "manysided exposition". He added : "Thereby it is implied that it is a statement made after taking into account all possible angles of vision regarding any object or idea."36 This explanation is somewhat inaccurate. For "vada" in this context usually means a theory or a philosophic position (e.g., sat-karya-vada, Sunya-vada). Thus one can translate anekantavada as 'the theory of many-sidedness or manifoldness of reality.' To be precise, anekanta-vada is to be contrasted with ekanta-vada, which stands for a definite, categorically asserted philosophical position. But aneka 'many' is not diametrically opposite of eka 'one', for many includes one. Different ekanta-vadas may thus be only constituents of the anekanta doctrine. Dr. Satkari Mookerjee explained anekanta as the philosophy of "non-absolutism." 37 But this seems hardly acceptable, for, according to some, even the Madhyamika philosophy can be described as one of "non-absolutism'. Dr. Y. J. Padmarajiah has translated Page #34 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Different Senses of Anekanta 25 anekanta-vada as 'the theory of manifoldness. 38 This is acceptable, but unfortunately he has also used such terms as 'indetermination' or 'indefinitness' to refer to the anekanta doctrine. This is misleading. For, as any Jaina scholar would point out, anekanta is certainly not a philosophy of indetermination or a philosophy of dubiety. It is, in fact, useful to make a distinction between two senses of anekanta-vada. The term is used, in the first place, to denote the Jaina metaphysical doctrine, by which I mean the Jaina view of reality. Roughly, the Jainas believe that reality is manifold and each entity has a manifold nature, consists of diverse forms and modes, of innumerable aspects. In this sense, therefore, the term can correctly be translated as 'the theory of manifoldness of reality.' But the term 'anekanta-vada' is also used for the Jaina philosophic method as a method which allows for reconciliation, integration and synthesis of conflicting philosophic views. In this sense, the anekanta-vada is the proper heir to the vibhajya-vada of Mahavira As a philosophic methodology, anekanta-vada takes its flight, to use Padmarajiah's metaphor, 39 on the two wings of naya-vada "the doctrine of standpoints' and saptabhangi 'the doctrine of sevenfold predication'. Anekanta-vada is sometimes called 'syad-vada', although the latter term is usually reserved for the dialectic of sevenfold predication'. Mallisena in his Syadvada-man jari explains (under verse five) syad-vada as anekanta-vada : "The particle 'syad' signifies 'manifoldness': and so the syaddoctrine is the doctrine of manifoldness. And that means the acceptance (of a view) that a single entity is variegated by a plurality of attributes, namely, non-eternal and eternal etc."40 F. W. Thomas translates "anekanta" as 'non-unequivocality'41. But this is also vague. In Haribhadra's Anekantajayapataka, several synonyms of "anekanta-vada" are found, such as : sa nhara-vada42 (p. 26) 'the philosophy of integration'; sarva-vastu-sabala-vada (p. 26) 'the theory of manifoldness of every real entity; akula-vada (p. 13) 'the philosophy of 'that' and 'not that'; and samkirna-vada (p. 13) 'the philosophy of intermixture'. These synonyms, to be sure, throw considerable light on the nature and meaning of the anekanta-vada. (The word 'akula' may mean 'confused' but since anekanta is not the philosophy of confusion, let us translate akula-vada as a position where conflicting views are entangled or harmonized together'.) Page #35 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ VI ANEKANTA AS A RESOLUTION OF THE PARADOX OF CAUSALITY The critique of causality was an important factor in the development of the early philosophical thoughts in India. The first beginning of Indian philosophy can be traced back to the cosmogonic hymns of the Vedas. Notably the Nasadiya hymn of the Rg-veda records two opposing views about the origin of the Universe : The Universe came out of Being or sat or the existent, and it came out of the non-existent or asat. During the period of philosophic systematization, those two views crystalized into two opposing philosophic positions on causality : satkarya-vada (of the Samkhya), which means that the effect pre-exists in the cause, and asat-karya-vada (of the Vaisesika), which means that the effect is a new creation. These two views actually present the two sides of the ancient philosophical paradox of change and permanence. This paradox is beautifully expressed in a line in the Bhagavad-gita. 43 "Whatever is non-existent or unreal does not come into existence, whatever is existent or real does not go out of existence." Nagarjuna expressed the paradox as follows : 44 "If something exists by nature, it would never cease to exist. For it is certainly not feasible that the nature will be otherwise." In the Samkhya system, Vacaspati-misra formulated the problem as follows:45 "The non-existent does not come into existence, nor the existent cease to exist." What we have here suggests a striking similarity in the origin of philosophic thought between India and Greece. In both traditions, it is significant to note, philosophy began with a search for a unity that would explain and give some coherence to the apparent incoherence of a universe in a flux. Philosophy originated in India, as much as it did in ancient Greece, when a purely mythological way of thinking was succeeded by a deeper reflection on what was primary in our universe of multiplicity and change. Page #36 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Anekanta as a Resolution of the Paradox of Causality The Samkhya solution of the paradox of change is embodied in its theory of real transformation (parinamavada). The paradox can be restated as follows: If change (origin and destruction) is intelligible, permanence is unintelligible, and if permanence is intelligible, change is not. The Samkhya posited the persistence of what it called the "unmanifest" or the "chief" matter. The "chief" in this system is said to be undergoing modifications or change at every moment while it itself remains unchanging or constant. It is conceived here as the unchanging core of all matter, as the repository of all the potentialities for change, as one that undergoes modifications. The 'chief' is existent, thus the Samkhya avoids the anomaly of conceding the existence of the non-existent (of na asato bhavah). Origination is explained as the unfolding of the hidden potentialities. Vacaspati-misra used the analogy of the turtle body which can make its limbs explicit and also withdraw them inside without really creating or destroying them.46 The Vaisesika solution leaned heavily on the other end of the paradox: asata eva bhavah 'only such things come into existence as did not exist before.' And the logical corollary to this position was: sata eva abhavah 'only what exists can be destroyed.' Thus, while explaining Vaisesika-sutra 9.2 "sad asat" ("the existent becomes non-existent"), Candrananda notes: "The effect which is existent is destroyed in 'posterior' time and thus becomes non-existent."47 Permanence is a separate characteristic in this system. Only those things are permanent that can neither be said to come into existence, nor cease to exist. 27 and The Buddhist solution agrees partly with the Vaisesika and partly with the Samkhya. The 'dependent origination' theory states that origination is conditioned by (i. e., dependent upon) other factors. As in the Vaisesika, change here is accepted as real. But the Buddhists are much more radical. Change (origin and destruction) is instantaneous automatic (and, in this regard, it comes closer to the Samkhya theory of instantaneous transformation). Change is the order of nature. Only sequence of events exists. There is nothing (no inner core) that changes from one state to another, but there is change (origin and destruction). The two states, the so-called cause-state and the effect-state, are nonidentical with each other (and, in this regard, the theory comes closer to the Vaisesika). But the Samkhya notion of potentiality and the Vaisesika notion of permanence or stability are both rejected in Buddhism. The Buddhist theory of causation is drawn to its extremity in the Sautrantika doctrine as universal flux. Page #37 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 28 The Central Philosophy of Jainism The Vedanta school accepted the other extreme in making the notion of permanence as ultimately real. It subordinated the notion of change completely under that of permanence. While the early Vedanta (Badarayana and Bhartsprapanca) rejected the Samkhya dualism of matter and spirit (making Brahman, the ultimate consciousness, the root of all things, spiritual and material), it accepted the Samkhya doctrine of real transformation or parinama. 48 Samkara carries this position to the further extreme by declaring all change to be illusory and superficial (cf. vivartavada). Stated simply, Samkara's position was acceptance of one extreme of the above paradox: If something exists, it should exist always. And since only Brahman is the existent, it is eternal, everlasting and unchanging. Hence change has to be ruled out as only appearance. Now we can consider the Jaina resolution of this dispute about causality with the help of their anekanta method and anekanta philosophy. The anekanta doctrine says that reality is both unchanging and everchanging, for reality has manifold nature, infinitefold complexity. To use the philosophical terminology of A. N. Whitehead, it is both a process and a reality. Thus, what Whitehead says about the 'chief task of metaphysics' will certainly be welcome to the Jainas : "That 'all things flow is the first vague generalization which the unsystematized, barely analysed, intuition of men has produced. Without doubt, if we are to go back to that ultimate, integral experience, unwarped by the sophistications of theory, that experience whose elucidation is the final aim of philosophy, the flux of things is one ultimate generalization around which we must weave our philosophical system."49 The notion of 'flux', Whitehead continues, has been held up by such philosophers as Heraclitus as one primary notion for further analysis, while others dwell on 'permanence of things, or on 'things'-the solid earth, the mountains, the stones, the Egyptian Pyramids, the spirit of man, God. The first group has given us the metaphysics of 'substance', and the second group the metaphysics of 'flux'. "But", Whitehead asserts, "in truth the two lines cannot be torn apart in this way." 50 This is almost an echo of what the Jaina philosophers say, viz., the Buddhists have given us the philosophy of flux while the Vedantins the philosophy of permanence, but in reality the two notions cannot be separated. The Jainas argue in the following way. The world has an aspect that is seen as unchanging - this is its sat-aspect or svabhava-aspect or its Page #38 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Anekanta as a Resolution of the Paradox of. Causality 29 "substance" aspect. The substantial essence of reality is permanent for it defies all change. But if one puts too much emphasis on this aspect one is driven to the extreme (ekanta) position of the Vedanta. A moderately extreme (ekanta) position is that of the Samkhya, which emphasizes permanence but recognizes also change. If one puts too much emphasis on the aspect of change, one is driven to the position of the (Sautrantika) Buddhist, who denies completely the substantial aspect of reality. The world is only a process, a sequence of events. A moderately extreme position in this direction is that of the Vaisesikas, for they accept both, the notion of unchanging substances and that of qualitative change and modifications. Page #39 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ VII THE JAINA NAYAS AND THE MADHYAMIKA DIALECTIC It will be interesting to compare the Jaina doctrine of Nayas 'standpoints' with Madhyamika dialectic. The Jainas argue that different philosophers, when they construct different philosophical systems, emphasize different 'standpoints.' The Jainas further point out that as long as we emphasize one aspect or standpoint (say the standpoint of 'substance') while being fully aware that this is only one out of many, equally viable, standpoints, we employ a naya 'a right philosophical method.' But when we emphasize only one standpoint by excluding all others, we employ a durnaya 'an incorrect philosophical method.' The business of the anekanta philosophy is to expose a durnaya, and isolate and identify the nayas. Following the above principle, the Jainas assert that reality appears to be unchanging when we consider its 'substantial' aspect, but it seems to be everchanging when we consider its qualities and modes. Other philosophers suffer from partiality of their outlook while the Jainas try to overcome partiality and one-sidedness and search for the totality of outlook, for omniscience, How does the Jaina position differ from that of the Madhyamikas ? The Madhyamikas also emphasize the paradoxicality of change and continuity. But they derive a different philosophic conclusion from this premise, for they do not share the same synthesizing and conciliatory (anekanta) attitude of the Jainas. The inherent paradoxicality of the notion of causation is, for the Madhyamikas, the ground for mistrusting the basic premise upon which the thesis of causality is grounded : viz., a thing exists by its 'one-nature' or essence (svabhava). Thus, the point is driven home by the Madhyamikas that a thing is empty of its 'own-nature' or essence, and this culminates in their thesis of Emptiness' (Sunyata). To illustrate Nagarjuna's philosphic argumentation, let me quote two verses from the Madhyamika-Karika: "The "own-nature' (of a thing) cannot be generated by causal conditions (hetus and pratyayas). For if the 'own-nature' is generated by causal conditions, it would be (artificially) created." "Now, how could 'own- nature' be (artificially) created ? For, Page #40 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Jaina Nayas and the Madhyamika Dialectic 31 'own-nature' is what is non-artificial (un-created) and independent of others"51 Nagarjuna, thus, carries this point to its logical extrme : "If the natue or essence (of a thing) does not exist, what is it then that will change ? And if the nature does exist, what again is it that will change ?"52 Consistent with the attitude of the Buddha, who refused to be dragged into the quicksand of philosophic disputations, the Madhyamika rejects most philosphic positions by exposing their inherent contradictions and anomalies and points out that tattva (truth) is not to be arrived at through such philosophic disputations, for it is only revealed to the prajna or insight. Similarly consistent with the attitude of Mahavira, who tried to resolve the philosophic disputations by analyzing various shades of meaning and implications of the concepts involved (see above), the Jainas tried to reconcile between different philosophical schools and showed that the difficulties involved in their ekanta positions resulted from their hidden assumptions and tacitly accepted standpoints. this A comment from Siddhasena is particularly illuminating in connection. He observes :53 "All the standpoints (nayas) are right in their own respective spheres-but if they are taken to be refutations, each of the other, then they are wrong. But a man who knows the 'non-one-sided' nature of reality never says that a particular view is absolutely wrong." It should, however, be noted that Nagarjuna's position of non-commitment was not always expressed through negation or rejection. On rare occasions, he seems to betray what may be called the Jaina spirit of concession and neutrality. For example, consider: Madhyamika Karika, chap. 18, verse 8 "Everything is true; not everything is true; both, everything is true, and not everything is true; or, neither everything is true nor is everything not true. This is the teaching of the Buddha." Page #41 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ VIII SUBSTANCE AND QUALITY : TWO MAIN STANDPOINTS Siddhasena Divakara has pointed out that there are two fundamental nayas 'standpoints' that can be derived from the teachings of Mahavira.54 They are expressed cryptically as follows: 1) Dravyastika, the "substance exists" standpoint, and 2) Paryayastika, the "modification exists" standpoint. The first has been called the standpoint of substance and the second the standpoint of change or modification. Alternatively, the first one may be called the viewpoint of generality, and the second one the viewpoint of particularity or differentiation. All the other standpoints, according to Siddhasena, fall under these two heads. Traditionally, the Jainas talk about seven(or six) types of standpoints. This was by way of taking into account the different philosophical views prevalent in classical India. Siddhasena observed that the methodology of standpoints was intended to explain the truths of the Jain. canons : "The 'pure' naya methodology consists in the exposition of the (Jaina) canons. (But) if it is not correctly applied it ruins both parties."55 Siddhasena's warning about the incorrect employment of the naya methodology is reminiscent of a similar warning from Nagarjuna regarding the misunderstanding of the 'Emptiness' doctrine :56 "Like a snake caught at the wrong end, or like a craft learnt in the wrong manner, the 'emptiness' doctrine may destroy the stupid person when it is misunderstood by him." Siddhasena was probably the first in the Jaina tradition to synthesize the Samkhya view with the Buddhist view : Thus, he observes :57 "The system of philosophy taught by Kapila is a representation of the only substance exists' viewpoint, and that which is taught by the son of Suddhodana (the Buddha) is an exposition of 'only modification exists' viewpoint." Regarding the Vaisesika system, Siddhasena comments that it employs both viewpoints. But still the Vaisesikas do not employ a pure, flawless methodology:58 Page #42 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Substance and Quality : Two Main Standpoints 33 "Although the philosophical system of Kanada (Uluka) applies both standpoints, it is also fallacious because the standpoints are emp loyed each independently of the other." The point of Siddhasena is that the Vaisesikas simply combine the two standpoints, but do not synthesize them. The Jainas, on the other hand, synthesize the two and build them into a coherent whole. Siddhasena also claims that the Vaisesikas and the Buddhists are correct in so far as they point out the faults and fallacies of the Samkhya view of causality and the Samkhya philosophers are correct in so far as they criticize the Buddhists and the Vaisesikas. But when these two views of causality (sat-karya and asat-karya) are adjusted together in compliance with the anekanta method, the result will be the True Insight (samyag-darsana, omniscience).59 Siddhasena, in fact, inentions six different standpoints as subdivisions of the two fundamental standpoints : "Substance exists" and "modification exists." The two standpoints called samgraha (the general) and vyavahara (the practical) are included under the 'substance exists' standpoint. The most general standpoint is that of the monistic philosophers, for whom there is only one, undifferentiated reality, the ultimate reality. The 'practical' standpoint is that of the pluralistic philosophers, who, for the sake of convenience in everyday behaviour, classify reality into two or several categories. The four standpoints known as rjusutra (the 'straight thread'), sabda (the verbal), samabhirudha (the 'subtle'), and eva.nbhuta (the 'thus-happened'), are included under the "modification exists" standpoint. The "straight-thread" standpoint is described by Siddha sena as the very foundation of the "modification exists" standpoint. And the 'verbal and other minor nayas are only subtle varieties of the "straightthread" standpoint, its branches and twigs. 60 The "straight-thread" standpoint is the viewpoint of particularity. It looks at a thing with regard to its present moment only. Thus, it reveals that a thing is in perpetual flux. This is how the Buddhists propound their doctrine of momentariness. In other words, this standpoint asks us to differentiate the thing of this moment from the thing of the next moment. The "verbal" standpoint asks us to differentiate a word having one particular set of grammatical inflections (such as 'gender' and 'person') from the same word having a different set of grammatical inflections. The "subtle" standpoint differentiates between 'synonymous' words (having the same denotation) on the basis of their etymological or functional meanings. The "thus-happened" standpoint takes the extreme form of particulari Page #43 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 34 The Central Philosophy of Jainism zation. It differentiates between different uses of the same word at different times or in different contexts. We can tabulate Siddhasena's scheme as follows: Standpoints "Substance exists" "Modification exists" The general The 'practical (Vedanta, Mahayana Buddhism) (Vaisesika, Samkhya) The "straigh-thread" (Sautrantika) The "verbal" The "subtle" (Grammarians) (Etymologists) The "thus-happened" (Pragmatists) Page #44 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ IX EXISTENCE AND SUBSTANCE It will be interesting to introduce at this point the Jaina discussion of the problem of existence and substance. The Jaina conception of 'existence' (sat) was intimately related to their notion of 'substance'. In fact, the Jainas redefined the notion of substance, in accordance with their anekanta principle, as a combination of the notion of being and becoming'. 61 The Tattvarthasutra 5.29 asserts :62 "What there is, has the nature of substance." And in the next Sutra it is added : "What there is (the existent), is endowed with the triple character, origin, decay and stability (persistence)." The Tattvartha-bhasya explains that whatever originates, perishes and continues to be is called the existent; anything different is called the non-existent. 63 In sutra 5.37, the substance is again characterized as follows : "The substance is possessed of qualities (guna) and modes (paryaya)." Here, the broad category "attribute' is apparently broken into two subcategories, qualities and modes. But the sutras do not give the definition of modes (paryaya); sutra 5.40 defines quality (guna) as : "What reside in a substance, and are themselves devoid of any quality, are called qualities." The Tattvartha-bhasya adds :64 "Though modes too reside in a substance and themselves devoid of any quality, they are subject to origin and destruction. Thus, they do not always reside in a substance. The qualities, on the other hand, are permanent, and hence they always reside in a substance. This is how qualities are to be distinguished from modes." Pujyapada, in his commentary Sarvarthasiddhi, is more specific about the distinction of qualities and modes : 65 "A quality is (actually) the distinguishing character of one substance from another. For example, the person (soul) is different from matter (non-soul) through its possession of) cognition etc.; the matter is distinguished from soul through qualities like colour. The generic attributes common to souls are cognition etc., and that of non-soul are colour etc. The modifications of these qualities, viewed in their particular nature, are called modes (paryaya), Page #45 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Central Philosophy of Jainism such as: cognition of a pot, anger, pride (in a soul); and intense or mild odour, deep or light colour in the case of the non-soul." In the above analysis of the Tattvarthasutra, we have at least two compatible notions of substance: (1) substance as the core of change or flux, and (2) substance as the substratum of attributes. Kundakunda combines these two notions as he defines substance in his Pravacanasara : "They call it a substance, which is characterized by origin, persistence and decay, without changing its 'own-nature', and which is endowed with qualities and accompanied by modifications. For the 'own-nature of the substance is its existence (sad-bhava), which is always accompanied by qualities and variegated modes, and at the same time, by origin, decay and continuity. Here the great Jina, while he was teaching his doctrine, had described only one among various characteristics, namely, existence, for it is allcomprising. The Jinas have truly declared that what is called the existent is, in fact, the substance existing by its own-nature. This is also established by the scripture. He who does not accept it is only a non--Jaina (cf. para-samaya)."66 The Vaisesika school emphasized rather the second aspect of the substance, substance as the substratum of qualities and action. Thus, Vaisesika-sutra 1.1.14 defined substance as follows: "The definition of a substance is that it possesses qualities (guna) and action/motion (kriya), and it is the substratum-cause."67 The notion of "substratum-cause" (samavayi-karana) is explained in this context as that which as substratum gives 'causal support to the changing attributes, qualities and action. Aristotle, in the Western tradition, was emphatic about both these notions of substance : (1) as a core of change, and (2) as a substratum of attributes. In Categories, he wrote : "The most distinctive mark of substance appears to be that, while remaining numerically one and the same, it is capable of admitting contrary qualities. From among things other than substance, we should find ourselves unable to bring forward any which possessed this mark."68 This comment underlines both notions of substance mentioned above. Aristotle, however, suggested also three other notions of substance, all of which became very influential in later Western philosophty : (3) sub Page #46 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Existence and Substance 37 stance as the concrete individual thing, (4) substance as essence, as one having independent existence, and (5) substance as the logical subject. From his remark that examples of substance can be "the individual man or horse", 69 one can infer the third notion of substance, substance as the concrete individual. But admittedly, Aristotle's remark was too vague to give us any definite conclusion. : The Vaisesika theory of substance included the concept of the 'concrete' individual, but it was extended to include such non-concrete things as the bodiless soul, the sky, time and space. Thus, the notion of substance as a concrete individual thing is too narrow to accomodate the Vaisesika view. Besides, one may reasonably ask : what constitutes the concreteness? The criteria of identification and individuation are clear enough with regard to the standard things like man, table and horse, but very unclear and problematic with regard to such non-standard things as cloud, water and iron. The idea of substance as the essence or the immutable core seems to have been suggested by Aristotle in his Metaphysics.70 A natural corollary to this notion is that a substance is independently existent. Thus, existence, according to Aristotle, can be applied, in proper sense of the term, to substances only, and qualities and relations have only a secondary existence, a parasitic mode of being. "Therefore, that which is primarily, i.e., not in a qualified sense but without qualification, must be substance." The Jainas too, identify the notion of "it is" (existence) with that of substance, but they add also that "it is" or "it exists" means only that it is endowed with the triple character of origin, decay and stability. The Jainas explicated the notion of substance in such a way as to avoid falling between the two stools of being and becoming. It was a grand compromise of flux and permanence. The substance is being, it is also becoming. Kundakunda observes : The substance has both natures: from the standpoint of its own--nature', it is being (sat, unchanging), and from the standpoint of its other 'own-nature', it has triple character, origin, decay and continuity, i.e., fluctuations.71 Siddhasena Divakara repeated the point more forcefully : "There is no substance that is devoid of modifications, nor is there any modification without an abiding something, a substance. For origin, decay and continuance are the three constituents of a substance."72 Page #47 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 38 The Central Philosophy of Jainism It may be noted that the notion of continuity in the so-called triple character of a substance is not identical with the notion of permanence of the substance. The former notion means persistence or continuance (pravahanityata). The latter notion means immutability. It is the notion in the background of which the triple character of origination, destruction and continuity becomes meaningful. 'Continuity', on the other hand, is a notion essentially dependent upon origin and decay. Thus, Kundakunda observes : "There is no origin without destruction, nor is there any destruction without origin, and neither is destruction nor origination possible without what continues to be."73 Amstacandra Suri, commentator of Kunda kunda, explains that when a pot is produced from a lump of clay, both the origin of the pot and the destruction of the lump together maintain the persistence of the clay-substance. In order to prove his contention, Amstcandra uses the following reductio (prasanga) : "If we do not accept it as true, origin, decay and continuity all three will then be really different from one another. In that case, when the mere origin of the pot is sought after, then either it will not originate for there will not be any (real) cause for its origin, or there will be origination of the non-existent (an untenable paradox). If the pot does not originate, no bhavas (things) will originate. If there is origination of the non-existent (asat), then the sky-flower etc. will come into being. Similarly, if mere destruction of the lump of clay is attempted at (to the exclusion of the production of the pot), then either there will not be any destruction of the lump for want of any (real) cause for such destruction, or there will be destruction of the existent or being another untenable position)."74 The Jainas were well aware of the Madhyamika critique of the own. nature' concept as well as of the problem involved in the doctrine of permanent substance. It is true that the immutability of own-nature invites a host of problems. But the notion of flux, the Jainas point out, is not sacrosanct. Thus, just as the Buddhist argues that there is only fluctuation from one state to another there being no permanent being, the Jaina takes the bull by the horn and counterargues that if there is no permanence there cannot be any change, any fluctuation, for it is only the permanent that can change. It is only the persisting soul that can transmigrate. Page #48 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Existence and Substance 39 In fact, the triple character that describes the Jaina conception of substance has been dwelt upon by many later authors. Samantabhadra points out that origin and decay relate to the specific nature of the substance and stability to the generic nature.75 Thus, if a golden pot is destroyed and a golden crown is made out of it, destruction, origination and continuity happen simultaneously and give rise to sorrow, joy and indifferent attitude respectively in the mind of three different kinds of people, those in favour of the pot, those in favour of the crown, and those in favour of the gold stuff. Kumarila stated the point more elaborately : "If the (gold) plate is destroyed and instead) a (gold) necklace is made, then the person who wanted the plate will grieve, and he who wishes the latter will be happy, but he who wishes for the gold stuff (only) will neither grive nor be happy. Thus, the triple nature of an entity is proved."76 Turning to the second conception of substance in the Tattvarthasutras (according to which substance is the substratum of qualities and modes), we can say that it was probably derived from the Vaisesika school. In fact, Tattvarthasutra 5.41 defines quality :77 "Qualities are located in substances, and are themselves devoid of qualities." This seems to be an echo of the Vaisesika definition of guna or quality. It is also significant that one of the most important Jaina ontological concepts, i.e. mode or modification, is not even defined in the Tattvarthasutras. The Jaina ontological principle of anekantata 'non-onesidedness', however, is not compatible with the rigid Vaisesika notions of substance and quality. Thus, Siddhasena has added that it would be as good as a heresy in Jainism, if one intends to make the notion of substance absoluty different from that of quality. Moreover, Siddhasena has argued, the supposed distinction between qualities and modes (tacitly accepted by both Umasvati and Kundakunda) should also be discarded altogether in order to remain true to the Jaina spirit.78 Siddhasena's philosophic insight in this regard was commendable. According to him, reality should be viewed from the two important standpoints, being and becoming, permanence and change. That is why Lord Mahavira acknowledged only two nayas or standpoints : "substance exists" and "modification exists". If x is an element of reality, then, according to Siddhasena, x can be viewed as a SUBSTANCE from the standpoint of being, and as a PROPERTY from the standpoint of be Page #49 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 40 The Central Philosophy of Jainism coming. The standpoint of becoming (modification) reveals that everything originates, stays and perishes; the standpoint of being' ("it is") reveals everything exists eternally without birth or decay.79 And, Siddhasena asserts, there cannot be being without becoming, or becoming without being; therefore, a substance (=reality) is defined as the combination of being with becoming, i.e., origin, decay and stability.80 Siddhasena connects the being' aspect with generalization and the becoming'aspect with particularization. It is pointed out that in our ordinary description of things, we necessarily combine the general with the particular. From the point of view of the highest generalization, a thing is described as "it is" which reveals the permanent being, the substance. But when, in ordinary descriptions, a thing is called a piece of wood, or a chair, or a red chair, we have an intermixture of being and 'becoming' aspects. In so far as the thing is identified as a nonfluctuating substance, it is the being standpoint. And in so far as the attributes of the thing, such as being a piece of wood, being a chair, or redness, are revealed by the description, it is the 'becoming standpoint. Qualities are nothing but modes or states of the substance. In any characterization or description of the thing there is thus an overlap of being and becoming standpoints, until we reach the ultimate particularity, pure becoming', i. e., the point-instants (ksanas) of the Buddhists. 81 Page #50 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ X THE SEVEN STANDPOINTS Tattvarthasutra 1.6 says that philosophic understanding is generated by both pramanas (means of knowledge) and nayas (discussion of standpoints). In other philosophical schools, it is asserted that reality is revealed through pramanas or means of knowledge (cf. pramanadhina vastusiddhih). Thus the Jainas requisition the service of the doctrine of standpoints, in addition to that of pramanas, for the ascertainment of reality. A thing, according to the Jainas, has innumerable characteristics, and a pramana may not reveal its detailed features. Thus the standpoints, by putting emphasis on one aspect or the other, can help us to grasp reality completely and in a proper manner. What is the distinction between a pramana and a naya? A pramana reveals the thing as a whole cf. (sakala-grahin) while a naya reveals only a portion of it (amsa-grahin). A naya is only a part of a pramana and hence it cannot be identical with the pramana. A pramana is compared to an ocean while nayas or standpoints are like ocean-water kept in different pitchers. 82 Akalanka has described the standpoints as the hidden intentions or presuppositions of inquirers, different points of view of persons searching for the truth.83 Akalanka further states that a pramana results in knowledge while a standpoint is only a view of the knower. Each viewer views a thing from a particular point. Thus, the nature of the thing that is revealed to him is necessarily conditioned or colored or limited by his particular point of view. This amounts to saying that only a partial aspect of reality is revealed to him. As long as he is not conscious that he views reality only from one among infinite number of points of view, his metaphysical thesis will remain 'one-sided' ekanta. To remedy this defect, the Jainas teach the doctrine of standpoints. Thus, Siddhasena notes in his Nyayavatara (verese 29): "Since a thing has manifold character, it is comprehended (only) by the omniscient. But a thing becomes the subject matter of a naya, when it is conceived from one particular standpoint." How many points of view are there from which one can view reality ? Since a thing has infinitefold constitution, according to the Jainas, there should be an infinite number of points of view. Siddhasena accepts this theoretical possibility :84 Page #51 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 42 The Central Philosophy of Jainism "There are just as many nayavadas (standpoints) as there are ways of putting a (philosophic) proposition. There are also as many nayas as there are views of the non-Jaina philosophers." I have already discussed briefly Siddhasena's six-fold classification of nayas on standpoints. But traditionally the Jainas accept a seven-fold classification. Tattvartha-sutra 1.34 mentions five kinds of standpoints. However, sutra 1.35 mentions two sub-varieties of the naigama (the common') and three sub-varieties of the sabda (the verbal). But generally all Digambara texts talk about seven standpoints, which are enumerated as follows: naigama (the common '), samgraha (the general), vyavahara (the practical), rjusutra (the 'straight-thread'), the sabda (the verbal), samabhirudha (the subtle), and evambhuta (the "thushappened"). Vadideva, following Akalanka and others, presents the following scheme of classification:85 Standpoint Substantial (Being) (1) The common ('non-distinguished') "The soul has consciousness." (2) The general (3) The practical "A thing exists" "A thing is either eternal or non-eternal." Modificational (Becoming) (4) The "straight-thread" "Everything is in flux" According to another scheme, the first four standpoints (1 through 4) are classified as the standpoint of 'things' while the last three (5 through 7) are classified as the standpoint of 'word' (cf. artha-naya and sabda-naya). It is claimed that the last three standpoints are concerned with only the linguistic uses. They pay attention to the distinction reflected in the grammatical inflections as well as in the specific uses of words. Using modern terminology, one may say that the first four are concerned with ontological distinctions while the last three with semantic distinctions. (5) (6) (7) The 'verbal' The subtle The "thus-happened" Kundakunda (as well as others following him) speaks of another scheme of classification of standpoints. This is the dual classification of Page #52 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Seven Standpoints 43 niscaya 'the standpoint of determination' and vyavahara "the standpoint of worldly behaviour.'86 This dual classification has no direct connection with the usual seven standpoints of the Jainas, but it corresponds to the well-known distinction of two levels of truth in Madhyamika Buddhism, 87 the standpoint of ultimate reality (paramartha) and the standpoint of conventional reality (vyavahara or samvrti). Almost the same distinction can be found in the Advaita Vedanta school of Samkara, viz., the distinction of the ultimate existence (paramarthika-satta) and the phenomenal existence (pratibhasika-satta). And perhaps the same distinction can be traced in the Upanisadic distinction of the 'subtle' (suksma) reality and the 'gross' (sthula) reality. Yogacara Buddhist, in a similar vein, distinguishes between the teachings of the Buddha which have direct meaning (nitartha) and the teachings of the Buddha which have hidden or implicit meaning (neyartha). Thus, according to the Yogacara, in such Sutras as the Sandhinirmocana and the Prajnaparamita the Buddha instructs the ultimate reality directly while in other places he gives instruction about the ultimate reality only indirectly. As far as the Jainas are concerned, the standpoint of 'determination' (niscaya) describes the soul as independent, self-existent and uncontaminated by matter. This is the truth in the ultimate sense, a goal to be arrived at the final stage. But the standpoint of 'worldly behaviour' (vyavahara) describes the soul as one that is involved in karma as well as in the birth and re-birth cycle (samsara). The traditional seven standpoints may be understood in the following way: Naigama ( the common, the non-distinguished ): It is a method of referring to an entity where its generic and specific characteristics are not distinguished from each other. It is an imprecise statement, but not an incorrect one, for it is conventionally accepted. ( Naigama means a village or market place hance a "Market place" statement ?) e. g., "Here is a brahmana-monk." Strictly speaking, a monk cannot be a brahmana for he is supposed to give up his caste-privileges. But the above statement is easily understandable as it refers to one who was a brahmana before he became a monk. Vadideva, however, explains this standpoint in a different manner. He cites such examples as "In soul there is an ever-lasting conciousness." Here, although "everlasting" has been used as a qualifier of "consciousness" there is, in principle, no substantive-adjective relation between the two. The two attributes, everlastingness and consciousness, are conceived as the adjective and the substantive in a 'non-distinguished' manner in the above construction. Page #53 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 44 The Central Philosophy of Jainism The meaning of "naigama" thus changed in the course of its development. When the practical' standpoint came to mean imprecise but popular statements, "naigama" was interpreted as the universal-cumparticular ) combined way of referring to things. It came to mean a deliberate ambiguity. Probably this is why Siddhasena omitted this standpoint from his classification. Sarngraha ( the general ): It emphasizes the generic character of a thing. E. g., " The universe is one, for it has universal existence." The speaker only considers the highest generic feature of things: existence ( or sattva ). He is indifferent, for the time being, to other specific claims. But if it is stated in absolute terms, as the thesis of Vedanta, for example, it turns into a pseudo-standpoint (cf. sangrahabhasa ). Vadideva notes other sub-varieties of sargraha depending upon the more general and the less general. 88 The word "samgraha" means also collection'. Thus, this standpoint implies a method by which we collect and bring together disparate entities under one class or notion. Thus, it indirectly refers to the doctrine of universals (samanya ) of the Vaisesikas, according to which one posits, on the basis of cognitive pattern, such class-properties as 'substance-ness or cow-ness. Vyavahara (the practical): This standpoint originally meant the practical, conventional mode of speech. Probably at that stage this standpoint was indistinguishable from the vyavahara standpoint mentioned above in connection with the niscaya standpoint. Later on, the practical' standpoint was interpreted as a complementary method of the 'general' (samgraha) standpoint. We collect disparate items through the 'practical' method under a comman denominator, a class, and through the 'practical method we classify the collected items under sub-classes or sub-types keeping their specific characters in mind. E.g., "Whatever exists is either a substance or a mode," or "A substance is either conscious or unconscious." Such classificatory exercise is helpful for understanding and exploring philosophic truths. Thus the 'general' standpoint implies collection and subsumption while the practical' standpoint implies classification and differentiation. But if classification is intended to separate the entities ultimately (ekantatah) from each other, then this becomes a pseudo-standpoint (nayabhasa). Vadideva mentions that the Carvaka view is an example of this pseudostandpoint. 89 Page #54 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Seven Standpoints Rju-sutra (the 'straight-thread'): This standpoint asks us to consider reality as the direct grasp of the here-and-now. Siddhasena has called it the prototype (mula) of the "modification exists" standpoint. It emphasizes the here-and-now aspect of a thing. It reduces reality to the point-instants, to ever-fluctuating moment. Vadideva points out that "rju' means also 'the clearly manifest' : e.g. "(Here and) now there is pleasure-moment." Thus, the evanescent modes (paryaya) and states (bhava) are held as matters of principal interest under this standpoint. The Sautrantika Buddhists take this standpoint as their starting point and are finally led to its logical extreme, i.e. the doctrine of universal flux, according to which, there is no enduring substance, no soul, but only flows or currents of events. This is an "events only " ontology. Each event is claimed as unique and momentary. Thus, according to the Jainas, the Buddhists became 'one-sided' ( ekanta-vadin ), and the standpoint they used degenerated into a pseudo-standpoint. Sabda (the verbal): In the 'verbal' standpoint, we proceed to consider (with the help of words) the distinction based upon the tensedpredication or upon the variation of grammatical inflections. Consider the following two sentences : (1) The king sees the boy ( raja pasyati manavakam ). (2) The boy sees the king ( manavakah pasyati rajanam ). The Sanskrit grammarians (Paniniyas) argue that although the same nominal stem 'ra jan' ('king') is used in both cases, it is proper to distinguish between the different functions of the word in both sentences indicated by their different grammatical inflections. The inflections are only phonetic representation of the different syntactic relations (in the English equivalents of these two sentences the said syntactic relations are revealed in their different syntactic structures). The grammarians point out that following the 'verbal' standpoint one should realise that different syntactic relations will have different semantic interpretation. This standpoint also indicates that the use of three different tenses in the predicate portion with regard to the same subject should be taken to imply distinction in the subject-term. A mountain, for example, persists through the three time-stages, past, present and future, and hence we say, "It was, it is, and it will be". Through the 'verbal method, we may consider the subjects of these three tensed-predications as distinct from one another. Thus, we can say, "The past mountain is, the present mountain is, and the future mountain is (i. e., exists)." This may simplify the notion of tensed-predication or tensed-existence. Page #55 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 46 The Central Philosophy of Jainism Samabhirudha (the 'subtle') : This standpoint asks us to make a subtle distinction in the meanings of words which are supposed to denote the same object. Such distinction can be based upon the etymological derivations of words concerned. Words like "rajan", "nrpa", and "bhupa" refer to the same person, the king, but each has different etymological formation and hence different meanings, i. e., different cognitive meanings. These cognitive meanings appear when we consider their etymology : "rajan" means one with the royal insignia, "nipa" means one who protects men, and "bhupa" means one who protects the earth. This standpoint probably assumes that all words are derived from some root or other, and hence must have some etymological meaning. 90 If we follow this principle strictly, we will have to admit that there can be very few, if any, true synonyms in a natural language. Even if we do not believe in the theory of etymology, this standpoint is not thereby rendered pointless. For, we can easily re-interpret this standpoint as pointing out (partly in the same way as G. Frege did 91) that there may be two different linguistic expressions (names or phrases) referring to the same entity but having different meanings or senses. Vadideva warns us that if we construe the difference in meanings as implying real difference in things, we will be indulging in a pseudo-standpoint. 92 Evambhuta (the 'thus-happened'): This standpoint carries the process of the previous 'subtle' standpoint a little further. It restricts the meaning of a particular word to its particular use. Thus each particular use of a word is supposed to have, according to this standpoint, only one unique meaning. This standpoint asks us to apply the word "pacaka" (=a cook ) to a person when and only when he is actually cooking, not when he is sleeping or walking. In other words, a cook is called a cook because he cooks, and not because of any of his other activities. But if we think, for the above reason, that a cook does not remain a cook if he is not cooking at the present moment, we will reduce the above standpoint to a pseudo-standpoint. 93 A pramana, as I have already noted, is concerned with the revealing of the object in its totality. A standpoint, as discussed above, reveals the thing only partially. A thing has manifold character, but when it is ascertained on the basis of one of its characters, it is a standpoint. A pramana can be reached through aggregation of all the constituent standpoints. E.g., "The soul is eternal" is a statement of a standpoint, for it considers only one aspect. "The soul is multiformed, for it has multifarious properties like eternity and transience." This amounts to a pramana. Page #56 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ HISTORICAL BACKGROUND OF THE JAINA DIALECTIC The philosophic methodology of the Jainas makes use of the doctrine of standpoints in the above manner on the one hand and the doctrine of Sevenfold Predication ( saptabhangi) on the other. The doctrine of Sevenfold Predication is also called the doctrine of syat ( syad-vada ), for it makes use of the convenient particle SYAT in all the seven varieties of a particular predication. According to the Jainas, each proposition (of any philosophic importance ) should be subjected to this sevenfold formulation in order to remove the danger of one-sidedness' (cf. ekantata) or dogmatism in philosophy. The sevenfold predication was historically a later development in Jainism, for we do not find it clearly mentioned in the early canons. A. N. Upadhye, however, has located references to the three primary predicates ( instead of seven ) in the Bhagavati-Sutra.94 Umasvati did not make any explicit reference to the seven alternative predicates.95 But Kundakunda mentioned the full-fledged seven alternative predicates in his Pancastikaya.96 As forerunner of the sevenfold formula of the Jainas, we have two similar formulas explicitly mentioned in the earlier literatures. The first was the fivefold formula of Sanjaya found in the Pali canons. In the Samannaphala-sutta of Dighanikaya I, Sanjaya is reported to have developed a fivefold formula to answer some metaphysical and moral questions, such as "whether there is another world or not" or "whether something is right or wrong". E. g., (1) Question: "Is it this (or so ) ?" Answer: "No." (2) Q: "Is it that (or thus ) ?" A: "No." (3) Q: "Is it otherwise ( different from both above ) ?" A: "No." (4) Q: "Is it not ( at all there) ?" A: "No." (5) Q: "Is it not that it is not ( at all there ) ?" A: "No."97 The first three alternatives in the above formula, "this-that-or-otherwise," can be easily reduced to two alternatives if we use the contradictories such as "this-or-not this," or "this-or-otherwise." Thus the fourfold alternatives of the Buddhists (later of the Madhyamikas) Page #57 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 48 The Central Philosophy of Jainism can be seen as an improved and more precise formulation of the earlier, rather imprecise, fivefold formula. The Madhyamika denial of the fourfold alternative was: (1) Question: "Does the effect come out of itself:" Answer: "No." (2) Q: "Does it come out of the others ?" A: "No." (3) Q: "Does it come out of both itself and other ?" A: "No." (4) Q: "Does it come out of neither (self or other)?" A: "No."98 It should be noted that the Buddhist answers to all these alternative questions were, like the answers of Sanjaya, in the negative. Scholars like Hermann Jacobi have surmised that Mahavira established the sevenfold syat predication in opposition to the " Agnosticism" of Sanjaya.99 There seems to be some truth in this claim. For Mahavira adopted the method of answering all metaphysical/philosophical questions with a qualified yes. But, as I have already noted, there is no textual evidence (either in the Pali or in the Prakrit canons) to show that Mahavira had actually used the sevenfold syat predication. K. N. Jayatilleke has apparently been very critical of Jacobi's view in this matter. He has been eager to show that the two ( the Jaina formula and the Sanjaya formula) " seem to have a common origin."100 In his eagerness to show this "common origin" Jayatilleke has mistranslated syat as "may be." I find the argument of Jayatilleke unconvincing as a rebuttal of Jacobi's thesis, viz., Mahavira's philosophy was formulated in opposition to the philosophy of Sanjaya. It is undeniable that while the former preferred a conditional affirmation of the answers to questions about after-life etc., the latter preferred a straightforward denial. Although Sanjaya resembled the Buddhist in giving negative answers to the metaphysical questions, we should note that Sanjaya's philosophic conclusion was different from that of Nagarjuna. Out of respect for truth and out of fear of, and distaste for, falsehood ( cf. musavada-bhaya) Sanjaya adopted a non-committal attitude towards questions about afterlife etc. His position was that definite knowledge about such matters as after-life was impossible to obtain, and he had the boldness to confess it. Thus, I think the Pali commentator was a bit unfair when he called him an "eel-wriggler." Nagarjuna's position was slightly different from that of total noncommitment. From the denial of the fourfold alternative, Nagarjuna was led to a definite philosophic conclusion that these questions about after-life, Page #58 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Historical Background of the Jaina Dialectic 49 cause etc. were only pseudo-questions or that the concepts (regarding which such questions were asked ) were only pseudo-concepts. They are, therefore, "empty" of their own-nature', of the essence. In this way, Nagarjuna was led to his "emptiness" doctrine, while Sanjaya was at best a Samsaya-vadin, an agnostic. In fact, it can be asserted with some confidence that the " threetermed" doctrine (cf. trairasika) of the Ajivakas foreshadowed the seven-fold predication of the Jainas. 101 This Ajivaka sect, established by Gosala, declared that everything is of triple character, viz., existent, non-existent and both; living, non-living and both living and non-living. This doctrine of triple character of every entity is more akin in spirit, and logically closer, to the later Jaina doctrine of sevenfold formula as well as the anekanta 'non-onesided' view of reality. For basically, the Jaina considers only three possibilities: positive, negative, and both positive and negative. The seven possibilities, as we shall see presently, were developed out of the three basic possibilities along with a more subtle distinction introduced in the third possibility, viz., both positive and negative. In the fourfold alternative of the Madhyamika, the fourth possibility is that of a "neither ... nor...." The question was formulated as "Is it neither A nor not-A?" And the answer was given in the negative by Nagarjuna (as well as by Sanjaya ). In the Jaina scheme, however, this question is not even formulated. Thus, we may say that "neither A nor not-A" is not even accepted as a possibility in Jainism. The reason may be that the "neither A nor not-A" alternative is one of strong denial or negativity (cf. prasajya-pratisedha ). 102 But since Mahavira, unlike the Buddha, did not follow the line of direct denial but rather the line of conditional acceptance, the followers of Mahavira were certainly true to the spirit of their master in leaving the neither A nor not-A" alternative out of their consideration. Besides, this point underlines another logical distinction between the Jaina position on the one hand and the Buddhist or the Sanjaya position on the other. The former apparently violated the principle of non-contradiction (since it accepted contradictory possibilities ) while the latter, in conceding a "neither A nor not-A" possibility, seemed to run against the principle of excluded middle. It may not be inappropriate in this connection to clarify my position on the interpretation of the Buddhist tetralemma (catuskoti). I have said earlier that the Madhyamika negation involved in the tetralemma should be interpreted as a prasajya pratisedha (a strong negation of the Page #59 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 50 The Central Philosophy of Jainism predication which would not commit one to the assertion of the opposite). In fact, my interpretation is based upon the explanation given by the commentators of Nagarjuna. For example, Candrakirti comments upon the first verse of the Madhyamikakarika as follows: "Q: 'Now, if it is asserted that the effect is not produced from itself, it will follow that the effect is produced from other things; and this will be undesirable.' A: 'No, this will not follow. For the 'strong form of negation' (prasajya prati sedha ) is intended here. And even the production of the effect from other things will be refuted.' 103 J. F. Staal has agreed with me regarding the use of the 'strong form of negation' in the Madhyamika tetralemma. But he has commented further that my "logical attempts to save the catuskoti from inconsistency" (along with that of some others ) "are further marred by " my "failure to distinguish clearly between the principle of non-contradiction on the one hand and, the two principles of excluded middle and of double negation on the other." 104 To clarify my position I can only repeat what I have stated already in the preceding paragraph. The Madhyamikas, insofar as they concede that the fourth possibility in the tetralemma is a refutable thesis or position, seem to run against the principle of excluded middle. But, of course, the Madhyamikas would reject any plausible philosophic position (including the "neither A nor not-A" type ). And they can avoid inconsistency as long as they can maintain their own non-committal attitude toward acceptance of any philosophic thesis. In my previous discussion of the Buddhist tetralemma and negation, I did not explicitly mention the expression " the principle of excluded middle", but I did say that the Madhyamikas would seem to violate "our generally accepted logical principle which may be stated as "Everything is either P or not P'." 105 Now the formulation 'Everything is either P or not P' is virtually equivalent to what is called the 'traditional formulation of the principle of excluded middle : 'Everything is either A or not-A'. 106 Evdently, this traditional formulation lacks the precision now achievable by means of the axiomatization and formalization of theories. But the above will at least show that what I had in mind when I mentioned "our generally accepted logical principle" was the principle of excluded middle. And thus, it may be pointed out that I, at least, did not confuse between the principle of non-contradiction and the principle of excluded middle in my discussion of the Buddhist negation. Page #60 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Historical Background of the Jaina Dialectic 51 Further, it may be noted that the Indian logicians, whose view I usually try to explain and interpret, did clearly distinguish between the principle of non-contradiction and the principle of excluded middle. Thus Udayana, for example, emphasized in his Nyayakusumanjali: chap III, verse 8: "If the two positions mutually oppose ( contradict ) each other, there cannot be any third alternative. And the two contradictory (opposing) positions cannot be unified or accepted together, for the very state ment of them together will destroy each other." Here, obviously, the first part is concered with a 'traditional formulation of the principle of excluded middle, and the second part with the principle of non-contradiction. Page #61 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ XII THE MEANING OF SYAT The uniqueness of the Jaina formula lies in its use of the "syat" particle in the predication. That is why the sevenfold predication of the Jainas is sometimes called Syad-vada. In ordinary Sanskrit, "syat" is used sometimes to mean "perhaps' or 'may be'. In fact it is one of the three words used to answer a direct question: "Is A B ?" viz., "Yes" or "No" or "Syat (may be )". But the Jainas used this particle in a very special sense. It is a particle that indicates the anekanta nature of a preposition. 107 Etymologically, "syat" is derived from the root as+potential/optative third form, singular. Bhattoji Diksita explained the optative suffix, lin in one context, as expressing probability (sambhavana). Thus, under Panini-sutra 1.4.96, the example "sarpiso' pi syat" is explained as: "There is even a chance of (a drop of) butter." But the Jaina syat is even different from this use of syat in the sense of probability. The Anekanta doctrine, to be sure, is neither a doctrine of doubt (or even uncertainty) nor a doctrine of probability. Thus, "syat" means, in the Jaina use, a conditional YES. It is like saying, "in a certain sense, yes." It amounts to a conditional approval. The particle syat, in fact, acts as an operator on the sentence in which it is used. It turns a categorical ("A is B" into a conditional: "If p then A is B." There is also a concessive use of "syat" frequently found in philosophical Sanskrit, viz., "syad etat." This expression means: " let it be so, (but)...." The use of syat in this context implies that the author (or the speaker) only provisionally concedes the position of the opponent, for he tries at the moment to raise a different and perhaps, a more serious ) objection to reject the opponent finally. But the Jaina use of the particle syat in the sevenfold formula is a much more refined sort of concession to the opponent. It concedes the opponent's thesis in order to blunt the sharpness of his attack and disagreement, and at the same time it is calculated to persuade the opponent to see another point of view or carefully consider the other side of the case. Thus, the Jaina use of "syat" has both; it has a disarming effect and contains (implicitly) a persuasive force. Samantabhadra has commented upon the meaning of "syat" as follows : 108 Page #62 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Meaning of Syat 53 "When the particle syat is used by you (Mahavira ) as well as by a fruta-kevalin (e. g., a saint ) in a sentence, it indicates, in connection with other meanings, non-onesidedness; it qualifies (since it is a particle=nipata) the meaning (of the sentence concerned )". In the next verse (V. 104), Samantabhadra notes that syat is ordinarily equal to such expressions as "kadacit" and "kathancit". But even these terms, "kadacit" or "Kathancit" do not have in this context such vague meaning as 'somehow' or 'sometimes'. They mean: 'in some respect' or 'from a certain point of view' or 'under a certain conditin'. Thus the particle "syar" in a sentence qualifies the acceptance or rejection of the proposition or predication expressed by the sentence.109 Page #63 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ XIII EXPLANATION OF THE SEVEN PREDICATES "From a certain point of view, you (Mahavira) accept, "It is," and from another point of view you accept, "It is not." Similarly, both "it is" and "it is not," as well as it is inexpressible." All these (four) are approved (by you) with reference to the doctrine of stand point ( naya ) only, not absolutely." ( Aptamimamsa, v. 14 ) In this way, Samantabhadra has formulated the first four of the seven alternative predicates, We can symbolize these four basic propositions +, -,+' and 'O'. The fourth predication, "it is inexpressible," is actually interpreted as the joint (combined) and simultaneous (cf. saharpana) application of both the positive and the negative. The fourth is distinct from the third proposition because in the latter there is joint but gradual ( one after another, non-simultaneous=kramarpana ) application of the positive and the negative. Since it is believed that the language lacks any expression which can adequately express this simultaneous and combined application of both the positive and the negative characters, the Jainas say that they are obliged to name this predicate "inexpressible" and we have symbolized it by 'O' accordingly. Although the predication "inexpressible" (or '0') has been reached in the above manner (as is evident from the Jaina texts ), the Jainas, however, regard it still as a unitary predicate, a unit, like the positive or the negative (i. e., "it is" or "it is not" ). Probably, it was thought that since the two components, positive and negative, are here perfectly balanced and totally neutralized, being applied simultaneously (in the same breath ), the predication had lost its compound character and melted into one unitary whole. In other words, a predicate that was compound in character in its inception (or when it was first thought out) turned into a non-compound, primary predicate because of its internal structure, so to say. I have thus used the neutral symbol, o', to indicate it. The Jainas have, in this way, three primary and non-compound predicates, positive, negative and the neutral ( +, -, O). Now it is easy to see how the Jainas reached the seven possible varieties. Let the three predication-units be represented by x, y, and z. A simple mathematical computation will generate only seven varieties, if we use these three units in three ways, one at a time, two at a time and three at a time: Page #64 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ x, y, z, xy, yz, zx, xyz +, -, 0, +, -0, +0, +0 Note that combination in this formula is comparable to the arithmetical conjunction or the truth functional 'and' such that the internal order in a combination is immaterial, there being no need to distinguish between 'xy' and 'yx'. In mathematical terminology, this is called the commutative property of conjunction. Explanation of the Seven Predicates The Jainas, however, enumerate the above combinations in a slightly different order (adding "syat" to each): 1. 3. 6. 2. "From a certain point of view, the pot does not exist." y "From a certain point of view, the pot exists and from xy another point of view, it does not exit." 4. "From a certain point of view, the pot is inexpressible.' 5. "From a certain point of view, the pot both exists and is inexpressible." 7. "From a certain point of view, or in a certain sense, the pot exists." 55 + x - 0 z +0 xz "From a certain point of view, the pot both does not -0 yz exist and is inexpressible." "From a certain point of view, the pot exists, does not +0 xyz exist, and is also inexpressible." One may note that predication no. 3 in the above list is not the third neutral predicate but a compound one combining the first and the second. In predication no. 4 above, we come across the third primary predicate, "inexpressible." While explaining the seven predicates, Vidyananda has noted as follows:110 "Someone says, let there be only four types of proposition. This is not tenable. For there are three (further) possibilities by combining the positive, the negative and both of them with the "inexpressible." Thus we have sevenfold predication: (1) affirmation, (2) denial, (3) both affirmation and denial, (4) the joint and simultaneous affirmation and denial, (5) affirmation, and the simultaneous affirmation and denial, (6) denial, and the joint and simultaneous affirmation and denial, (7) affirmation, denial, and the joint and simultaneous affirmation and denial." Page #65 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Central Philosophy of Jainism It is obvious, however, that the fourth predicate here ('the joint and simultaneous affirmation and denial' ), which is Vidyananda's explanation of the term "inexpressible") must be taken to be a unitary whole, a primary predicate. For otherwise it would be difficult to explain the sevenfold combination with Mathematical computation. And Vidyananda himself has emphasized that there are seven and only seven alternatives in the Jaina system. 56 A common objection against the Jaina sevenfold formula has been that instead of accepting only seven alternative predicates in this manner, one might go up to a hundred or a thousand (i. e., to an unlimited number). Thus a critic like Kumarila has said, "Even one hundred alternatives can be generated through generous use of the method used (by the Jainas) to generate only seven alternatives.'111 But certainly this is not a fair criticism of the Jaina method. It is based on a misunderstanding. Thus, Vidyananda goes on to point out that there may be an infinite number of properties or predicates that are ascribable to a subject. The Jaina Anekanta doctrine of reality only welcomes such attribution. For, according to the Anekanta doctrine, a thing or entity is supposed to possess infinite or innumerable aspects or characters. But the sevenfold formula (i. e., the seven alternative formulations of predicates using the three principal modes, positive, negative and the neutral) will be applicable to each attribution of a property, i. e., to each individual predication. In other words, as long as we accept only three basic qualities of one individual predicate (positive, negative and the neutralized), we will get only seven possible combinations.112. Page #66 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ XIV TRADITIONAL OBJECTIONS Critics of the Jaina sevenfold formula have mentioned many faults or anomalies that are supposed to arise if the doctrine is accepted as a philosophic method. The Jaina writers beginning from Akalanka and Vidyananda have analyzed these objections and tried to answer them in detail. Let us make a brief survey of these objections and answers. Samkara in his Brahmasutra-bhasyal13 mentions, among other things, two specific problems involved in the Jaina position: virodha 'contradiction, and samsaya 'doubt' or 'dubiety.' Santaraksita adds another, samkara 'intermixture. 114 Akalanka notes seven demerits of the anekanta doctrine in his Pramanasangraha: dubiety, contradiction, lack of conformity of bases (vaiyadhikaranya), joint fault" (ubhaya-dosa), infinite regress, intermixture, and absence (abhava). Vidyananda gives a list of eight faults; he omits "joint fault" from the list of Akalanka, but adds two more: 'cross-breeding' (vyatikara) and the lack of comprehension (apratipatti).115 Prabhacandra mentions also a list of eight, but he replaces 'lack of comprehension' by the above-mentioned "joint fault"116 Vadideva drops "absence" (abhava) from the list of Prabhacandra and makes it a list of seven faults.117 Most of these faults or defects are only minor variations of the three major problems faced by the Jaina doctrine of the sevenfold predication: intermixture, dubiety and contradiction. " Vyomasiva has mentioned another unique problem of the anekanta doctrine. 118 He says that a free (liberated=mukta) person will not really be liberated under anekanta doctrine. For he will be considered, from one point of view, both liberated and not liberated, and, from another point of view, simply not-liberated. Besides, if the statement "the thing has anekanta nature" involves an unconditional predication, then it falsifies the anekanta doctrine, for, according to the anekanta principal no philosophic predication should be unconditional or unqualified. But if the above predication is conditionalized with the syat operator following the Jaina anekanta principal (viz., "in a certain sense, the thing has anekanta nature "and" in a certain sence, it does not have anekanta nature," and so on), then we will be led into a paradoxical situation or circularity. The above problem of anekanta is reminiscent of a similar problem or paradox posed against the "Emptiness" doctrine of the Madhyamika. Page #67 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 58 The Central Philosophy of Jainism Nagarjuna discussed this problem at the beginning of his Vigraha-vyavartani. If the statement "everything is empty" is itself empty, then it falsifies the "Emptiness" doctrine, and if that statement is not empty, then there is at least one thing that is not empty which also falsifies the doctrine. Nagarjuna explained this paradox and answered the objection against his doctrine quite satisfactorily from the Madhyamika point of view.119 As far as I can see, it is not impossible to construct a similar defence of the Jaina doctrine of anekanta philosophy or syad-vada to answer the criticism of Vyomasiva. Page #68 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ XV IN DEFENCE OF THE JAINA POSITION Of all the charges against the anekanta philosophy or the sevenfold syat predication, the charge of contradiction or self-contradiction is certainly the most serious one. For a philosopher, to contradict himself is like writing or stating something and then cancelling it altogether. Do the Jainas really suffer from this offence ? Could the Jaina view be defended against the charge of self-contradiction or inconsistency ? Let us focus our attention on the sevenfold predication. It is, however, clear from the interpretation of syat particle given above that the first predication does not really contradict the second. The Jainas avoid contradiction by adding the syat particle. The syat operator turns the categorical proposition into a conditional, and thus the logical forms of the first two are: (1) If p then a is F. (2) If q then a is non-F. Or, more fully: (3) For all x, if x is considered from standpoint 1, x is eternal: [(x) (FxGx)] (4) For all x, if x is considered from standpoint 2, x is not eternal: [(x) (Hx o -Gx )] It is clear that neither (1) and (2), nor (3) and (4) are, in any sense, contradictories. Thus, I think that when the Jainas say that from the standpoint of persisting substance, the person is eternal, but from the standpoint of modal changes (cf. paryaya ), the person is not eternal, they do not make any self-contradictory assertion. How about the third and the fourth predications ? The third, to be sure, is the joint (but non-simultaneous ) assertion of the first and the second. But if the first and the second are not contradictories, then the third (which is only the truth-functional conjunction of the first and the second ) will not be self-contradictory. In other words, the third predication can be easily seen to be free from contradiction in this way. The fourth predication, however, presents a problem. For it seems to apply two incompatible predicates, eternal and non-cternal, to the subject Page #69 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 60 The Central Philosophy of Jainism in the same breath or simultaneously. Although the statement is conditionalized with the syat operator, it only means that under certain condition a thing will have two contradiciory characters. Thus, the speaker here may be taken to have contradicted himself and said nothing. (This may partially justify the use of "inexpressible" to denote this predication, for two contradictory predicates are supposed to cancel or earse each other) In defence of the Jaina doctrine, we can make two points here. First, by simple application of contradictory predicates to a thing in the same breath (or simultaneously ) the speaker does not land himself into a self-contradiction. For there is always the chance of there being some hidden meaning which the speaker can explain in order to resolve the apparent self-contradiction. For example, we can say of a man, "He is both over six feet tall and under six feet tall," and then explain that he has a disease which makes him stoop, but that if he were cured and were able to stand upright, he would top the six-foot mark. 120 Mahavira himself followed a similar line of explanation in order to elaborate upon the apparently contradictory assertions like the person is both eternal and non-eternal.'121 In this way, I think the Jainas may somehow answer the charge of self-contradiction against the fourth predication. This leads to our second point. The basic assumption in Jainism seems to be the anekanta (non-onesided ) nature of reality. A thing is supposed to have infinite-fold character or innumerable aspects or properties. If this premise is conceded then, of course, it becomes possible to apply all kinds of predicates (including contradictories ) to the thing depending upon one's point of view or standpoint. One obvious difficulty in the above concession is this: If it becomes possible to apply incompatible predicates to the same thing, then it defeats the purpose of predication. For, one important function of describing a thing or a person with predicates is to distinguish it from other things, to exclude it from other groups (cf. the apoha theory of the Buddhist). 122 The Jainas, however, might reply that the fourth predication "the thing is, in a sense, inexpressible" is not intended to distinguish the thing from other things, but to include it in everything else. For, remember, the Jainas would be prepared to apply this predicate "Inexpressible" (if we call it a predicate) to everything without exception. This statement is actually in the same level with statements of other schools like "everything is empty" or "everything is existent (sat)." The idea of the Jainas is probably that in such predication the purpose of description might fail, but the purpose of stating a truth will not fail. Page #70 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ In Defence of the Jaina Position 61 To sum up: The anekanta-vada is thus a philosophy of synthesis and reconciliation since it tries to establish a rapproachment between seemingly disagreeing philosophical schools. Jaina philosophers contend that no philosophic proposition can be true if it is only unconditionally asserted. They say that the lesson to be drawn from age-old disputes and controversies regarding philosophic or metaphysical propositions is the following. Each school asserts its thesis and claims it to be true. Thus a philosopher does not really understand the point that is being made by the opposite side. Rival schools only encourage dogmatism and intoleration in philosophy. This, according to the Jainas, is the evil of ekanta 'one sided' philosophies. Even the conflicting propositions of rival schools may be in order, provided they are asserted with proper qualifications or conditionalization. This is what exactly the Anekanta doctrine teaches. Add a syat particle to your philosophic proposition and you have captured the truth, Non-violence, i. e. abstention from killing or taking the life of others, was the dominent trend in the whole sramana movement in India, particularly in Buddhism and Jainism. I think the Jainas carried the principle of non-violence to the intellectual level, and thus propounded their anekanta doctrine. Thus the hallmark of the anekanta doctrine. was toleration. The principal embodied in the respect for the life of others was transformed by the Jaina philosophers at the intellectual level into respect for the views of others. This is, I think, a unique attempt to harmonize the persistent discord in the field of philosophy. Page #71 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ FOOTNOTES 1D. Malvania, ed,, Sanmati Tarka (Bombay, 1939) Introduction, p. 133. 2A. Chakrabartinayar, Pancastikaya-sara, Sacred Books of the Jainas (1920), No. 3, Introduction, p. 193. 3santisuri, Nyayavatara-varttika-vrtti (Bombay: Bhara tiya Vidya Bhavan, 1941 ), Hindi Introduction, pp. 11-35. 4 Haribhadra, Anekantajayapataka, H. B. Kapadia, ed., Introduction. See also Bhagchandra Jain, p. 194. 5 Rg-Veda, X. 129. 6 Isa, verse 5. 7Svetasvatara, chap. 3, verse 9. 8See my "Mysticism and Reality: Ineffability," Journal of Indian Philo sophy 3, nos. 1 and 2 (1975) 9For such a list of conflicting philosophic views, see Brahmajalasutra in Majjhima-nikaya, and Sutrakrtanga, 10 See Introduction to Haribhadra's Anekantajaya-pataka. If"Panatipata akusalam, panatipata-veramani kuoalam," Majjhimanikaya Sammaditthi sutta, 9. 12 Digha-nikaya, vol. 3, Sangiti suttanta 33. 13 Majjhima-nikaya, I:368 14 Acaranga-sutra, Sacred Book of the East, XXII:36. 15See D. Malvania, "Jain Theory and Practice of Non-violence," Sambodhi, vol. 2, no. 1: p. 3. 16 See H. Kapadia, op. cit., p. cxiv, 17 Dighanikaya, 1:191. 18 See Jayatilleke, p. 280. 19 Majjhimanikaya, Sutta 99. 20 Sutrakrtanga, 1.14.22: "Bhikkhu vibhajjavayam ca viyagarejja." 21 See Malvania, Hindi Introduction to Nyayavatara-varttika-vrtti, pp. 11-13. 22 Arguttara-nikaya, 11:46 (Panhavyakaranasutta). 23 Abhidharmakosa-bhasya, chap. V, p. 805. 24 See Aristotle, De interpretatione, 17b (McKeon), p. 44. 25See Milinda-panha, pp. 144-5, and Abhidharmakosa-bhasya, chap. V, verse 22, pp. 797-801. 26 Jayatilleke, pp. 282 and 286. 27See Abhidharmakosa-bhasya pp. 798-9. 28 Jayatilleke, pp. 475-6. 29See T. R. V. Murti, p. 36. 30See Sphutartha on Abhidharmakosa-bhasya, p. 798. Page #72 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Footnotes 63 63 31See Vasubandhu, Abhidharmakosa-bhasya, p. 799. 32See Malvania, op. cit., pp, 14-24 33See Bhagavati-sutra, Pupphabhikkhu, ed.. pp. 609-610, 34 Ibid., p. 692. 35See Aptamimamsa, verse 3. 36 See Introduction to Anekantajayapataka of Haribhadra. 37See The Jaina Philosophy of No-Absolutism ( Calcutta, 1944). 38See Padmarajiah, pp. 273-5. 39See Ibid., p. 273. 40 Syadvada-man jari, A. B. Dhruva, ed. (Bombay, 1933), p. 13. See also Hemacandra's Sabdanusasana ( 1954), 1.1.2. 41F. W. Thomas, The Flowerspray of the Quodammodo Doctrine (Berlin: Akademia-Verlage, 1960). 42See Haribhadra's Anekantajayapataka, pp. 13 and 26. 43 Bhagavad-gita, chap. 2, verse 16. 44 Madhyamikakarika chap. 15, verse 8. 45 Samkhya-tattvakaumudi, p. 249. 46 Sankhya-tattvakaumudi, p. 249. 47 See Vaisegikasutras of Kanada, Candrananda's Vrtti on Sutra 9.2. 48See Brahmasutras, 2.2.4-25. 49 Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology (New York: The Free Press, paperback, 1969), p. 240. 50 Ibid, p. 241. 51 Madhyamika-karika, chap. 15, verses 1 and 2 52Ibid., verse 9. 53 Sanmati-tarka, chap. 1 verse 28. 54Ibid., chap. 1, verse 3. 55Ibid., chap. 3, verse 46. 56 Madhyamiku-karika, chap. 24, verse 11. 57 Sanmati-tarka, chap. 3, verse 48. 58Ibid., chap. 3, verse 49. 59Ibid., chap. 3, verses 50 and 51. 60 Ibid., chap. 3, verses 4 and 5. 61 For more on this point, see my "A note on the Jaina Conception of Substance" (Sambodhi Vol. 5 Nos. 2-3). 62 Sat dravya-laksanam, Tattvarthasutra 5.29. 63See Umasvati, under sutra 5.29. 64 Ibid., under sutra 5.40. 65See Pujyapada, under sutra 5.38. 66Kundakunda, Pravacanasara, chap. II, verses 3-6. 67 See Vaibesika-sutra 1.1.14 ( Gaekward's edition). 68 Aristotle, Categories ( 4a 10-14), p. 13. Page #73 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 64 The Central Philosophy of Jainism 69 Ibid., (2a 13), p. 9. 70 Aristotle, Metaphysics (1028a 29-30 ), p. 783. 71 Kundakunda, Pravacanasara, chap. II, verse 7. 72 Sanmati-tarka, chap. I, verse 12. 73 Pravacanasara, chap. II, verse 8. 74 Amrtacandra Suri, comm. on Pravacanasara, chap. II, verse 8, p. 125 75 Aptamimamsa, chap. III, verse 57 76 Mimamsa-sloka-vartika, p. 613. 77 Tattvarthasutra, 5.14. 78 Sanmati-tarka, chap. III, verses 8 and 9. 79Ibid., chap. I, verse 7. 80Ibid., chap. I, verse 9. 81Ibid., verse 8. 82 Akalanka, Tattvartharajavarttika, p. 118 under sutra 1.6. 83 Siddhiviniscaya, chap. X, verse 1. 84 Sanmati-tarka, chap. 3, verse 47. 85 Pramananayatattvalokalamkara, chap. VII, sutras 5-42. 86B. Bhatt has traced two distinct patterns of application of this pair: The Mystic Pattern and the Non-mystic Pattern. See his article, pp. 280-291. 87 Nagarjuna, Madhyamika-karika, chap. 24, verse 8. 88 Vadideva, op. cit.. chap. VII, sutras 7-10. 89Ibid., chap. VII, sutra 26 90 Yaska in his Nirukta, I.12., speaks of both views (1) All nouns are derived from some verbal root or other, and (2) some nouns do not have verbal origins. 91See G. Frege's pioneering article (Feigl and sellars), p. 85-102. 92 Vadideva, chap. VII, sutras 38-39. 93Ibid., chap. VII, sutra 43. 94A. N. Upadhye, Introduction to Pravacanasara ( Bombay: 1955), p. 83 95 Some scholars believe that Umasvati implicity referred to the saptabhangi in sutra 5.32. 96 See Pancastikaya, ed. A. Chakravartinayar. 97See Dighanikaya I, Samannaphalasutta. 98 See Nagarjuna, chap. 1, verse 1. 99 See Jaina Sutras, Tr. H. Jacobi, Introduction, p. xxvii. 100K. N. Jaytilleke, p. 139. 101A. L. Basham made this suggestion. See. Basham, p. 274-5. 102See B. K. Matilal, Epistemology, Logic, and Grammar in Indian Philosophical Analysis, 162-5. 103 Candrakirti's comm. on Nagarjuna, p. 5. 104J. F. Staal, Exploring Mysticism, p. 38. Page #74 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Footnotes 105See B. K. Matilal, Epistemology, pp. 161-162. 106See S. Korner's essay on "Law of Thought" in P. Edwards, The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Even Staal formulated the principle of excluded middle as "either A or not-A." See page 38. 107Compare: Siddhih syad-vadat (1. 1. 2 ) in Hemacandra's Sabdanusasana 108Samantabhadra, verse 103. 109Compare Bhartrhari's comment on the significance of nipata, Vakyapadiya, chap. 2. verse 204. 110 Vidyananda, Astasahasri, p. 125. 111 Kumarila, "saptabhangi-prasadena satabhangi api jayate," Mimamsa sloka-varttika. 112See Vidyananda, p. 126. 113See Samkara under Brahmasutra, 2.2.33, pp. 559-562. 114 See santaraksita, verse 1722. 115See Vidyananda, p. 227. 116See Prabhacandra, p. 156. 117See Vadideva's Syadvadaratnakara, p. 738. 118 See Vyomavati, p. 20. 119See also B. K. Matilal, Epistemology, pp. 146-167. 120 This example is taken from P. F. Strawson, Introduction to Logical Theory, pp. 16-19. 121 Compare Bhagavati-sutra, 2.1.90. 122See B. K. Matilal, Epistemology, pp. 39-46. Page #75 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ APPENDIX A ekAMzato vyAkaraNaM vibhajya paripRcchya c| sthApyaM ca maraNotpattiviziSTAtmA'nyatAdivat / / 22 "kiM sarvasattvA mariSyanti' ityekAMzena vyAkarttavyam - mrissyntiiti| 'kiM sarve janiSyante' iti vibhajya vyAkarttavyam - saMklezA janiSyante, na niklezA iti / ki 'manuSyo viziSTo hInaH' iti paripRcchaca vyAkarttavyam - kAnadhikRtya praznayasIti / yadi brUyAd - devaaniti| hIna iti vyaakrttvym| atha brUyAd - apaayaaniti| viziSTa iti vyaakrtvym| 'kimanyaH skandhebhyaH sattvo'nanyaH' iti sthApanIyaH sattvadravyasyAbhAvAt, vndhyaaputrshyaamgaurtaadivt| Vasubandhu : Abhidharmakosa-bhasya, Pancama-Kosasthana, p. 797-8, verse 22 : (Follow the translation given on p. 9-10) B alaM hi te, vaccha, ajJANAya, alaM smmohaay| gaMbhIro hAyaM, baccha, dhammo duddaso durnubodho| . . . . tena hi vaccha, taJavettha paTipucchissAmi; "yathA te khameyya tathA naM vyAkareyyAsi / taM ki maJasi, vaccha, sace te purato aggi jaleyya, jAneyyAsi tvaM - ayaM me purato aggi jalatI" ti? "sace me, bho gotama, purato aggi jaleyya, jAneyyAha - ayaM me purato aggi jalatI" ti / sace pana taM vaccha, evaM puccheyya - "yo te ayaM purato aggi jalati ayaM aggi kiM paTicca jalatI 'ti evaM puTTho tvaM, vaccha, kinti vyAkareyyAsI ti" ? sace maM bho gotama, evaM puccheyya -yo te ayaM purato aggi jalati, ayaM aggi kiM paTicca jalatI 'ti evaM puTTho ahaM bho gotama, evaM vyAkareyyaM - yo me ayaM purato aggi jalati ayaM aggi tiNakaTThapAdAnaM paTicca jltii"ti| sace te vaccha, purato so aggi nivvAyeyya, jAneyyAsi tvaM - "ayaM me purato aggi nivvutto "ti sace pana taM vaccha evaM puccheyya - "yo te ayaM purato aggi nivvuto so aggi ito katamaM disaM gato-puratthimaM vA dakkhiNaM vA pacchimaM vA uttaraM vA'ti, evaM puTTho tvaM, vaccha, kinti vyAkareyyAsI "ti ? Page #76 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Appendix 67 na upeti bho gotama, yaM hi so bho gotama, aggi tiNakaThThapAdAnaM paTicca ajali tassa ca pariyAdAnA acassa ca anupahArA anAhAro nibbuto tveva saGkha gacchatI"ti / Majjhimanikaya, II.22 Vacchagotta sutta : (Follow the translation given on page 13.) seyyathApi poLapAda, puriso evaM vadeyya - 'ahaM yA imasmi janapade janapadakalyANI taM icchAmi taM kAmemI'ti tamenaM evaM vadeyyu - 'ambho purisa, yaM tvaM janapadakalyANi icchasi kAmesi, jAnAsi taM janapadakalyANi, khattiyI vA brAhmaNI vA vessI vA suddI vA 'ti? iti puTTho 'no' ti vadeyya / tamenaM evaM vadeyyu - ambho purisa, yaM tvaM janapadakalyANi icchasi kAmesi, jAnAsi taM janapadakalyANi evaM nAmA evaM gottA ti vA dIghA vA rassA vA majjhimA vA kALI vA sAmA vA maGguracchavI' vA ti, amukasmiM gAme vA nigame vA nagare vA'ti? iti puTTho 'no' vadeyya / tamenaM evaM vadeyyu- ambho purisa, yaM tvaM na jAnAsi na passasi taM tvaM icchasi kAmesI 'ti? iti puTTho 'AmA' ti vadeyya / __"taM kiM maJjasi, poTThapAda, nanu evaM sante tassa purisassa appATihIrakataM bhAsitaM sampajjatI" ti| addhA kho, bhante, evaM sante tassa purisassa appATihIrakataM bhAsitaM sampajjatI "ti / Dighanikaya, I.95 Janapadakalyanisutta: (Follow the translation given on pages 14-16.) D sAvatthiyaM vihrti| atha kho lokAyatiko brAhmaNo yena bhagavA . . . pe0 . . . ekamantaM nisinno kho lokAyatiko brAhmaNo bhagavaMtaM etadavoca - "kiM nu kho bho gotama, savvamatthI "ti ? " savvamattho' ti kho, brAhmaNa, jeTThametaM lokAyataM / "ki pana, bho gotama, savvaM natthI"ti ? "sab natthI' ti kho, brAhmaNa, dutiyametaM lokAyataM / "kiM nu kho bho gotama, sabvamekattaM" ti ? " savvamekattaM' ti kho brAhmaNa, tatiyametaM lokAyataM / " kiM pana bho gotama, savvaM puthuttaM "ti ? "savvaM puthuttaM ti kho brAhmaNa catutthametaM lokAyataM / ete te brAhmaNa, ubho ante anupagamma majjhena tathAgato dhamma deseti- avijjApaccayA saMkhArA, saMkhArapaccayA vijJANaM . . . pe0 evametassa kevalassa dukkhakkhandhassa samudayo hoti / avijjAya tveva asesavirAganirodhA saMkhA Page #77 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 68 The Central Philosophy of Jainism ranirodho; saMkhAranirodhA vijJANanirodho . . . pe0 evametassa kevalassa dukkhakkhaMdhassa nirodho hotii"ti| Samyuttanikaya, XII.47 Lokayatikasutta : (Follow the translation given on page 16) taM jovaM taM saroraM ti vA, bhikkhu, diThThiyA sati brahmacariyava.so na hoti; ajhaM jIvaM ajhaM sarIraM ti vA, bhikkhU diTThiyA mati brahmacariyavAso na hoti / ete te, bhikkhU ubho kante anupagamma majjhena tathAgato ghamma desati / Avijjapaccayasutta : (Follow the translation given on page 17) E yathoktaM bhagavatA - " kinnu bho gautama sa karoti, sa pratisaMvedayate ? avyAkRtametad braahmnn| anyaH karoti anyaH pratisaMvedayate? avyAkRtametad braahmnn| saH karoti, sa pratisaMvedayate' iti pRSTaH 'avyAkRtametad' iti vadasi, 'anyaH karoti, anyaH pratisaMvedayate' iti pRSTa: 'avyAkRtametad' iti vadasi; tat ko'tra khalvasya bhavato gautamasya bhASitasyArthaH ? sa karoti, sa pratisaMvedayate' iti brAhmaNa ! zAzvatAya paraiti, anyaH karoti, anyaH pratisaMvedayate' iti ucchedAya paraiti; etAvantAvanupagamya tathAgato madhyamayA pratipadA dharma dezayati / " ( 1 ) iti / Yasomitra, Sphutartha, pancama-kosasthana, p. 798 : (Translation on page 17) F sAsae loe jamAlI ! asAsae loe jamAlI? sAsae jIve jamAlI ! asAsae jIve jamAlI? tae NaM se jamAlI aNagAre bhagavayA goyameNaM evaM vutte samANe saMkie kaMkhie jAva kalusasamAvaNNe jAe yAvi hotthA, No saMcAei bhagavao goyamassa kiMciMvi pabhokkhamAikkhittae tusiNIe sNcitttthi| jamAlIti samaNe bhagavaM mahAvIre jamAli aNagAraM evaM vayAsI - atthi NaM jamAlI ! mamaM bahave aMtevAsI samaNA niggaMthA chaumatthA je NaM pabhU evaM vAgaraNaM vAgarittae jahA NaM ahaM, no ceva NaM eyappagAraM bhAsaM bhAsittae jahA NaM tumaM, sAsae loe jamAlI ! janna kayAi NAsi, Na kayAi Na bhavai, Na kayAi Na bhavissai, bhuvi ca bhavai ya bhavissai ya dhuve Niie sAsae akkhae avvae avaTThie nicce| asAsae loe jamAlI! jao osappiNI bhavittA usappiNI bhvi| ussappiNI bhavittA osAppiNI bhavai, sAsae jIve jamAlI! jaM na kayAi NAsi jAva Nicce, asAsae jIve jamAlI ! jannaM neraie bhavittA tirikkhajoNie bhavittA maNusse bhavai maNusse bhavittA deve bhvi| Bhagavatisutra, (Pupphabhikkhu, ed.), 9.386, p. 609-610 : (Translation on p. 19) haMtA atthi, je vi ya te khaMdayA! ayameyArUve abbhatthie ciMtie patthie manogae saMkappe samappajjitthA-ki saaMte loe aNaMte loe| Page #78 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Appendix Bhagavatisutra, 2.1.90, p. 420 : (Translation on p. 20-21) H aparicattasahAveNuppAdavvayadhuvattasaMbaddhaM / guNavaM ca sapajjAyaM jattaM davvatti vuccaMti / / 3 / / sabbhAvo hi sahAvo guNehi sagapajjaehiM cittehiM / davvassa savvakAlaM uppAdavvayadhuvattehiM // 4 // iha vivihalakkhaNANaM lakkhaNamegaM saditti savvagayaM / uvadisadA khalu dhammaM jiNavaravasaheNa paNNattaM / / 5 / / davvaM sahAvasiddhaM saditi jiNA taccado smkkhaado| siddhaM tadha Agamado Necchadi jo so hi prsmo||6|| Kundakunda, Pravacanasara, Ch. ii, verses 3-6 (Translation on p. 36) yadi punarnedamevamiSyeta tadAnyaH sargo'nyaH saMhAraH anyA sthitirityaayaati| tathA sati hi kevalaM sagaM mRgayamANasya kumbhasyotpAdanakAraNAbhAvAdabhavanireva bhvet| asadutpAda eva vaa| tatra kumbhasyAbhavanau sarveSAmeva bhAvAnAmabhavanireva bhvet| asadutpAdo vA vyomaprasavAdInAmapyutpAdaH syAt / tathA kevalaM saMharamANasya mRtpiNDasya saMhArakAraNAbhAvAdasaMharaNireva bhavet / saduccheda eva vaa| Amrtacandra Suri, Comm. on Pravacanasara, (A. N. Upadhye's edition) : Ch. ii, under verse 8, p. 125 (Translation on p. 38) Page #79 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BIBLIOGRAPHICAL REFERENCES Acaranga sutra. Edited by H. Jacobi. Part 1. London; Sacred Book of the East, 1882. Akalanka. Tattvarthara javarttika. Edited by Gajadharlal Jain. Kasi (Benares). Sanatana Jaina Granthamala, 1915. Siddhiviniscaya. Edited by Mahendrakumar Jain. Kasi (Banares): Bharatiya Jnanapitha, 1959. Amstacandra Suri. Comm. on Pravacanasara. See Kundakunda. Anguttara-nikaya. Edited by R. Morris and E. Hardy. 5 vols. London: Pali Text Society, 1885-1900. Aristotle. The Basic Works of Aristotle. Edited by R. McKeon. New York: Random House, 1941. Basham, A. L. History and Doctrines of the Ajivikas. London: Luzac, 1951. Bhagavad-gita. Edited by Swami Sivananda. 7th edition. Sivanandanagar: Divine Life Society, 1969. Bhagavati-sutra. Edited by Pupphabhikkhu. Bhartphari. Vakyapadiya. Edited by K. V. Abhyankar and V. P. Limaye. Poona: University of Poona, 1965. Bhatt, B. "Vyavahara-naya and niscaya-naya in Kundakunda's Works." Zeitschrift der Deutschen Morgenlandischen Gesellschaft. Weisbaden: F.S. Verlag, 1974. Brahmasutras of Badarayana. Comm. of Samkara. Edited by A. K. Shastri. Bombay: Nirnay Sagar, 1938. Candrkirti. Comm. on Madhyamika-sastra. See Nagarjuna. Chakravartinayar, A. Introduction to Pancastikaya. See Kundakunda. Dighanikaya. Edited by T. W. Rhys Davids and J. E. Carpenter. 3 vols. London: Pali Text Society, 1890-1911. Frege, G. "On Sense and Nominatum." 1892. Included in Feigl and Sellars. Readings in Philosophical Analysis. New York: Appleton, 1949. Haribhadra. Anekantajayapataka. Edited by H. R. Kapadia. Baroda: Ori ental Institute, 1940 (vol. 1), 1947 (vol. 2). Hemacandra. Sabdanusasana. Edited by D. C. Sircar. Motilal Banarasidas. New Delhi: 1970. isa Upanisad. Eighteen Principal Upanisads. Vol. I. Edited by V. P. Limaye and R. D. Vadekar. Poona: Vaidika Samsodhana Mandala 1958. Jacobi, H. Introdution to the Jaina Sutras. Part I. Oxford: Sacred Book of the East, 1884. Jain, Bhagcandra. Jainism in Buddhist Literature. 1st ed. Nagpur: Alok Prakashan, 1972. Page #80 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Bibliographical References Jayatilleke, K. N. Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge. London: Allen and Unwin, 1963. Kapadia, H. R. Introduction. See Haribhadra. Korner, S. "Laws of Thought." The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by P. Edwards. New York: Macmillan and Free Press, 1967. Kumarila. Mimamsaslokavarttika. Edited by R. S. Tailanga Manavalli. Benares: Chowkhamba, 1898. Kundakunda. Pancastikaya. Edited by A. Chakravartinayar. Arah: Sacred Book of the East, 1920. Pravacanasara. Edited by A. N. Upadhya. Agas: Rajachandra Jaina Sastramala, 1964. Majjhima-nikaya. Edited by V. Trenkner and R. Chalmers. 3 vols. London: Pali Text Society, 1948-51. Mallisena. Syadvada-man jari. Edited by A. B. Dhruva. Bombay: Bombay University, 1933. Malvania, D. Introduction to Sanmati. See Siddhasena. Introducton (Hindi) to Nyayavatara. See Siddhasena. "Jaina Theory and Practice of Non-violence." Sambodhi. Vol. 2, no. 1. Matilal B. K. "Mysticism and Reality: Ineffability." Journal of Indian Philosophy. Vol. 3, nos. 3 and 4 (1975). "A Note on the Jaina Conception of Substance." Forthcoming in Sambodhi. 71 Epistemology, Logic and Grammar in Indian Philosophical Analysis. The Hangue/Paris: Monton and Co., 1971. Milinda Panha. Edited by V. Trenkner. London: Pali Text society, 1928. Mookerjee, S. The Jaina Philosophy of Non-Absolutism. Calcutta: Bharati Mahavidyalaya, 1944. Murti, T. R. V. The Central Philosophy of Buddhism. London: Allen and Unwin, 1953. Nagarjuna. Madhyamika-sastra. Edited by P. L. Vaidya. Darbhanga : Mithila Institute, 1960. Padmarajiah, Y. J. Jaina Theory of Reality and Knowledge. Bombay: Jaina Sahitya Vikas Mandal, 1963. * Prabhacandra. Prameyakamalamartanda. Edited by Mahendra Kumar Sastri. Bombay: Nirnaya Sagar, 1941. Pujyapada. Sarvarthasiddhi. Comm. on Tattvarthasutras. Edited by Jinadasa Sastri. Sodasapura: Sakharama Granthamala, 1939. Samantabhadra. Aptamimamsa Comm. of Akalanka. Edited by Gajadharalal Jain. Kasi (Benares): Sanatana Jaina Granthamala, 1914. Samkara. Comm. on Brahmasutras. See Brahmasutras. Page #81 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Central Philosophy of Jainism Santaraksita. Tattvasangraha. Edited by E. Krishnamacharyya, Baroda : Oriental Institute, 1926. Santisuri. Nyayavatara-varttika-vrtti. Edited by D. Malvania. Bombay: Bharatiya Vidya Bhavan, 1939. Siddhasena. Sanmati-Tarka. Edited by S. Sanghavi and B. Doshi. 5 pts. Ahmedabad: Gujarat Puratattva Mandira Granthavali, 1924-31. Nyayavatara. Edited by A. N. Upadhye. Bombay; Jaina Sahitya Vikas Mandal, 1971. Staal, F. Exploring Mysticism. Berkeley: University of California Press, 72 1975. Strawson, P. F. Introduction to Logical Theory. London: Methuen, 1952. Sutrakrtanga. Edited by A. S. Suri and C. Ganindra. 2. vols. Bhavanagar: Jain Publications, 1950-3. Svetasvatara Upanisad. See Isa. Tattvartha-sutras. Of Umaswami or Umasvati. Edited by J. L. Jain. Arah: Bibliotheca Jainica, 1920. Reprint AMS Press, New York, 1974. Thomas, F. W. The Flowerspray of the Quodommodo Doctrine. Berlin: Akademia Verlag, 1960. Umasvati. Tattvarthabhasya. Edited by K. Siddhantasastri. Bombay: Jaina Mandala, 1932. Upadhye, A. N. Introduction to Pravacanasara. See Kundakunda. Vacaspati Misra. Samkhyatattvakaumudi. Edited by P. Jawaji. Bombay : Nirnaya Sagar, 1940. Vadideva Suri. Pramana-naya-tattvaloka-lankara. Edited by H. S. Bhattacharya. Bombay: Jain Sahitya Vikas Mandal, 1967. Syad-vada-ratnakara. 5 pts. Edited by Motilal Laghaji. Poona: Vaisesikasutras of Kanada. Edited by Muni Sri Jambuvijayaji. Baroda: Oriental Institute, 1961. Vasubandhu. Abhidharmakosa-bhasya. Edited by Swami Dwarikadas Sastri. Benares: Bauddha Bharati, 1970-72. Vidyananda. Astasahasri. Edited by Vamsidhara. Bombay: Nirnaya Sagar, 1915. Vyomasiva. Vyomavati. Edited by G. Kaviraj and Dhundhiraj Sastri. Benares: Chowkhamba, 1930. Whitehead, A. N. Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology. New York: The Free Press, 1969. (First published by Macmillan Co., 1929, ) Yaska. Nirukta. Edited by Manasukha Raya Mora. Calcutta: Gopal Printings, 1951. Yasomitra. Comm. on Vasubandhu. See Vasubandhu. Page #82 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ www.jainglor