Book Title: Facets of Jain Philosophy Religion and Culture
Author(s): Shreechand Rampuriya, Ashwini Kumar, T M Dak, Anil Dutt Mishra
Publisher: Jain Vishva Bharati
________________
336 Anekāntavāda and Syādvāda
the example suspect as according to Jain philosophy 'Our judgments about things are relative—but relative to or dependent upon not simply the mood of the judging mind but upon the relational characters of the many-sided reality itself”,37 It seems that syādvada is to be associated with the pluraiity of objective reality rather than the whimsicality of subjective notions.
VIII It could perhaps be plausibly suggested that such examples represent (legitimate) extensions of the doctrine. The same could perhaps be said of P.T. Raju's remark, made while discussing the doctrine of seven-fold predication ... called syādvāda'.
The Jainas would say that from the point of view of microscopic perception, germs exist; and that they do not exist from the point of view of ordinary perception."
It needs to be borne in mind, however, that in its classical formulation non-existence is not related to the non-existence of the
itself but its non-existence as another object. That is to say, a jar is not said to non-exist as a jar, but as a piece of cloth.
Modern illustrations sometimes tend to exemplify syadvāda in such a way that the case of predications of the non-existence of the object includes the possibility of it not exising by itself in some sense and not necessarily in the sense that it does not exist as another object. The concept of non-existence has been taken in the sense of possibility of the co-existence of different aspects in the same object, such as could lead one to assert the existence of the opposite of the first predicate. Thus A may exist as a father but he can also exist as someone's son so that it can be said of him: (a) He is a father; (b) He is not a father; and so on. However, on the strict application of syadváda one would have to say (a) He is his child's father; ( not the father of someone else's child.
Similarly, another modern tendency is to illustrate syadvada b indicating the possibility of change through time. On the strict application of the doctrine, one should speak of things as they are at a point in time; the classical formulation seems to be static rather then dynamic. Here again the same development occurs which was noted earlier-non-existence is predicated about the object itself and not in relation to its non-existence as another object at a point in time. Here
37. Satischandra Chatterjee and Dhirendramohan Datta, op. cit., p. 86. 38. P.T. Raju, op. cit., p. 100.