Book Title: Jaina Ethics
Author(s): Dayanand Bhargav
Publisher: Motilal Banarasidas
Catalog link: https://jainqq.org/explore/001334/1

JAIN EDUCATION INTERNATIONAL FOR PRIVATE AND PERSONAL USE ONLY
Page #1 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Reloan to gab stah B0032 JAINA ETHICS DAYANAND BHARGAVA Page #2 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ JAINA ETHICS - (A thesis approved for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy by the University of Delhi) Dayanand Bhargava M.A., Ph. D. Lecturer in Sanskrit Ramjas College, Delhi. MOTILAL BAN ARSIDASS DELHI :: VARANASI :: PATNA Page #3 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ MOTILAL BANARSI DASS BUNGALOW ROAD, JAWAHARNAGAR, DELH1-7 CHOWK, VARANASI (U.P.) ASHOK RAJ PATH, PATNA (BIHAR) फ६९३ फ४ ૧૧૧ ટે ख ६२५५ First Edition 1968 Price Rs. 20.00 कालभाई दलपत प्रन्थालय भारतीय कति Printed in India by Shantilal Jain, at Shri Jainendra Press, Bungalow Road, Jawaharnagar, Delhi-7, and published by Sundarlal Jain, Motilal Banarsidass, Bungalow Road, Jawahar Nagar, Delhi-7 Page #4 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ ये पुरुषे ब्रह्म विदुस्ते विदुः परमेष्ठिनम् Those who know Brahman in Man know the Being who is supreme. -अथर्ववेद, १०.७.१७ Page #5 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ SCHEME OF TRANSLITERATION Vowels 3 37 E a, s, ā, ļ, i, e , i, ai, 3. u, 3 ū, 371 o, 37 au. Consonants 4,046,0 ,64 ç त् प् 5 ç $, t, P, y, ș, & th, थ् th, फ् ph, I r, s, 15' mortor for tend g, , d, d, b, I, h, gh, झ् jh, dh, ध् dh, भ् bh, v, . í, I न् म् 1 ņ, n, m, $, þ. , ABBREVIATIONS C.I. Coorg Inscriptions E.C. Epigraphia Carnatica E.I. Epigraphia Indica E.R.E. Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics S.B.E. Sacred Books of the East S.B.H. Sacred Books of the Hindus S.B.J. Sacred Books of the Jainas V.S. or Vik. Sam. Vikrama Samvat S.S. Saka Samvat V.N.S. or Vir. Nir. Sam. Vira Nirvāņa Samvat Page #6 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ FOREWORD I have very great pleasure in writing these few words by way of introducing the thesis (JAINA ETHICS' by Dr. Dayanand Bhargava which is now appearing in print. This work was submitted by Dr. Bhargava for his Doctorate Degree of the Delhi University and he has revised it with a view to making it more comprehensive as well as useful both to the general reader and the student seriously interested in Jaina Studies. Jainism has made very significant contribution to Indian thought and has added both to its variety and richness. Dr. Bhargava's present work attempts to study and highlight the contribution to the ethical thought. His study is deep and wide in extent and critical and original in approach. He has also discussed the metaphysical concepts since these are vitally connected with ethics in any system. He has attempted to carry out a comparative as well as historical study of this ethics and discussed the ethical thought of the six systems of Indian Philosophy. I have no doubt that the work will be very widely welcomed and appreciated by scholars and students alike. T. G. Mainkar Delhi, 29th April, 1968. Professor and Head of the Department of Sanskrit, University of Delhi, Delhi. Page #7 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Page #8 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ PREFACE sub The metaphysical Reality or the Truth of logical co. herence must remain merely a theoretical possibility unless it is translated into good of life through right-living. In fact, the Reality or Truth is supra-logical and can be better realised by living it practically than by speculating on it intellectually. Indian philosophy in general and Jainism in particular, therefore, ascribes the supreme place, of all the branches of philosophy, to ethics. Šilānka, a great commentator on Jaina Āgamas, considers all the branches of philosophy only subsidiary to and meant for ethics. Yet there is no work, written on the lines of modern research, dealing with the Jaina view of life in its entirety. The present work is a humble attempt to cover up that lacuna. I do not lay claim either to perfection or to originality. I could only pick up a few pebbles out of the vast ocean of Jaina scriptures and explore the scattered theme of my thesis from the original sources to arrange it into a systematic whole. I am presenting the ethical views of the ancient Jaina! thinkers, as faithfully as I can, before the world of scholars, who are the best judges of the degree of success achieved in! this effort and whose satisfaction will be my best reward. . I have adopted a synthetic view of things, while making comparisons and emphasised the unity existing in the diversity of Indian thinking. I believe that this is in keeping with the traditional Taina way of looking at problems. Syädvāda, which has become almost a synonym for Jainism, teaches us that the same truth could be differently expressed without involving us in any real contradiction. As I have always kept the problems of modern society in view, and shown the utility of Jaina ethical concepts for humanity in general, I hope that the book would interest the general reader also. Jaina ācāryas have always stood for the dignity of man, and equality of all, advocated the birth-right of indepen Page #9 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ ( viii ) dence of all individuals and have preached the elevated ideal of non-violence. I dedicate my work to these noble and lofty causes for which all right thinking men of all times and nations have striven. Before I conclude, I have to place on record my sincerest gratitude for Dr. Indra Chandra Sāstri, M.A., Ph.D., Šāstrācārya, Nyāyatirtha and formerly Head of the Department of Sanskrit in the Institute of post-Graduate (Evening) Studies, University of Delhi, for his invaluable guidance with out which the thesis for my Ph.D. would have been a Herculean task for me. My sincerest thanks to Dr. R.V. Joshi, M.A., Ph D., D.Litt. (Paris), my teacher, to Late Babu Jai Bhagwan Jain, and to Rev. Kșullaka Jinendra Varņi, whose assistance and guidance have served as beacon-light during the progress of my research-work. Pandit Dalsukh Bhai Malavania, Professor, University of Toronto (Canada), one of the examiners of my thesis deserves special thanks for his valuable suggestions. Dr. T.G. Mainkar, M.A., Ph.D., D.Litt., Professor and Head of the Department of Sanskrit in the University of Delhi, who has the rarest combination of benevolence and scholarship in him, has very kindly contributed a foreword to this book for which he deserves my sincere gratitude. I take this opportunity of acknowledging my obligations to Lala Sundar Lal Jain, the proprietor of M/s. Moti Lal Banarsidass, for his keen personal interest in the publication of this work. The Manager and the staff of the Jainendra Press also deserve my thanks for their active co-operation. Shri J.L. Shastri,who spared no pains in reading the proofs, also deserves my gratefulness. Needless to say that suggestions for improvement will be most welcome and incorporated in the next edition. Dayanand Bhargava Delhi, 27th May, 1968. Page #10 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CONTENTS Scheme of transliteration Abbreviations Foreword Preface (iv) (iv) (vii) CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION (The figures indicate pages) Nature of ethics-Ethics defined (1-2)-Summum Bonum of life (3)—Happiness and misery (3-4) Preyas and Śreyas (4)-Suddhopayoga and Subhopayoga (4-5). Problems of ethics-Removal of misery (5-6)-At titude of Brāhmaṇism (6)--Attitude of Buddhism (6-7)—Six systems of philosophy (7-9) ---Jaina view (10-11). Metaphysics and ethics --Buddhist view (11 )--Jaina view (11-12) -Seven fundamentals of Jainism (13-14)--Doctrine of Karman (14). Other schools of thought-Introductory (14-15) - Time (15-16)—Nature (16-17)-Fatalism (17) — Views of Makkhali Gosāla (17) and Purāņa Kāśyapa (17-18) - Jaina view (18-19) --Chance (19)—Matter (19-21)-Purușa-Human Beings (21)-Brahman (21-22)-God (22). Popular theories about God-In Hinduism (22)-In Christianity (22-23) ---In Islam (23)—Some remarks on theism (23-25)- Jaina view about God (25-26). Mckenzie's objections to the doctrine of karman examined—(26-31). The question of freedom of will-Modern thin kers (31-32), Jaina view--Human efforts and fate —the synthesis of the two (32-37). Page #11 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ (x) Conclusion-Some basic concepts of Jaina ethics (37-38). CHAPTER II METAPHYSICAL BACKGROUND The seven predicaments—(39). Nature of self (Jiva )-Different views--Upanişads (39-40)-Cārvāka (40) --Nyāya-Vaiseșika (40-41 ) Sāmkhya ( 41 )--Pūrvamimāṁsā (41), Vedānta (41-42)—Jaina view (42-43)-The empirical self and the transcendental self (43-44)-Different categories of empirical self (44) -Based on intellect (44)-(116)—Based on biology (44-45)— Western view Vs. Indian view ( 45-47). Non-self (Ajiva )-Different views--Cãrvāka (47) Sāṁkhya (47-48)-Nyāya-Vaiseșika (48)-Mimāṁsā (48)—Vedānta (49)-Jaina view-Six substances (dravyas) (49-51)-Nature of reality (51-52 )--Contact of self with non-self (52). The cause of misery-inflow of karmic matter and bondage (āśrava and bandha)-Different views—Upanişads (53-54)-Buddhism (54)Sāṁkhya (54-55) - Nyāya (55)—Mimámsā (55) — Vedānta (56)-Jaina view. Inflow of kārmic matter (āśrava) --Introductory (56)-A list of sinful activities (57-58 )–Eight types of karmans (58-61 ) Bondage (bandha)Wrong belief (mithyādarśana) (61-62)-Vowlessness (avirati) (62)—Negligence (pramāda) (62)-Passion (Kaşāya)(62)--Activities (Yoga) (62-63). The removal of misery ---Different views-Buddhism (63-64 )—Samkhya-Yoga (64-65 )--Nyāya-Vaiseșika (65-66 )--Mimāmsā (66-67)—Jaina view (67). Checking of the inflow of fresh Kārmic matter (Saṁvara)(67-69 )-Shedding of the accumulated kārmic matter (nirjarā) (69-70). State of liberation-Different views--Upanişads (70) Buddhism (70-71 )-Sāṁkhya-Yoga (71)—Nyāya Page #12 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ ( xi ) Vaišeșika ( 71 )-Mimāṁsā (71-72)—Vedānta (72) Jaina view (72) Conclusion ( 72-73) CHAPTER III CONCEPTION OF MORALITY Jaina view of morality--Limitations of virtuous life (74) --Practical path (vyavahāra mārga) (74) -- Transcendental morality (niscaya mārga) (75-76)Synthesis of the two 776-78). Non-Jaina systems-Upanişads ( 78-79 )--Buddhism (79-80 )-Nyāya-Vaiseșika (80) ---Sāmkhya-Yoga (80)-Mimāṁsā system (80)-Vedānta (81) – Christianity (81-82). Conclusion (82). CHAPTER IV THE PATH OF THREE JEWELS Introductory (83-84). Right Faith (Samyagdarśana) - Meaning (84-85), Transgressions and blemishes (85-86), Eight essentials (86-87)-Kundakunda on the eight essentials (88)-Means of attaining Samyaktva (88-89.) Moral corollaries of right faith (89-91)-Position of faith in Indian Culture (91 )—Some points on Samyagdarśana (91 93). Right Knowledge-Right faith and right knowledge (93-94)-Right knowledge defined (94)—Place of right knowledge according to Jñānasāra (95) -Right Vs. wrong knowledge (95-96)-Limitations of knowledge (96)-Position of right knowledge in Indian Culture (96-97)-Some points on right knowledge (97). Right Conduct - Transcendental conduct (98)-Practi cal point of view (98). Conclusion (99). Page #13 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ ( xii) CHAPTER V THE CONDUCT OF A HOUSEHOLDER Introductory-Householder defined (100) — His posi tion (100-101)-Position of an aviratasamyag drsti (101-102). Vow of Non-Violence-Non-violence in Jainism (105-106 )–Violence in thought (106-107)-- Violence in action (107-108 )--Non-absolutism. and non-violence (108-109) --Types of violence (109-110)-Limitations of the small vow of nonviolence (110-111)--Eight mūlaguņas (111-112) -Dietic prohibitions (112-113) – Transgressions of the vow of non-violence (113-114)—Some misconceptions about non-violence (114)— Violence in the name of religion (114-115). Vow of Truthfulness-Classification of truth (116 117)-Conception of truth (117)—Transgressions 117-118 )--Praise of truthfulness (118-119) Position of truth in Brāhmaṇism (119). Vow of non-stealing-Its transgressions (119-121). Vow of brahmacarya (celibacy) —Transgressions (121-122). Vow of non-possession-Transgressions (122-124). Supplementary vows of householder—( 124-126). Guņavratas-Digvrata and Deśāvakāśikavrata (126) -Transgressions of Digvrata ( 126 )-Deśāvakāśikavrata (126-227)—Transgressions of deśāvakāśikavrata (127)Anarthadanda-viramaņavrata (127-128 )-Five forms of anarthadanda (128. 128)-Transgressions of anarthadaņdavrata (129130) --Bhogopabhogaparimāņavrata (130-132 )-- Transgressions of Bhogopabhogaparimāņavrata (132-133). Sikşāvratas--Sāmāyika (133-134) - Transgressions of Sāmāyikavratas (134-135)-Proșadhopavāsavrata (135)—Transgressions of Proșadhopavāsavrata (136)-Atithisaṁvibhāgavrata (136-138) – Transgressions of Atithisamvibhāgavrata (138139)-Sallekhanāvrata ( 141-142). Page #14 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ ( xiii ) Pratimas-Darśana (142-143) —Vrata (143)-Sāmā yika (143)— Proşadha (143)—Sacittatyāga (143) --Rātribhuktivirati (144)---Brahmacarya (144) -Arambhatyāga (144)– Parigrahatyāga (144) Anumatityāga ( 145 )-Uddistatyāga (145). Conclusion (145-146). CHAPTER VI THE CONDUCT OF A JAINA MONK Introductory-Position of an ascetic in Jainism (147-148) -Qualifications for initiation into monkhood (148-149) -Types of monks (149-150) -Twenty-eight essential qualities. (mūlagunas) of a monk (150-151). Five great vows--Vow of non-violence (152-153 Vow of truthfulness (153-154)-Vow of nonstealing (154-155)—Vow of celibacy (155)-Vow of non-possession (156-159). Eight essentials (pravacanamātskās) of the conduct of a monk-Three guptis (159) Five samitis 160-163). Other characteristics of a monk--Ten excellent · qualities (Daśalakṣaṇadharma)(163-164) ---Attitude of a monk towards hardships (164-165 ) - Pañcacāritra (165 )--Sadāvaśyakas (166-171 ). Food for the monk-Four categories of faults (171 174). Samgha organisation (174r175)—Monks and nuns (175-176)-Monks and fellow-monks (176). Secondary duties of monks (uttaraguņas )-(177). Sallekhanā—(177-178). Conclusion (179). CHAPTER VII PENANCES Introductory-Importance of tapas (180-181 )--Place of tapas in Jainism (181-182). Page #15 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ ( xiv ) External austerities-Anaśana ( 183 )--Avamaudarya (183) —Vrttiparisankhyāna (183)-Rasaparityāga (183-184)-Vivista sayyāsana (184)-Kāya klesa (184). Internal austerities-Expiation-its ten types (185) Alocanā—its transgressions (185-187) --Pratikramaņa (187)-Tadubhaya(187)-Viveka (187) Kāyotsarga (188)-Tapa (188)-Cheda (189) Mūla (189)–Parihāra (189-190)-Sraddhāna (190)-Vinaya—its five types (190)-Darsana (190)- Jñāna (190-191)--Cāritra (191)-Tapa (191)—Upacara (191-192)-Vaiyyāvștya (192) Svādhyāya (192) —Vyutsarga (193). Dhyāna-(193) --its position in Indian philosophy (193) ---in Jainism (193-194)-Types of dhyāna (194)-Inauspicious-Arta (194-195 )–Raudra (195-196 )--Auspicious. Dharma Dhyana-Its requirements (196) —its place (196-197)—its postures (197) --other auxilaries (197-198)—its objects (198-199) —its types (199) -Ajñāvicaya (199)-Apāyavicaya (199) —Vipāka vicaya (199)-Saṁsthāna vicaya (199-200)Piņdastha (200)-Pārthivi dhāraņā (200) Āgneyi dhāraṇā (200)--Mārutī dhāraņā (201) Vāruņi dhāraņā (201)-Tattvarūpāvatī dhāraņā ( 201 )--Padastha (201)-Rūpastha (201-202) Rūpātīta (202)-Fruits of dharma dhyāna (202) Sukla Dhyāna (202)—its stages (202)-Pșthaktva vitarka savicāra (202-203)—Ekatva vitarka savicāra (203) -Sūkşmakriyā pratipatti (203-204) Samucchinnakriyā (204). Conclusion (204) CHAPTER IX STAGES OF SPIRITUAL DEVELOPMENT Introduction (205-206 )--Delusion (Moha) the great obstacle (206)-Threefold division of AtmanBahirātman (extrovert soul) (206-207)-Antarāt Page #16 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ ( xv ) man (introvert soul) (207)-Paramātman (super soul)(208)-Five Labdhis (208)-Three Karaņas (209-210)--Two Śrenis (210-211). Ganasthānas--Mithyādịști (211-213) --Sāsvādana samyagdụşți (213)--Samyagmithyādrsţi (213214)--Aviratasamyagdrsţi (214)—Deśasamyata (215) --Pramattasaṁyata (215)-Apramattasamyata (215-216)-Nivṛttibādara (216)-Anivștti-sāmparāya (216)—Sūkşma-sāmparāya (217) Upaśāntamohaniya (217)-Kșīņakaṣāyachadmasthavitarāga (217) --Sayogikevali (217-218) -Ayogikevali (218)." Conclusion (219). CONCLUSION 220-224 APPENDIX Introductory Remarks (225 )--Four anuyogas (226) -The Anga literature ( 226). Redaction of Agamas--Council of Pāțaliputra and loss of Āgamas (226-227) —Council of Mathurā (227-228 )-Council of Valabhi (228)-Second Council of Valabhi (228)-A chronological list of ācāryas (228-230 )—The extant āgamas (230-231). The canonical literature of Svetāmbaras-The Angas (231-235)-The Upāngas (235-236) - Cheda Sūtras (236-237)-Müla Sūtras (237-238) Ten Prakirņakas (238-239) -Cūlikā Sūtras (239) -Exegetical literature on Āgamas ( 239-240). Non-Canonical literature of Svetāmbaras--Śrāva kaprajñapti and Tattvārthasūtra of Umāsvāti (241-242) -Haribhadra Sūri and his works (242-243) ---Siddhasena Gaộin and his commentary on Tattvārtha-sūtra (243)-Devagupta (243)—Sänti sūri (243)-Deva Sūri (243) - Nemicandra and his Pravacanasāroddhāra (243-244 )-Hemacandra and his Yogaśāstra ( 244 )--Yaśovijaya (244). www.jajnelibrary.org Page #17 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ ( xvi ) Canonical literature of Digambaras-Kaşāyaprā bhịta (244-245 )—Satkhandāgama and Mahā bandha ( 245-246). Pro-canonical literature of Digambaras-Kunda kundācārya (246-248). Mūlācāra (248-249)— Bhagavati Arādhanā (249-250) Kārtikeyānuprekşā (250-251)-Tattvārthasūtra (251)Samantalbhadra (251-253)-Pujyapada (253)Āśādhara (253 )--Vasunandi (253-2545)— Amstacandra (254)--Amitagati (254-255) Sub hacandra (255). A list of other works in their chronological order 255 Bibliography 256-265 Index I 267-270 Index II 271-273 Index III 274.296 For Private & Personal Use Ortly Page #18 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION What is Ethics? 12 The word Ethics is derived from n gos, meaning character, and noos is derived, from e dos, meaning custom or habit. The term 'moral, closely associated with ethics, comes from the latin word 'mores', which primarily stands for 'custom' or 'habit' and secondarily means "character'.1 In India also, the word dharma' has been explained in two ways. On the one hand, it stands for preservation of traditional values as reflected in social customs; on the other, it means moral qualites of universal nature like non-violence and truth. The former view is emphasised by Pūrvamimāṁsā, which defines dharma as 'rules laid down by the Vedas”,3 which are repositories of the traditional social virtues. The latter view is emphasised by Jainism, which says that dharma is made up of 'non-violence, self-control and austerity'.4 Manusmộti fuses both of these views together when it says that dharma is characterised by Veda, Smrti, good conduct and that which appeals to the conscience.5 1. Muirhead, John H., The Elements of Ethics, London, 1910, p. 4. 2. The word 'dharma' has been defined as conduct (căritra) cf. चारित्तं खलु धम्मो-Pravacanasara, I.7. Also धर्मञ्चारित्रलक्षणम् Abhayadeva on Sthānānga sútra, 4.3.320. 3. TIGATSETUSET: :1 -Mimāmsādarśana, Benaras, 1929, 1.1.2. The definition of 'dharma' of Mimāṁsādarśana can be compared with the following words of Mahāvīra "BTTTT ATAT EFH" (Dharma consists in following my commandments). Ācārängasūtra, 1.6.2.180. 4. धम्मो मंगलमुक्किठें अहिंसा संजमो तवो । -Dašavaikālika, 1.1. 5. at: Fyfa: HETETT: FIFT a RATTATHA: 1 एतच्चतुर्विधं प्राहुः साक्षाद्धर्मस्य लक्षणम् ।। -Manusmộti, Bombay, 1894, 2.12. Page #19 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Jaina Ethics In the West, ethics has been precisely defined 'as the study of what is right or good in conduct'.1 What do, however, the terms ‘right and 'good' signify ? An answer to this question may help us in understanding the nature and scope of ethics. (i) Right : This term, derived from Latin word “rectus", means 'according to rule'. Its Greek synonym, dikaios, also signifies the same sense. Right conduct, therefore, would mean a conduct according to some rules'. (ii) Good : This term, derived from Greek ay a fòs, means 'which is valuable for some end. Good conduct, therefore, will mean a conduct which is ‘valuable for some end'. It will be observed that the same conduct may be termed both 'right' and 'good' from two different angles. Rules are framed with some end in view. Therefore, a conduct, which will be 'according to rules' or right will also be 'valuable for some end', which is kept in view while framing those rules, and therefore it will also be good. It is this main problem of ethics, viz. the study of what is 'good' or 'right' in conduct, which has many more corrolaries. For example, "Is happiness the ultimate end of action ? Is virtue preferable to pleasure ? How do pleasure and happiness differ ? What is meant by saying that I ought to perform some particular action or to respect some general precept, such as the keeping of promises ? Am I under any obligation to seek the welfare of other persons, as well as my own ? If so, what is the right proportion between the two welfares ? What is meant by 'freedom of the will’? Is feeling or reason the right guide to conduct ? What do the terms 'good', 'right', 'obligation', 'duty', 'conscience signify practically and theoretically ?”. Thus, there are many dilemmas at every step in our life, when we cannot escape the responsibility of passing a moral judgement on problems arising from such conflict as that of self and others, pleasure and duty, freedom and necessity, law and liberality and circumstances and character.3 I. Mack Mackenzie, John S., A Manual of Ethics, London, 1929, p. 1. 2. Rogers, A.P., A Short History of Ethics, London, 1913, p. 1. 3. Muirhead, John H., The Elements of Ethics, p. 1, Page #20 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction Summum Bonum of our life 23 All these problems are to be answered by referring to certain rules of conduct, which are to be framed with some end in view. Ethics does not deal with any particular conduct but with conduct in general. Therefore, the rules under a system of ethics are not to be framed for a particular end; but for the attainment of the supreme good, which is termed as summum bonum of life. People with different tastes and setup of mind have different ends in view. Some crave for wealth; others for knowledge; still others for fame. There are people who would sacrifice one of these for the sake of others. Many of these aims cannot be regarded as ultimate. Wealth, knowledge and fame are not ends in themselves; they are means to some end. True, that many of the philosophers have preached the theory of knowledge for the sake of knowledge and have opposed any attempt at attributing any ulterior motive to it; but no philosopher can afford to neglect the impact of knowledge on life. One may differ as to his conception of happiness, as he may differ about the ways through which he seeks happiness; but there is no denying the fact that every man, and every sentient being for that matter, seeks happiness and repels misery. There is no dearth of men who voluntarily impose sufferings on themselves; but in fact they find happiness through sufferings. The question why we seek happiness is as absurd as the question why water is cold or fire is hot. Reasoning stops here. The inherent nature of things cannot be reasoned out. It is the inherent blissful nature of the self that makes us repulsive to misery. We can, therefore, conclude that all conduct should be such as would bring us the maximum of happiness and remove miseries from our lives. This, of course, is a very general sort of statement and requires some further clarification in as much as the terms like 'happiness' and 'misery' are very vague. Happiness and miserythm Wealth, health, beautiful persons, good food, clothing and houses are some of the objects which an average man general 1. Fantasmat :- Pañcādhyāyi, Indore, Vir. Nir. Sam. 2444, 2.53. Page #21 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Faina Ethics ly likes to have. The anti-thesis of it may be called misery which includes poverty, ill-health, ugly faces, starvation or ill-feeding, and absence of proper clothing and residence. A vivid description of objects of pleasure have been given in Indian scriptures. Similarly, the miseries of the world known as trividhatāpa also form the subject matter of many a good number of books on philosophy and religion. Preyas and Sreyas 3 The above account of happiness and misery, however, is obviouly very gross and incomplete. Our rich possessions do not make us necessarily and fully happy." Nor are poor people always unhappy. Happiness does not depend merely on possessions or their absence but is mainly dependent on our mental attitude. A state of mental poise and calmness, which springs forth from self-control and integrity of personality, cannot be bought for money or worldly possessions. There is a happiness which comes from within and not from without, which is more commonly known as 'bliss' or 'beatitude'. Sometimes this state is explained in negative term as absence of pain. In fact, this state is inexplicable in words. The two ends of worldly happiness and spiritual bliss are termed as preyas and śreyas, respectively. Suddhopayoga and Subhopayoga We may point it out here that the main concern of Jaina ethics is Śreyas and not preyas. It means that it aims at spiritual upliftment of the individual rather than his worldly well-being. It implies a supra-moral plan of life, where one transcends both, good and bad. Any extrovert activity, whether vicious or virtuous, is a deviation from the path of liberation. Kundakunda says that vice and virtue are shackles of iron and gold respectively, both of which bind us to the physical world.3 1. Kathopanişad, 1.1.23-25. (For this and other Upanisads see the Prin cipal Upanişads', London, 1953). 2. a faâa aunt HTCTT: 1 --Ibid., 1.1.27. 3. सौवणियं पि णियलं बंधदि कालायसं पि जह पुरिसं। बंधदि एवं जीवं सुहमसुहं वा कदं कम्मं ॥ -Samayasāra, Delhi, 1959, Gātha 146. Page #22 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ İntroduction A state of self-absorption, with inner awakening, is the highest moral ideal. This lofty ideal of transcendental morality should, however, be no excuse for obliteration of distinction between vice and virtue. The supra-ethical plan of life can be realised only by persons with higher spiritual attainments, who have dived deep into the realm of self.. Everybody should aspire for this lofty ideal but with due consideration to one's limitations. At the initial stage, the force of habit does not allow the aspirant to remain selfabsorbed. Here he is required to be vigilant, lest he should go astray. Pujyapāda says that virtuous life is definitely to be preferred to licentiousness, for it is better to wait, if we have to wait at all, in the cool shade rather than in the hot sun.' Thus the distinction of good and bad is not to be totally obliterated. The path of virtuous activities, leading to worldly and heavenly pleasures, is known as śubhopayoga, as against the path of transcendental morality, known as Suddhopayogi. As we shall deal with this problem in a later chapter separately, we may here point out only this that the above mentioned emphasis on the transcendental morality in Jainism has made it highly spiritualistic and individualistic. Dharma as a means to wordly prosperity (artha and kāma), as mentioned by the Mahābhārata,a does not occupy an eminent position in Jainism. The problem of ethics-removal of misery The problem of ethics has been differently stated by different schools of Indian philosophy. These schools can be broadly classified under the following three heads : (i) Those who are mainly concerned with the enjoyments of this world and the world beyond, but are silent about the concept of liberation. This is the older tradition of the Vedas represented by Pūrvamimāṁsā school. 1. a aa a aa, arata arrain छायातपस्थयोर्भेदः, प्रतिपालयतोर्महान् ॥ - Istopadeśa, Bombay, 1954, verse 3. . 2. धर्मादर्थश्च कामश्च स किमर्थन सेव्यते ॥ -Mahābhārata, Poona, 1933, 18.5.62. Page #23 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Faina Ethics (ii) Those who are mainly concerned with the spiritual well-being of the man. This tradition, represented by the Upanisads includes Sārkhya, Yoga, Nyāya and Vedānta amongst orthodox school, and Buddhism and Jainism amongst the unorthodox systems. (iii) The third category consists of those who strike a balance between the two opposite views mentioned above, and give equal importance to both of them. Vaiseșika system may be mentioned amongst this category. The attitude of Brāhmaṇism H3 In the Vedic period, the Rșis seem to be anxious for long life, progeny, wealth and fame. It was in the Upanisadic age that the pressure of the problem of misery was acutely felt. In the Chāndogyopanişad, Nārada, who had mastered all branches of knowledge, including the Vedas could not find out the way to get rid of misery. He approached Sanatkumāra in all humbleness, and told him that though he had heard that a man with self-realisation crossed miseries, he himself was not capable of overcoming them. “O Lord ! I am in grief; lead me to the shore that lies beyond grief”, he requested. In response to this request, Sanatakumāra unfolded the mysteries of life to Nārada. The attitude of Buddhismeling The credit of dealing with this problem of misery in a systematic way goes to Lord Buddha, who expounded an elaborate ethical system for the removal of misery. He realised the universality of suffering and explained its existence in these words : "Birth is misery ; old age, decay, sickness, death, sorrow, grief, woe, lamentation and despair are misery; not to get what one desires is misery. In short, the five groups based on grasping are misery."Lord Budddha preached not only the existence of misery but also brought the hope of redemption therefrom for the suffering humanity. He asserted 1. सो हं भगवः शोचामि तं मां भगवञ्छोकस्य पारं तारयत्विति । -Chandog yopanişad, 7.1.3. 2. Anguttara Nikāya, London, 1951, 3.62.10. PTS translation (slightly modified.) Page #24 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ * Introduction that sufferings can be avoided, and should be avoided, by properly following the ethical discipline of self-control. He asserted not only that there is (i) misery (dukkha), but also that (ii) it has causal chain (dukkhasamudaya), (iii) that it can be stopped (dukkhanirodha) and that (iv) there is a way to check it (dukkhanirodhagāminipatipada). These are known as four noble truths.1 Lord Buddha did not accept that misery was an inevitable part of life, nor could he agree with those absolute fatalists who would believe that misery would be automatically removed at a fixed time and we need not make any effort for it.2 Six systems of Philosophy Amongst the six orthodox systems of philosophy, the earliest trend of search for happiness is represented by the Pūrvamīmāmsā school, which, as already pointed out, did not conceive of liberation but conceived of heaven only. The means of attainment of heaven include performance of actions prescribed by the Veda and avoidance of actions prohibited by it. Some of the karmans, called nityanaimittika are to be performed by everybody without any exception. Negligence in their performance entails sin. Other karmans, called Kamya, are to be performed only with a certain object in view. The actions prohibited by the Vedas are called Nişiddha and should be avoided absolutely. Thus in Pūrvamīmāmsā, the Veda is the highest authority, the actions prescribed therein are the highest duty and heaven is the highest goal. For Mimāṁsā there is no contradiction in a prosperous, rich life and religious life. The Sankhya school, on the other hand, is perhaps the oldest orthodox system which conceived of renunciation as a necessary condition for spiritualism. It begins with the idea that our mundane life is beset with three types of sufferings viz. (i) adhyatmika i.e. arising from psychophysical nature of man, e.g. pain caused by physical or mental disorders. (ii) adhibhautika i.e. arising from some agencies other than the perso I. Ibid. 3.61.1-13. 2. Zimmer, Heinrich, Philosophies of India, London, 1951, p. 246. 3. Mīmāmsādarśana, 1.2.1. Page #25 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Faina Ethics nality of the sufferer e.g. pain caused by beasts or enemies. (iii) ādhidaivika i.e. arising from supernatural powers, including six calamities (sadītis), planets and elemental agencies.1 It may be argued that there are tangible means of getting rid of these miseries, e.g. disease can be cured by medicine; and therefore one need not worry about ethics. But there are two objections to it. In the first place, it is not sure that a particular misery can be cured by a particular tangible means without fail, e.g. a medicine may or may not cure the disease. Secondly, the relief is only temporary. Therefore, we cannot depend on tangible means. The root cause of these miseries will have to be found and a check imposed so as to uproot miseries premanently and unfailingly. Hence the necessity of a moral discipline.2 In Särkhya the element of rajas, which represents misery, is said to be present in all our experience and, therefore, all our intellectual operations are said to be beset with misery.3 Coming to Yoga, which represents the ethical aspect of the same system of which Sārkhya is the metaphysical representation, we find that even so-called pleasures of life have also been considered as miseries; and a check on those miseries, which are yet to come, has been advised. Yoga Sūtra gives many reasons for condemning even so-called pleasures as misery. In the first place, they are not stable. Secondly, even these temporary enjoyments are achieved with a lot of trouble and struggle. Thirdly, dependence on these objects bereaves us of independence. Fourthly, desires never die. Fulfilment of one desire leads to multiplicity of desires, and thus the chain never ends. Fifthly, hankering after worldly objects brings us in clash with those who are running after the self-same object. 1. Miśra, Vācaspati on Sānkhyakārikā, Poona, 1934, kārikā 1. 2. दुःखत्रयाभिघाताज्जिज्ञासा तदपघातके हेतौ । दृष्टे साऽपार्था चेन्नकान्तात्यन्ततोऽभावात् ।। --Sūnkhyakārikā, Poona, 1934, kārikā 1. 3. तदेतत्प्रत्यात्मवेदनीयं दुःखं रजःपरिणामभेदो न शक्यते प्रत्याख्यातुम् । --Miśra, Vācaspati on Sārkhyakärikā, 1. 4. Teg:CHATTE -Yogasūtra, Gorakhapura, Vik. Sam. 2013, 2.16. Page #26 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction 9 Sixthly, in illness or in old age, after impairment of senses, on which alone such enjoyment depends, we cannot remain happy.1 Therefore, the Yoga system strongly opposes the tendency of hankering after temporary gratification of lust which is generally mistaken for happiness. According to Nyaya system, suffering is said to be the very nature of the world. There is a causal chain behind pain, at the root of which is false notion (mithyājñāna). On the removal of the following in turn, there is automatic removal of the preceding one : (i) Pain (ii) Birth (iii) Activity (iv) Fault (v) False notion.2 The Vaiseşika system reconciles the two attitudes-one represented by Purvamīmāṁsā and the other represented by Sankhya, Yoga and Nyaya. It gives worldly prosperity as well as spiritual happiness as the aim of dharma.3 According to Vedanta, bliss is the nature of self. As soon as the veil of ignorance is removed, the fetters that shut ourselves out from the reality, which we are, are broken asunder and then the self experiences no misery but bliss. Thus we see that the various systems of Indian philosophy agree on this point that a state of complete mental poise, free from discords and uncertainties of life, is the ultimate aim of life. I. 9fc91192198=173:g'oqfafazìara g:aña aå' faàfmn: 1 -Ibid., 2.15. ག 2. दु. खजन्मप्रवृत्तिदोषमिथ्याज्ञानानामुत्तरापाये तदन्तरापायादवर्गः । L -Nyayasutra, Poona, 1939, 1.1.2. Also सुखसाधनमाप्तुमिच्छति दुःखसाधनं हातुमिच्छति । प्राप्तीच्छाप्रयुक्तस्यास्य सुखसाघनावाप्त्यं समीहाविशेष आरम्भः । जिहासाप्रयुक्तस्य दुःखसाधन परिवर्जनं निवृत्तिः । -Vatsyāyana on Nyayasutra, Poona, 1939, 3.2.34. 3. यतोऽभ्युदयनिःश्रेयससिद्धिः स धर्मः । -Vaisesikas ātra, Allahabad, 1923, 1.1.2. Page #27 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Faina Ethics - Faina view H3 The existence of misery and suffering is as much recognised by Jainism as by its sister religions, Brāhmaṇism and Buddhism. of "The world is afflicted, miserable, difficult to instruet and | without discrimination”,1 says the Acārāngasūtra. Silänka, a commentator of Ācārāngasūtra begins his commentary with the following words : All creatures, overcome by attachment, aversion and delusion, tormented by various, excessively bitter physical and mental miseries should try to know what is good and what is bad for the removal of that misery, and this is not possible without a peculiar type of discrimination. The Uttarādhyayana says that all worldly pleasure is suffering in the ultimate analysis. All "singing is but prattle, all dancing is but mocking, all ornaments are but a burden, all pleasures produce but pain.”3 The same eternal question haunts the mind of the thinker again and again : "By what acts can I escape a sorrowful lot in this unstable, ineternal saṁsāra, which is full of misery ??4 “Birth is misery, old age is mis ery, and so are disease and death." The main attraction 'is a safe place in view of all, but difficult of approach, where there is no old age nor death, no pain nor disease.'' “The transitory condition is like a wheel at a well where before one bucketful of distress is got over a large number of afflictions overtake the soul”.? Out of the seven fundamental elements of Jaina philosophy, only two, the 'self' and the 'non-self' are dealt with 1. Ācārāngasūtra, SBE, Vol. XXII, 1.1.2.1. (P. 3). 2. इह हि रागद्वेषमोहाद्यभिभूतेन सर्वेणापि संसारिजन्तुना शारीरमानमा (सा?) नेकदुःखोपनिपातपीडितेन (त) दपनयनाय हेयोपादेयपरिज्ञाने यत्नो विधेयः । स च न विशिष्टविवेकमृते । --Silānka, on Ibid., p. 3. 3, Uttarādhyayana, Gurgaon, 1954, 13.16. 4. Ibid., 8.1. 5. Ibid., 19.15. 6. Ibid., 23.81. 7. विपद्भवपदावर्ते पादिकेवातिवाह्यते । यावत्तावद्भवन्त्यन्याः प्रचुरा विपदः पुरः । --Istopadeśa, 12. Page #28 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction from a metaphysical point of view; the other five are mere corrolaries of the problem of getting rid of miseries. Sarvadarsanasamgraha very beautifully summarises the position when it says : "Ăstava (inflow of kārmic matter causing misery) is the cause of mundane existence and Saṁvara (stoppage of that inflow) is the cause of liberation : this is the faina view (in short), every thing else is only its amplification.” Metaphysics and Ethics ld 2 Buddhistic View H 3 Where is the necessity of dealing with self and non-self at all? To quote the famous example of Lord Buddha, a man hit by an arrow, need not, and should not, ask such superficial questions as to the caste of the doctor who comes to his rescue, or the details of the arrow which hit him. He need know only this that the arrow has hit him and the doctor can cure him. To those who asked Lord Buddha about the nature of self, he did not answer, rejecting their question summarily as unexplained (avyākyta).2 This attitude of Lord Buddha was probably a reaction to those thinkers of his time who would go on philosophising everything without improving the daily conduct of life Jaina View H3 The Jainas, however, true to their tradition of reconciliatory attitude, followed the middle path. They did realise that a strict moral discipline is necessary for purity of life. But they did not overlook such metaphysical questions as the nature of self. Our behaviour cannot be isolated from our metaphysical beliefs. Truth and valuation are inseparable. Without knowing what truth in reality is how can that reality be realised, which is the ultimate aim of all philosophy. Therefore, metaphysics and ethics are the two sides of the same coin. There could not have been a better proof of the realisa 1. 371771 HTT: FICHERT 187ATTUTEL इतीयमाहती दृष्टिरन्यदस्याः प्रपञ्चनम् ।। --Sarvadarśanasamgraha, Poona, 1951, p. 80. 2. Majjhima Nikaya, Saranatha, 1933, 2.2.3. Page #29 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Jaina Ethics tion of this relation between metaphysics and ethics than the employment of the word 'dharma' for the 'essential nature of things' (vastusvabhāvah) on the one hand, and for 'moral duties' on the other. Samantabhadra goes to the extent of saying that without knowing the real nature of things, which is permanency in transitoriness, all moral distinction between the antithesis of bondage and liberation, punya and pāpa, heaven and hell, pleasure and pain will be blurred.1 Belief, for example, in the metaphysical view that the nature of things is absolutely transitory would make it impossible to carry on any financial transaction, or to explain the fact of memory, or to have any relation like that of husband and wife.2 ___I. पुण्यपापक्रिया न स्यात्प्रेत्यभावः फले कुतः । बन्धमोक्षौ च तेषां न येषां त्वं नासि नायकः ॥ क्षणिकैकान्तपक्षेऽपि प्रेत्यभावाद्यसम्भवः । प्रत्यभिज्ञाद्यभावान्न कार्यारम्भः कुतः फलम् ॥ -Aptamimāmsa, Solapura, Sak. Sain. 1826, 40-41. Also न बन्धमोक्षौ क्षणिकैकसंस्थौ न संवृतिः सापि मृषा स्वभावा । मुख्याहते गौणविधिर्न दृष्टो विभ्रान्तदृष्टिस्तव दृष्टितोऽन्या ॥ --Yuktyanuśāsana, Saharanapura, 1951, verse 15. Also नकान्तवादे सुखदुःखभोगी न पुण्यपापे न च बन्धमोक्षौ । दुर्नीतिवादव्यसनासिन परविलुप्तं जगदप्यशेषम् ॥ ---Syādvādamañjari, Bombay, 1935, verse 35. 2. प्रतिक्षणं भङ्गिषु तत्पृथक्त्वा न मातृधाती स्वपतिः स्व-जाया । दत्तग्रहो नाधिगतस्मृतिर्न तत्वार्थसत्यं न कुलं न जातिः ॥ -Tuktyanusāsana, 16. Page #30 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction 13 Seven fundamentals of Jainism 2 It is due to this close relation between metaphysics and ethics that Jainācāryas, though as much interested in the ethical problem of removal of misery as the Buddhists, begin their philosophy with a metaphysical discussion of self and non-self, which are the first and second fundamental truths of Jainism. Thus Jainism is a dualistic system, bifurcating the universe into two exhaustive categories : jiva, soul; and ajiva, matter. This division of the universe comes nearer to the division of puruṣa' and 'prakrti' of Sāňkhya system. The mystery of how the jiva or self joins hands with ajiva or non-self in mundane existence still remains unexplained. In Jainism, Kārmic matter or subtle material particles are held to be the medium of holding the gross body with the conscious soul. The soul has an inherent quality of attracting these particles towards itself. This is psychophysical process. Whenever the soul entertains any such idea as that of attachment or aversion (called bhāvāšrava), it attracts some very subtle particles, which differ in each case in accordance with the nature of the idea entertained by the soul (dravyāśrava). This, in short, is the third fundamental truth of Jainism. The mere inflow of this kārmic matter is no obstacle. But four fundamental passions (Kaşāya) viz. anger, pride, deceitfulness and greed, together with wrong belief (mithyādarśana), non-discipline ( avirati), negligence (pramāda), and psychophysical activities (yoga), hold the kārmic matter in bondage ( bandha) with soul. This is the fourth fundamental truth of Jainism. The fifth fundamental truth is that this inflow of fresh kārmic matter is to be checked (Samvara). This requires a constant vigilance against such trends of mind, deeds and words as may lead to such inflow. The sixth fundamental truth is regarding shedding (nirjarā) of such kārmic matter as may already be accumulated by the soul. This is rendered possible by penance and meditation. The seventh fundamental truth is that of liberation, where the soul, engulfed in the mud of kārmic matter from times immemorial, after getting rid of it, shines forth in its intrinsic purity of infinite knowledge, intuition, bliss and potency. 1. Tattvārthasūtra, Banaras, 1952, 1.4. Page #31 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Faina Ethics These seven fundamentals of Jainism, it will be seen, are the corrolaries of the famous doctrine of Karman, on the foundation of which not only the edifice of Jaina ethics but of all ethical systems of India stands. As you sow, so shall you reap' is the most fundamental doctrine of all ethical systems. Man is the architect of his own fate. It is this belief which holds him responsible for his own miseries and happiness. It is this belief again, which inspires him to ethical considerations in his conduct. The brief sketch of seven fundamentals of Jainism, which is given here, is a bit difficult to grasp at the beginning and shall be dealt with in detail in the following chapter. But before that, the basis of these principles viz. the doctrine of Karman, should be examined now and here, because of its supreme importance for any ethical discussion. Doctrine of Karman ko What is known as the law of cause and effect in the sphere of physical science is known by the name of karmasiddhānta in the sphere of ethics. It is not possible to behave in a particular way and escape its concommitant result. Similarly, no result ensues without a corresponding action. No effort, however small, goes for nought. We do not meet any result, which is not justified by our own past doings. This, in short, is the doctrine of karman, which is accepted by Brāhmaṇical, Buddhistic and Jaina schools of thought. But even this doctrine of karman has not gone unchallenged in the history of philosophy. We shall refer to some objections to the doctrine of karman at the end of this chapter. Herebelow we give a description of some schools of thought, which hold different factors to be responsible for our miseries and pleasures. We shall also try to explain the Jaina attitude towards these schools. Different schools y g The Svetāśvataropanişad gives a beautiful summary of the various schools of thought regarding the causes of misery and happiness prevalent in ancient India. It enumerates seven schools of thought which give prominence to either one or the other of the following factors : Page #32 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction 15 1. Time (Kāla) 2. Nature (Svabhāva) 3. Fate (Niyati) Chance (Yadrccha) 5. Matter (Bhūta) 6. Puruşa 7. A combination of all these (Samyoga eșām).1 There is reference to many of these sects in Sūtrakrtānga and Gommațasāra also. Before we proceed to discuss these schools individually, let us note in the very beginning that the Jaina thinkers have not rejected any of these schools outright. What they have rejected, is the rejection of any one of these factors. The mistake that others have committed, according to Jainism, is that they have over-emphasised the role of one of these factors and have not taken others into consideration at all.2 Therefore, the seventh school of thought, taking into consideration all these factors together, seems to represent the Jaina school of thought. This attitude of Jainism is in consonance with its general attitude of non-absolutism (Syādvāda). Now, we discuss below each of the schools individually, (i) Time B · The Kālasūkta of Atharvaveda gives a vivid description of time. “It is he (time) who drew forth the worlds and encompasseth them.... There is no power superior to him”.3 Gommațasāra summarises this theory in these words : “Time 1. 15: Faurat faufaezagot भूतानि योनिः पुरुष इति चिन्त्याः संयोग एषां नत्वात्मभावादात्माप्यनीशः सुखदुःखहेतोः । --Svetāśvataropanişad, 1.12. परसमयाणं वयणं मिच्छं खलु होइ सव्वहा वयणा जेणाणं पुण वयणं सम्म खु कहंचिवयणादो । -Gommațasāra, Lucknow, 1937, Karmakānda, 895. 3. स एव सं भुवनान्याभरत् स एव सं भुवनानि पर्यत् । "तस्माद् व नान्यत् परमस्ति तेजः ॥ -Atharvaveda, Aundha, 19.53.4. Page #33 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 16 Faina Ethics creates all, time destroys all; time is waking among sleeping people. Time can be deceived by none.” This is an absolutistic (ekānta) view according to which everything is determined by time. Obviously, time cannot be the sole factor in controlling our misery or happiness. Otherwise, how is it that some people are happy and others unhappy at the same time ? Time is something unconscious and cannot be held responsible for miseries and happiness which obviously result from our conscious efforts. While rejecting this theory for such obvious reasons, the force of time-factor should be fully recognised. It is one of the factors affecting our condition. It is not easy to nullify the effects of old age, for which time is primarily responsible. In every walk of life, we do watch that time plays an important part. The mistake lies in believing that everything else is impotent before time. (ii) Nature B Nature stands for inherent properties of things. Some philosophers, called Svabhāvavādins, hold that events are determined by their own inherent nature. They argue out that if nature is not the cause then 'who makes the sharpness of thorns, and who creates variety in deer and birds'? Therefore, they establish that everything behaves according to its own nature.2 This school of thought denies any freedom of action. A thief must remain a thief for he is so by nature. This leaves no scope for human effort. We become puppets in the hands of our nature. In fact, the Jainas believe that nature, which does influence our conduct to a remarkable degree, is of our own making and we can unmake or modify it by our efforts. If the Svabhāvavādins want to refute the existence of any ultramundane controller of this universe, the Jainas join hand 1. Gommațasāra, Karmakānda, 879. २. को करइ कंटयाणं तिक्खत्तं मियविहंगमादीणं । विविहत्तं तु सहाओ इदि संव्वपि य सहाओत्ति ॥ -Gommațasāra, karmakānda, 883. Page #34 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction with them. But to say that there is no freedom of will, amounts to denial of moral responsibility for action. Obviously, such a theory cannot become the basis of any sound ethical system. (iii) Fatalism Fate means that whatever happens, happens necessarily. Everything is predetermined. We cannot choose between good or bad, for our future course of action is already fixed. Amongst modern philosophers, name of Spinoza may be mentioned, who was a staunch believer in determinism. "Only ignorance makes us think that we can alter the future; what will be will be, and the future is as unalterably fixed as the past. This is why hope and fear are condemned: both depend upon viewing the future as uncertain, and therefore spring from lack of wisdom."1 The Mahabharata has a long discussion on the controversy of fate VS. human efforts.2 Amongst contemporaries of Mahavira and Buddha, Makkhali Gosāla (or Maskarin Gosāla) seems to be an absolute fatalist. According to him, the soul after completing the number of inevitable births is automatically freed of miseries. There is no punishment or reward for any conscious practice of vice or virtue. Not that vice and virtue are not connected with bondage or release, but to quote Zimmer: "According to this "hempen shirt" doctrine of Gosāla, man's moral conduct is not without significance......Our words and deeds, that is to say, announce to ourselves—and to the world-every minute, just what mile stones we have come to......pious acts, then, are not the causes, but the effects; they do not bring but they foretell release."'4 17 Another fatalist with a difference but again a contemporary of Mahāvīra, was Purāṇakāsyapa (or Pūrṇakāśyapa). He says: 'that to one who kills a living creature, who takes what is not given, who breaks into house, who commits dacoity, or 1. Bertrand Russel, History of Western Philosophy, London, 1948, p. 597. 2. Mahabharata, 13.6.7-12. 3. Digha Nikaya, Pt. I, Bombay, 1942, 1.2.20. 4. Zimmer, H., Philosophies of India, pp. 267-268, Page #35 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 18 Faina Ethics robbery, or highway robbery, or adultery, or who speaks lies; to him thus acting there is no guilt. Again, 'in generosity, in self-mastery, in control of the senses, in speaking the truth there is neither merit nor increase of merit'.1 The distinction between these two can be easily noticed. Makhhali Gosāla.does make a distinction between good and bad, but he denies a man any right of improving his lot which is predetermined. In other words, a man would automatically become good when the time for his release approaches. But for Purāņa Kāśyapa there is nothing like moral. It seems that these two thinkers were misrepresented by their opponents by exaggerating their emphasis on fatalism. But it is also true that any such philosophy which over-emphasises fatalism may prove detrimental for moral progress of a man who may become inert. It was this aspect of fatalism which made Buddha retort such philosophers in these words : “There exists a 'heroic effort (vīryam) in man, there exists the possibility of a successful exertion (utsäha) aimed at the disengaging of man from the vortex of rebirths... provided he strives whole-heartedly for this end."2 The Sūtraktānga summed up this doctrine of fatalism in these words : “But misery (and pleasure) is not caused by (the souls) themselves; how could it be caused by other (agents, as time etc.)? Pleasure and misery, final beatitude and temporal (pleasure and pain) are not caused by the souls) themselves, nor by others; but the individual souls experience them; it is the lot assigned them by destiny." This attitude is criticised in the following words : “Those who proclaim these opinions, are fools who fancy themselves learned; they have no knowledge and do not understand that things depend partly on fate, and partly on human exertion. Thus the Jainas have a synthetic view in this respect also. There are passages in Jaina literature which favour ralative determinism; but it is never done at the cost of human effort, 1. Digha Nikaya, I.2. 2. Zimmer, H., Philosophies of India, p. 226. 3. Sūtrakrtānga, Bangalore, Vik. Sam. 1993, 1.1.2.2-3. SBE. Translation. 4. Ibid., 1.1.2.4. Also cf. Gommatasära, Karmakānda, 882. Page #36 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction which the Jainas hold to be of supreme value for all moral progress. This synthetic position is not self-contradictory. We shall deal with this problem of determinism vs. freedom of will at the end of this discussion separately. For the present we can say that if our miseries and happiness were to be guided by some blind fate, all ethics, religions and instructions will lose their importance. 19 4. Chance (Yadṛccha) B This school of thought is called by the name of 'accidentalism' by modern thinkers. These accidentalists believe that there is no so-called 'cause and effect' relation between any objects. Their argument is that we cannot show the ultimate cause of any event. Therefore, they conclude that every event is merely a matter of chance. The only good that this theory can do to us, according to the Jainas, is that it reminds us of the subordinate position of instrumental cause (nimittakāraṇa) as against the substanţial cause (upādānakāraṇa) which holds the primary position. In the history of Western philosophy, Plato and Aristotle are inclined towards accidentalism. Stoics, on the other hand, realised that a law is working in this universe and every effect can be traced to some cause.1 Grier Hibben has remarked that accidentalism is a view of the world which characterises a pre-scientific period of thought." 5. Bhūta (Matter) B Materialists hold unconscious matter to be responsible for everything. They only believe in pratyaksa (authority of perception) and therefore, do not agree with other systems of Indian philosophy with regard to the existence of soul. The Sūtrakṛtānga gives the ethical implications of this theory. "There is neither virtue nor vice, there is no world beyond; on the dissolution of the body the individual ceases to be'.3 1. James, Hastings, (ed.), Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics, New York, 1955, Vol. I, p. 65. 2. Ibid., p. 64. 3. Sütrakṛtänga, SBE Vol. XLV, Oxford, 1895, 1.1.1.12 (p. 237). Page #37 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 20 Jaina Ethics Sarvadarśanasangraha summarises the attitude of materialism towards pain and pleasure in these words : “They (i. e. opponents) conceive that you ought to throw away the pleasures of life because they are mixed with pain; but what prudent man will throw away unpeeled rice which encloses excellent grain because it is covered with husk."1 It is clear from this that materialism glorifies gratification of the lust of senses as the highest good of life. There are, however, reasons to believe that materialism has been misrepresented by the opponents of this school. Materialists did caution us against being too much other-wordly. They tried to organise society not on any theocratic but on a secular basis. They launched an agitation against many baseless superstitions of society, e.g. they argued that if the animal killed in a sacrifice went to heaven why did the sacrificer not kill his own father and send him to heaven. The 'matter is as real to Jainism as to materialism. But to say that matter is the only reality would be against all principles of Jainism. It is not conceivable how consciousness can be the result of natural forces. We shall open another chapter with this discussion. For the present, suffice it to say that the very idea that we can escape the responsibility of our actions is repulsive to ethics. Unrestrained sensualism is self-destructive. Unchecked desires of the members of society may lead to anarchism. If we accept that there are only two aims of life, money and sex (arthakāmau), and righteousness and liberation (dharmamokşau) are mere fabrications of human mind then where is the 1. त्याज्यं सुखं विषयसङगमजन्म पुसां दुःखोपसृष्टमिति मूर्खविचारणेषा। वीहीजिहासति सितोत्तमतण्डुलाढ्यान् को नाम भोस्तुषकणोपहितान् हितार्थी । -Sarvadarśanasangraha. p. 4. 2. पशुश्चेन्निहतः स्वर्ग ज्योतिष्टोमे गमिष्यति । स्वपिता यजमानेन तत्र कस्मान्न हिंस्यते ॥ Ibid., p. 13, Jairi Education International Page #38 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction distinction between a man and an animal and where is the necessity of any ethics ? 6. Puruşa R . The word puruşa has many connotations in Indian philosophy. The more important of them are (i) Human beings (ii) Brahman and (iii) God or īśvara. All of these are held responsible for misery by one or the other school of thought. (i) Human beings: This school believes that there is no exterior cause of human miseries except the efforts of human beings themselves. There is complete freedom of will. A man may do whatever he likes. There are no limitations on our efforts. This is called theory of indeterminism as against the theory of determinism which is a modern name for fatalism. This theory is quite congenial to ethics because it does not hold environments responsible for our actions of commission and omission. We cannot be charged for an immoral action which we did not commit of our own choice. Therefore, this theory believes in the capability of a man to choose a path of his own choice. Jainism supports this theory so far. But the force of circumstances should also be recognised, or else what is the use of our previous actions if they do not and cannot mould our present ? The past actions do not go for nought. They leave their impressions on us. We are, therefore, free only to the extent we have not curtailed our freedom by our own past actions. (ii) Brahman : We have discussed above the case of materialism, holding matter to be the only reality. The Vedāntists hold just the opposite view. They hold consciousness to be the only reality. This one conscious entity, called Brahman, is the substantial as well as the instrumental cause of this universe. It pervades the whole universe. Samantabhadra in his Aptamīmāṁsā has given the following implications of this theory : “If we accept monism, no distinction between the doer and the action can be made. The existence of good and bad actions, pain and pleasure, this world and the next world, knowledge and nescience, and bondage and liberation, implies duality. And logical conclusion can be drawn only on the basis of two premises, which again imply Page #39 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Jaina Éthics duality. If monism is based on scriptures and not on logic, dualism may also be said to be based on scriptures. Nothing is contradicted unless it exists ; and therefore non-duality, which contradicts duality, from this very fact accepts the existence of duality." (iii) God : Many popular religions, together with some systems of philosophy, assert that there is an eternal Lord of the universe who creates, sustains and destroys it. It is He who sends us misery and happiness. Of course, according to some religions, He does so in accordance with the actions that we perform. Thus the idea of God is not always disconnected with the doctrine of karman in India. But Jainism does not hold it logical to believe that there is an eternal God ruling over the universe and sitting on us in judgment. Before we give reasons for it as forwarded by Jainism, let us examine what the popular religions like Christianity, Islam and Hinduism say about this interesting problem. Popular theories about Godblog : (A) Hinduism : The popular devotional approach of Hinduism towards God is best represented by the Gitā. God is all-in-all. We are just puppets in his hands. We should surrender ourselves unconditionally to the will of Almighty. Nothing can be done without His will. He is situated in every heart, moving every body according to His will. The fruit of every good or bad action must be surrendered to Him. It is, however, repeatedly told by Hindu Scriptures that the consequences of an action performed by a man must be borne by him. So there is no denying the responsibility. (B) Christianity : Coming to Christianity, the old Testament presupposes the existence of God. It does not consider it necessary to give any arguments to prove it. It teaches us to worship one and one God alone and not to pay any attention to lesser deities. 1. Aptamimaṁsā, 24-27. 2. Gitā, Madras, 1930. 18.66. 3. Ibid., 18.6r. Page #40 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction 23 God is one.1 He is Spirit, holy and righteous, merciful and forgiving. He cares for the lowliest. Jesus, who is the son of God, knows his father as no other can.5 Added to these two, God and His Christ, Spirit makes the Holy Trinity of Christianity complete. "The Father is the primal source, the son the mediating power, the spirit the executive energy; and every Divine act is to be understood as a working of the Father, through the son, in and by the Holy Spirit." Evidently, there is not much difference between the idea of God as represented in these popular religions. In Christianity, the mediating power of Christ is an extra entity. He may be compared to the incarnation of Hinduism. The second thing is the denial of any deity other than God. In Hinduism also, Sikhism and Arya Samaja show the same tendency. (C) Islam Islam lays even greater emphasis on Oneness of God. It condemns the trinity of Christianity in the following words: "Believe, therefore, in God and his apostles, and God say not, "Three"; forbear, it will be better for you. is only one God. Far be it from His Glory that He should have a son." "...And when God shall say: 'O Jesus, son of Mary, hast thou said unto mankind : Take me and my mother as two Gods beside God?" He shall say: "Glory be unto thee; it is not for me to say that which I know to be not 958 true. Muslim theologians have given the following seven attributes of God: (i) Life (hayah) (ii) Knowledge (ilm) (iii) Power (qudra) (iv) Will (irāda) (v) Hearing (Sam), (vi) Seeing (başar) and (vii) Speech (Kalam).9 All these attributes hardly make any difference for the ethical discussion with which we are concerned presently. The basic 1. Mark, 12.29 (The Holy Bible, London, year is not mentioned). 2. John, 4.24. (The Holy Bible). 3. John, 17.11, 25. (The Holy Bible). 4. Matthew, 6.30. (The Holy Bible). 5. Matthew, 11.27. (The Holy Bible). 6. Hastings, James, E.R.E. Vol. VI, p. 261. 7. Ibid., Vol. VI. p. 300. 8. Hastings, James, E.R.E. Vol. VI., p. 300. 9. Ibid., Vol. VI, p. 300. Page #41 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 24 Faina Ethics truth about these theistic religions is that they all believe in one eternal God, who is omnipresent, omnipotent and omniscient and who is the author of not only this universe but also of our fate, miseries and happiness. Now, let us examine this contention. I The theory of God is based on the idea that every action must have an agent. So there should be some power which created this universe. Now, the question is whether the supposed creator created this universe out of nothing or out of some material which already existed. He could not create it out of nothing because nothing can be created out of nothing. "There is no existence out of non-existence nor is there destruction of what exists." This is an axiomatic truth. The other alternative that God created this universe out of a pre-existent matter, leaves unanswered the question how a non-creative God suddenly became creative at a particular time. Ethically also, theistic theory of creation is not free from doubts. "The Dilemma of Epicurus is still with us; if God wishes to prevent evil but cannot, then He is impotent; if he could but will not, he is malevolent; if He has both the power and the will, whence then is evil."2 W. D. Niven has tried to analyse the problem. There are, according to him, three alternatives (1) God is not good or (2) He is not impotent or (3) Evil is not what it seems to be. He has discussed the pros and cons of every alternative and this is how he concludes: "......Every proposed solution either leaves the old question unanswered or raises new ones. The problem is for the human mind insoluble."'3 The so-called orthodox systems of Indian philosophy were also familiar with the difficulties about the theistic hypothesis. Samkhyatattvakaumudi, a commentary on Samkhyakärikä, says: .It becomes impossible to assume that the creation cc 1. नासतो विद्यते भावो नाभावो विद्यते सतः । -Gitā, 2.16. Cf. Pañcāstikaya,, Bombay, Vik. Sam. 1972, 15 2. W.R. Sorley and other, The Elements of Pain and Conflict in Human life. p. 48. quoted from ERE, Vol. XXII, p. 1. 3. Hastings, James, ERE, Vol. VI. p. 324. Page #42 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction of the world was due to conscious action. For a God, whose wishes are all fulfilled, can have had no personal interest whatever in the creation for kindness, since before the creation souls suffered no pain...... from what could the kindness of God wish to have souls released ? Further, a God who is actuated by kindness would create only joyful creatures."1 Besides, Kumārilabhatta in his Slokavārtika, has held that there could be no creator of this universe.2 Even Nyāya and Vaiseșika, according to new researches, were originally atheistic.3 Jaina view about God : s Keeping in view all these difficulties in accepting a universal Lord of the world, the Jainas believe that the hypothesis that an eternal self-subsistent God made this world, . which stood in need of maker, does not hold good. If God could be eternal and self-subsistent, there is no difficulty in holding that the universe, with all its constituent spiritual and material forces, is also eternal and self-subsistent. Substances, which are endowed with certain qualities, can produce new sets of qualities by the process of permutation and combination. These substances are independent of any external agency in their functioning and do not obey any superior power. Of what use is the inherent quality of a substance if it works only under God's supervision ? If fire burns and water cools, it is not due to the will of God; it is due to their inherent qualities. To say that these inherent qualities were bestowed on these substances by God is also an impossibility. Can we imagine these substances bereft of their qualities at any time? Therefore, this physical world is ruled by physical law and not by any divine law. This, however, does not mean that there is no God. "God is only the highest, noblest and fullest manifestation of the powers which lie latent in souls of men."'4 There is no eternal God sitting upon judgement on human beings. Human souls themselves attain Godhood or Siddhhood by shedding away al impurities. Such human souls become completely free and 1. Miśra, Vācaspati, on Sāṁkhyakārikā, 57. cf. Also Sarvadarśanasar graha, p. 228. Slokavārtika, Calcutta, 1909, Sambandhākṣepaparihāra, 47-59; 74-88. 3. Hastings, James, ERE, Vol. II, p. 186. 4. S. Radhakrishnan, Indian Philosophy, London, 1941, Vol. I, p. 21 Page #43 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 26 . faina Ethics are possessed of infinite knowledge, potency, perception and bliss. These Siddhas are far more above gods or deities. They neither create nor destroy any thing. They have conquered, once for all, their nescience and passions and cannot be molested by them again. These Siddhas do not and cannot return our prayers. They do not take the law in their hands so as to show to their devotees any grace or forgiveness for which there is no place in the strict law of karman. How can they, who have completely conquered attachment and aversion and are equanimous to all, be pleased or angry with anybody ? This does not mean that prayer has no place in Jainascheme of life. By meditating upon the attributes of Siddhas and by showing respect to them we neither flatter them nor please them but simply try to awaken in us the latent potentialities of Godhood. The Siddhas do not come to our rescue but a constant mental association with our ideal, through their medium, helps us in its realisation. Therefore, it is insisted that “even though one may be inclined towards the knowledge of padārthas, and devotion of tirtharkaras and may have interest in the scriptures and may observe self-control and penance, yet Nirvāṇa is far away from him (without self-realisation).1 Some objections to the doctrine of Karman We have seen above that accidentalism has no scope in modern times. Nothing can fall outside the circle of cause and effect. The interacting causes may cooperate or oppose or neutralise one another in such an intricate manner that the resultant combinations are not predictable easily. If we do not know this intricate chain of causes, we may call an incident accidental; but all the same, it is not without cause. On the same ground, the theories of Time, Nature or Blind Fate or Matter can be dismissed as overlooking the universal rule that there is no effect without a cause I. सपयत्थं तित्थयरं अभिगदबुद्धिस्स सुत्तरोइस्स । दूरतरं णिव्वाणं संजमतवसंपओत्तस्स ।। -Pañcāstikāya, 170. Page #44 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction and there is no cause without an effect. Logically, we have noticed, that even a creator God cannot be the author of our fate. In fact, we are left with no other alternative but to accept that man is the architect of his own fate. Our deeds are like the seeds, the fruits of which are the miseries and happiness of life. "Vidhi, the Saṁskyta word for . destiny, literally means a 'law and not accident. Every belief, liking, disliking and tendency of life goes to form our temperament, inclinations and capabilities. Every thought, word and deed bears its full fruit. Thus the doctrine of Karman involves a great faith in human effort. In spite of this inevitability of the doctrine of karman for all moral considerations, Western scholars do not agree with it. As examples, we quote below some of the important objections raised against the doctrine of Karman by Mr. John Mckenzie in his book “Hindu Ethics' : (i) “The kind of actions that are supposed to produce good and bad fruits respectively, are by no means always actions that most of us would regard as ethically good and bad.” (ü) "Reward and punishment are given twice over, once in heaven or hell, and again in a new birth on earth.”2 (iii) “The idea of the grace of God is. in contradiction to the Karma doctrine." (iv) “The doctrine of Karman makes our admiration of pain and suffering endured by men for the sake of others absurd. "4 (v) Mckenzie thinks that one should not demand justification for suffering which humanity endures. (vi) Mckenzie thinks that in the theory of Karman no provision is made for the intentions underlying the action of the doer and that the doctrine works mechanically and does not take the psychological aspect of morality into consideration. (vii) Doctrine of Karman implies fatalism and leaves no room for human efforts. Mckenzie, John, Hindu Ethics, London, 1922, p. 218. 2. Ibid., p. 220. 3. Ibid., p. 223. 4. Ibid., p. 224. Page #45 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 28 Faina Ethics These objections have been raised by a scholar like Mckenzie and need careful examination. Here below we would endeavour to examine them one by one : The first objection can be raised against three types of actions : (a) to quote Mckenzie himself, 'many kinds of rituals and magical acts'; (b) such negative and individual virtues as non-violence and meditation; (c) acts of kindness to small insects and animals, which are hardly considered to be ethical by Western thinkers. As far as the rituals are concerned they do form a part of popular religion in India as elsewhere. Whether we believe in doctrine of karman or not, popular forms of religion always develop certain rituals, which are important for religious discipline in life. Of course, these rituals become meaningless in the absence of a genuine moral consciousness. The institution of sacrifice (yajña), when it lost its moral background, was condemned not only by the Jainas and the Buddhists but by the Upanişads also. As regards the negative virtues, like non-violence, it may be pointed out that negation of evil is also an important part of ethics. Similarly, virtues like meditation may not come under morality according to Western scholars; in fact, they think that oply those virtues which have a social bearing can be termed as ethical. But society is made up of individuals; and, therefore, to exclude virtues which lift up the individual from the realm of morality will not be proper. As regards such actions as showing kindness to small insects, we should remember that Jainism particularly believes in equality of all life. Man is superior to other animals; but that does not give him the licence to tyrannise them. They demand as much of our attention as other fellow beings in the society. The Christian conception that beasts are made for men is not acceptable to Karmavādins, who believe in the theory of reincarnation; and, therefore, believe that an animal in this birth may have been a human being in his previous birth. (i) Mckenzie seems to confuse the Vedic conception of the other world, which does not conceive of rebirth, with the later conception of hell and heaven, which is much more Page #46 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction rational. It is not necessary, according to karmavādins to take birth on earth for receiving punishment or reward for past deeds. Even going to hell or heaven is a sort of rebirth. It is wrong to say that the same deeds are punished or rewarded twice, once in hell or heaven and again in a new birth on earth. One deed yields its fruit only once; it may be either in hell or heaven or on earth. A deed which has yielded its fruit once exhausts, and cannot yield the same fruit again. (iii) It is perfectly true, as already explained, that the idea of 'grace of God' is in contradiction to the doctrine of Karman. But where is the necessity of bringing in a merciful God in human affairs? 'Man thou art thy own friend, why wishest thou a friend beyond thyself ?", asks the Jaina scripture, Acārānga Sutra.1 The doctrine of Karman teaches us self-dependence and not dependence on some imaginary grace of an imaginary God. 2 (iv) Here Mckenzie seems to miss the distinction between the real point of view (niscayanaya) and practical point of view (vyavahāranaya). The former takes substantial cause to be main factor whereas the latter takes instrumental cause to be predominating. Both of them are to be taken in their proper perspective. From the real point of view nobody can inherit the acts of others and every body suffers the results of his actions all alone. Therefore, we cannot share the miseries of others. On this view-point is based the conduct of a monk, whose life is devoted to the higher cause of self realisation and emancipation. He is above social obligations. His contribution to the society is limited to the spiritual enlightenment that he gives and of which he is a living embodiment. 29 The case of a householder is different. His conduct is based on practical point of view. He is always ready to help his fellow beings. To undergo sufferings for others is a highly meritorious action and strongly recommended for a householder. If a householder shirks helping his fellow beings under the pretext of being unable to share the miseries of 1. Acārāngasūtra, 1.3.3.4. Max Müller. (ed.), SBE, Vol. XXII, p. 33. 2. आत्माश्रितो निश्चयनयः पराश्रितो व्यवहारनयः । -Amṛtacandra on Samayasara, Delhi, 1959, gāthā 272. (p. 352) 52)./ Page #47 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 30 Jaina Ethics anybody else, he is a great hypocrite, who tries to rationalise or justify his selfish motives by quoting the scriptures. Our obligations, therefore, vary as we ascend the ladders of spirituality. Spiritual realisation and not social service is the ultimate aim of life. But social service can and often does prove a stepping stone to spiritual realisation (v) The answer to this question is simple. There should be a cause for every effect. The sufferings, which humanity endures, should have also some cause. It will be a pity to accept that anybody can be miserable without any moral lapse on his part. It amounts to suggest that even a moral man can be miserable and even an immoral man can be happy. Then we will have to confess that there is no justice in the universe. If we believe in God, it must be admitted as a sheer cruelty on His part to inflict miseries on innocent creatures. If we do not believe in God we will have to say that the fates of human beings depend either on the vagaries of nature or on mere accident. We have already indicated that this is not tenable. Why should, after all, an action be considered good or right if it does not bring any good to the agent ? (vi) The docrine of Karman, as expounded by Jainism, takes notice of the ‘motives' behind actions fully. There are two aspects of an action : (i) psychological or subjective; and (ii) physical or objective. The law of Karman is inexorable, but it does not mean that it is mechanical. The same action may yield different results in accordance with the motive of the agent. There are examples where a lesser sin was met with heavier punishment on account of the intensity of the feeling of the agent. The story of Tandulamatsya, a small fish, sitting in the ear of a bigger fish, can be quoted in this connection. The bigger fish was eating smaller fishes while the Tandulamatsya looked on. The bigger fish ate some of the fishes and left others. The Tandulamatsya always thought that had he been in the place of the bigger fish he would not have left a single fish alive. Merely by entertaining this violent idea with great intensity the Tandulamatsya had to go to lower hells than the bigger fish who actually committed 1. Upasakādhyayana, pp. 141.142. Page #48 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction 31 the sin of violence. It is, therefore, wrong to say that the doctrine of Karman does not take into account the psychological aspect of our actions. (vii) The last, but not the least, objection against the doctrine of Karman is its fatalistic tendency. This question needs to be examined in greater detail, for it is a complicated problem of Jaina ethics. Even in modern times there are as many views regarding this question as there are sub-sects in Jainism. Great controversy seems to continue even among the thinkers of the same sect and, therefore, the question requires a careful study. The question is : is it possible and consistent to hold the view that freedom of will exists, while accepting the doctrine of Karman ? In other words, while admitting the inevitable forces of habit, inherited character and circumstances, can one rise above these and move in a different direction ? If one can, then alone the ethical commandments, whether negative or positive, have any meaning and then only can we hold somebody morally responsible for his actions. Modern thinkers have shown how a deterministic view of life makes one irresponsible towards moral obligations. Pringle Pattison says that on the basis of determinism one may “really seek to excuse himself in sequel, by trying to show that it was impossible for a man with his particular antecedents to act otherwise than he did .." Butler dismissed necessity with a 'disrespect amounting to contempt from the same point of view. According to this view, the course of things cannot be changed ; and praise and blame, punishment, obligation and the hope of progress are illusions. Kant has viewed this problem from two different angles.3 Man, as an intellectual, demands coherence in experience. Character is empirical from this point of view, i.e. it falls under the law of causation. But as intelligent moral beings, we feel that we fix our ends for ourselves. Viewed from this angle, man seems to possess freedom of will. How to reconcile these I. Pattison, Pringle, The Philosophical, Radicals, Edn. 1907, p. 101. 2. Gladstone W.E., Studies subsidiary to Butler's Works, Oxford, 1896, p. 268. 3. Hastings, James, Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics, Vol. VI, p. 124. Page #49 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 32 Jaina Ethics two views is the problem before a thinker on moral problems. He cannot reject either of them and yet it seems difficult to accept both because of their apparently contradictory nature. Dr. Green has pointed out that 'if I could be something today irrespective of what I was yesterday, or something tomorrow irrespective of what I am today, the motive to the selfreforming effort, furnished by regrets, for a part of which I reap the fruit, that growing success of the effort that comes with habituation, and the assurance of a better future which animates it, would alike be impossible.'1 Mr. W. James, on the other hand, says that free will gives some ground of hope to those who feel the burden of the past and thus is 'a doctrine of relief. Jaina View on Freedom of Wirts It has been already pointed out above that Jainism neither rejects fate nor efforts. Samantabhadra has attributed our success or failure to the following three factors : (1) Bhavitavyatā or fate (2) Upādānakāraña or substantial cause, which means human efforts (puruṣārtha) in the case of human beings3 (3) Nimittakāraņa or instrumental cause which includes past actions and the forced circumstances. Thus there are many, and not one, factors which act and counteract in the process of liberation. No action takes place in isolation. Our efforts are affected by our circumstances. But it does not mean that we are puppets in the hands of circumstances. Nevertheless, future is predictable to some extent. In Dvādaśānupreksā it has been said that process of birth or death of a person is already known to the omniscient Jinas and nobody can change it.4 Padmapurāņa says that a person gets a 1. Green, T.H., Prolegomena to Ethics, Oxford, 1899. p. 129. 2. James, W., Pragmatism, New York, 1948, p. 121. 3. अलंघ्यशक्तिर्भवितव्यतेयं हेतुईयाऽऽविष्कृत-कार्य लिङ्गा । -Svayambhūstotra, 33. 4. जं जस्स जम्मि देसे जेण विहाणेण जम्मि कालम्मि । णादं जिणेण णियदं जम्म वा अहब मरणं वा ॥ तं तस्स तस्मि देसे तेण विहाणेण तम्मि कालम्मि । को सक्कदि वारेदु इंदो वा अह जिणिदो वा ॥ Kārtikeyānuprekṣā, Agas, 1960. 321-322. Page #50 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction 33 thing at a time and place predetermined by fate. In Astasāhasri, a verse is quoted which says that our intellect, effort, and helpers turn the same way as our destiny. Now, if we accept so in absolute sense, then all moral teachings become futile. It is no use telling a person what he should or should not do, if he has no freedom of choice. The dangers of determinism are evident. It may paralyze all our efforts. It may make us immoral. Therefore, generally the Acāryas speak about determinism with great caution. They generally praise human efforts and avoid referring to determinism. But all the same truth has to be faced. The theory of omniscience and the theory of karman do favour determinism in a certain sense. But they need neither paralyze our effort nor make us immoral. Let us explain it. Kundakunda says that all of us have two-fold consciousness (i) knowledge-consciousness (iñānacetanā) (ii) Action- ! consciousness (karmacetanā).3 Knowledge consciousness means the state of absolute freedom from the sense of being an agent of an action (kartstvabhāvanā): In this state of knowledgeconsciousness, the soul remains absorbed in its pure intrinsic, blissful, conscious state. It has no desire or initiative for action. This is a state of supra-moral plane of life which is beyond good and bad both. This is not a state of inertia but a state of sense of fulfilment of the purpose of life. This is the ultimate end of life. Determinism paralyzes not only the good activities but bad activities also and what remains is the pure consciousness of blissful nature of the self. This is spoken of ;. 1. TEETHOL Tarta Targatsa ar i तत्प्राप्यते तदा तेन तत्र तावत्ततो ध्र वम् ॥ -Padmapurāna, Kashi, 1959, 29.83. 2. तादृशी जायते बुद्धिर्व्यवसायश्च तादृशः। __ सहायास्तादृशाः सन्ति यादृशी भवितव्यता ॥ -Quoted by Sūri, Vidyānandi, on Äptamīmāṁsā, Rajnagar, Vik. Sam. 1993, 5. 3. परिणमदि चेदणाए आदा पुण चेदणा तिघाभिमदा । सा पुण णाणे कम्मे फलम्मि वा कम्मणो भणिदा॥ ---Prapacanasära, 2.31. Page #51 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 34 Jaina Ethics as the real point of view. This is a state of complete freedom from attachment and aversion. From practical point of view, however, it is actionconsciousness (karmacetana) which predominates. The aspiant has not as yet risen above the sense of being an agent of an action (kartytvabhāvanā). He has, therefore, not transcended moral obligations of life. He has not wiped away passions and has, therefore, always to choose between the good and bad. He comes the role of human efforts (puruşārtha). We cannot escape the responsibility of being overpowered by passions if we choose to follow the immoral path. A common man cannot be led by consideration of determinism, which is a feature of knowledge-consciousness (jñānacetanā) only. Knowledgeconsciousness is not to be confused with action-consciouness, because both of them are exclusive of each other and cannot exist side by side. A man with action-consciousness aims at knowledge-consciousness, but it is not possible to attain knowledge-consciousness without perfect detachment. The path to supra-ethical plane of life is only through practical path of morality and not through immorality. The doctrine of karman, therefore, does not license us to act in a wanton manner. The ultimate aim is the complete cessation of all activities and attainment of knowlegde-consciousness and from this point of view determinism may be justified, but a man with action-consciousness has no knowledge of future and from his standpoint of view everything is indetermined. It is only his effort and exertion which brings him nearer his goal. Pandita Țodara Mala has put the problem in this way? : The self makes effort and brings about its liberation. Other factors of time or fate or subsidisation of delusive karmans syncronise with human efforts. Efforts on the part of self automatically imply that the time and fate is favourable and the delusive karmans have subsided. It is human efforts (puruşārtha) which leads to liberation ; the other two factors of time and fate are passive. In fact, we have no knowledge of our future ; and even though it may be determined we can depend only on our efforts. 1. Todaramala, Mokşamārgaprakāša, Mathurā, 1948, pp. 279-280. Page #52 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction 35 We have here tried to show that the doctrine of karman of which partial determinism is a corollary, neither teaches us to be immoral or idle nor does it deprive us of the right of improving our lot by overcoming the force of circumstances and past actions. Even an inherited character is the making of the agent and he can blame nobody for impairing his freedom of will except himself. This problem of 'freedom of will can be viewed from another angle also. No action takes place in seclusion. Human beings are also affected by circumstances and environment. The main factor, however, remains human effort (puruşārtha). Here we accept the existence of freedom of will over circumstances. The position is like this : there are two types of causes, (i) substantial cause (Upādānakärana) and (ii) instrumental cause (nimittakäraņa). The inherent power of the agent is the substantial cause aud every other factor is only an instrumental cause. It is the substantial cause which predominates and the instrumental causes merely subsidise. The reality is that no object can interfere with the working of another object, whether animate or inanimate. The self accordingly is the agent of its own psychic modifications (paryāyas). It is only from practical point of view that we speak of ātman as the agent of various activities. Jainism believes in the independence of each and every object. Our freedom implies freedom of others also. Therefore, Kundakundācārya favours svakartvāda, viz. the idea that the self is the agent of its own modification; but rejects parakartyvāda, viz. that the self can interfere in the activities of others. This attitude, which gives subsidiary position to instrumental causes, accepts the doctrine of freedom of will and glorifies human efforts. This attitude makes Jaina ethics inclined towards introversion also. “The self, within self, satisfied with self' is the motto of all individualistic systems of philosophy. This has a far-reaching impact on Jaina ethics, as will be observed during our study at many places. Extroversion, whether it is due to our incapability of self-control or for the cause of social service, never leads us nearer the goal. It is 1. Samayasāra, 372. Page #53 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 36 Jaina Ethics rather withdrawal from the outside world which takes us nearer to self-realisation. Here again, we are faced with the danger of an immoral man defending himself on the ground that he is not the real agent of the action for which he is being blamed. Sütrakṛtānga refers to some schools of philosophy known as akriyāvādins.1 The adherents of Sänkhya and Buddhists are reckoned as Akriyāvādins. According to Sankhya, the purușa or self is transcendental and does not participate in mundane activities. According to Buddhists, and Sunyavādins also, either the self changes every moment or it does not exist at all. It is clear that these systems are faced with a dilemma. Either they have to accept that the self suffers for such actions which he does not perform or they have to deny the common-place experience that the self suffers. The Kriyāvādins are those who ascribe the quality of activity or non-activity to soul (atman).3 Jacobi thinks that they were perhaps the ritualists because Silanka informs us that the Kriyāvādins held constructions of sanctuaries (caitykarma) to be the principal means of attainment of liberation. Sometimes, even the Jainas are mentioned as Kriyāvādins.5 We have explained above the position of Jainism in this respect. To take a concrete example, a murderer may try to get rid of the responsibility of the murder either by (i) saying that he is not the agent of the action or by (ii) contending that the death of the victim has been brought about by his own actions and that he is merely an instrumental cause in the murder. Both of these arguments can be counteracted, according to Jainism, effectively. As regards his first argument, he may not be an agent of death of the victim but he is an agent of entertaining the idea of murdering the victim and then he is also responsible for acting in a way which led to the death of the victim. Therefore, he cannot escape the I. Max Müller (ed.), SBE. Vol. XLV, p. 316. 2. Ibid., p. 316, foot-note 3. 3. Ibid., p. 83, foot-note 2. 4. Ibid., p. 242, foot-note 3. 5. Ibid., p. 319, foot-note 2. cf. Mahāvagga, Bihar, 1956, 6.19.31. Page #54 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Introduction 37 moral responsibility. Similarly, we can answer his second argument : though he is an instrumental cause as far as the death of the victim is concerned, yet he is the substantial cause of the idea of violence in which the victim had no hand. Thus the realisation of predominance of substantial cause should lead to self-absorption and not to wanton activities. Conclusion ☺ rain Ethic set2 We have tried to discuss some fundamental problems of Jaina ethics in this chapter. From this discussion some of the chief characteristics of Jaina ethics can also be inferred. Here, below we mention a few of the salient features of Jaina view of life : Firstly, Jaina ethics is based on the fundamental doctrine of non-absolutism (anekāntavāda). This has saved Jaina-ethics from being one-sided. Jaina ethics always takes into account all the different views and tries to reconcile them. We have seen, for example, that various factors of time, nature, fate, accident and matter find their proper place in Jaina view of life. The approach of Jainism towards opponent schools of thought is constructive and not destructive. We can mention how non-absolutistic view led to the balanced view between such opposite conceptions as that of practical morality and transcendental morality, between fate and human efforts, between kartrvāda, and akartyvāda and between the efficacy of substantial cause and instrumental cause. Many more instances can be added to the list. In fact, we shall feel the impact of non-absolutism at every step during the course of our study. All other characteristics of Jaina view of life may be said to be the corollory of this one main characteristic. Secondly, Jaina ethics does not confuse the science of spirituality (mokşaśāstra) with science of social righteousness (dharmaśāstra). It has thus been able to distinguish the essential nature of dharma from its non-essential beliefs, which change from time to time and place to place. The acts of public welfare (istāpūrta) can be dealt with separately in books of social sciences; but they should not be confused with the essential problem of ethics which is emancipation. On account of the influence of sister religions like Hinduism, the Page #55 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 38 Jaina Ethics Jainācāryas also spoke of social duties, including duties towards city, nation and family; but they never confused them with Mokṣaśāstra, which-they are very clear on this point-deals with the conquest of animal passions (kaṣāyavijaya) in man. Thirdly, Jaina ethics lays emphasis on the unity of faith, knowledge and conduct. Thus Jaina ethics is not merely a system giving certain code of morality, but it is a religion to be lived in practice. There are many adherents of Jainism, both among householders and monks, who scrupulously practise the rules of conduct in their lives. Thus, it is a living system of ethics. Its study becomes more fascinating if we compare the lives of the present Jaina householders and monks with the rules given in their scriptures. Equal emphasis on faith, knowledge and conduct saves Jaina ethics from being either a mere speculation of philosophy or merely a religion of rituals. Fourthly, Jaina ethics assigns primary place to the life of a monk and the life of a householder occupies only a secondary place. It is due to this fact that Jaina ethics lays more emphasis on individual and ascetic virtues than social and positive virtues. The ultimate aim of life being liberation, nothing short of complete renunciation of the mundane life could satisfy Jaina ācāryas. on Fifthly, Jaina ethics is based neither on oneness of life as in Vedanta, nor on momentary nature of self as in Buddhism. It is based on equality of life. Basically, all souls are equal. Therefore, no wonder that such precepts as non-violence in Jainism take into account not only the human beings or animals or insects but even plant-life or one-sensed elemental life, like water etc. Sixthly, the social organisation as anticipated by Jaina ethics, does not make any distinction on the basis of caste, creed or colour. At present, however, the Jaina society has borrowed caste system from Hinduism and observes it as strictly as the latter. Page #56 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CHAPTER II THE METAPHYSICAL BACKGROUND We have already spoken of the close relation of ethics and metaphysics in the foregoing chapter. The Daśavaikālika Sūtra asks, "one, who does not know the self and the nonself, how can he know the path to self-control (samyama)”.1 In this connection, we have also referred to the seven predicaments of Jainism. We propose to elaborate the following seven predicaments in the present chapter as they form the metaphysical background of Jaina ethics : 1. Self (jiva) 2. Non-self (ajiva) 3, 4. The inflow of kārmic matter ( āśrava) and bondage (bandha). 5, 6. Checking (samvara) and shedding (nirjarā) of kārmic matter. 7. Liberation (mokşa).3 The Nature of Self (jiva) The first of these predicaments is ‘self' (jiva). Self is subject as well as object of all meditation. The nature of self is, therefore, the most fundamental of all problems. Self is the stay of all our experience. It is the truth of truths. But for it, there is neither any reality nor any truth. The Upanişads According to the Chôndog yopanişad the basic problem of ethics—the removal of misery—can be solved only by selfrealisation. The Brhadāranyakopanişad clearly says that it is 1. Daśavaikālika, 4.12 2. Supra, p. 13. 3. Tattvärthasūtra, 1.4. 4. acfa tifarhari Crāndogyopanişad. 7.1.3. Page #57 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 40 Faina Ethics the self which we should perceive, hear, of which we should meditate. 1 The Cārvāka view To the category of Cārvāka view philosophers, there is only one reality and that is ‘matter'. Self is body, characterised by consciousness. It is wrong to say that matter cannot possess consciousness. Just as the mixtures of certain ingredients give birth to the power of intoxication, similarly combination of certain material elements results in consciousness. On the dissolution of body, the self is annihilated. The Nyāya-Vaiseșika view The first and foremost to give proof of the existence of soul are the Naiyāyikas. They hold that the existence of a permanent jīvātman can be proved through inference and authority.5 Nyāyasūtra has given the following signs to prove the existence of ātman (i) desire. (ii) hatred, (iii) effort, (iv) pleasure, (v) pain and (vi) consciousness. Vaiseșikasūtra added the following to these : (i) The vital airs----prāna and apāna (ii) the closing and opening of eyelids, (iii) state of living (iv) the movements of mind; and (v) the affections.? The Nyāyavaiseșika systems hold that ātman is essentially non-conscious and consciousness becomes manifest in it only by its association with mind, sense-organs and objects of contact. 8 The state of liberation is, therefore, a state of complete non I. आत्मा वारे द्रष्टव्यः श्रोतव्यो मन्तव्यो निदिध्यासितव्यः । -Byhadăranyakopanişad, 2.4.5. 2. gaarufalatozaa Catari Sarvadarśanasangraha, p. 3. 3. किण्वादिभ्यो मदशक्तिवच्चैतन्यमुपजायते। Ibid., p. 2. 4. Seat STIFT I Brhaspatisütra 2.4.12. Quoted in Ibid., p. 3. 5. Vätsyäyana on Nyāyasutra, 1.1.9. 6. Nyāyasūtra, 1.1.10. 7. Vaiseșikasūtra, 3.2.4. 8. Jayantabhatta on Nyāyas ātra, Benaras, 1934, pt. II, 1.1.9., pp. 4-7. Page #58 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Metaphysical Background consciousness. Vātsyāyana clearly states that there can be no bliss in the state of liberation.1 The Sankhya system The Sankhya system believes in a permanent soul,2 but all visible conscious activities of knowing, feeling and willing are attributed to the workings of three gunas of matter attached to it. The conception of lingasarira or subtle body is peculiar to the Sankhya system. It is this subtle body which is the substratum of consciousness, which gets awakened by its association with soul. This subtle body is also the vehicle of merit and demerit. It accompanies the soul on its wanderings from one body to another.3 Conscious life is a bondage of pain which includes pleasure also. Salvation means the existence of soul individually in an isolated condition free from all conscious activities after the dissolution of the subtle body. Thus, according to Sänkhya, it is the lingasarira, which is bound; the soul remains detached.4 The Purvamimāṁsā The existence of atman as distinguished from body, is implied in the Purvamimāṁsā system. Attainment of heaven by performing actions implies that alman is different from body. In this connection, the arguments given by the Vedantist are acceptable to Purvamimämsä also. But it does not believe in the unity of soul. It attributes the qualities of knowledge, activity and experience to the soul.5 .. 41 The Vedanta school All systems given above, except the Carvaka system, are dualistic and realistic in nature. Vedanta, on the other hand, is monistic in nature. It believes that all reality is reduced 1. Vätsyāyana on Nyayas ütra, 1.1.22, 2. Sankhyakärikā. 17. 8 3. Ibid., 40-42. 4. Ibid., 62. 5. Radhakrishnan, S., Indian Philosophy, London. 1956, Vol. II, pp. 407-409. Page #59 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Faina Ethics to one in the ultimate analysis. This system is diametrically opposed to Cārvāka in as much as Cārvāka holds matter to be the only reality whereas Vedānta holds spirit to be the only reality. As far as its realisation is concerned, it is the substratum and subject of all knowledge, and therefore, selfevident.1 Sankarācārya in his commentary upon Brahmas ütra has explained the oneness of all souls. The reality of self is infinite, the unreality which is to be got rid of is finite. Mention may also be made of the distinction of empirical self and transcendental self. Empirical self is a creation of illusion. The transcendental self is, on the other hand, free from all miseries. All moral responsibilities lie with the empirical self. The Jaina view Neminātha Siddhanta Cakravarti gives the following nine attributes of self. According to Brahmadeva's commentary these nine attributes stand in contradiction to one or the other on to one or the other school of thought. We give these nine attributes and explain them according to the commentary of Brahmadeva : (i) It is a conscious entity. Here self is conceived as distinct from matter. This, according to Brahmadeva, refutes the Cārvāka view of self. (ii) It is endowed with apprehension and knowledge this refutes the Naiyāyika view of self. (iii) It is an intangible entity. By saying this the Mimāṁsā school of thought is rçfuted. (iv) It is the agent of actions. This quality is by way of refutation of Sārkhya system. (v) It is co-extensive with the body which is animated by it. This view refutes the views of Nyāya, Mimāṁsā and Sārkhya systems. (vi) It is the enjoyer of the fruit of its actions. This goes to refute the momentary theory of the Buddhists. (vii) It passes through births and deaths. This view goes against the followers of Sadāśiva cult, which most probably 1. Sankara on Vedāntas útra, Bombay, 1917, 2.3.7. 2. Dasgupta, S., A History of Indian Philosophy, Cambridge, 1932, Vol. I, p. 476. Page #60 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Metaphysical Background 43 held the view that the phenomena of transmigration is merely an illusion and that the soul is ever liberated. (viii) It gets liberation. This goes against the view of Mimämsakas and Cārvāka. (ix) It has a natural potentiality of upward motion. This quality has been stated by way of refutation of Māṇḍalika philosophy 1 even The nine qualities of self given above fairly summarise the Jaina view of self. It may be pointed out that though the different systems of philosophy have many differences about the nature of self from the point of view of metaphysics, they do not differ regarding the basic moral principles which are the only means of self-realisation. For example the fifth quality, mentioned above, viz. whether the self is atomic in size or all-pervasive or it expands and contracts according to the size of body, does not affect the ethical behaviour and, therefore, need not detain us. The fourth quality, mentioned above, viz., whether ātman is the agent or not is rather significant. Another question of importance is whether atman is endowed with consciousness or not. Last, but not the least, is the question of oneness or otherwise of soul. The empirical self and the transcendental self The differences in various schools of thought regarding these problems, are not so important ethically. A clear distinction is to be made between the empirical self and transcendental self. From empirical point of view, the self is the agent of actions and it undergoes such experiences as those of pain and pleasure. The Purvamīmāṁsā school seems to emphasise the empirical nature of self. From transcendental point of view, the self is pure, unalloyed and free from material pollution. The Sänkhya system seems to emphasise this aspect of self. Jainism, true to its tradition of non-absolutism, takes both these aspects into consideration together. The empirical 1. Dravyasangraha, Delhi, 1956, 2. 2. Samayasara, 7. Page #61 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 44 Jaina Ethics self is the self with kärmāņa sarira. We have adṛsta in Nyāyavaiśeşika and kāraṇa sarira (casual body) in Sankhyayoga corresponding to kārmāṇasarira of Jainism. In Vedanta also, we have a conception of empirical self which, though an illusion, is to be accepted for all practical purposes. As far as transcendental nature of self is concerned, it is, according to Jaina view, possessed of only one distinguishing, quality of consciousness, which distinguishes it from matter.1 Here Jainism resembles more or less the Sankhya and Vedanta systems and differs from Nyāyavaiśeşika and Pūrvamîmāṁsā who, as already pointed out, do not consider consciousness as the essential quality of self. The transcendental nature of self means its state of pure existence. The self, which is bound, gets emancipated by efforts and shines in its pure intrinsic form. Different Categories of empirical self While making this distinction between the empirical and transcendental nature of self, we have seen that it is not possible to classify transcendental self into any categories. But the empirical self is classified into many categories from different points of view. A brief description of these categories of empirical self will be helpful in understanding the Jaina doctrines of ethics, especially the doctrine of non-violence. Based on intellect (manas)2 From the point of view of intellect, the jivas are of two types: (i) Having a mind. jivas of this class are possessed of a faculty of distinguishing between right and wrong. Some of the five-sensed jivas are included in this category e.g. men. (ii) Having no mind. All the jivas having one to four senses as also some of the five-sensed jivas are included in this category. Based on biology3 From the point of view of biology, the jivas are of two 1. ... णिच्चयणयदो दु चेदणा जस्स । Dravyasangraha, 3. 2. Tattvärthasutra, 2. 11. 3. Ibid., 2.12,14. Page #62 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Metaphysical Background 45 types : (i) mobile and (ii) immobile. The latter include the four elemental-bodied jivas, viz. (a) earth-bodied (prthvikāyika), (b) water-bodied (apkājika), (c) fire-bodied (tejaskāyika), (d) air-bodied (vāyukāyika) and (e) vegetable-bodied (vanaspatikāyika).1 All these immobile jīvas have only one sense of touch. These jivas do not explicitly manifest the signs of life. But since they also show the tendency to grow and decay, they are supposed to be possessed of life. The Jaina doctrine of non-violence is, therefore, not confined only to men or animals but embraces these mute, immobile jīvas also. The mobile souls, have two to five senses. The onesensed (ekendriya) souls have four prāņas (vitalities) viz. touch, power of body, age and respiration. The two-sensed souls have six prāņas, the above four plus the sense of taste and power of speech. The three-sensed souls add to these six, the sense of smell. The four-sensed souls add to the above seven, the sense of sight. All five-sensed souls add to the above eight, the sense of hearing: whereas the rational (samanaska) five-sensed souls have one more prāna, the power of mind. 3 Thus, though all souls are equal in their transcendental form, they vary in degrees of prāṇas from empirical point of view. It is this distinction which makes taking of vegetable life less violent than taking away animal life or human life. Western View Vs. Indian View Though it is neither possible nor desirable to deal with Western view of self in detail here, yet some important points may be noted because Western thinkers have also contemplated on the problem of self with the same enthusiasm as Eastern thinkers have done. The common-place view of man's personality, resembl. ing more or less Cārvāka way of thinking, is put by W. James in these words : “In its widest possible sense, however, a man's ME is the sum-total of all that he can call his; not only his 1. Tattvārthas útra, 2.13. 2. Pujyapāda on Ibid., 2.30. 3. Ibid., 2.24. Page #63 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Jaina Ethics body and his psychic powers, but his clothes, and his house, his wife and children, his ancestors and friends, his reputation and work, his lands and horses, and yacht and bank account. All these things give him the same emotions. If they wax and prosper, he feels triumphant; if they dwindle and die away, he feels cast down; not necessarily in the same degree for every thing, but in much the same way for all”,1 Obviously, W. James is enumerating the possessions of the self but not the possessor, who is the real self. This tendency of identifying the self with non-self is said to be the result of infatuation in Jainism. In this respect, Mr. Hume observes : “For my part when I enter most intimately into what I call ‘myself', I always stumble on some particular perception or other, of heat or cold, light or shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure. I never can catch 'myself' at any time without a perception, and never can observe anything but the perception. When my perceptions are removed for any time, as by sound sleep, so long am I insensible of 'myself', and may truely be said not to exist." W. James has identified the self with external objects whereas Mr. Hume has the inner ideas of love and hatred etc. identified with the self. This identification of the self either with the external possession (bāhyaparigraha) or with inner possession (āntarikaparigraha ) is natural to man who is to get rid of them through knowledge and self-realisation. Thus, there is a basic difference between the Eastern approach and Western approach to the problem of self and personality. This is how Zimmer has summarised this : The term “personality' is derived from the Latin word 'persona' which means the mask that is worn over his face by an actor. Indian philosophy insists upon discriminating between the actor and the mask, which is not the true self, but only a veil that hides it. Western philosophy, on the other hand, has annulled this distinction. The 'self' and the mask of 1. James, William, Psychology, New York, 1920. p. 176. 2. Hume, David, A Treatise of human Nature, London, 1951, Vol. I, p. 239. Page #64 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 47 Metaphysical Background personality have become identical in the West. Indian philosophy, on the other hand, aims at piercing through the layers of manifest personality so as to arrive at the actor of life, who from times immemorial has been assuming various personalities.' This fundamental difference between the East and West makes it difficult to appeciate the ethical conceptions of each other. The West is engaged in developing means for full growth of personality whereas the East is concerned with the inner self, which is hidden behind the visible personality and is far beyond the limits of this short span of our life. Non-self (ajiva) The views about the matter can be summarised by classifying them into two categories. The first category of thinkers holds that every outer object is a projection of mind. Vedānta amongst orthodox systems and Yogācāra sect of Buddhism are of this view. The other group of thinkers holds that perception of mind is an image of the real, outside world. With the exception of the above mentioned two schools, all systems of Indian philosophy belong to this category. The Cārvāka system Amongst realists, the Cārvāka system holds the first place. They hold that the earth, water, fire and air are real and they are the only reality. They attribute even consciousness to matter 3 The Sänkhya system Sārkhya system is dualistic. In addition to Prakyti, it believes in furuşa also. But the conception of praksli in Sārkhya is that even such conscious objects as mind or intellect are the outcome of praksti. This praksti is subtler than the atoms of Nyāya-vaiseșika system. It has three guņas, sattva, rajas and tamas. It is called avyakta because it is not manifest, pradhāna because it is the primary cause of universe. The effects (vikytis) 1. Zimmer, H., Philosophies of India, pp. 236-37. 2. Sarvadarśanasangraha, p. 2. 3. Tart: narogareiri i Ibid., p. 7. Page #65 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 48 Jaina Ethics of this praksti are sixteen, the five jñānendriyas, five karmendriyas, mind and the five elements. The seven prakstivikrti, mahattattva, ahankāra and five tanmätrās are also the effect of prakrti.1 Thus excepting puruşa, which is neither a cause nor an effect, praksti is the cause of every object in this world. The cause, according to Sārkhya, is not fundamentally different from effect. This is known as satkāryavāda. The Nyāya-vaiseșika system The Nyāya-vaiseșika system believes that effect is basically different from the cause. This is known as ārambhavāda. The matter or praksti is not held to be one in Nyāyavaiseșika system. It is composed of atoms (parmāņu). The sixth part of a dust particle which is visible in the rays of sun coming from a ventilation is called a paramāņu. The combination of two such paramāņus, form one dvyaņu, three dvyanus form one trasareņuka and four trasareņukas form one catureņuka. It is only trasareņuka which can be perceived. It is from catureņukas that the creation proceeds. Thus Vaiseșika is a pluralistic system which holds that matter has its own independent existence. The Mimāṁsā system As far as Pūrvamimāṁsā is concerned, many of the thinkers believe in paramāņuvāda but others do not. Even those who believe, differ from Vaiseșikas regarding its size. They believe that paramāņu can be perceived and the dust particles are visible in the rays of the sun.. I. Sänkhyakärikā, 3. 2. Sānkhyakārikā, 9. Bahaduri, S. Studies in Nyāyavaiseşika, Metaphysics. Poona, 1947, p. 82. 4. Ibid., pp. 76-81. 5. Afina 71934fcua qara: 1 ślokavārtika, Madras, 1940, p. 348. 6. जालरन्ध्रविसरद्रवितेजो जालभासुरपदार्थविशेषान् । अल्पकानिह पुनः परमाणून् कल्पयन्ति हि कुमारिलशिष्याः ।। Mānameyodaya, Madras, 1933, p. 164. Page #66 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Metaphysical Background The Vedānta system Vedānta believes that the cause, or Brahman, is real (sat) whereas the effect or the world is unreal. This is known as vivart avāda, 1 In the Brahmas ütra , it has been clearly brought out that prakrti itself cannot act. How can insentient prakrti change into this universe without the supervision of a sentient God ? Thus Sāmkhya view has been contradicted. Neither Vaiseșika view is upheid as right. How can insentient atoms combine into a systematic universe ? Even adrsta which is supposed to govern the atoms, is insentient. The praksti, therefore, accord ing to Vedānta is an effect of Brahman and has no independent existence. The Jaina view Dr. Radhakrishnan presents the Jaina view with regard to materialism and monism in these words : "To regard the intelligent subject as the product of five elements is as fruitless from the ethical point of view as to make out that the variety of world is a manifold presentation of the one intelligent principle.''3 The correctness of this view is upheld by the fact that materialism shows no regard for ethical principles, whereas Vedānta thinks monism correct only from philosophical point of view; for all practical purposes, where ethical principles are involved, it accepts the reality of material world as much as any other system. According to Jainism, therefore, matter is as real as spirit. In this, Jainism agrees with realistic systems. It agrees with Samkhya that self ( puruşa) and matter (prakrti) are two different entities. But it does not agree with Sāṁkhya regarding the inactivity of purusa and oneness of praksti. Matter consists, according to Jainism, of atoms. But the Jaina conception of atoms is different from Nyāyavaiseșika view. The atoms, according to Jainism, are far more subtler than conceived by Nyāyavaiseșika. 1. Upadhyāya, Baladeva, Bhārtīyadarśana, Benaras, 1948, P, 442, 2. Sankara on Vedāntasūtra, 2.2.12-18. 3. Radhakrishnan, $. Indian Philosophy, Vol. I, p. 312, Page #67 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 50 Faina Ethics Six substances ( dravyas) As regards non-self, Jainism holds that there are five nonsentient substances; dharma (medium of motion ), adharma (medium of stay), ākāśa (space), pudgala (matter) and kāla (time). If we add self to it, we get the six dravyas (substances) in all. Starting with matter, every atom of matter is possessed of touch, taste, smell and colour.1 Matter, composed of these atoms, forms the basis of body, speech, mind and vital airs (prāņa, apāna etc.).2 Worldly enjoyment, pain, life and death are also caused by matter. 3 As for sound, it is not held to be the quality of ākāśa as by the Nyāyavaiseșikas. Sound is produced by matter, but it is not its quality. The other forms of non-self : dharma, adharma and ākāśa (space) have one substance each. All of them are motionless. The dharma and adharma occupy limited units of space whereas ākāśa occupies unlimited units.? Out of these, dharma and adharma are the medium of motion and rest, respectively. They are said to be occupying the whole inhabited space of universe (lokākāša).' The idea of these two substances is peculiar to Jainism. No other system of philosophy ever conceived of these two. Just as space gives room, time effects change, similarly dharma and adharma are the medium of motion and rest. Space is infinite, but the universe is finite and it is due to these two substances. Beyond universe (lokākāśa) no object can move because of the absence of these two substances. Thus a limit is put on universe by these two substances. The function of space is to give room to all substances.10 1. Tattavārthasūtra, 5.23, 2. Ibid., 5.19. 3. Ibid., 5.20. 4. Ibid., 5.5. 5. Ibid., 5,6. 6. Ibid., 5.7. 7. Ibid., 5.9. 8. Ibid., 5.17. 9. Ibid., 5.18. 10. Ibid., 5.18. Page #68 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Metaphysical Background Kāla or time is also a substance. The time-substance consists of many samayas (the smallest unit of time consisting of the period taken in going of the smallest particle of matter from one pradeśa to another pradeśa). Nature of reality Having discussed the general nature of the six dravyas or substances, we are faced with the question of definition of sat or reality. These six dravyas—the self, the matter, the time, the space, and dharma and adharma-are characterised by sat. What is sat ? We have, on one hand, Vedāntins who define sat as unchangeable in all three times. According to this definition transcendental self or Brahman is the only reality, everything else being changeable. Buddhism, on the other hand, thinks that there is nothing permanent in this universe as everything, whether self or non-self, is undergoing change every moment. The Sāṁkhya philosophy adopts a middle course and holds purușa to be of permanent nature without change whereas prakrti is held to be permanent with change. The Jaina view in this respect is based on its general principle of non-absolutisin; and reality, according to Jainism, consists of continuity with change.' Substance is not only the constant substratum but also its changing modes.2 The essence of a substance is never annihilated and that is the idea in saying that an object is permanent. Sometimes the unchangeable essence of the substance is taken into consideration (dravyārthikanaya) and sometimes its modification (paryāyārthikanaya ). Both of them are equally real. The substance (dravya) does not change but the modes (paryāya) change every moment. Thus, though the substance changes in appearance, it remains the same in essence, just as a piece of gold is permanent with regard to its substratum, even though it may be changing with regard to its modifications like necklace, anklet, ear-rings etc., just as the ocean is permanent with regard to its water but it is ever-changing 1. 2. 3. 4. Tattvärthasūtra, 5.29. Ibid., 5.37. Ibid., 5.30. Ibid., 5.31. Page #69 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 52 Faina Ethics with regard to its waves rising within it. Change means disappearance of previous state of modification (paryaya) and appearance of a new one with continuity of the same substratum (dravja). We cannot, and should not, reject any one of the two-the continuity and the change-because one is impossible without the other. Jainism reconciled the absolute permanency (kūṭasthanityata) of Vedanta with momentariness (kṣaṇikatā) of Buddhism, holding that neither the change is sheer illusion nor the permanency underlying the change is unreal. Yamakami Sōgen has interpreted Buddhist view in a way which comes very near to Jainism. Answering the objections of Sankara against Buddhists, he says: The substratum of everything is eternal and permanent. What changes every moment is merely the phase of a thing, so that it is erroneous to affirm that, according, to Buddhism, the thing of the first moment ceases to exist when the second moment arrives.1 We may not go into philosophical discussion of this metaphysical problem of the definition of reality, for we are dealing with the metaphysics only in its relation to ethics. But it may be pointed out that any moral system can be easily based on the Jaina conception of reality. The contact of the self with the non-self Before we proceed to deal with the other predicaments of Jainism, it will not be out of place to consider an important problem of philosophy. The self and non-self are the two basic categories but they do not exist exclusive of each other. Had it been so, there would have been no problem of birth and death at all. All living beings are the combination of both the self and the non-self. All problems arise from this union and are solved with their disunion. Self, independent of matter, is as already stated, possessed of four infinite intrinsic qualities (anantacatuştaya), and with the separation of the self from the non-self, every problem is solved. So the question is how self comes into contact with nonself. Self is intangible, whereas matter is tangible. Can there 1. Sōgen, Yamakami, Systems of Buddhist Thought, Calcutta, 1912, p. 134. . Page #70 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 53 Metaphysical Background 1 be a union of the intangible with the tangible? When did this union between the self and matter first occur? These are the questions which should be answered. The question as to when the union of soul with matter occurred for the first time cannot arise, since this is a beginningless relation.1 As for the relation of the tangible matter with intangible soul, just as knowledge inspite of its being nontangible gets obliterated into the influence of wine, similarly self, though intangible, gets his qualities obstructed under the influence of tangible kārmāņa particles. Moreover, the soul, in its state of bondage, is conceived to be tangible.2 The union between the body and soul is made possible by the medium of kārmāṇaśarīra which, though made up of tangible material, is very subtle.3 The cause of misery-the inflow af Karmic matter and Bondage The two predicaments, self and non-self, discussed so far, answer mainly such metaphysical curiosity as 'who am I ?' and 'what is the nature of the universe?' The remaining five predicaments are mainly the results of thinking on such ethical problems as 'what is the cause of misery ?' and 'how misery can be stopped?' The coming chapters will attempt to answer these enquiries. But, herebelow, we deal with these predicaments in a nut-shell so as to give a bird's eye view of what we propose to discuss later on in some detail. The Upanisadic view Cārvāka represented a common man's view that either lack of worldly possessions or some mental or physical disability is the cause of misery. This was the first answer that reason afforded to the question. It is, however, in the Upanisads that the limitations of this answer have been brought out. The real reason of misery lies deeper than it appears to be, at the surface. It is not finitude which can give us happiness; only infinitude can lead us to happiness. The transient world of birth, old 1. Pañcadhyayi, Indore. Vir Nir-Sam 2444, 2.35-36. 2. Ibid.. 2.57. 3. Ibid., 2.60. 4. यो वै भूमा तत्सुखं नाल्पे सुखमस्ति । -Chandogyopaniṣad, 7.23.1. Page #71 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Faina Ethics age, and death is full of sufferings. It is this basic assumption of the Upanișads which brings Indian ethics out of the meshes of blind hedonism. The Buddhist view It was felt at the time of Lord Buddha that even though the Upanişads rejected the hedonism of Cārvāka, they have their own limitations. They could not, for example, openly challenge the authority of the Vedas, which preached performance of sacrifice, involving violence. It seems that the Upanişads were more concerned with the abstract metaphysical aspect of the whole problem, rather than concrete ethical path of liberation. This accounts for Lord Buddha's rejection of abstract metaphysics and emphasis on the moral character. He deeply felt the transient nature of everything in the universe. To him all objects of enjoyment seemed empty shows, unsubstantial and impermanent. He gave the following chain of twelve causes of misery : (i) Jarāmaraņa (ii) Jāti (iii) Mada (iv) Upādāna (v) Trşņā (vi) Vedanā (vii) Sparśa (viii) Sadāyatana (ix) Nämarūpa (x) Vijñāna (xi) Saṁskāra (xii) Avidyā.? The Sārkhya System In Sāṁkhya nescience or avidyā is held to be the root cause of misery. Nescience means absence of distinction between the two categories of prakrti and puruṣa. Misery really belongs to prakrti but we wrongly attribute it to self. It is this perversity of knowledge (viprayaya) which leads to the following five miseries : (i) Nescience (Avi dyā) (ii) Egoism ( Asmitā) (iii) Attachment (rāga) (iv) Hatred ( dveșa ) (v) Fear of death ( abhiniveśa). All these afflictions are only the varieties of avidyā in as much avidyā pervades them all.3 This avidyā, according to 1. Visuddhimagga, Part II, Benaras, 1943, Chapter 17. 2. अविद्यास्मितारागद्वेषाभिनिवेशाः । – Yogas ūtra 2.3. 3. सर्व एवामी क्लेशा अविद्याभेदाः कस्मात् सर्वेष्वविद्यवाभिप्लवते। --Vyāsa on Yogas ātra 2.4. Page #72 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Metaphysical Background Yogas ātra, consists in taking transitory, impure, pain and nonself to be eternal, pure, happiness and self.1 The Nyāya system The immediate cause of misery, according to Nyāya, is birth (janma). This birth is the result of those activities which are prompted by attachment (rāga), aversion (dveşa) and infatuation (moha).2 From attachment arise the following five defects which lead to misery : (i) Love (kāma) (ii) Selfishness (matsara) (iii) Longing (sprhā) (iv) Hankering ( trşņā) (v) Greed (lobha). Aversion also gives birth to the following five defects : (i) Anger (krodha) (ii) Jealousy (irsyā) (iii) Envy (as āyā) (iv) Malice (droha) (v) Resentment (amarşa ). Infatuation is the cause of the following four defects : (i) Error (mithyājñāna) (ii) Suspicion (vicikitsā) (iii) Pride (māna) (iv) Negligence (pramāda ).3 These fourteen defects, in short, are the causes of misery. Out of these, infatuation is the worst which breeds attachment and aversion. The Mimāṁsā systems According to Pūrvamimāṁsā, any infringement of the duties, laid down by the Vedas leads to misery,5 Vedānta, on the other hand, allows only nityanaimittikakarmans and thinks that even performance of kāmyakarmans is a cause of bondage. The performance of nityanaimittika karman, however, is necessary for the purification of mind. 1. afacarafag arichy facrafagaraistifatfami' -Yogasūtra 2.5. 2. तत्त्रराश्यं रागद्वेषमोहार्थान्तराभावात् । - Nyāyas ūtra, 4.1.3. 3. Vätsyāyana on Ibid., 4.1.3. 4. agi hta aratamata hatia: 1 Nyāyas ütra,, 4.1.6. 5. cf. Mimāṁsādarśana, 1.1.2. 6. Sankara on Gitā, Bombay, 1936, 18.10. Page #73 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ faina Ethics According to Vedānta, it is the deceptive nature (Māyā) of the universe which has held us in bondage. A mind, purified by karman and stabilised by upāsanā, gets its veil of igno. rance removed by knowledge. So, according to Vedānta, the root cause of misery is nescience. The Jaina view The cause of misery is dealt with under two heads in Jainism : (i) Inflow of kārmic matter (afrava), and (ii) Bondage (bandha). We shall deal with both of them. 1. Inflow of kārmic matter (äśrava ) All activities of body, speech and mind, cause inflow of kārmic matter. These activities, if good, cause the inflow of meritorious karmans leading to worldly happiness. If, these activities are bad they cause the inflow of demeritorious karmans leading to misery. At first sight it would appear as if only bad activities are to be avoided since they lead to misery. But even good activities are to be checked ultimately. These good activities are, of course, preferable to bad activities from practical point of view, but from real point of view are as much bondage to the soul as the good activities. As we would discuss this problem separately in the following chapter, we leave it for present, and proceed to explain which activities are good and which bad. It may be mentioned here that the force of holding the soul in bondage comes from four basic passions (kaşāya), viz. anger, pride, hypocrisy, and greed. Some subtle activities force inflow of kārmic matter (iryāpatha) even in the advanced stages of spiritual progress. This is not important from the point of view of morality. It is only sāmparāyika inflow, backed by the four passions, which causes the cycle of births and rebirths. The activitics which lead to the sāmparāyika inflow of kārmic matter are 39 in all.4 1. Tattvärthasūtra, 6.1-2. 2. Ibid., 6.3-4. 3. Ibid., 6.5 and 8.2. 4. Pūjyapāda on Ibid., 6.5. Page #74 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ - 37 Metaphysical Background These activities are given below : I-V. Five activities of five senses. VI-IX. Four activities of four kasāyas. IX-XIV. Five activities arising out of the non-observance of five cardinal moral virtues of non-violence, truth, nonstealing, celibacy and non-possession. XV. Activities strengthening right belief e.g. worship (samyaktvakriyā). XVI. Activities strengthening wrong belief e.g. superstition (mithyātvakriya), XVII. Physical activities (prayogakriyā) XVIII. Tendency to neglect the vows which have been taken (samādānakriyā). XIX. Walking carefully to avoid injury to the living beings by one's feet (īryāpathakriyā). XX. Tendency to accuse others in anger (prādosikikriyā). XXI. Tendency to hurt others (kāyikikriyā) XXII. Having weapon of violence (adhikaraạikikriyā). XXIII. Having means of giving mental pain (paritāpikikriyā). XXIV. Depriving others of their prāṇas (prānātipātikikriyā). XXV. Desire to see a pleasing form (darśanakriyā). XXVI. Touching a pleasant object (sparśanakriyā). XXVII. Searching for new means of enjoyment (prātyāyikikriyā). XXVIII. Answering call of nature in a place frequented by men, women and animals (samantāpatanakriyā). XXIX. Throwing things on the ground without care (anabhogakriyā). XXX. Doing oneself which should be done by other (svahastakriyā). XXXI. Admiring what is wrong (nisargkriyā) XXXII. Disclosing sins of others (Vidāraṇakriyā). XXXIII. Misinterpreting the injunctions of the scriptures (ājñāvyāpādikikrijā). XXXIV. Disrespect to the injunctions of the scriptures (anākānkşakriyā). XXXV. Engaging in harmful activities (prārambhakriyā). Page #75 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ kriyā). Faina Ethics XXXVI. Attachment to worldly objects (parigrāhiki XXXVII. Deceitfully disturbing one's right faith and knowledge (māyākriyā). XXXVIII. Admiring wrong belief (mithyādarśanakriyā). XXXIX. Not renouncing what should be renounced (apratyākhyānakrijā). This long list of thirty-nine activities is not exhaustive. The basic idea is that any type of activity is the cause of inflow of kārmic matter. Now, to classify these activities into two categories of good and bad, we should know that there are eight types of karmans in all, having 148 sub-varieties, Those eight types of karmans arel.: (i) Knowledge—obscuring karmans (jñānāvaraniya). (ii) Connotation-obscuring karmans ( darśanāvarniya). (iii) Deluding karmans (mohaniya). (iv) Destructive karmans (antarāya). (v) Feeling-breeding karmans (vedaniya). (vi) Family-determining karmans (gotrakarman). (vii) Age-determining karmans (āyuşakarman). (viii) Body-determining karmans (nāmakarman). Sinful activities: The inflow of the first two types of kārmic matter is caused by the following five moral lapses : (i) Condemnation of the learned in the scriptures (pradosa). (ii) Concealing the knowledge (ninhava). (iii) Envy (mätsarya). (iv) Obstructing the progress of knowledge (antarāya). (v) Denying the truth proclaimed by others (āsādanā). (vi) Refutation of truth purposely (Upaghāta). Coming to deluding karmans (mohaniya), they are of two types : (i) Right-belief-deluding (darśanamohaniya) (ii) Right-conduct-deluding (cāritramohaniya). 1. 2. Tattvārthasülra, 8.5 Ibid.,, 6.11 Page #76 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Metaphysical Background 59 The right-belief-deluding karmans are the result of defaming the liberated persons (kevali) or the scripture (śruta) or the church (samgha) or the religion (dharma) or gods (deva), whereas the right-conduct-deluding karmans are the result of intense passionate feelings.2 The fourth type of inflow of kārmic matter results from disturbing others in their activity of charity (dāna), gain (lābha), enjoyment of consumable things (bhoga), enjoyment of non-consumable things (upabhoga) and making use of their power (vīrya), These above four karmans are called ghātik armans as they tend to obscure the real nature of self. The activities enumerated under these four heads, not only lead to worldly misery but also retard the moral progress of the aspirant. The aghāti karmans The remaining four types of karmans have good as well as bad aspect. The good activities lead to worldly happiness and bad activities to worldly miseries. But neither of these four karmans can retard the moral progress of a person in the absence of the ghātikarmans. Vedaniya Coming to the feeling-breeding karmans (vedaniyakarmans ), those which lead to miseries are called asātā and those which lead to worldly happiness are called sātā. The asātāvedaniyakarmans result from the following six activities : (i) pain (duḥkha) (ii) sorrow (soka) (iii) remorse (tāpa) (iv) weeping (ākrandana) (v) killing (vadha) (vi) pathetic moaning (paridevanā). The sātāvedaniya result from the following ten good qualitles.5 (i) Compassion for living beings (bhūtānukampā). 1. Tattvārthas ātra, 6.14. 2. Ibid., 6.15. 3. Ibid., 8.14. 4. Ibid., 6.12. 5. Ibid., 6.13. Page #77 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Jaina Ethics (ii) Compassion for the vowers (vratyanukampā). (iii) Charity (dāna). (iv) Self-control with attachment towards worldly enjoyment (sarāgasamyama). (v) Partial control (samyamāsamyama). (vi) Equanimous submission to the fruition of karman (akāmanirjarā). (vii) Austerities not based on right knowledge (bālatapas). (viii) Contemplation (yoga). (ix) Forgiveness (Ksamā). (x) Contentment (sauca). Gotrakar man The following cause the inflow of low-family-determin ing karmansi : (i) Speaking ill of other (paranindā). (ii) Self-praise (ātmaprasaṁsā). (iii) Concealing the good qualities of others (sadgunā cchädana). (iv) Proclaiming those good qualities in oneself which one does not possess (asadguņodbhedana). The inflow of high-family-determining Karmans comes from the qualities opposite to those mentioned above, by showing humility towards one's superior (nīcai hurtti) and by not being proud of one's achievements (anutseka). ? Ayuşakarmans The age-determining karmans may lead one either to hell or to sub-human life or to human birth or to heaven in the next birth. The inflow of that kärmic matter leading to birth in hell results from too much of sinful activity and attachment.3 Deceitfulness leads to subhuman birth. Less of worldly activity and attachments and humble indisposition leads to human birth. The activities from five to seven, enumerated in the list of sātāvedaniya lead to heavenly birth. 1. 2. 8. Tattvārthas ütra 6.24. Ibid., 6.25. Ibid., 6.16. Ibid., 6.17. Ibid., 6.18. Ibid., 6.20. Page #78 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 61 Metaphysical Background Nāmakarman Crookedness of the mind, body and speech (yogavakratā) and disintegrity (visanvāda) of character lead to bad body-determining karman, whereas the opposite of them lead to good-body-determining karman. Besides, excellent moral character leads to the birth of the soul in a tīrthankara body, Such excellent moral character includes the following sixteen virtues : (i) Purity of right belief (darśanavisuddhi). (ii) Humbleness (vinayasampannatā). (iii) Faultless observance of the five vows (silavrates vanaticāra). (iv) Ceaseless pursuit of right knowledge (abhikşņajñānopayoga). (v) Apprehension of mundane miseries (samvega). (vi) Renunciation according to one's capacity (Saktita styāga). (vii) Practising penance according to one's capacity (faktitastapas). (viii) Service of the saints (sādhusamādhi). (ix) Service of the meritorious (vaiyāvstyakaraña). (x) Devotion to Arhants (arhadbhakti). (xi) Devotion to the Acārya or the head of the orders of saints (ācāryabhakti). (xii) Devotion to the learned saint (bahuśrutabakti). (xiii) Devotion to the scriptures (pravacanabhakti). (xiv) Carefulness in the six essential duties of a saint (āvašyakāparihāņi). (xv) Propagation of the path of liberation (märgapra bhāvanā). (xvi) Affection for one's co-religionist (pravacanava tsalatā). Bondage (bandha) As already pointed, only that inflow of kārmic matter, which is backed by passion, becomes effective. This is called 1. Tattvārthasūtra, 6.61. 2. Ibid., 6.22. 3. Ibid., 6.26. Page #79 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 62 Faina Ethics bondage,1 Without passion, the kārmāņa particles may come and go but they do not affect the soul. This position can be compared to the anāsakti-yoga of the Gitā. To be more elaborate, the causes of bondage are five-fold : (i) Wrong-belief (mithyādarśana) It has five varieties (a) taking only one aspect of truth (ekānta) (b) perverse belief (viparita) (c) scepticism (sambaya) (d) showing equal belief in all religions (vinaya) (e) nescience (ajñāna). (ii) Vowlessness (avirati) It includes lack of compassion for six classes of embodied soul through lack of control over five senses and mind.” (iii) Negligence (pramāda) It includes talks about (a) food (bhojanakathā), (b) women (strikathā), (c) politics (rājyakathā), (d) scandal (deśakathā), lack of control over five senses, four passions, affection and sleep.4 (iv) Passion (kaşāya) These include four degrees of intensities of four passions, viz. (a) pride (māna), (b) deceitfulness (māyā), (c) anger (krodha), (d) greed (lobha) and nine semi-passions.5 (v) Yoga ( activities) These activities are either mental or vocal or physical. (A) Mental activities are either from (a) true mind (satyamana) (b) false mind (asatyamana) or (c)mixed mind (ubhayamana) or (d) neither true nor false mind (anubhayamana). (B) Vocal activities are either (a) true or (b) false or (c) both or (d) none. (C) Physical activities are possible by the seven bodies. 1. Tattvärthas ütra 8.2-3. 2. Pujyapada, on Ibid.. 8.1. 3. Ibid., 8.1. 4. Bhatta Akalarkadeva on Tattvārthasūtra, Calcutta, Translation, p. 806). 5. Pujyapāda on Tattvärthas ütra, 8.1. 1929, 8.1. (Hindi Page #80 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Metaphysical Background (a) Physical (audārika) (b) Physical and kārmic (audārikamiśra) (c) Fluid (vaikriyaka) (d) Fluid with kārmic (vaikrayikamiéra) (c) Ahāraka (f) Ahāraka with physical (āhārakamiśra) (g) Kārmic ( kārmāna). Thus we have fifteen yogas in all.1 The Jaina conception of working of the law of Karman is based in the psychological theory of habit. We sow an action and reap a habit, we sow a habit and reap a character; we sow a character and reap our fate. Repetition of similar actions makes us habituated and we are forced by habit to repeat them. But, as already shown, this does not deprive us of our freedom.2 Human efforts have their own part to play in the whole working of this process. The previous action can be altered, amended, aggravated or affected through exertion (puruşārtha). That is why the ācāryas have asked us to exert and stop the inflow of fresh kārmic matter and also to annihilate the previous karmans. It may also be noted that these karmans have not only psychical impressions ( saṁskāras) but also force physical molecules to be attached to the soul. The processes are known as psychic (bhāva) and material (dravya ) inflow.3 These two aspects of the inflow of kārmic matter mutually influence each other. The various psychic modifications attract the kārmic matter, and give birth to fresh psychic modifications. In its impure state, the soul, overcome by attachment, aversion and delusion, attracts the kārmic matter as magnet attracts needles to itself. This chain of kārmic holds the self bound to the miserable worldly existence. The removal of misery The Buddhistic view The third noble truth, dukkhanirodha, concerns the means of checking misery. The ethical teachings of Lord Buddha are summarised in the following triple jewels4 (triratnas) in 1. Upadhyāya, Baladeva, Bhārtiyadarśana, pp. 182-183. 2. Bhatta Akalankadeva on Tattvārthas utra, 8.1.(Hindi Translation, p. 805). 3. Supra, pp. 32-37. 4. Dravyasangraha, 29-31. . Page #81 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 64 Jaina Ethics the Hinayāna tradition : (i) Conduct (sila), (ii) Meditation (samādhi) (iii) contemplation (prajñā). (i) Conduct includes the observance of the following vows : (a) non-violence (b) non-stealing (c) truth (d) celibacy (e) abstinence from intoxication. These vows are meant for all. The mendicants are asked, in addition, to observe abstinence from (a) evening meals (b) garlands (c) valuable beds (d) music (e) gold and silver. (ii) Meditation, in Buddhism, has been given a special status. (iii) Contemplation includes (a) study (frutamayi) (b) rational thinking (cintāmayi) (d) affirmed knowledge acquired by meditation (samādhijanyaniscaya). These three stage of contemplation are strikingly similar to śravana, manana and nididhyāsana of Vedānta system. The ethical principles of Buddhism can be described from another view-point also. It is the eight-fold path (astāngika mārga) which leads to liberation. These include right attitude (samyagdssti), determination (saṁkalpa), speech (vāk), action ( karmānta), living (jiva) effort (viryam). The Sāṁkhya-yoga According to Sāṁkhya, the discriminating faculty (vivekakhyāti), which makes clear distinction between puruşa and praksti, leads to liberation. In Yoga, which deals with the ethical aspect of that very system, which is metaphysically represented by Samkhya the cardinal moral virtues are said to be five yamās which literally resemble the five vratas of Jainism. Here the Vyāsabhāsya of Yogasūtra clarifies that truth is subservient to nonviolence. A truth, which leads to violence, is said to be virtue in appearance but sin in reality.2 1. Ibid., pp. 181-182. 2. "वागुक्ता सा यदि न वंचिता भ्रान्ता वा प्रतिपत्तिवन्ध्या वा भवेदित्येषा सर्वभूतोपकारार्थ प्रवृत्ता न भूतोपघाताय यदि चैवमप्यभिधीयमाना भूतोपघातपरव स्यान्न सत्यं भवेत् पापमेव भवेत्तेन पुण्याभासेन पुण्यप्रतिरूपकेण कष्टं तमः प्राप्नुयात्तस्मात्परीक्ष्य सर्वभूतहितं सत्यं ब्रूयात् । - Vyāsa on Yogas ūtra, Allahabad, 1912, 2.30. Page #82 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Metaphysical Background In addition to these five yamas, we have the following niyamas also : (i) Purity (sauca). (ii) Satisfaction (santosa), (iii) Penance (tapas), (iv) Study (svādhyāya) and (v) Meditation upon God (isvarapraṇidhāna).1 In addition to yama and niyama, the other principles of eight-fold path of yoga (aṣṭāngayoga) are asana, präṇāyāma, pratyāhāra, dhāraṇā, dhyana, and samadhi, which, respectively, mean mystic posture, control over vital air, withdrawal of senses from outward objects, concentration on one point, continuity of concentration, meditation and complete absorption.2 The Nyayavaisesika view While dealing with the causes of misery under Nyāya system, we have enlisted fourteen moral faults. These faults get a man involved in worldly pursuits (pravṛtti), which lead to the circle of births and rebirths. On the renunciation of these moral faults, the worldly pursuits come to a standI still and the self is released from miseries. In Vaiseşika system, the moral duties are classified under two heads: (i) Common duties (ii) Special characteristic duties. 65 Common duties embrace the following virtues :-(a) Faith (Sraddha) (b) Non-violence (ahimsa) (c) Welfare of all living beings (prāṇihitasādhana) (d) Truth (satya), (e) Non-stealing (asteya), (f) Celibacy (Brahmacarya), (g) Purity of heart (anupadha), (h) Absence of anger (akrodha), (i) Bathing (snāna), (j) Purity of food (pavitradravyasevana), (k) Devotion to deity (devopāsanā), (1) Fasting (upavāsa), (m) Alertness (apramāda).3 As far as the special duties belonging to particular caste or asrama are concerned, the Vaisesika system holds smṛtis to be the authority. All these duties should be performed without any desire for the fruit. This leads to comprehension of reality (tatt 1. Yogasútra, 2.32. 2. Ibid. 2.29. 3. Prasastapādabhasya, Benaras, 1924, p. 640. Page #83 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 66 Faina Ethics vajñāna), which is the means of liberation. Thus desireless performance of the moral duties is the indirect means whereas the real knowledge is the direct means of liberation. The mimāṁsā views According to pūrvamimāṁsā, karmans lead to bondage as well as liberation. There are two theories about the performance of karman. According to Kumārilabhatta, actions can be performed only when one is sure about their yielding the desired fruit (istasādhanatājñāna) whereas, according to Prabhākara, the knowledge that such and such action is prescribed by the Vedas (kāryatājñāna) is enough for engaging one in that duty. Thus, according to Kumārilabhatta, an action is always motivated by a desire whereas according to Prahhākara desire is not necessary. The theory of Prabhākara comes to the niskāmakarmayoga of the Gitā.8 The Pūrvamimāmsā, in any case, lays it down yery clearly that the actions prescribed by the Vedas should be performed, but actions which have been prohibited (nisiddha) by the vedas should be avoided. The actions prescribed by the Vedas are, again, of two kinds : (i) Wishfulfilling actions (kāmyakarma), which include those actions which are to be performed with certain desire in view e.g. svargakāmo yajeta. (ii) Daily and occasional (niytyanaimittika karman), which include such actions as sandhyā and śräddha which are to be performed without any particular motive. 4 Coming so Vedānta, the Sarkara school believes that knowledge is the only means of liberation. This principle has been subsequently elaborated by two followers of Sarkara, Vācaspati Miśra and Suresvarācārya who wrote Bhāmati and Vivarana commentaries, respectively, on the Sārkara Bhāsya of Vedānta. The main difference between the two can be summarised thus : . 1. JANTAIA:STA I -Vaiseșika sūtra, 1.1.4. 2. तत्त्वज्ञानकर्मणोर्मोक्षं प्रति तत्त्वज्ञानस्य साक्षाज्जनकता कर्मणस्तु परम्परयेCOTSTU: I --Kirnävalibhaskara, Benaras, 1920, p. 21. 3. Upadhyāya, Baladeya, Bharatiyadarśana, p. 394 4. Ibid,. pp. 394-395. Page #84 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 67 Metaphysical Background Vācaspati Misra thinks that even after hearing (śravana) of such mahāvākya as 'that thou art' (tattvamasi) one needs contemplation (manana) and meditation (nididhyâsana) also. According to Suresvarācārya, the sentence that thou art is capable of imparting direct knowledge of Brahman. This is the main difference between Bhāmatiprasthāna and Vivaranaprasthāna. In both the cases, however, action is subservient to knowledge. Naiskarmyasiddhi has classified the objects attainable by actions into four : 1. utpădya, 2. āpya, 3. saṁskārya, 4. vikärya. Since ātman is neither of these, therefore, it cannot be realised by action. The Jaina view The Jaina view regarding the removal of misery is classified under two heads : (1) Checking of the inflow of fresh kārmic matter (samvara) and (2) Annihilation of the kārmic matter already accumulated (nirjarā). 1. Checking of the inflow of fresh kārmic matter (samvara) The inflow of fresh kārmic matter can be checked best by not allowing those causes to work which effect the inflow. The means for this check are as follows : (i) Three-fold self-discipline (trigupti) (ii) Five-fold path of vigilance (pañca-samiti) (iii) Ten categorical qualities (daśa-lakṣaṇa-dharma) (iv) Twelve-fold reflections on the nature of the universe (dvādaśānuprakṣā). (v) Equanimous fortitude of twenty-two hardships (dvāvimšati-parisahajaya). I. तस्मान्निविचिकित्सशाब्द-ज्ञान-सन्ततिरूपासना कर्मसहकारिण्यविद्याDET: ra, Vācaspati, on Vedantas útra Bombay, 1917, p. 55. 2. सकृत्प्रकृत्या मद्नाति क्रियावारकरूपभूत् । अज्ञानमागमज्ञानं सांगत्यं नास्त्यतोऽनयोः ।। - Naişkarmyasiddhi, Poona, 1925, 1.67. 3. उत्पाद्यमाप्यं संस्कार्य विकार्यञ्च क्रियाफलम् । नैवं मुक्तिर्यतस्तस्मात् कर्म तस्या न साधनम् ॥ -Ibid., 1.53 Page #85 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 68 (vi) Five types of conduct (pañcacāritra).1 I. Three-fold self-discipline means withdrawal of the mind, body and speech from the mundane activities." II. Five-fold vigilance means carefulness in walking, talking, eating, in handling the objects and in evacuating bowls.3 III. The ten categorical qualities are: (a) forgiveness, (b) humility, (c) straightforwardness, (d) contentment, (e) truthfulness, (f) self-control, (g) penance, (h) renunciation, (i) detachment, (j) chastity.1 IV. The twelve reflections are: Contemplations about (i) transitoriness, (ii) helplessness, (iii) mundane existence, (iv) loveliness, (v) distinctness, (vi) impurity, (vii) inflow of karmic matter, (viii) checking of karmic matter, (ix) annihilation of karmic matter, (x) universe, (xi) rarity of right path and (xii) nature of right path.5 Jaina Ethics V. The twenty two hardships to be endured are: (a) hunger, (b) thirst, (c) cold, (d) heat, (e) mosquitoes (f) nakedness, (g) disgust, (h) women, (i) too much of walking, (j) posture, (k) sleeping, (1) abuse, (m) beating, (n) begging, (o) failure to attain an object, (p) disease, (q) contact with thorns, (r) dirt, (s) respect or disrespect, (t) conceited knowledge (u) lack of knowledge (v) slackness of belief." VI. The five types of conduct are : (a) equanimity (b) recovery of equanimity if one falls from it, (c) purity and completeness in non-violence, (d) freedom from passions except in some subtle form, (e) ideal state of complete freedom from passion." Here we have just given a list of moral virtues that check the inflow of karmic matter. We propose to discuss them in detail while dealing with the conduct of the house-holder anp I. Tattvärthas ütra, 9.2. 2. Pujyapada on Ibid., 9.4. 3. Tattvärthas utra, 9.5. 4. Ibid., 9.6. 5. Ibid., 9.7. 6. Ibid., 9.9. 7. Ibid., 9.18. Page #86 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Metaphysical Background 69 a monk, separately. It may, however, be pointed out that the list of moral virtues given above mentions ascetic and spiritual virtues mainly. As already pointed out this is due to the fact that Jaina thinkers do not mix up the science of spiritualism (adhyatmaśāstra) with sociology (samājasāstra) as some of the Hindu scriptures like Manusmrti have done. Shedding of the accumulated karmic matter (nirjară) Merely checking of the inflow of fresh karmic matter does not remove miseries unless the karmic matter already accumulated is also shed away. This, the Jainism believes, can be done by austerities.1 These austerities are in addition to what has been prescribed above under samvara. Austerities are external and internal. The external austerities include (i) fasting (ii) eating less than one's fill (iii) taking a secret vow to accept the food only if certain conditions, about which no one knows, are fulfilled, (iv) renouncing delicacies, (v) sitting and sleeping in lonely place and (vi) mortifying the body with mental equanimity.2 The internal austerities include: (i) expiation (ii) reverence (iii) service (iv) study (v) detachment and (vi) renunciation.3 All these austerities are propounded mainly with the monk's life in view and we shall take them one by one at proper places. To sum up, it is through the activities of mind, body and speech, tinged with passion, that the karmic matter gets an inflow into the realm of soul. It is, therefore, obvious that when the self is absorbed in its own intrinsic, pure consciousness, shutting out the impure states of desire, aversion and delusion, the inflow of karmic matter does not take place. It is an ideal stage. The aspirant, if he has to act at all, should be very much alert against sinful tendencies in his daily routine. As regards shedding of the previously accumulated karmans, Jainism prescribes performance of penance. This is based on the psychological law of habit. An old habit can be broken only by acting against it forcibly and purposely. Our I. Tattvärthasutra, 9.3. 2. Ibid., 9.19. 3. Ibid., 9.20. Page #87 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Jaina Ethics attachments are deep-rooted and can be uprooted only by hard austerities. It should not be thought that these austerities have any super-natural power of pleasing some gods who can forgive us for our previous acts of omission and commission. It is a simple question of resoluteness of will-power. Repeated blows of voluntary infliction break the old habits and efface those impressions (saṁskāras), which lead to further birth. The state ef liberation The Upanişadic view Except for Cārvāka, who does not believe in existence after death, all other systems of Indian philosophy have conceived of a liberated soul, which after having exhausted all karmans attains perfection. The Upanişads were the first to conceive of such a state. A soul in such a state, according to the Upanişads. is indescribable. This is how rajñavalkya attempts an answer to the question of the nature of a liberated soul : Just as a lump of salt put in water loses its identity and cannot be taken out separately, but in whatever portion of water we taste, we find the salt; so, Maitreyi, does this great reality, infinite and limitless, consisting only of pure intelligence manifesting itself in all these (phenomenal existences), becomes identical with them and there is no phenomenal knowledge.1 The Buddhist view Nirvāṇa, the name for liberation in Buddhist philosophy, means 'extinction'. It implies extinction of the five, viz. forms (rupa), names (sasjñā) the old impressions (saṁskāra), the analytical knowledge (vijñāna) and the feeling of pain and pleasures (vedanā). That nirvāṇa is the state of highest bliss is proved by many passages of Buddhist scriptures.2 Lord Buddha, however, was more concerned with the ethical problem of the removal of misery rather than indulging in such sub 1. Bịhadāranyakopanişad, 2.4.12. 2. fali qift Taft Pali-English Dictionary, p. 364. Page #88 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Metaphysical Background 71 tleties of metaphysical problems as the nature of the liberated soul.1 The Samkhya-Yoga view From what has already been said about the nature of purusa and prakṛti according to Samkhya, it can easily be concluded that in the state of liberation, when the self stands separated from prakṛti, there can be no happiness.2 Happiness and misery are the workings of the gunas. The liberated soul, having gone beyond these gunas, shines forth in pure consciousness. The Nyaya-vaisesika view According to Nyaya, liberation is not a state of bliss but a state of perfect qualitilessness where the self remains in its mere existence. It is a state of complete freedom from pain.3 This state is compared to a deep dreamless sleep. Nyaya holds that since it is the state of complete freedom from pain, the scriptures speak of this state of happiness. In fact, liberation cannot be a state of happiness for happiness is always tainted with pain'. There is no consciousness in a a liberated soul. Therefore, the self remains in a passive state of its original and natural purity unassociated with pleasure, pain, knowledge and will. The Mimāmsā view The purvamimāṁsā did not originally conceive of liberation but of heaven only. The heavenly state is not free from misery but one where all desires are fulfilled. The later authors 1. Dasgupta, Surendranath, A History of Indian Philosophy, Vol. I, pp. 108-109. 2. नानन्दाभिव्यक्तिमुक्तिनिर्धर्मत्वात् । -Samkhyasutra, 5.74. 3. तदत्यन्तविमोक्षोऽपवर्गः । Nyayasutra, 1.1.22. 4. सुषुप्तस्य स्वप्नादर्शने क्लेशाभावादपवर्गः । Ibid., 4.1.63. Page #89 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Jaina Ethics have dealt with liberation also. They hold that release means freedom from pain where the self exists in its pure essence. The Vedānta view In Vedānta, liberation means removal of duality and merger of self with Brahman. In this state, the self shines forth in its intrinsic existence, intelligence and bliss (sat, cit, ānanda). Here everything, having name and form, vanishes as illusory. The Jaina viero Liberation, according to Tattvārthasūtra, is a state free from all karmans due to absence of causes of bondage and shedding of the karmans. The four ghātins (destructive karmans) are the main concern of the aspirant, because the other four aghātin karmans do not stand in the way of liberation. One gets freedom from these karmans gradually as he ascends the fourteen stages of spiritual development. At the end of the twelfth stage, all the ghātin karmans are destroyed and the aspirant gets perfect knowledge, perception, potency and bliss. This conception of liberation comes nearer to that of Vedānta, the only difference being that the self, according to Jainism, does not lose its identity in the emancipated state. After the liberation, the self, which has a natural upward motion, goes right upto the end of the universe (lokākāśa)5 beyond which it cannot proceed due to the absence of dharmāstikāya, the medium of motion. Conclusion To conclude, the following points may be noted regarding our discussion in this chapter : (1) In the first place, even though, the different systems of Indian philosophy disagree about such problems as the 1. Radhakrishnan, S., Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, p. 422-423. 2. Tattvārthasūtra, 10.2.3. 3. Ibid., 10.1. 4. Infra, Chapter VIII. 5. Tattvārthasūtra, 10.5. 6. Ibid., 10.8. Page #90 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 73 Metaphysical Background nature of self or the position of a liberated soul, yet as far as the practical side of morality is concerned, they seldom differ. (2) Secondly in Jainism we find a combination of both types of systems of morality, those which emphasise on knowledge and those which emphasise on conduct and faith. (3) The brief sketch of the fundamentals of Jainism, āšrva, bandha, samvara and nirjarā—in this chapter gives an answer to the question why most of the ethical principles of Jainism are negative in character. Any action prolongs rather than cuts short the mundane existence of the soul. If the actions are good, they lead to birth in favourable circumstances; if they are bad, they lead to birth in unfavourable circumstances. But since the ultimate aim is to get rid of the circle of birth and rebirth, all actions are in reality a source of misery. We shall elaborate this point in the following chapter. (4) The Jaina ācāryas have a tendency to go on enumerating the varieties and subvarieties of a single fact. We shall have more occasions to meet with this tendency during the course of our discussion. This has made the discussion of problems more concrete and objective. Page #91 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CHAPTER III CONCEPTION OF MORALITY Limitations of virtuous Life We have spoken of some moral virtues in the foregoing chapter. These virtues lead to happiness and are to be preferred to vices which lead to misery. But is that the end of morality? We have already noted that worldly happiness is not the ultimate end of morality. Emancipation from mundane existence, which is the ultimate end of life, cannot be attained by mere observance of virtue.1 An inner awakening followed by withdrawal from all activities of life, whether good or bad, is necessary for that. It is a state beyond vice and virtue. One may become worse or better by vicious or virtuous activities, but not perfect. Practical path (vyavahāramārga) This, however, does not mean total obliteration between good and bad. Perfection is a far cry for an ordinary man who has to discharge the normal duties of life. He has to choose between good and bad at every step. For him is prescribed a code of morality which may be called as practical path (vyavahāramarga). Here a clear distinction between good and bad is made. This path is a means and not an end in itself. It ultimately yields place to the supramoral plane of life where one gets rid of normal duties of life. What is necessary is a considered balance between the two, the supra-moral plane of life and the practical code of morality. The practical code of morality serves no good if it does not lead to the higher supra-moral plane of life. Transcendental code of morality, on the other hand, should be no excuse for licentiousness. As long as one becomes perfect I. Pravacanasara, 3.56. 2. Samayasarakalasa, Delhi, 1959, 267. Page #92 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ . 4o Conception of Morality 25 and passes beyond his mundane consciousness completely, he does require a clear distinction between good and bad. The complete conception of morality, therefore, includes both, the practical as well as the transcendental morality, which are inter-related with each other. With this background we proceed to examine this problem, first according to Jainism and then according to other systems of Indian Philosophy. Vice and Virtue · The result of virtues are birth as tirtharkara, gañadhara, sage, universal monarch, Baladeva, Väsudeva, god and vidyādharas and supernatural powers. The result of vices are pain, birth amongst subhumans and bad men, old age, death, disease, misery and poverty etc. It is the motive behind an action which is taken into account and not merely the outer action.2 We have given a list of actions which lead to worldly happiness (sätāvedaniya) as well as those which lead to misery (asātāvedaniya).3 It may be mentioned that both types of these acts are actuated by attachment; in the case of the former it is mild, in the case of the later it is intense. In Kārtikeyānuprekṣā, therefore, vice has been defined as intense passion whereas virtue has been defined as mild passion.4 ! Attachment, however, is present in both the cases. Transcendental morality (niscayamārga) : The ultimate aim is to uproot even the subtlest form of passions. Therefore the relative life of vice and virtue is to be abandoned in favour of a life of pure consciousness (fuddhopayoga). The activities of soul can be classified under three heads : (i) The auspicious activities (subhopayoga), (ii) ! The inauspicious activities (aśubhopayoga), (iii) The pure activities (suddhopayoga). In śuddhopayoga the self remains absorbed in its own nature of consciousness. In śubhopayoga as well as aśubhopagoga, the self becomes extrovert and con 1. Vīrasena on șațkhandāgama, Vol. I, p. 105. 2. A 91997. QuafHathiTia wafail --Pujyapâda on Tattvärthasülra, 6.11. 3. Supra, pp. 59-60 4. Kārtikeyānuprekṣā, go. Page #93 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 76 Jaina Ethics centrates on non-self. Thus from the point of view of Suddhopayoga, Subhopayoga and asubhopayoga are bracketed together under the common name of aŝuddh payoga. ? From transcendental point of view, therefore, it is said that ultimately the distinction of good and bad cannot be held.1 Vice and virtue, bind the soul by effecting the inflow of foreign karmic matter. All the eight types of karmans are pudgala (non-self) and yield a fruit which is miserable in the ultimate analysis. Both of them cause bondage. Therefore, both types of Karmans are to be condemned equally. Just as a skilful elephant does not get attached either to an ugly or to a beautiful she-elephant, meant for his capture, similarly a wise man does not get attached either to good or to bad actions, because both cause bondage. Those who have a yearning for good actions, wander in this world in delusion.5 How an action, leading to bondage, can be called good ? A person should transcend the duality of good and bad actions. "The meritorious action leads to wealth, wealth to pride, pride to infatuation and infatuation to sin; let, therefore, be no good actions for us" It is said that even good 1. ततः परमार्थतः शुभाशुभोपयोगयोः पृथक्त्वव्यवस्था नावतिष्ठते । -Amṛtacandra on Pravacanasara, Bombay, 1935, 1.72. Also न खलु परमार्थतः पुण्यपापद्वैतमवतिष्ठते । -Ibid., 1.77. Also Samayasara, 145. 2. Samayasara, 45. 3. Pañcastikaya, 147. 4. Amṛtacandra on Samayasara, 148-149. Also कर्म सर्वमपि सर्वविदो यद्बन्धसाघनमुशन्त्य विशेषात् । तेन सर्वमपि तत्प्रतिषिद्धं ज्ञानमेव विहितं शिवहेतु ॥ -Samayasarakalasa, 103 5. Pravacanasära, 1.77 Also Paramätmaprakāśa, Bombay, 1937, 2.53. 55. कह तं होदि सुसीलं जं संसारं पवेसेदि ? 6. -Samayasara, 145. 7. पुणेण होइ विहवो विहवेण मओ मएण मह-मोहो । मइ — मोहेण य पावं ता पुण्णं अम्ह मा होउ ॥ -Paramātmaprakāśa, 2.60 Page #94 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Conception of Morality 77 actions lead to hell in future. Rare is a wise man who considers even a virtue to be a vice. A man should not be thus satisfied by anything less than self-realisation. With this ultimate aim of transcendental morality in view, we are asked to be moral in the practical sense of the term till the achievement of that aim. Vice and virtue are chains of iron and gold, respectively, and as such are equally bad. But is it not better to wait in the shade rather than in the hot sun ?4 It is from his point of view that good actions are approved. If the ultimate aim is not lost sight of, good actions are also indirectly helpful in the achievement of liberation. To conclude, though good and bad actions are equated from transcendental view-point, yet from practical point of view good actions are to be preferred to bad action for the following reasons: 1. For a man, engaged in worldly affairs, it is not possible to remain absorbed in pure consciousness.? So when he turns to activities under compulsion it is wiser to indulge in $ubhopayoga which leads to happiness rather than in aśubhopayoga, which leads to misery8. Worldly happiness and misery, both dwindle into insignificance before the ecstacies of blissfulness of self-consciousness, but given a choice between the two, happiness is naturally preferable to misery. 1. तेन निदानबद्धपुण्येन भवान्तरे भोगान् लब्ध्वा पश्चान्नरकादिकं गच्छन्ति । ---Brahmadeva on Paramātmaprakāša, Bombay, 1937, 2.58. 2. जो पुण्णु वि पाउ वि भणइ सो बुह को वि हवेइ। - Yogasära, 71. 3. Samayasāra, 146. 4. Istopadeśa, 3. 5. जोहाणं णिरवेक्खं सागारणगार चरियजुत्ताणं । अणुकंपयोवयारं कुव्वदु लेवो जदि वि अप्पो ।। -Pravacanasāra, 3.51. 6. Bhävasaṁgraha, Bombay, Vik. Sam. 1978, 610-618. 7. गृहव्यापारयुक्तस्य मुख्यत्वेनेह दुर्घटम् । निर्विकल्पचिदानन्दं निजात्मचिन्तनं परम् ।। -Ibid., 607. 8. Ibid., 611, 612, 9. Istopadeśa, 3. Page #95 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 78 Faina Ethics 2. Secondly, good activities are governed by self-denial and negation of passions. Liberality, for example, implies greedlessness and is a sort of penance.1 3. Man is a social animal. He wants to preserve and promote the interest of the society in which he lives. Thus good acts which benefit the society are preferable to bad ones which cause its disintegration. It is from this point of view that the Jaina ācāryas have asked their adherents to follow those general customs of the society which are not contrary to spiritual teachings. Thus we see that even though a man with right attitude will not attach much importance to the performance of good actions from the point of transcendental morality, yet at the same time while he is acting as a practical man, he will be a moral man in the ordinary sense of the word. The higher an aspirant ascends, the greater his devotion to fuddho payoga. But in the interim period he tries his best to avoid aśubhopayoga and to devote to śubhopaynga. Non-Jaina Systems The Upanişadic View Jainism shares this attitude with other systems of Indian philosophy. The chief interest of the Vedic seers lies in this world rather than the other world. They do not sing of the emptiness of this world and the futility of worldly pleasures. But by passage of time, mankind became introvert. In the later portions of the Ķgveda itself, a recluse is described roaming fearlessly from one forest to another, remaining detached from the villages and fearing noney. It is, however, in the Upanişads that we find a clear distinction betwean the mundane good (preyas) and transcendental good (śreyas). In the Byhadāranyakopanişad, the old sage rājñavalkya gave up all his worldly possessions in favour of higher spiritual life. 1. Bhāvasamgraha, 616,617. 2. सर्व एव हि जैनानां प्रमाणं लौकिको विधिः । यत्र सम्यक्त्वहानिर्न यत्र न व्रतदूषणम् ।। -Yaśastilakacampu, Bombay, 1901, 8.34. 3. Rgveda, 10.146.1. Page #96 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 79 Conception of Morality When he was distributing his wealth amongst his wives, one of them, Maitreyi, pondering over the temporary nature of worldly possessions, refused her share of it with these words : "What are these to me, if I am not thereby to gain life eternal'l. This anti-hedonistic tendency is brought out more clearly in the story of rama and Naciketas in the Kathopanișad. Yama tempted the youthful imagination of Naciketas and placed all human and divine pleasures at his disposal. There : a colourful description of the damsels and long life that were promised to him. Chariots ringing with divine music were offered. But none of these could budge him from his keen desire of knowledge of the self because he knew that all worldly pleasures would wither away by to-morrow.3 Thus when it was established that Naciketas was really a deserving candidate for spiritual knowledge, Yama began his discourse with a clear distinction between the good (śrejas) and the pleasurable (preyas). He made it clear that both of these were diametrically opposed to each other and lead a person to diverse ends. The path of good has the prerequisite of freedom from the allurement of environment. Modern scholars have also emphasised the supra-moral nature of the ethical teachings of the Upanisads. Dr. Radhakrishnan, while discussing the ethics of the Upanişads, remarked, “Duty is a means to the end of the highest perfection. Nothing can be satisfying short of this highest condition. Morality is valuable only as leading to it."5 Deussen has also very clearly pointed out this. He observes that when “the knowledge of the Atman has been gained, every action and, therefore, every moral action also has been deprived of meaning". 8 Buddhist View According to Buddhism it is meditation, which is beyond ci o 1. Bịhadāranyakopanisad, 2.4.2. 2. Kathopanişad, 1.1.25. Ibid., 1.1.26. Ibid., 1.2.1. 5. Radhakrishnan, S., Indian Philosophy, Vol. I, p. 208. Deussan, Paul, The Philosophy of the Upanişads, Edinburgh, 1919, p. 362. * Page #97 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 80 Jaina Ethics good or bad, which leads to Arhat-ship. From the point of view of meditation all acts, whether good or bad, are impure.1 The Nyāya-Vaišeșika System The Naiyāyikas hold that 'so long as we act we are under the sway of attachment and aversion and cannot attain the highest good. According to the Vaiseșika system also the ceremonial piety can lead simply to worldly prosperity whereas spiritual insight (tattvajñāna) leads to liberation.3 Whether it is dharma or adharma, both lead to embodied - existence. The Sāṁkhya-Yoga System In Sāṁkhya, the heaven which is the result of sättvika activities, is considered undesirable in comparison to liberation. Unselfish activities are, no doubt, the indirect cause of liberation. 5 In the Yoga system our actions are classified under four heads : (1) The black or wicked deeds, as speaking ill of others; (2) The white or virtuous deeds, as wisdom; (3) The white and black or mixed deeds, as performance of sacrifice, which involves violence also; (4) The neither-white-nor-black or supra-moral deeds, as meditation of the self. It is only this last-mentioned type of action which leads to liberation. The Mimāṁsā system Even in Pūrvamimāṁsā, which is the strongest votary of action, it is held that liberation, which lies in absolute cessation of the body, comes only when not only the virtuous (dharma) but vicious (adharma) actions also are exhausted.? 1. Radhakrishnan, S., Indian Philosophy, Vol. I, p. 419: 2. Ibid., p. 162. Candrakānta on Vaišeşikasūtra, Allahabad, 1924, 1.1.2. Samkhyas útra: 3.52-53. 5. Vijñānabhikṣu on Sāṁkkyadarśana, Calcutta, 1936, 1.82, 85. 6. Vyäsa on rogasūtra, 4.7. 7. आत्यन्तिकस्तु देहोच्छेदो निश्शेषधर्माधर्मपरिक्षयनिबन्धनो मोक्ष इति TATTI -Prakaranapañcāśikā, Benaras, 1961, p. 341. Page #98 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Conception of Morality : 81 In Vedānta, Sarkarācārya makes it clear while commenting on the Upanișads that since self is neither āpya (to be attained) nor utpādy 2 (to be generated) nor vikārya (to be modified) nor saņskārya (to be refined), it cannot be realised by karmans.1 Wherever Sankara finds a plea for action in the Upanişads he interprets it as an injunction for those who are still at a lower plane of existence and who cannot follow the path of renunciation. It is this common attitude of all systems of Indian philosophy towards ethics which makes it basically different from Western ethics. This is why Mckenzie remarks: 6...it can be at least maintained with full assurance that Hindu ethical thought and practice have rested on pre-suppositions of a different kind from those on which the ethical thought and practice of the West have rested. 3 Christian View Mckenzie is right to some extent. But we cannot say that such ideas are absolutely lacking in Christian ethics. The Bible says, “Love not the world, neither the things that are in the world. If any man loves the world, the love of the Father is not in him."4 Asked by a young man as to what he should do to inherit eternal life, Jesus Christ said, “Go thy way, sell whatsoever thou hast, and give to the poor and thou shalt have treasure in heaven.” Jesus teaches us complete non-possession (aparigraha) when he says, “...So likewise, whosoever he be of you that foresaketh not all that he hath, he cannot be my disciple.96 Dr. Radhakrishnan has rightly remarked, “The only ethics that Jesus can preach is a negative one, to enable man to free himself from the world and fit himself for the Kingdom."? He further adds that 'the eschatological teaching of Jesus that the end of the world 1. Sankara on Isopanişad, Gorakhapura, Vik. Sam. 1994, 1. 2. Cf. Ibid., 2. 3. Mckenzie, John, Hindu Ethics, p. 205. 4. I John, 2.15. 5. Mark, 10.21. 6. Luke, 14.33. 7. Radhakrishnan, S., Eastern Religion and Western Thought, London, p. 69. Page #99 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 82 Jaina Ethics was at hand reveals an attitude of world and life negation so far as He did not assume that the Kingdom of God would be realised in this natural world but expected its sudden and startling inauguration by supernatural power."l Conclusion Thus we see that (1) The lofty ideal of social service is also motivated by subtle self-interests. We indulge in good activities either for name and fame here or for heavenly happiness hereafter. Even the so-called desireless actions (niskāmakarmans) can be at the best rated as action motivated by the noblest desire of alleviating the miseries of others or by the higher desires of following the teachings of the scriptures and performing the duty for the sake of duty. But can it lead to liberation without self-realisation ? Perhaps not, for both--to dive deep into the realm of the self and to indulge in worldly activitiescannot go together. (2) Good activities are to be deemed as a means and not as an end in itself. Even the subtlest form of passion in the form of ego is to be swept away. The moral virtues should be observed with the ultimate end in view without a tinge of egoism. (3) The transcendental morality is not an excuse for moral slackness. The enlightened rise above the ordinary duties of life in the awareness of a higher purpose of life. The ordinary man should fulfil his duties with a detached view. 1. Radhakrishnan, S., Eastern Religion and Western Thought, p. 68. Page #100 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CHAPTER IV THE PATH OF THREE JEWELS We have seen that some systems of Indian philosophy like Sankhya and Vedanta hold knowledge (tatvajñāna) to be the means of liberation, Other systems like Mimämsä hold karman or right action to be superior to any other thing. The followers of bhakti-cult hold devotion and faith to be the only way to liberation. The position of Jainism here also, as elsewhere, is reconciliatory. In fact, right faith, right knowledge and right conduct cannot exist exclusively of each other. It is true that right conduct is the direct means of liberation, but right conduct with right faith and right knowledge only can lead to liberation.3 From real point of view right attitude, right knowledge and right conduct can be summarised in one word 'selfabsorption'. From practical point of view right faith means faith in seven predicaments of Jainism, whereas right knowledge consists in a knowledge thereof. Right conduct is the conduct based on detachment." 1. Uttaradhyayana, 28.2. 2. चारित्रमन्ते गृह्यते मोक्षप्राप्तेः साक्षात्कारणमिति ज्ञापनार्थम् । -Pujyapada on Tattvarthasutra, 9.18. 3. अतः सम्यग्दर्शनं सम्यग्ज्ञानं सम्यक्चारित्रमित्येतत्त्रितय समुदितं मोक्षस्य साक्षान्मार्गो वेदितव्यः । -Ibid, 1.1. 4. आदा खु मज्झणाणं आदा मे दंसणं चरितं च । -Samayasara, 277. 5. Tattvarthasutra, 1.2. 6. येन येन प्रकारेण जीवादयः पदार्था व्यवस्थितास्तेन तेनावगमः सम्यग्ज्ञानम् | 1 -Pujyapada on Tattvarthasutra, 1.1. 7. रायादी परिहरणं चरणं । -Samayasara, 155. Page #101 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 84 Faina Ethics The necessity of combining the three is brought out in many passages. Just as a person knowing a man to be king, and having faith in him, follows him for money, similarly a person knowing the real path and having faith therein should follow it for liberation.1 Conduct without faith and knowledge is as futile as faith and knowledge without conduct. Right faith ( samyagdarfana) The meaning of samyagdarśana Samyagdarśana, which has been rendered as 'right atti. tude', “right faith', or ‘right conviction', indicates complete saturation of mind with a principle or idea. From real point of view, samyagdarśana means a sense of feeling-realisation of self. From practical point of view, samyagdarśana means a firm belief in the fundamental principles of Jainism. The vyavahāra-samyagdarśana may be said to be the means of niscaya samyagdarśana. Different ācāryas have expressed the same idea in different words. We give below some of the representative descriptions of the nature of samyagdarśana : (1) The Uttarādhyayana defines samyaktva as belief in the nine categories.In his Darśanapāhuda, Kundakunda also defines samyagdarśana as a firm belief in the six substances and nine categories. In Moksapāhuda, he expresses the same idea in different words by defining samyagdarśana as belief in the dharma devoid of violence, in faultless deity and in the way of life, prescribed by the omniscients.5 In Niyamasāra, samyagáarśana is explained as a belief in liberated souls, Jaina scriptures and Jaina principles. In Mülācāra, the samyagdarśana is defined as belief in nine categories.? (2) Svāmikārtikeya added belief in non-absolutism as a condition for samyagdarśana.8 He held that the nature of nine 1. Samayasāra, 17-18. 2. Darśanapāhuda, Delhi, 1943, 20. Uttarādhyayana, 28.14,15. 4. Darśanapähuậa, Delhi, 1943, 19. 5. Mokşapāhuda, Delhi, 1943, 90. 6. Niyamasāra, Lucknow, 1931, 57. Mülācāra, 5.6. 8. Kartikeyānuprekṣā, 311, 312, Page #102 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Path of Three Jewels 85 categories cannot be rightly ascertained without the help of Pramāņa and naya. (3) Umāsvāti, who is followed by Amṛtacandrācārya and Nemicandra Siddhantacakravarti, defines samyagadarsana as belief in the seven predicaments of Jainism.1 (4) Samantabhadra defines samyagdars ina as a belief in true deities, true scriptures and true teachers as against the three follies of belief in pseudo-deva, pseudo-belief and pseudo-teacher. Samantabhadra also speaks of the eight essentials of right faith and the necessity of freedom from eight types of pride for a right believer.2 (5) Vasunandi in his Śrāvakācāra says that, in addition to belief in the seven predicaments, samyagdarsana includes belief in liberated soul and Jaina scriptures. Here Vasunandi follows Niyamasara of Kundakunda. Transgressions and blemishes of samyagdarsana The Tativārthasutra speaks of following five transgressions of samyagdarsana: (i) Šankā (doubt) (ii) Akankṣā (desire) (iii) Vicikitsā (repulsion) (iv) Anyadṛstipras aṁsā (admiration of followers of other creeds) (v) Anyadṛṣṭisamstava ( praise of followers of other creeds).4 The fourth transgression differs from the fifth in as much as the former means secretly thinking admiringly of wrong believers, whereas the latter means announcing the praise of wrong believers loudly.5 Banarasi Dāsa in his Naṭakasamayasara has given a different list of transgressions of right faith: (i) Fear of public censure. (ii) Attachment towards worldly pleasures. I. Tattvärthas utra, 1.2. 2. Ratnakaraṇḍaśrävakācāra, Delhi, 1955, 4. 3. Vasunandiśravakācāra, 6. 4. Upasakadaśānga, 1.40. Also Tattvarthasutra, 7.18. 5. Caritrasāra, Shri Mahaviraji, Vira Nir. Sam. 2488, p. 7. Page #103 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 86 Faina Ethics (iii) Thinking of attainment of worldly pleasures in the next birth. (iv) Praise of false scriptures. (v) Service of wrong believers." Eight essentials of samyagdarśana An aspirant should be firm in his belief. Any doubt or scepticism hampers moral progress. The firmness of his belief is indicated by the following eight qualities which are essential characteristics of samyagdarśana. All these characteristics together make the right faith complete and effective. 1. Nissankita (Absence of doubt about scriptures). The right believer, because of this quality, is free from the seven fears of (1) this world (2) another world (3) death (4) pain (5) accident, (6) absence of protector and (7) absence of forts, etc. This shows a state of complete fearlessness, which is obviously necessary for a moral life. 2. Niķkārksita (having no desire for the worldly pleasures). It comes from the firm belief that worldly enjoyments are impermanent, fraught with miseries, root of sins and evils.3 right believer, therefore, has a detached view of life. According to Amrtacandrācārya, he has non-absolutistic attitude and avoids one-sided view.4 3. Nirvicikitsā (absence of doubt about the attainments of spiritual path). A right believer should not have any repulsion from the impurity of the body of a person possessed of three jewels.5 4. Amūdhadışți (no confusion about the ideal). A right believer does not follow the wrong path even if it may sometimes lead to seemingly favourable results. He disassociates himself from those persons who follow the wrong path. This is not out of any hatred for them but because of the possible 1. Nāțakasamayasära, Bombay, Vik. Sam. 1986, 13-38. . 2. Mülācāra, 2.52, 53. Ratnakarandaśravakācāra, 12. 4. Puruşārthasiddhyupāya, Agas, Vik. Sam. 2022, 23. 5. Ratnakarandastāvakācāra, 13. 6. Ibid., 14. Page #104 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Path of Three Jewels dangers of deviating from right path by their association.1 He should not recognise violence as right under any fear of greed. He should avoid pseudo-guru, pseudo-deva, pseudoscripture pseudo-conduct and common false conceptions.3 5. Upabrhana (Augumenting the spiritual qualites). The right believer should perpetually endeavour to increase his spiritual qualities. Another name for this characteristic is Upaguhana, consisting in concealing one's own merit and demerits of others.5 6. Sthirikarana (Re-establishing those who deviate from truth). Any time any one may be tempted by passions to follow the wrong path. It is the duty of the aspirant to reestablish himself and others also on the right path by remin ding him of its glory. 7. Vatsalya (Sense of brotherhoods towards the followers of the right path). It includes respect for spiritual principles and for those who follow them." One must be devoted to meritorious persons, show respect to them and speak nobly. 8. Prabhāvanā (preaching the importance of truth). One should try to propagate the truth to others also by means of charity, austerity, devotion, profound learning and by such means as are suited to the time and place.9 It would be observed here that the first five characteristics pertain to the individual life of the aspirant whereas the last three pertain to the social aspect of religion. A true aspirant is not satisfied with his progress only but tries his best to help others also in self-realisation. 1. माध्यस्थ्यभावं विपरीतवृत्तौ । -Sāmāyikapāṭha, Delhi, 166, 1. 2. Kartikeyanuprekṣā, 418. 3. Puruşarthasiddhupaya, 26. 4. Ibid., 27. 5. 87 Ibid., 27. Also Kartikeyanuprekṣā, 419. 6. Ibid.. 28. 7. Puruşarthsiddhyupaya, 29. 8. Ibid., 421. 9. Ibid., 30. Also Ratnakaranḍaśrāvakācāra, 18; Kartikeyanuprekṣā, 422. Page #105 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Jaina Ethics Kundakunda on the eight essentials Kundakunda in his Samayasāra explains the above eight characteristics from a different point of view. Niśśarkita according to his interpretation, means freedom from fear of seven types. Niskāňkşita means having no yearning for the fruits of one's actions.2 Nirvicikitsă stands for non-abhorrence towards the natural qualities of objects.3 Amūờhadrsti means that one should have no confusion about the nature of things. Upabịhaņa means covering the pseudo-characteristics of self by devotion to Siddhas. Sthirikarana means re-establishing one-self on the right path. Vātsalya is love for three jewels and monks.? Prabhāvanā means devoting oneself to the selfknowledge. 8 The means of attaining samyaktva : Some people attain samyaktva through intuition (nisarga) others by a study of scriptures (adhigama). The persons having right faith can be classified into ten categories according to the means they adopt for the attainment of samyaktva : 1. Nisarga-Those who have an inborn spontaneous inclination towards righteousness. 2. Upadeśa-Those who learn truth from somebody by instruction. 3. Ajñā-Those who, being free from love and hate, follow the path of righteousness by command. 4. Sūtra—Those who obtain righteousness by the study of sūtras. 5. Bija-Those who comprehend the truth just by COUT 1. Samayasāra, 228. 2. Ibid., 230. 3. Ibid., 231. 4. Ibid., 232. Ibid., 233 6. Ibid., 234. Ibid., 235 8. Ibid., 236. 9. Tattvärthas ütra, 1.3. Page #106 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Path of Three Jewels having a suggestion about it, just as a drop of oil expands on the surface of the oil. 6. Abhigama--Those who comprehend the truth by the study of the eleven Angas, the Prakiranas and the Dişțivāda. 7. Vistāra— Those who understand the truth by undergoing the full course of study by means of all pramāṇas and nayas. 8. Kriyā—Those who believe in performing all the duties prescribed by the scriptures under right knowledge, faith and conduct. 9. Saṁksepa-Those who understand the truth by a brief exposition only though ignorant of other systems of philosophy. 10. Dharma-Those who believe in the law, or the words of the Jinas.1 The classification shows that human disposition differs from person to person but if the aim is correct we should make an allowance for the different methods of attainment of truth in accordance with one's own nature. Moral corollaries of right faith : It is clear from the above description that right faith implies such moral qualities as fearlessness, detachment, firmness, absence of scepticism, alertness, selflessness, sincerity of purpose, single-minded devotion, and propagation of truth. Besides, Pūjyapāda gives the following four essential virtues of a right believer : (i) Calmness (praśama), (ii) detachment (samvega), (iii) kindness ( anukampā) and (iv) self-realisation (āstikya). Somadeva says that 'just as virility of a man, which cannot be perceived with the senses, can be ascertained from his relations with women, or the generation of children, or his fortitude in danger, or the execution of his designs, similarly the existence of the jewel of right faith, although 1. Uttarādhyayana, 28.26-27. Also Dharmasamgraha, Palitana, 1905, 2.23 (p. 144). 2. Pujyapāda on Tattvārthasutra, 1.2. Page #107 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 90 Jaina Ethics extremely subtle owing to its being a condition of soul, may be inferred from the qualities of prasama, samvega, anukampā and ästikya.1 In the first place, an excited person, who becomes the victim of his own ill-considered actions, and is overcome by such negative ideas as that of rage, hatred and jealousy, cannot focus his energies with a single minded devotion to the purpose of liberation. The calmness comes from the realisation of the true aim of life. Secondly, a true aspirant of liberation is not only detached from all worldy pleasures but is also afraid of them because these allurements can take him away from the right path. This is called samvega and comes from the realisation of the fact that happiness comes from within and not from without. Thirdly, right believer is not a bigoted, hard-hearted and bitter man but he has respect for all, willing to let others lead a happy life, and has tendency of proving helpful in the miseries of others. Fourthly he understands the equality of all. He has friendship for all (maitri) but feels special bondage of kinship for those who are spiritually advanced (pramoda). Those who are away from truth, he tries to improve their lot (karuņā). But if they do not listen to him, he does not develop any hatred for them; he rather becomes indifferent to them (mādhyasthya.) Beside these four primary moral qualities, a right believer is asked to renounce eight types of pride of (i) the position of relatives on the maternal side (jatimada), (ii) the position of relatives on the paternal side (kulamada), (iii) beauty (rupamada), (iv) wealth (vibhutimada), (v) scholarship (dhimada), (vi) strength (saktimada), (vii) austerities (tapomada) and (viii) honour (arcanamada). The following five vices vitiate his right faith: (i) pride of knowledge, (ii) dullness of intellect, (iii) harsh speech, (iv) cruelty and (v) idleness.* I. Handiqui, K. K., Yasastilaka and Indian Culture, Solapura, 1949, p. 255. 2. Samayikapatha, 1. 3. Anāgāradharmamṛta, Bombay, 1919, 2.87. 4. Naṭakasamayasāra, 13.37. Page #108 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Path of Three Jewels 91 On the other hand, the five qualities that adorn his right faith are as follows: (i) The eagerness to propagate right faith (ii) knowledge of right and wrong (iii) Steadfastness, (iv) happiness at the attainment of right attitude, (v) dexterity in thinking over metaphysical problems.1 The Acārānga, Sūtra brings out the moral significance of right faith with great emphasis when it says, "He who has right faith commits' no sin."2 Position of faith in Indian Culture Faith marks the start of the journey towards the ultimate goal. It indicates the first glimpses of truth. Faith has been praised as a great moral virtue and necessary for all spiritual progress by all. The Rgveda praises faith (fraddhā).3 The Chāndogyopanişad asks us to be faithful.4 The Gitā says that only the faithful attains knowledge. We find a further development of this idea of faith in the Bhaktis ūtra of Nārada and Sändilya which are solely based on the idea of faith and devotion. In Vedānta, Rāmānujācārya held that salvation is not possible by knowledge, as held by Sarkara, but by bhakti. Thus we find that the importance of faith has been impressed throughout the history of Indian culture. Some points on Samyagdarśana In the above description of the nature, characteristics, types and means of right faith, the following points are discernible : (1) Right faith is not something dogmatic. The way in which a man may fall and regain the right attitude proves that it is a dynamic quality and not mere conversion from 1. Nățakasamayasāra, 13.31. 2. सम्मत्तदंसी न करेइ पावं --Acārārgas ütra, 1.3.2.1. 3. Rgveda, 10.151.1-5. 4. Chandogyopanişad, 6.12.3. 5. Teatesà Tapi -Gitā, 4.39 6. Radhakrishnan, S., Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, p. 703. 7. Cf. infra chapter VIII. Page #109 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Jaina Ethics one faith to another faith in the missionary sense of the term. (2) In Jainism, as in other religions of India, only acceptance of a code of principles is necessary but we need not accept the over-all supremacy of a particular person. There can be no Mohammedan without accepting Mohammad as the messenger of God and no Christian without accepting Christ as the son of God. No person is assigned such superhuman position by Jainism. The Tirtharkaras were as human as we are; only they conquered their passions which we can also do and attain the same status which they did. (3) Jainism realises the direct comprehension of truth as a landmark in the life of an aspirant. But it is only the beginning of the journey, not the end. Belief does affect our conduct but old habits do not break instantaneously. Right faith must lead to right conduct. Our conviction must compell us to act accordingly. Hence right faith, from which the ethics begins, can lead to perfection only when followed by right conduct. (4) Mere conduct and knowledge are impotent without right faith. It means that all moral virtues should be deeply rooted in the spiritual realisation. Without right faith, the moral virtues remain merely means of attaining selfish motives like name and fame. Right faith implies that duty is to be performed not for some petty immediate gain but for the attainment of the highest goal of perfection. This saves the aspirant from being entrapped in the allurements of worldly pleasures which he may easily come across as a result of his good activities. (5) To some extent, the position of a right believer may be compared to that of a nişkāma karmayogi of the Gitā. He has no desire, no attachment, still he engages himself in activities under the influence of previous karmans. These activities are not always good. But the inner detachment of the right believer weakens the force of karmans remarkably. We shall have more occasion to deal with the character of a samyagdarsi while dealing with the stages of spiritual development (gunasthāna). Suffice it to say for the present, that right faith means an inner conversion and not merely verbal acceptance of certain truths. The truth of truths is the self. Therefore from real point of view, samyagdarśana means Page #110 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Path of Three Jewels 93 realisation of the self. The description of samyagdarśana from practical point of view is to be interpreted in the light of this niścayasamyagdarśana. Now we turn to the second jewel of right knowledge with special reference to its ethical value. Right knowledge The Uttarādhyayana clearly says that without knowledge, there is no virtuous conduct. In the history of mankind the word 'knowledge' has been considered to be very sacred. In Jainism, a utilitarian view of knowledge has been taken. Knowledge is a means to something higher, which is emancipation, Knowledge should not only be right epistemologically but should be backed by right faith as to be spiritually useful. Right faith and right knowledge Though right faith and right knowledge emerge simultaneously on the removal of mithyātva as heat and light simultaneously rise from sun on the removal of clouds, yet the two are to be distinguished from each other. Right faith is the result of removal of vision-deluding karmans (darśanamohanīya) whereas right knowledge is the result of removal of knowlengeobscuring karmans ( jñānāvaraņi). For liberation, right attitude should be free from all blemishes, whereas it is not necessary to know more than the bare fundamental truths of spirituality. We have a story of Sivabhūti in Bhāvapāhuda, who attained liberation even though he had little knowledge of scriptures.3 On the other hand, not an iota of scepticism can be tolerated with regard to right attitude. What is comparable to avidyā of other systems, is darśanamohanīya in Jainism. Ignorance or ajñāna, in the ordinary sense of absence of mundane knowledge, is not a great hindrance in the realisation of truth. While discussing the stages of spiritual development in 1. Floor faut 7 ggfa TUT - -Uttarādhyayana, 28.go. Also HOT 7311 291 – -Daśavaikälikasútra, 4.10. 2. Pūjyapäda on Tattvārthasūtra, 1.1. 3. Bhāvapähuda, 53. Page #111 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 94 Jaina Ethics a subsequent chapter, we shall see that as the aspirant ascends upwards, he has to fight against vision-deluding (darśanamohaniya) karmans and conduct-deluding (caritramohaniya) karmnas, whereas the jñānāvarani karmans continue to the last till he attains the highest stage of omniscience. As far as moral progress is concerned, only the knowledge of basic principles of spiritualism is essential. Therefore, the knowledge-obscuring karmans are not considered detrimental (ghātins) for moral progress. What is right knowledge ? To know the jar as a jar does not make the knowledge right. A right knowledge is that in which a clear distinction is made between the self and the non-self.1 The real knowledge is the knowledge of the self. The word jñānī may be used in three different contexts : 1. A man possessed of knowledge is called jñāni. From this point of view all are jñānīs. 2. A man possessed of right faith is called jñānī. All overcome by wrong belief are ajñānis from this point of view, even though their knowledge may be epistemologically right. 3. A man having perfect knowledge is called jñāni. All souls in bondage are ajñānis from this point of view.2 It is only the second type of jñāni, whose knowledge leads him to liberation.3 Right knowledge is that which leads one towards his goal. The knowledge of the scriptures is valuable only if it leads to detachment and self-realisation.4 Right knowledge should help in the realisation of truth and in controlling the mind and purifying the self. 1. ***aqzaż ararfa 9: a arafa | -Istopadesa, 33. 2. Jayacanda on Samayasara, Delhi, 1959, 177-178. 3. सम्मत्तरयणभट्टा जाणंता वहुविहारं सत्थाई । आराहणाविरहिया भमंति तत्थेव तत्थेव || -Darśanapahuḍa, 4. 4. एवं पवयणसारं पंचत्थियसंगहं कियाणित्ता । जो मुयदि रागदोसे सो गाहदि दुक्ख परिमोक्खं ॥ -Pañcastikāya, 103. Page #112 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 95 The Path of Three Jewels The special position of right knowledge according to Jõānasāra Jñānasāra lays greater emphasis on knowledge. There seems to be an influence of Sankhya, Yoga and Vedānta on the author of the book. He defines avidyā or ignorance, after the fashion of Patañjali, as miscomprehending non-eternal as eternal, impure as pure and non-self as self. Obviously, Jñānasāra includes mithyādarśana and mithyājñāna, both in avidyā. “If the knowledge, capable of cutting the Gordian knot, exists what is the use of strange tantras and yantras ? "If the sight itself is dispeller of darkness why use the lamps ?"2 The book continues to speak in poetic tones, "The wise declare knowledge to be a nectar, which does not arise from ocean, a tonic, without being a medicine, a glory which does not depend on others." Knowledge of scriptures is to be distinguished from inner knowledge. A man, intoxicated with penance and scriptural knowledge etc. even though devoted to religious rites, gets attached; whereas a man possessed of the inner knowledge, even though not devoted to religious rites, does not get attached. The wise cuts, with the sickle of knowi ledge, the creeper of the poison of desire, which yields th¢ fruits of drying up of the mouth, attachment and helpless ness.5 Knowledge makes a man fearless. It is the real penance (tapas) because it burns (tāpanāt) the karmans.? All this praise which jñāna sāra showers on knowledge is justified in case of the broader sense of the term, which it attributes to it. Right knowledge Vs. wrong knowledge : All knowledge of a wrong believer is wrong because it does not lead to liberation. Even otherwise, if a man does 1. Jñānasära, Bhavanagar, Vik. Sam. 1969, Vidhyaştaka, 1. (For other Aştakas also see Jñanāsára) cf. Yogasūtra, 2.5. 2. Jñānāştaka, 6. 3. Ibid., 8. 4. Nirlepāstaka, 5. 5. Nihsphästaka, 3. 6. Cf. Nirbhayāstaka. 7. Tha at: gg: HTT T971979: 1 -Tapoștaka, 1. Page #113 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 96 Jaina Ethics not know even the substratum of all knowledge, how can his knowledge be right? The truth is that one who knows one, knows all and who knows all, knows one.1 Knowledge to be right should be relative. This implies non-absolutism which is another name for right faith. Absence of bookish knowledge or wrong perception arising out of the weakness of senses is not real ignorance. Limitations of knowledge Some of the systems of Indian Philosophy hold that knowledge alone can lead to liberation. Vidyanandi has refuted this view in the beginning of his commentary on Tattvärthas ūtra. His arguments can be summarised thus: A man, even after acquisition of knowledge remains embodied for some time. This is also accepted by Sankhya, Vaiseşika and Vedanta as necessary for the enjoyment of residual karmans. Now the question is this that a person who has acquired right knowledge will not be reborn; then how does it become possible for him to exhaust all his residual karmans before leaving his body ?2 The soul must put some special efforts for it. This effort in the form of meditation is a form of conduct, which annihilates the residual karmans by the process of nirjara. Therefore, right knowledge combined with right conduct brings emancipation. The position of right knowledge in Indian culture Knowledge occupies a very significant position in the history of Indian philosophy. By the term 'knowledge', two psychological phenomena are indicated: (1) Knowledge of the external objects, which may be called 'mundane knowledge', (2) Knowledge of the self, which directly comes through self-realisation.4 This is the latter type of knowledge, called tattvajñāna, which according to Vedanta, Nyaya and Sankhya systems of philosophy, directly leads to liberation. In Jainism, which is mainly an ethical system, know I. Acārāngasútra, 1. .4.1. SBE, Vol. XXII, p. 34. 2. Vidyanandi on Tattvärthasutra, Bombay, 1918, 1.1. (verses 50-51). 3. Ibid. 1.1. (verses 52). 4. Mundakopanisad, 1.1.5. Page #114 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Path of Three Jewels ledge occupies only a subservient place to conduct. It believes that knowledge is a power which can be rightly utilised only by a man possessed of right attitude (samyagdrsti). Even the mundane knowledge, in Jainism, is held to be leading towards liberation provided that it is utilised for developing a detached view of life. Since Jainism is a realistic system, it does not look upon mundane knowledge as false, as is the case with Vedanta system which holds this world and knowledge thereof to be illusory. Coming to the Brāhmaṇical attitude, we find prayers for knowledge and intelligence at many places. Knowledge occupies such an important position in the Upanisads that they are called jñānakāṇḍa (portions dealing with knowledge) of the Veda. Isopanisad says that through knowledge one gets immortality.2 The Gita says that there is nothing purer than knowledge. According to Sankhya, Vaisesika and Vedanta, knowledge is the only means of liberation. Some points on right knowledge From the above discussion it may be concluded that: (1) Jainism places ethics above metaphysics and epistemology. To believe that 'to know the jar even as a jar' is wrong if the knowledge is not accompanied by right faith, is a clear indication of the above fact. The motto is not 'knowledge for the sake of knowledge' but 'knowledge for the sake of liberation.' (2) Jainism and other systems of Indian philosophy make a distinction between verbal knowledge and knowledge acquired through direct spiritual experience. The former, even though much in quantity, cannot save whereas a little of the latter can lead us to liberation. (3) Knowledge without faith and conduct is impotent, Knowledge without faith is a mere pedantic gymnasticism whereas knowledge without conduct is a futile burden on the head. It is the union of the three that brings real bliss to the soul. I. 2. 97 Sukla Yajurveda, Bombay, 1929, 32.15. विद्ययामृतमश्नुते । -Isopanisad, 11. 3. Gitä, 4.38. Page #115 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 98 Jaina Ethics Right Conduct Right faith precedes right conduct. No conduct or knowledge without right faith can be said to be right.2 Transcendental conduct From transcendental point of view, right conduct consists in self-absorption. We have spoken of this conception in the foregoing chapter. From this point of view conduct has only one variety viz., self-absorption. Conduct is dharma, dharma , is equanimity (sāmya), and equanimity means that condition of ātman which is free from delusion and agitation.3 Conduct from practial point of view It is only in the background of this transcendental conception of conduct that all religious conduct is to be justified.4 Persons are purified by the purification of mind, all austerities are mere torturing of body without that. A person who is inwardly detached, is detached in the real sense of the term; he who is detached only outwardly does not get emancipation. Right conduct is something spontaneous, it is not forced. The vows, the three-fold path of self-discipline and the five-fold path of vigilance are the constituents of practical conduct. Without conduct all knowledge is futile.? I. तत्र सम्यक्त्वस्यादौ वचनं तत्पूर्वकत्वाच्चारित्रस्य। -Pūjyapāda on Tattvārthas ātra, 2.3. 2. यत्पुनद्रव्यचारित्रं श्रुतं ज्ञानं विनापि दृक् । न तज्ज्ञानं न चारित्रमस्ति चेत्कर्मबन्धकृत् ।। --Pañcādhyāyi, 2.771. 3. aiferiam qH, EFH) TT A F# færforçaII मोहक्खोहविहीणो परिणामो अप्पणो हु समो । -Pravacanasāra, 1.7. Also Pañcâdhyāyi, 2.764. 4. Amstacandra on Samayasära, 307. 5. मनःशुयैव शुद्धिः स्याद्देहिनां नात्र संशयः। वृथा तद्व्यतिरेकेण कायस्यैव कदर्थनम् ॥ -Jħānārņava, Bombay, 1907, 22.14. 6. Byhaddravyasamgraha, Bombay, Vir. Nir. Sam. 2433, 45. 7. Arādhanāsāra, Bombay, Vik, Sam. 1973, 54. Page #116 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Path of Three Jewels Conclusion In this chapter, we have observed that according to Jainism the main cause of bondage is perversity of attitude. The right faith, therefore, occupies the most important position. At the same time, right conduct is no less important. The soul has to exert itself in order to check the inflow of fresh karmic matter and also to annihilate the previously accumulated karmic matter. This is, as given in the second chapter, called samvara and nirjarā. Now we proceed to deal with the rules of conduct, which form the main part of Jaina ethics. As attainment of right conduct is a gradual process, the aspirant may not be able to achieve the highest ideals of conduct at the first stage. He, therefore, can observe only partial self-control at the stage of householder, whereas at the advanced stage of monkhood he becomes capable of observing the rules of conduct more comprehensively and completely. So we have two sets of rules of conduct one for the householder, another for the monk. We shall deal with both of them in the following two chapters. 99 Page #117 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CHAPTER V THE CONDUCT OF A HOUSEHOLDER Who is a householder ? The Jaina word for a householder, frāvaka, covers all those persons who have attained right faith but have not adopted monkhood. These persons either observe the vows partially (aņuvrata) or do not observe them (aviratasamygdrsți). But pure right faith is the necessary condition for a śrāvaka. This purity of right faith comes from its eight essentials1 and from freedom from eight prides and three follies. 3 Having conquered the vision-deluding karmans (darśanamohaniya), the śrāvaka continues to struggle against another enemy, the character-obstructing (caritramohaniya) karmans. He adopts the twelve vows prescribed for a laity and then proceeds to limit his desires till he is able to take the absolute vows (mahāvrata) and adopt the life of a monk. This is generally a gradual process. At the higher stage of spiritual development a śrāvaka is called Naisthika who renounces the worldly life and takes to a life that resembles the life of a monk (śramanabhūtapratimā). Thus śrāvakācāra includes not only the conduct of a grhastha but also the conduct of one who is known as vānaprastha in Hindu-dharma-śāstras. The position of a householder: Jaina ethics is primarily ascetic. The life of a householder is meant to be a short stay, only for those who are still incapable of enduring the hardships of the life of a monk. The morality of a householder, therefore, occupies a secondary place to the morality of a monk. We, therefore, find that the older books like Ācārānga of the Svetāmbaras or Mülācāra of the Digambaras, deal primarily with the life of a monk. i 1. Supra, pp. 86-87. 2. Supra, pp. 90. 3. Supra, p. 85. Page #118 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 101 In Brāhmaṇism, the position is just the reverse. The older books of Brāhmaṇism conceive primarily of a householder's life. It is only in the later books that the institution of ascetics came to its own and occupied that prominent place which it does to-day. The Manusmrti represents the Brāhmaņical thinking on the whole when it says that just as all rivers find shelter in ocean, similarly all āśramas find shelter in grhasthāśrama. The position of an aviratasamyagdršļi : The first stage of a Jaina householder begins with right attitude. This right attitude should be perfect in respect of eight essential limbs. Just as a mantra, short of even a single letter, does not remove the pain of poison similarly right attitude, devoid of any of the essentials, does not pierce the ! line of births.2 Even a pariah, having right faith is like god and is like the lustre of a live charcoal covered by the ashes.3 Right faith acts like a pilot in the path of liberation 4 A householder with right faith is better than a monk without it.5 Even if a person does not observe the vows, but if he is blessed with right faith, he is not reborn in hell or as animal, bird, eunuch or woman or in a low family, and does not suffer from deformity, or short life or poverty. Those who are purified by right faith become lords of splendour, energy, wisdom, prowess, fame, wealth, victory, and greatness and are born in great families and are very prosperous.? Jainism emphasises both, an inner detachment and renunciation of the worldly objects. The latter is the result of former and has no spiritual significance without it. Right attitude signifies inner detachment. It may not be possible for a man of right faith to renounce the worldly objects instantaneously, but once he has developed inner detachment 1. Manusmrti, 6.go. 2. Ratnakarandastāvakācāra, 21. 3. Ibid. 28. 4. Ibid., 31. 5. Ibid., 33. 6. Ibid., 35. 7. Ibid., 36. Page #119 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 102 Jaina Ethics the karmans cannot hold him in bondage for long. It is said that he attains liberation within a maximum time-limit of an ardhapudgalaparāvarta. He performs actions but they have so little influence on him that the karmans, it is said, do not bind him. This position can be compared to the niskāma karmayoga of the Gitā. The person with an inner detachment performs actions, but is not attached to their fruits or results. But the aspirant is not satisfied with anything short of liberation, which requires not only inner detachment but a complete renunciation of worldly activities. As his right faith gains ground, he proceeds towards monkhood by adopting small vows which are less strict than the great vows of a monk. The vows of a householder : According to Upāsakadašānga as well as Ratnakarandafrāvakācāra, the householder should observe the following twelve Vows : (1) Five partial vows. (2) Three gunavratas (3) Four purificatory śikṣāvratas.1 According to Ratnakaramdaśrāvakācāra the eight essentials of a śrāvaka are the five small vows and renunciation of wine, meat and honey. The five small vows include partial observance of the five moral principles of non-violence, truth, non-stealing, celibacy and non-possession. These vows are supplemented by the guņavratas which discipline the external movements and the sikşāvratas which emphasise inner purity of heart. The five rows and Caturyāmadharma: The number 'five' seems to have some special significance for ancient Indian thinkers. The Chāndogyopanişad gives the following five qualities as constituents of the life of a good man. (1) Penance (tapas) (2) Liberality (dāna) (3) Simple dealing (ārjavam) (4) Non-violence (ahimsā) (5) Truthfulness . 1. Upāsakadasänga, Rajakota, 1961, 1.11 (pp. 201-244). Also Ratnakarandaśravakācāra, 51. 2. Ratnakarandaśrāvakācāra, 66. Page #120 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 103 (satyavacana).1 The last two of these qualities are the same as the first two vows of Jainism. The third of these may be interpreted as non-stealing.2 Thus these moral qualities of the Chāndog yopanişad very much resemble the Jaina vows. Baudhāyana gives the following list of cardinal moral virtues : 1. Abstinence from injuring the living beings. 2. Truthfulness. 3. Abstention from appropriating the property of others. 4. Continence. 5. Liberality3 This description has replaced penance of Chāndog yopanişad by continence, thus bringing these moral virtues still nearer to Jaina vows. The fifth vow of liberality, which was a cardinal virtue of Brāhmaṇism was a misfit in the Jaina view of inorality. It was, therefore, replaced by nonpossession. This was, however, done only at the time of the last Tirthankara, Mahāvira. Pārsvanātha the Tirthankara prior to him, conceived, only of four vows (caturyāmas 1.4 . The five vows (pañcasila), which are binding on a Buddhist laity, include the vow of abstinence from intoxicants as the fifth vow. The Jaina view of non-possession is more comprehensive than this. Thus we see that the first four of these vows are unanimously accepted by Brāhmaṇism, Buddhism and Jainism. The fifth vow was, however, modified by each religion according to its own requirements. Later on, the Brāhmaṇical tradition also adopted the same vows as those of Jainism when Yogasūtra of Patañjali replaced the original vow of liberality by the ascetic vow of non-possession.6 The reason why Mahāvīra replaced the four Yamas of 1. Chandog yopanişad, 3.17.4. Also Taittariyopanişad. 1.9. 2. Ācāränga mentions three vows also. SBE, Vol. XXII, p. 63. 3. Baudhāyana, 2.10.18. quoted from SBE, Vol. XXII, Introduction, p. XXIII. Sthānānga, 4.1.266. 5. SBE, Vol. XXII, Introduction, p. XXIV. 6. Yogasutra, 2.30. Page #121 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 104 Faina Ethics Pārsvanātha by five vows is given as follows in the Uttaradhyayana. The followers of Pārsvanälha were simple and wise whereas the followers of Mahāvira were prevaricating and slow of understanding. So Mahāvīra had to make it clear to his followers that celibacy and non-possession were equally important and, therefore, he split one vow into two. From yet another reference to nakedness of the followers of Mahāvira in contrast to the wearing of clothes by the followers of Pārsvanāthait may be inferred that perhaps Mahāvīra was more strict on the observance of absolute vow of non-possession. This is, however, a tradition of the Svetāmbara sect. Kundakunda of the Digambara sect, has clearly prohibited use of clothes for all monks. It may also be pointed out that in the Brāhmaṇical tradition, these vows for mendicants were nowhere prescribed for a houcholder till perhaps Yogasūtra first of all thought of having small vows (aņuvratas ) for the householder. Originally, the life of a householder, according to Brāhmaṇism, was guided by such social virtues as sacrifice, study and liberality rather than by the ascetic virtues.. The life of a householder according to śramaņa tradition is, however, only a preparation for monkhood and, therefore, he was expected from the very beginning to practise the same virtues on a smaller scale which a monk was ex- pected to follow with perfection. Thus it is a long journey from the list of five cardinal moral virtues given by Chāndogyopanişad to the five Yamas of Yogasūtra. We see that the ascetic tradition of Jainism influenced the Brāhmaṇical tradition also, which replaced the social virtue of liberality by the ascetic virtue of non-possession. The emphasis on non-possession may be considered to be a contribution of Mahāvīra to the Jaina tradition itself. Originally, the Brāhmaṇical tradition, again, did not favour the idea of renouncing the world in the prime of youth. It was only after the duties of worldly life were fulfilled that a person could adopt monkhood to lead a retired life in the 1. Uttarādhyayana, 23.26-27. 2. Cf. Uttarādhyayana, XXIII. 3. Mūlācāra, 1.30. Page #122 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 105 forest, devoted to meditation. The framana tradition influenced the Brāhmaṇical tradition in this respect also. The old division of āśramas continued; but the new idea of renouncing the world, the very day one attains detachment, was also introduced.1 . The vow of non-violence : its background The Vedic people seem to have been more inclined towards worldly engagements than spiritual attainments. They glorified the institution of war as means of destroying enemies.2 This glorification of war is repeated in the later Brāhmanical literature also. At the time of Mahavira, animals were mercilessly killed in sacrifices. But this does not mean that Brāhmaṇical literature has no mention of non-violence. Āsādhara tells us that the animal sacrifice was started by Vasu by misinterpreting such sentences as 'ajairyastavyam'.4 The Manusmrti praises avoidance of meat-eating. The famous sentence that non-violence is the supreme duty (ahimsā paramo dharmaḥ) occurs in the Mahabhārata itself. The Mahābhārata declares that the sum-total of duties is contained in the maxim : "Thou shalt not do to others what is disagreeable to thyself." Thus two distinct currents can be seen from the very beginning of Indian culture. Manusmệti has beautifully summarised the position by saying that human nature is inclined towards meat-eating but a check on this natural inclination yields immensely favourable results. There is great truth in the saying that life lives on life.? Still justice demands that we should not inflict misery on others, if we do not want others to inflict misery on us. Between these two facts, the inevitability of violence on one hand and the demand of our inner 1. Jābālopanişad, 4. 2. Rgveda, 1.166.10. 3. Gitā, 2.37. 4. Sāgāradharmām;ta, 8.84. 5. Manusm;ti, 5.45-55. 6. Ibid., 5.56. 7. stat ogey qaal -Srimadbhāgavatapurana, Gorakhapura, Vik. Sam. 2010, 1.14.46. Page #123 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 106 faina Ethics most heart of being non-injurious to others, we are to fix our duty of non-violence. Non-violence in Jainism : Thought is the father of action. We commit violence in thought (bhāvahimsā) before we commit it in action dravyahińsā). It is the former, violence in thought, which is real violence (niścayahiṁsā). Therefore, merely taking away of life does not constitute complete definition of violence. Violence has been defined as injury to one's vitalities out of negligence (pramāda). Negligence means, in short, the passionate ideas of attachment and aversion. These ideas have been classified under fifteen heads. Entertaining such ideas is violence, whereas absention from such ideas is non-violence.? Violence in thought Bhāvahiṁsā, violence in thought, has predominated in the discussion of ahimsā by Jaina thinkers. Even before Umāsvāti defined himsā, Ācārya Kundakunda had declared that whether one was killed or not, a negligent person certainly committed violence. A vigilant person, on the other hand, who acted with care, did not suffer bondage by mere (material) injury. The commentator Amrtacandrācārya says that the inner violence is the impure state of self, whereas the injury to vitalities is the external manifestation of violence. He is clear about it that the material vitalities of others are sometimes injured and sometimes not; a person gets the bondage of karmans because of defilement of his abstract vitalities (bhāvaprāna) by attachment. Jayasenācārya made the sense clearer by means of a metaphor. "Just as a person desirous of killing others by a burning iron bar burns his ownself first, similarly an ignorant person first afflicts his own pureself by getting influenced by the ideas of infatuation etc., which are like the burning iron bar; there is no rigid rule 1. Supra, p. 62. 2. Puruşārthasiddhyupāya, 44. 3. Pravacanasāra, 3.17., also Puruşārthasiddhyupāya, 45. 4. Amrtacandra on Pravacanasāra, 3.17. 5. Ibid., 2.57. Page #124 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 107 for the affliction of others."1 The Daśavaikālikasūtra declares that to one who walks, stands, sits, sleeps, eats and speaks with vigilence, no sin accrues.2 Kundakundācārya also says that a śramaņa who is negligent is said to be violent with regard to all the six kāyas but if he behaves vigilantly, he remains unattached, just like lotus in water. This is how absolute non-violence is made possible. Coming to the commentaries of Taltvārthasūtra, Sarvārthasiddhi of Pūjyapāda repeats the same thing and says that a negligent soul afflicts the self by self and it is not important whether others are killed or not.4 Akalarkadeva in his Rājavārtika defines pramatta as a ; person who loses all sense of discrimination under the influence of passions. The objection that if a person cannot be held responsible for happiness and miseries of others, how could he be held responsible for any act of violence, has been answered on the basis of predominance of bhāvahiṁsā. True that a person is not responsible for the miseries of another persone, yet he cannot escape responsibility of defiling his pure nature by entertaining the ideas of attachment and aversion, which is the real sin. Violence in action (Dravyahiṁsā) : Non-violence in thought should be translated into action also. To say that if internal mind is undefiled external purity of actions is unnecessary, would be denying the unbreakable relation between thought and action. Non-violence is not merely an abstract idea but also a concrete way of life. What has been said about the importance of bhāvahiṁsā and niscayhiṁsā does not mean negligence in outward behaviour. 1. Jayasena, on Pravacanasāra, 2.57. 2. Daśavaikälika, 4.8. 3. Pravacanasära, 3.18. 4. स्वयमेवात्मनात्मानं हिनस्त्यात्मा प्रमादवान् ।। पूर्व प्राण्यन्तराणान्तु पश्चात्स्याद्वा न वा वधः ।। Quoted by Pūjyapāda on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.10. 5. Akalarka on Tattvārthas útra, Calcutta, 7.13.1. 6. Samayasära, 266. Page #125 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 108 Faina Ethics “The wheel of different view-points (nayacakra) is extremely sharp-edged and difficult to ward off; when it is used by misguided intellect it cuts off one's own head quickly."l Hence avoidance of external violence is as necessary as the aviodance of feelings of attachment or aversion. From practical point of view, any kind of injury to any of the ten vitalities of a living being is violence. These ten vitalities are five senses : three powers of mind, speech and body; age and respiration. Violence thus includes not only killing or physical injury but also curtailing the freedom of thought and speech of others. None should be forced to do anything against his wish. Thus it would be wrong to restrict non-violence only to the limited field of non-injury to living beings; it should also be extended to the higher plane of independence of thought and speech, which is the very basis of democracy and free society. Amrtacandra has shown the importance of the intention of the agent. He has pointed out that, on account of intensity or mildness of passions, trifling violence may yield serious results and grievous violence may yield trifling results. 3 Thus the same violent action may yield different results on account of variation in the intensity of passion. Sometimes violence leads to benefits of non-violence and non-violence to the harms of violence.5 Non-absolutism and non-violence When we extend non-violence from respect for life to respect for thought, we are automatically led to non-absolutism. That is why non-absolutism is held as important as non-violence by Jaina thinkers. All statements or points of view are relative and, therefore, every one of them has a grain of truth. Every object has complex nature and unity can be found in diversity. Given two contradictory statements, it is not necessary to reject one of them, for the 1. Puruşärthasiddhyupāya, 59. 2. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvärthasútra, Surat, 1930, 7.8. 3. Puruşarthasiddhyupāya, 52. 4. Ibid., 53. 5. Ibid., 57. Page #126 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder ? contradiction may be superficial and not real. A wider outlook is necessary to avoid quarrels which lead not only to mental conflicts but to so much of bloodshed in the name of religion and ideologies. It is a matter of daily experience that contradictory attributes can be assigned to the same object from different points of view. The same tree which is said to be movable from the point of view of branches, is said to be immovable from the point of view of root and trunk. We do not like to listen to the view-points of others on account of our prides and prejudices. But a non-violent person, who is free from attachment and aversion, will dispassionately look at every problem and would be able to arrive at the truth by reconciling different points of view by putting them in their proper perspective. In fact, most of the so-called ideological conflicts are motivated by selfish interest. Non-violence teaches us to be master of our passions and accept objective views on all problems. Types of violence From real point of view violence is only of one type; but from practical point of view it can be classified into many varieties. Jaina thinkers have classified violence into 108] varieties so that the aspirant can detect even the minutest form of violence.1 The violence is three-fold in as much as it can be (1) committed by the person himself (kṛta) or (2) got committed by others (kārita) or (3) got committed by others by giving consent (anumodanā). This three-fold violence becomes nine-fold as it can be committed by either of the three agencies of mind, speech and body. This nine-fold violence becomes twentyseven-fold as it has three stages: (1) thinking of violent action (samrambha), (2) making preparation for violence (Samārambha) and (3) actual committal (ārambha). This twentyseven-fold violence becomes one hundred and eightfold as it could be inspired by either of the four passions. This classification shows that Jainācāryas took a comprehensive view of non-violence. Avoidance of violence in all its varieties is possible only 1. Amitagatisravakācāra, Bombay, Vik. Sam. 1979, 6.12-13. 109 Page #127 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 110 Faina Ethics for a monk who observes absolute non-violence. We shall deal with the absolute non-violence in the following chapter while dealing with the conduct of a monk. Herebelow we deal with the vow of non-violence as it is observed by a householder. Limitations of the small vow of non-violencel The conception of the vow of non-violence for houseder is based on two considerations : (1) The householder has certain responsibilities towards his family of earning livelihood and procuring necessities of life for them. (2) He has to safeguard himself and his country against enemies. For the first requirement, the householder has to adopt a certain profession. He should be careful to choose a profession which involves the least violence. The violence that he commits under compulsion of professional circumstances is called Udyamihimsā; and it can be avoided only at the higher stage of spiritual progress in the eighth pratimā. Unintentional violence is also involved in such daily routine of a householder, as cooking etc. It is not possible to abondon such violence in the initial stages. This is known as ārambhahińsā and is abondoned only in the eighth pratimā. As regards the second requirement of self-defence, the house-holder takes a defensive attitude in wars. He is never offensive, but he can take part in defensive wars. When compelled by circumstances, he accepts the challenge of war as a necessary evil (virodhihiṁsā). It is only the fourth type of himsā, called intentional violence (samkalpihiṁsā), which can be and should be absolutely avoided by a householder. Samkalpihiṁsā includes violence for the sake of fun or violence performed under intense passion. Avoidance of this type of violence interferes neither with his duty of earning his livelihood nor with discharging his responsibilities of self-protection as a self-respecting citizen of his country. This, however, does not mean that other three types of 1. Muni Nathamala, Ahimsa-tattra-darsana, Cull, 19€0, jf. 85-26. 2. Amitagatisravakācāra, 6.6-7. 3. Ratnakarndaśrāvakācāra, 53. Page #128 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 111 violence that the householder commits under compulsion are not to be abondoned ultimately. As the aspirant ascends the steps of spiritual progress, he minimises all types of violence in his conduct. In the meantime, he has a constant feeling of self-condemnation (nindana, garhaņa) for the violence that he commits. 1 Eight mūlaguņas : Amrtacandra has considered the renunciation of wine, meat, honey and five types of Udumbara fruits as necessary for a householder, who wants to observe the vow of nonviolence. These are called basic qualities or mūlaguņas of a householder. The earlier writers like Samantabhadra included the five aņuvratas also in the mülagunas. Samantabhadra had five anuvratas and abstinence from wine, meat and honey as the eight mūlaguņas.3 Ācārya Somadeva introduced altogether a different tradition by replacing five anuvr atas by abstinence from five Udumbaras. This must be considered as concession, since observance of five anucratas is much more difficult than avoidance of five Udumbaras. Amrtacandras üri followed Somadeva in this respect. The number of these basic qualities has not remained constant. Acārya Amitagati added to the eight basic qualities given by Amrtacandra, the avoidance of eating at night.5 Vasunandi added, the avoidance of gambling, hunting, prostitution, adultery and stealing. Pandita Asādhara gives another list of these basic qualities in which he has added devotion to the adorable five, viz. Arihanta, Siddha, Acārya, Upādhyāya and Sadhu ; use of only that water which is strained through a cloth and a compassionate attitude towards the sentient beings.? It may be observed from these different lists of basic qualities of a householder that non-violence predominates in 1. Amitagatisrāvakācāra, 6.8. 2. Puruşārthasiddhyupāya, 61. 3. Ratnakarandastāvakācāra, 66. 4. Handiqui, K. K., Yaśastilaka and Indian Culture, p. 262. 5. Amitagatisravakācāra, 5.1. 6. Vasunandiśrāvakā āra, 59. 7. Săgăradharmām;ta, 2.18. Page #129 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 112 Jaina Ethics every list. These lists also show that Jaina Acaryas were particular about non-violence not only towards fellow human beings but towards small insects and animals also. Dietic prohibition : Food is the basic necessity of life. The necessary violence involved in the preparation of food is unavoidable for a house-holder and is considered as arambhi himsā. But violence for food should be restricted within certain limits. Meat, for example, which is obtained by merciless killing of innocent animals, is not allowed for eating in any case. Vegetables and animals are endowed with life alike but it will be wrong to argue that just as we take vegetable life for food, we can also kill animals for food. To use a simile of Asadhara, though both mother and wife are possessed of womanhood, yet only wife is used for gratification of sex and not mother.1 Killing of a five-sensed animal causes hardening of heart and involves much more callousness than is required for preparing food out of vegetables. Not that violence to vegetable life is not a sin but that is lesser of the two evils, and perhaps an unavoidable one, for a householder. Wine is another item which should be avoided by a house-holder. Wine stupefies the mind; the man whose mind is stupefied forgets righteousness; and he who forgets righteousness, commits violence. Moreover, a man who takes wine necessarily commits violence because he destroys many creatures which are generated in liquor. Pride, fear, hatred, ridicule, disgust, grief, passion for sex and anger are concomitants of wine.3 Besides wine and honey, five Udumbaras are also prohibited for food purposes. Even though the living beings in these five fruits may not be present on account of their being dry, their use involves violence in as much as it indicates strong attachment for them. Butter, even though not included in the above list of eight mulagunas, should also be avoided as 1. Sāgāradharmamṛta, 2.10. 2. Puruşarthasidhyupaya, 62. 3. Ibid., 64. 4. Ibid., 73. Page #130 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder germs are believed to be taking birth in it. Butter together with honey, wine and meat, is known as mahāvikṛti, as all of these have excessive fermentations.1 Asādhara has included the following abhaksya under eight mūlagunas (1) Abstinence from wine includes abstinence from rice-gruel that has fermented pickles and curds kept for more than two days. (2) Abstinence from meat includes abstinence from water or other liquids contained in leather, as afoetida in contact with leather and tainted food. (3) Abstinence from honey includes abstinence from honey as collyrium and flowers like mahuā. (4) Abstinence from udumbara includes abstinence from pods as rājamāşa, aubergines and unknown fruits. (5) Abstinence from taking food at night includes avoidance of food in the first and last muhurtas of the day and avoidance of taking of ghee or mango even as a medicine at night.2 Transgressions of the vow of non-violence: When the householder takes a vow of non-violence, he has to know the acts which defile his vow, so that he can avoid them. The scope of non-violence is so wide that the traditional five aticāras (transgressions) of the vow can be hardly said to be comprehensive. Any intentional violation of the rule of non-violence is a defilement of the vow. A householder in initial stages may not be able to avoid violence of the immobile life but he should avoid violence of mobile life.3 113 The traditional aticāras of non-violence are : (1) tying up living beings tightly (2) beating them (3) mutilating them (4) overloading them (5) withholding their food and drink.4 All these five aticāras are condemnable if done under the pressure of passions. But a householder may adopt them for correcting a child or a servant.5 Similarly, food may be 1. Puruşarthasiddhyupaya, 71. 2. Sāgāradharmamṛta, 3.11-15. 3. Puruşarthasiddhyupaya, 75. 4. Upasakadaśänga, 1.45. 5. Ganiu Siddhasena on Tattvärthasutra, Surat, 1930, 7.20. Page #131 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 114 denied to a patient suffering from good.1 Jaina Ethics fever for his physical Some misconceptions about non-violence: There are certain misconceptions about non-violence. Some hold that there is no violence in taking the flesh of those animals who have met natural death. It is not true, because in the flesh of a dead body, nigoda creatures of same genus are constantly being generated which are killed even by touching of that flesh.2 Similar argument is advanced against taking of honey which has itself dropped down from th honeycomb. It is due to this existence of nigodas in the carcass of an animal that the plea for saving many lives of small creatures by taking away the life of one animal of huge size, is refuted. Even violent animals should not be killed either with an intention of saving the possible destruction of other animals by them or to save them from the possibility of incurring the great sin of violence. The only way of removing one away from sin is to teach him to control his passions and not to destroy him. Even mercy-killing is a form of violence. The animal, which is suffering, is a victim of his own past karmans, and his suffering cannot be cut short by killing him. Violence in the name of religion: Violence is not to be justified for the sake of so-called religious rituals. Non-violence, compassion and love is the core of every religion and yet in many of the great religions of the world we find that violence is prescribed in the name of religion itself. Jainism has vehemently opposed all such violence. It is argued that dharma is difficult to comprehend; and, therefore, even though violence is otherwise bad, when sanc 1. Ganin Siddhasena on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.20. 2. Puruşārthasiddhyupāya, 66-68. 3. Ibid., 70. 4. Ibid., 82. 5. Ibid., 83-84... 6. Ibid., 85, Jain. Education International Page #132 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a House holder 115 tioned by religion, violence is no sin.1 Everything can be offered to gods including flesh of animals, as religion flourishes through gods. But this argument should not be used for violence. Puruşārthasiddhyupāya refers to some other strange beliefs. One of these beliefs is that if a person is killed when he is in a state of happiness, that state will continue in future life also.3 Another belief is that if a person engrossed in deep meditation is killed he gets liberation. The third group called kharapaţikās believed that liberation automatically comes at the dissolution of body. All violence under such misconceptions is condemned. Under no pretext, therefore, can violence be justified. The implication of the precept of non-violence in Jainism is manifold. It is against all cruelty towards animals. It is against wars even though it gives us the right of self-defence. It guarantees freedom of thought, speech and action to all alike and it asks us to shun violence in the name of religion. This force of non-violence became a powerful weapon, recognised by all, under the dynamic personality of Gandhiji. Nonviolence means victory over one's baser instincts, the unbridled expression of which is sometimes wrongly eulogised as bravery. The vow of truthfulness The word 'satyam' conveys much wider meaning than the English word 'truth'. In Brāhmaṇism it indicates not only the ethical principle of truthfulness but also the metaphysical reality. The following points may be noted as regards the conception of satyam in Jainism; (1) Satyam refers to an ethical principle rather than to abstract metaphysical entity as Brahman; (2) Mere statement of fact is not truth unless it is 1. Puruşārthasiddhyupāya, 79. 2. Ibid., 80. 3. Ibid., 86. 4. Ibid., 87. 5. Ibid., 88. 6. FRI TITAFETTI -Taittariyopanişad, 2.1.1. Here the word 'satyam' is used in its abstract metaphysical sense. Page #133 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 116 Jaina Ethics motivated by beneficial intentions;1 (3) Truth is subservient to non-violence. Classification of truth Truth and untruth are classified, sometimes according to their causes, sometimes according to their nature, and sometimes according to their intensity. Amrtacandra has given four types of falsehood :2 (1) Denial of the existence of a thing with reference to its position, time and nature. (2) Asserting the existence of a non-existent thing with reference to its position, time and nature. (3) Representing a thing as something else. (4) The fourth type of falsehood includes (a) Reprehensible speech (garhita) (b) Sinful speech (sāvadya) (c) Hurtful speech (apriya). (a) A reprehensible speech includes back-bitting, joke, harsh, unbecoming, non-sensical and anti-canonical speech. (b) Sinful speech includes speech which prompts piercing, cutting, beating, ploughing, trading and stealing. (c) Hurtful speech causes unpleasantness, fear, pain, enmity, grief, quarrel or anguish in the mind of another person. The sinful speech includes what may be called the professional lie which is allowed for a householder.5 Speech causing ploughing or trading may not be considered as a lie at all ; but it has been called so because these professions involve violence. Another classification, based on the mixture of truth and falsehood, is given by Somadeva: (1) satyasatya—wholly true, (2) asatyasatya--intermixture of truth and falsehood, the latter being predominant, (3) satyāsatya-intermixture of truth with falsehood, the former being predominant, 1. Cf. aawafa Tamache HT HAI – Mahābhārata, 12.329.13. 2. Puruşārthasiddhyupāya, 91-96. 3. Ibid., 97. 4. Ibid., 97. 5. Ibid. 101. 6. Handiqui, K.K., Yasastilaka and Indian Culture, p. 265: . . Page #134 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 117 (4) asatyāsatya-wholly false. Amongst Digambaras, Asadhara also follows Somadeva's classification.1 Conception of truth: In speech one should aim at moderation rather than exaggeration, esteem rather than denigration, at distinction rather than vulgarity of expression.2 Even truth if it is harmful to others should be avoided. Language should be balanced and expressive of the sacred truths.4 All untruth necessarily involves violence for it is caused by negligence, which is the back-bone of violence. It is, therefore, unthoughtful speech, anger, greed, fear and cutting of jokes which should be avoided to protect the vow of truthfulness. Transgressions of the vow of truthfulness The five aticāras of the vow of truthfulness according to Upāsakadasanga are as follows : (1) Sudden calumniating (sahasābhyākhyāna) (2) Disclosing others' secrets (raho' bhyākhyāna) (3) Divulging the confidence of one's wife (svadāramantra bheda). (4) False advice (Mṛsopadeśa) 6 (5) Writing false statements (kūṭalekhakarana). The Digambara tradition has the following aticāras : (1) False preaching (mithyopadeśadāna) (2) Divulging one's secret (raho'bhyākhyāna) (3) Forgery (Kuṭalekhakriya) (4) Breach of trust (nyāsāpahāra) (5) Disclosing one's secret purpose (sākāramantrabheda)." 1. Sāgāradharmamṛta, 4.40-43 2. Handiqui, K. K., Yasastilaka and Indian Culture, p. 266. 3. सत्यं विमोक्तव्यं परपीडारम्भतापभयजनकम् । -Amitagatisravakācāra, 6.47. 4. Kartikeyanuprekṣā, 234-4. 5. Puruṣārthasiddhyupāya, 99. 6. Upasakadaśānga, 1.46. 7. Puruşarthasiddhyupaya, 184. Also Sägäradharmamṛta, 4-45. Amitagatisrāvakācāra, 7.4. Page #135 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 118 Jaina Ethics Besides, mention may be made of Samantabhadra, who considers paisunya (calumny) and parivāda (reproach), and of Somadeva? who considers mudhāsākṣipadokti (false evidence), as the transgressions of the vow of truthfulness. Now we deal with these aticāras in some details. (1) Mithyopadeśadāna : According to Cāmundarāya, it means such advice as is detrimental to the attainment of liberation or heaven.3 Āsādhara explains it as speaking such words as may cause suffering to others or show the methods of winning in a dispute by dishonesty. (2) Rahobhyākhyāna : In Digambard, tradition it means divulging secret actions of men and women.5 Siddhasena Gaņin seems to interpret this aticāra in the sense of svadāramantrabheda of Upāsakadašānga.6 (3) Kūțalekhakriyā : It means alleging in writing what was not in fact said or done by someone.? Siddhasena Garin connects it with false writing of symbols on birch bark. 8 (4) Nyāsāpahāra : It means dishonesty with regard to the deposits of a person. If a person deposited Rs. 500 with another man but forgot the exact amount, the second may then deceive him by saying that he had deposited only Rs. 400 with himo. Then this would be aticāra called nyāsāpahāra. (5) Sākāramantrabheda : It means divulging the intention of a person as inferred from his facial expressions.10 Praise of truthfulness : The Jaina scriptures praise truthfulness as a great virtue. A liar suffers in this life and the next. A truthful man, on the other hand, enjoys great security.11 A truthful man should neither exaggerate, nor find fault with others, nor use indecent speech, and should use noble, beneficial and balanced speech. DA CON 1. Ratnakarandaśrāvakācāra, 56. 2. Upāsakādhyayana, 381. Caritrasāra, Shri Mahaviraji, VNS 2488, p. 9. 4. Sāgāradharmāmrta, 4.45. Pujyapāda on Tattv ārthasūtra, 7.26. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvārthas ütra, 7.21 (p. 105). Căritrasāra, p. 19. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.21. 9. Ibid., 7-21. 10. Ibid., 7.21. 11. Yogaśāstra, 2.53-64. 8. Page #136 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 119 He should have equanimity of mind, be noble and kind and should not extol himself.1 The position of truth in Brahmanism Truth held a prominent place in Brāhmaṇism from the Rgvedic times. In the Rgveda, rta which is another name for truth, is considered to be the chief divine quality.2 In Satapatha, truthfulness is identified with dharma.3 The Upanisads declare in unequivocal terms that truth alone conquers and not falsehood.4 The vow of non-stealing The vow of non-stealing, which means abstention from taking a thing which is not given, is very comprehensive and includes avoidance of dishonesty in all walks of life. Like other vices, even stealing is connected with violence by Amitagati. Wealth is, as if it were, external vital force of a man, and whosoever takes that away commits violence.5 Moreover, pramattayoga which is the backbone of violence, is also present in the act of stealing. 6 Dvādaśānuprekṣā summarises the scope of this vow in these words: one should not buy a valuable article at low price, nor sell it at low price, nor appropriate something that has been forgotten, nor take the property of others through anger or greed.' Similarly, Asadhara forbids taking a thing whose ownership is doubtful. He also says that valuables like a buried hoard should be considered as the property of the state. Samantabhadra holds that what is unoffered, placed, dropped or forgotten by others, should neither be taken nor 1. Handiqui, K. K., Yasastilaka and Indian Culture, p. 266. 2. Rgueda, 10.190.1. 3. यो वै स धर्मः सत्यं वै तत् । -Satapathabrahmana, Kashi, VS 1994, 14-4.2.26. 4. Mundakopanisad, 3.1.6. 5. Purṣarthasiddhyupaya, 103. 6. Ibid., 104. 7. Kartikeyanuprekṣā, 335. 8. Sāgāradharmāmṛta, 4.49. 9. Ibid., 4.48. Page #137 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 120 Faina Ethics be given to somebody. One may take possession of property of one's kinsman after his death ; but during his life his permission should be sought.2 The transgressions of the vow of non-stealing All authors, except Somadeva, agree with regard to the following five transgressions of the vow of non-stealing : (1) Abetment of theft (stenaprayoga) (2) Receiving stolen property (tadāhrtādāna) (3) Violating state rules (viruddharājyātikrama) (4) Use of false weights and measures (hinādhikamānonmāna) (5) Adulteration (pratir ūpaka vyavahāra).3 (1) Stenaprayoga : According to Pūjyapāda, it means direct or indirect instigation of theft.“ Siddhasena Gamin has a different interpretation. According to him this transgression means helping thieves with money.5 (2) Tadāhrtādāna : According to Pūjyapada, it means obtaining something stolen by a thief, without having employed or prompted him. According to Siddhasena Garin, it means obtaining goods which are proceeds of a robbery for nothing or at low price.? (3) Viruddharājyātikrama : According to Pūjyapāda it means all illicit business. 8 According to Siddhasena Ganin, it means unlawful acquisition of property in another country which is engaged in hostilities with one's own country since even grass or wood acquired under such circumstances must be regarded as stolen. (4) Hinādhikamānonmāna : According to Cāmundarāya, it means trading in which more is taken from oneself and less I. Ratnakarandastāvakācāra, 57. Also Vasunandiśrāvakācāra, 211; Sāgāradharmāmrla, 4.48. 2. Handiqui, K. K., Yasastilaka and Indian Culture, p. 265. 3. Upåsakadaśānga, 1.47. Also Tattvārthasūtra 7.22; Ratnakarandastāvakācāra, 58; Amitagatisrāvakācāra, 7.5; Puruşārthasiddhyupāya, 185; and Sagaradharmāmrta, 1.47. 4. Pūjyapāda on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.27. 5. Gaņin, Siddhasena on Tattvärthasūtra, 7.22. 6. Pūjyapāda on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.27. 7. Ganin, Siddhasena, on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.27. 8. Pūj yapāda on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.27. 9. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvärthasütra, 7.22. Page #138 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 121 given to others when weighing or measuring.1 Siddhasena Ganın includes charging abnormal interest on the lent money under this transgression.2 (5) Pratir upaka Vyavahāra: According to Camuṇḍarāya, it means fraudulent trading in fictitious or alloyed gold and similar commodities. According to Siddhasena, it means alloying of gold, silver, brass, copper, oil, ghee, milk or curds with materials that resemble them in colour, weight and other properties.4 It is clear from the foregoing account of the aticāras of the vow of non-stealing that the vow is very comprehensive and forbids almost all such acts of direct or indirect theft as are punishable under modern law. Vow of brahmacarya (celibacy) : The vow of brahmacarya, which literally means 'treading into the soul', stands for abstinence from sexual intercourse. In wider sense, any action which leads to extroversion goes against this vow. The importance of brahmacarya has been emphasised since Vedic times.5 In Jainism, which lays more emphasis on ascetic qualities than Brāhmaṇism, brahmacarya occupies a much more important place. In Brāhmaṇism, the position is quite different because marriage is considered to be a social obligation. This is not so in Jainism where total avoidance of sex is highly extolled. All these traditions, however, agree in prohibiting the sexual intercourse beyond one's duly married wife (svadāra). Samantabhadra has, therefore, included in this vow renunciation of contact with another man's wife and remaining contented with one's own wife." Somadeva has advised to consider all women except one's wife, as mother, sister, or daughter. According to him the ten concomitants of sexual desire are wine, meat, gambling, music including songs and dance, bodily decoration, intoxication, libertines and aimless wanderings.7 1. Caritrasāra, pp. 10-11. 2. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvärthasutra, 7.22. 3. Caritrasāra, p. 11. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvärthasutra, 7.22. 4. 5. Atharvaveda, 11.5. 6. Ratnakarandaśrāvakācāra, 59. 7. Handiqui, K. K., Tasastilaka and Indian Culture, pp. 266-267. Page #139 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 122 Jaina Ethics The five transgressions of this yow are as follows: (1) Itvaräparigrhītāgamana : The word 'itvarā' has been explained as harlot or a kept woman, Asādhara calls this transgression by the name of itvarikāgamana, explaining 'itvarā' not merely as harlot but as any woman leading a disorderly life 3 (2) Aparigrhitāgamana : The word 'aparig!hita' has been explained as 'harlot', 'widow' or 'ownerless'. Both in the first and the second cases transgression of original vow of svadārasantoșa is involved.4 (3) Anangakrīdā : It includes use of artificial phalli, caressing the sexual organs to influence desire.5 Obviously, this goes againt the common standards of chastity and should be avoided. (4) Kāmabhogativrābhilāşa : Literally, it means an excessive desire for sexual intercourse. It means that sexual passions even in relation to ones's own wife should not cross a limit. Siddhasena Ganin includes the use of artificial means for excessive sexual enjoyments under this transgression. (5) Paravivāhakaraṇa : Here the word 'para' excludes one's own children which a householder has to get married not only as social obligation but also as a duty of saying them from going astray.? A householder, however, should not indulge in unnecessarily arranging marriages of others which may only indicate his excessive interest in sexual indulgence. The vow of non-possession Aparigraha has been explained as mūrchhā' or the hallucination of possessions.s Amitagati says that every violence is committed for parigraha ;' therefore, a householder should constantly try to limit his activities for possessions. 1. Upasakadašānga, 1.48. 2. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvārthas ütra, 7.23. 3. Sagaradharmāmsta, 4.58. 4. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.23. 5. Ibid., 7.23 6. Ibid., 7.23. 7. Ibid., 7.23. 8. Daśavaikālika, 6.20, Also Tattvārthasūtra, 7.16. 9. Amitagatisrāvakācāra, 6.75. Page #140 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 123 Parigraha is the result of mohakarma, which is the main obstacle to self-realisation. Moha has two sides : (i) attachment and (ii) aversion. The former of these manifests itself as parigraha whereas the latter as himsā. Therefore, on its subjective side parigraha represents one side of moha, whereas hiṁsā represents another side. Aparigraha, therefore, is as important as non-violence. Aparigraha is neither only non-attachment nor only nonpossession; it is both. It stands, in its inner meaning, for non-attachment. To be particular, inner parigraha includes mithyādarśana, four kaşāyas and nine nokaṣāyas. 2 These are, as it were, symbols of attachment and should be avoided for the perfection of this vow. • The external parigraha is classified under ten heads : (1) kşetra (land) (2) vāstu (house) (3) hiranya (coins etc. of gold) (4) suvarņa (gold) (5) dhana (livestock etc.) (6) dāsi (maid servants) (7) dāsa (men servants) (8) kupya (jewels etc.) (9) sayyāsana (bed), (10) other luxury items.3 Transgressions of the vow of non-possession The five transgressions of the vow of non-possession are :4 (1) Kșetra-vāstu-pramāṇātikramana : This means adding a field or a house to the existing one in order to save himself from breaking the vow under which he must have fixed the number. Though the number of the fields or houses does not exceed the fixed limit yet the spirit of the vow is violated. (2) Hiranyasuvarṇapramāṇātikramaņa : This means giving some newly acquired precious articles to one's acquaintance with the understanding that he will return the same to hi after the expiry of the time for which he may have taken the vow. (3) Dhanadhānyapramāṇātikramana : This means keeping 1. Puruşarthasiddhyupāya, 113. 2. Ibid., 116. 3. Caritrasāra, p. 12. 4. Upāsakadaśānga, 1.49. Also Tattvārthas ütra, 7.24. for explanations of these aticāras. 5. Cf. Hemacandra on Yogaśāstra, Bhavanagar, 1926, 3.56 (p. 195). Page #141 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 124 Jaina Ethics extra grains etc. at some place to bring it to one's house when the commodity that already exists is exhausted. (4) Dvipadacatuspadapramāṇātikramaņa : This means so arranging that even though the animals do not actually give birth to the younger ones during the period of vow, they become pregnant and give birth to the younger ones after the expiry of the period of the vow... (5) Kupyadhātupramāṇātikramana : This means welding ornaments to keep their number within the limit of the vow. Similarly, other objects may be acquired and joined with the already existing ones so as to keep the number unchanged and yet actually exceed the limit. These aticāras of aparigraha point to the weakness of human nature, which is often self-deceptive. A man may declare to the world that he is greedless and yet may satisfy his desire for acquiring new objects under one or the o pretext. Samantabhadra has given a different list of the atic of this vowi : (1) Ativāhana : Compelling the beasts of burden to cover more distance than they can easily do, out of greed. . (2) Atisamgraha : Hoarding of grains out of greed to sell them at higher price at a later date. (3) Ativismaya : To be extremely sad at a loss incurred in some transaction. (4) Atilobha : To desire for a higher price when a reasonable price has already been offered for an article. (5) Atibhāra-Vāhana : Overloading the animal out of greed. This means that a householder is expected to be a contented type of man. He should not sacrifice either his own spiritual well-being or the social well-being of others at the alter of uncontrolled greed. Hoarding and profiteering which are impediments to spiritual progress are also obstacles in establishing economic justice in the society, and retard social progress. The supplementary vows of a householder The following seven supplementary vows protect the 1. Ratnakarandaśrāvakācāra, 62. Page #142 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 125 above five anuvratas. These supplementary vows, collectively known as filavratas, include three gunavratas and four śikṣāvratas. The gunavratas according to Tattvārthasūtra are : 1. Digvrata, 2. Deśāvakāśika, 3. Anarthadaņdavrata. The Svetāmbara tradition replaces deśāvakāśikavrata by bhogopabhoga, a practice which is followed by Kundakunda, Kārtikeya, Samantabhadra and Āsādhara also. The four śikṣāvratas according to Tattvārthas ūtra are : 1. Sāmāyika, 2. Proșadhopavāsa, 3. Bhogopabhoga and 4. Ātithisamvibhāga.3 As Svetāmbara tradition includes bhogopabhoga in gunavratas, it replaces this vrata by deśāvakāśikat which, as shown above, is a guņavrata according to Tattvārthasūtra. Samantabhadra, Āsādhara and Kārtikeya follow the Svetāmbara tradition here also. Kundakunda replaces bhogopabhoga by sallekhana. Vasunandi divides this vrata into two : bhogavirati and paribhogavirati, the other two being dāna and sallekhana. It would be observed here that there is much difference of opinion regarding the list of guņavratas and sikṣāvratas and there is also some controversy as to the nature of these two categories which is clear from the fact that bhogopabhoga is a gunavrata according to one tradition and śikṣāvrata according to another. It may, however, be pointed out that there is no fundamental differenee amongst ācāryas, and they perhaps classify these vratas differently only due to their personal likings and not on a matter of principle. According to Samanlabhadra, the guņavratas increase the capacity of observing the five vows with greater determination and purity. In fact, by the observance of gunavratas, the aņuvratas attain the status of mahāvratas for a limited period with reference to the place falling outside the limits set by the aspirant.6 The śikṣāvratas, as the name shows, are helpful in 1. Tattvārthasūtra, 7.16. 2. Upāsak adaśānga, 1.11. (pp. 216-226). 3. Tattvārthasūtra, 7.16. 4. Upāsakadašānga, 1.11 (p. 227). 5. Ratnakarandaśrāvak ācāra, 67. 6. Ibid., 70. Page #143 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 126 · Jaina Ethics educating the aspirant for the higher life of complete renunciation. 1 Guňavratas Digurata and deśārakāśikavrata There seems to be no material difference between these two vratas. The idea of both of these vratas is to restrict the movements of a householder in order to avoid violence to the maximum extent and also to minimise his greed. For this purpose Dešāvak āśikavrata sets narrower limits but for a shorter time than digurata. Transgressions of digvrata The five aticāras of the digurata are? : 1. Urdhvadikpramāṇātikramaņa : It includes climbing on trees or ascending a mountain outside the limit one has set for himself. 2. Adhodikpramāṇātikramaņa : It includes descending into a well or the underground store-house outside the limit. 3. Tiryagdik pramānātikramana : It may mean travelling any direction outside the limit. Entering a cave outside the limit is also given as an example of this aticāra. 4. K setra-urddhi : This means extending the limits for freedom of movement. 5. Smrtyantardhāna : It means transgressing the limits through forgetfulness. Dešāvakāśikavrata : In the opinion of Svāmikärtikeya, 3 deśāvakāśikavrata limits the extent of territory of movement as well as the objects of senses, whereas according to Samantabhadra“, Deśāvakāśikavrata is connected with the limitation of the territory of movement only. Vasunandi has offered a different explanation. He says 1. Sāgāradharmāmsta, 5.1. 2. Upăsakadašānga, 1.50. Also Tattvārthas ütra, 7.25. 3. Kārtikeyānupreksā, 367. 4. Ratnakarandaśrāvakācāra, 92-93. Page #144 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder that under this vow one should renounce going to such places where the aṇuvratas are impossible or difficult to observe.1 Transgression of desavakäsikavrata :2 As already pointed out, the deśāvakāśikavrata sets limits narrower than set under the digoratas, but for a shorter time. It has, therefore, different types of transgressions. Obviously, as the duration of vrata is short, there is little possibility of forgetting the exact limit. The idea behind the transgression of desavakäsikavrata is that the vrati should have no direct or indirect connection with the territory falling outside the limits. 1. Anayana-prayoga: This means asking somebody to bring something from outside the limits. The idea is that one should not ask others to move in that area where he himself does not move under the vow.3 2. Presya-prayoga This means ordering one's servant to do some work outside the limits. Under first transgression the work is got done by request whereas under the second transgression it is got done by orders to a servant.4 3. Sabdānupāta: This means making some sound and giving hints to those who are outside the limits to do certain jobs.5 4. Rūpānupāta: Here some signs and gestures are used instead of sounds for the same purpose as in the previous case.6 127 5. Pudgalapraksepa: Here some article may be thrown for the same purpose.? Anarthadandaviramaṇavrala: This is included in gunavratas by all Jaina ācāryas. the name of the vow shows, it means abstaining from such As Vasunandiśravakācāra, 215. I. 2. Upasakadaśānga, 1.54. 3. Pujyapada on Tattvärthasutra, 7,31. 4. Ibid., 7.31. 5. Ibid., 7.31. 6. Ibid., 7.31. 7. Ibid., 7.31. Page #145 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 128 Jaina Ethics harmful activities as will do no good to the agent. Samantabhadra has pointed out that such activities are to be avoided even within the limits set under diguruta and deśāvakāśikavrata.? Five forms of anarthadaņdavrata : Pūjyapāda has mentioned the following five forms of Anarthadaņda : 1. Evil thinking (apadhyāna), 2. Advice to commit sin (pāpopadeśa), 3. Non-vigilant action (pramādācarita), 4. Giving of weapons of violence (hıṁsādāna), 5. Wrongreading (aśubhasruli).3 1. Apadhyāna : This involves (1) finding faults with others (2) wishing loss to others, (3) seeing wives of others with a lusty eye, (4) taking interest in other's dispute.4 Amrtacandra adds thoughts about hunting, victory, defeat, war, adultery and theft to these. In short, all ārthadhyāna and raudradhyāna is a form of apadhyāna. 2. Pāpopadeśa : It means giving instructions to a fellow man in sinful professions. Samantabhadra includes in it : (1) advising to buy cheap slaves to sell them dearer elsewhere (kleśavānijya), (2) to advise the same thing for beasts (tiryagvānijya), (3) to tell about the animals to hunters, or trappers (badhikopadeśa), (4) to advise about such activities as involve violence (ārambhakopadeśa ).6 Here it may be noted that though, Upāsakadaśānga did not prohibit agriculture, yet in Ratna karandaśrāvakācāra it is held to be a profession which involves violence; and, therefore, advising a man to cultivate the land is also prohibited under this vow.? 3. Pramādācarita or Pramādacaryā : Kārtikeyānuprekşā gives the following under Pramādācarita : (i) digging of land (ii) crushing stones, (iii) sprinkling water on lawns, (iv) burning fire, (v) plucking leaves, fruits or flowers and (vi) blowing wind.8 Āsādhara adds to these, obstructing the wind, irrigat1. Kārtikeyānuprekṣā, 343. 2. Ratnakarandafrāvakācāra, 74.. 3. Pujyapāda on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.21. 4. Kartikeyānuprekşā, 344 Also Ratnakarandaśrāvakācāra, 78. Puruşārthasiddhyupāya, 141. 6. Ratnakarandastāvakācāra, 76. 7. Ibid., 77. 8. Subhacandra on Kärtikeyānupreksā, 346. Page #146 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 129 ing a field, and unnecessary travelling under pramādācarita. Hemacandra has also included recreations like going to see a dance or drama, or playing with dice, or watching cockfights or sleeping for the whole night even when one is neither ill nor tired on account of journey.2 . 4. Himsādāna : pūjyapāda has explained it as supplying of poison, thorns, weapons, fire, rope, whips, staffs, and other such objects as may lead to violence.3 Svāmikārtikeya thinks that keeping of such violent animals as cats, and doing business in such materials as irons and lac come under this head. Hemacandra has pointed out that objects like carts, ploughs, etc. could be given only to one's son or other relatives as a sort of help. 5. Duḥśruti : It means listening to or reciting such stories which excite passion. Kārtikeya has given the example of reading Kāmaśāstra under this heading.? Aśādhara has given examples of each type of literature which may be included under this heading. Kāmas ātra is given as an example of sex literature, lataka of violence, vārtānīti of parigraha, vīrakathā of sāhasa, Brahmādvaita of mithyātva, vašikaraṇatantra of rāga, and text exalting the position of Brāhmaṇa as example of literature which incites pride (mada).8 The transgressions of anarthada ndavrata The five transgressions which defile the vow of anarthadandavrata according to Tattvārthas ūtra are as follows® : (i) kandarpa-licentious speech, (ii) kautkucya-obscene speech, (iii) maukharya-prattling senselessly, (iv) asamiksyādhikarana—acting without thought, (v) Upabhogādhi kya-excess in enjoyments. Somadeva also includes giving instructions for the follow 1. Sāgāradharmamyta, 5.10-11. 2. Yogaśāstra, 3.78-80. 3. Pujyapada on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.21. 4. Kärtikeyānuprek șă, 347. 5. Hemacandra on Yogaśāstra, 3.77 (p. 173). 6. Puruşärthasiddhyup āya, 145. 7. Kārtikeyānuprekşā, 348. 8. Sāgāradharmāmặta, 5.9. (p. 171) 9. Tattvārthasūtra, 7.27; Also Upāsakadašānga, 1.52. Page #147 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 130 Faina Ethics ing five as transgression of this vowl : 1. Deceit (vañcanāpravartana), 2. Harmful activity (ärambhapravartana), 3. Violence (himsāpravartana), 4. Overloading of animals (bhārādhikya), 5. Inflicting the animals excessively (ati klesa). Now we proceed to discuss the transgressions of anarthadaņdaviramaņa as shown by Tattvārthas ülra : 1. Kandarpa : It is associated with concupiscence.? According to Cāmundarāya kandarpa is the result of cāritramoha.3 2. Kautkucya : It means vulgar speech.4 The idea is that a frāvaka should be modest and should not be outspoken. 3. Maukharya : It means non-sensical and purposeless talking 5 The above three transgressions exhort a śrāvaka to use speech sparingly and carefully. 4. Upabhogādhikya : This refers to unnecessary accumulation of articles and avoidance of excessive use of ornaments etc. 5. Asamikspādhikaraṇa : This includes destroying life without any self-interest.? Bhogopabhogaparimāņavrata All Svetāmbara, and even amongst Digambaras Kundakunda, Samantabhadra, and Āsādhara, include bhogopabhogaparimāņavrata in gunavratas. The tradition of Tattvārthas ūtra, however, places it in sikşāvratas. The word upabhoga indicates those objects which can be used only once, for example, food, drink, garland. etc. The word paribhoga means objects which can be used. repeatedly as cover, ornaments, bed, seat, house, etc.3 Thus this vow 1. Handique, K.K.. : Yaśastilaka and Indian Culture, p. 269. 2. Garin, Siddhasena on Tattvārthas ütra, 7.27. 3. Caritrasāra, pp. 17-18. 4. Ibid., p. 18. 5. Ibid, p. 18. 6. Gamin. Siddhasena on Tattvārthas ātra, 7.27. 7. Ibid., 7.27. 8. Pujyapāda on Tattvārthas ātra, 7.21. Amitagatisrāvakācāra 6.93. Sāgäradharmāmrta 5.14. Page #148 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 131 means putting limit to the use of objects of up abhoga and paribhoga in order to minimise attachment to them. According to Ratnakaraṇḍa-śravakācāra, a thing may be renounced for the whole life, in which case it is called yama or for a limited period, in which case it is called niyama.1 It seems that as yama, or a vow taken for the whole life, it is taken to be gunavrata; and as niyama, it is taken to be a sikṣāvrata. That is, perhaps, the reason why there are two traditions about this vow as shown above. Things which should be renounced for the whole life include2 meat and honey which cause misery to those living beings who are possessed of more than one sense, (2) intoxicants like wine, opium etc., (3) such objects which cause injury to anantakayajiva or infinite living being, possessed of one sense, like ginger, raddish, carrot, butter, etc. (4) unsuitable means of conveyance or unsuitable ornaments, (5) the use of bizarre dresses. The main idea is that such objects as are unnecessary and cause hurdle in the spiritual development should be renounced for the whole life as this causes no difficulty for the aspirant even from worldly point of view. Objects, the renunciation of which, even though desirable, may create difficulty for a householder, may be renounced for a limited period only. Amongst such things are included food, conveyance, couch, betel-leaf, clothes, ornaments, music, singing, etc.3 Svāmikārtikeya has pointed out that the householder should renounce those things which he possesses or is likely to possess. Where is the use of renouncing a thing which one is not likely to possess? Amṛtacandra says that even such things as are not generally prohibited should be renounced for a limited period under this vow.5 The idea of all these ācāryas is that giving up objects of bhoga and upabhoga should not 1. Ratnakaranḍaśrävakācāra, 87. Also Sagaradharmamṛta, 5.14. 2. Sāgāradharmāmṛta, 5.15-17. 3. Ratnakaraṇḍaśrāvakācāra, 88-89. 4. Kartikeyanuprekṣā, 351. 5. Puruşarthasiddhyupaya, 164, Page #149 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 132 Jaina Ethics be a mere formality but should cut at the very root of attachment. Transgressions of bhogopabhogaparimāņavrata The transgressions of this vow according to Tattvārthasūtra are limited to restriction on food. They are eating of (1) articles having life, (2) articles mixed with other articles having life, (3) articles in contact with those having life, (4) articles not fully cooked, (5) articles conserved by fermentation.1 The Svetāmbara tradition replaces the third and fifth aticāras of this list by mentioning the consuming of uncooked food and hollow-vegetable products, respectively, as aticāra of this vrata. According to Somadeva, taking of prohibited food (nişiddhāhāra ) and such food, the preparation of which has not been supervised personally (avikṣitāhāra), are the first and fifth aticāras of this vow; the fourth is the same as that mentioned in the Tattvārthasūtra; and the second and third, though different in name, are substantially the same. Samantabhadra has made a substantial contribution in enhancing the scope of the aticāra of this vow. In keeping with the wider spirit of the vow, he enumerates the following aticāras? : (i) Lack of indifferenee to the poison of sensual pleasures (vişayavişato’nupekṣā). (ii) Remembering past pleasures ( anusmrti). (iii) Indulging in pleasures after enjoying them (atilaulya). (iv) Acute craving for pleasures in future (atitrşā). (v) Excessive indulgence (atyanubhāva). Now we take each aticāra individually : 1. Sacittāhāra : The word Sacitta means body of those who have one sense, as prthvikāya or apkāya or vegetables.3 Siddhasenagaộin says that anantakāyas are to be avoided. Vegetables etc. should be taken only when they have been rendered as acitta by cooking, etc. 1. Tattvärthasūtra, 7.30; Also Upāsakadaśānga, 1.51; Sāgardharmāmsta, 520. 2. Ratnakarandaśrävakācāra, go. 3. rogaśāstra, 3.98 (p. 196). 4. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvärthas ülra, 7.30. Page #150 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 133 2. Sacittasambandhāhāra : Any thing acitta associated with something sacitta, should also be avoided.1 3. Sacittasamifrāhāra : As the name itself shows it means taking of food a part of which is Sacitta.2 4. Abhişava : Cāmundarāya cites the sour gruels as an example of this kind of food.3 Āsādhara prohibits taking of such liquids as milk or rice-gruel in large quantities. 4 5. Duspakvoşadhi : Every grain should be fully cooked so as to ensure that it is not sacitta.5 The essence of these aticāras is that least harm is done to the living beings for the sake of food and our sense of taste is kept under control. Amrtacandra has said that renunciation of bhogopabhoga leads to the avoidance of hiṁsā.6 It is but natural that in Jainism, where householder's life is nothing but a stepping-stone to monk's life, self-denial to the utmost possible should have been recommended from the very beginning. Siksāvratas Sāmāyikavrata Except Vasunandin, all other ācāryas accept sāmāyika to be a śikṣāvrata. Literally, sāmāyika means the practice of becoming one (ekatvagamana) with the ätman.? In other words, it means practising equanimous state of mind. Samantabhadra has said that a householder, while performing sāmāyika, is like a monk on whom clothes have been put by others. 8 Svāmi kārtikeya mentions place, time and posture for sāmāyika.' The place for sāmāyika should be free from disturbances such as noise, crowd, mosquitoes and insects.10 The 1. Pūjyapāda on Tattvārthasūtra, 7-35. 2. Tattvārthasūtra, 7.35. 3. Cāritrasāra p. 25. 4. Sāgāradharmāmsta, 5.20. 5. Caritrasāra, p. 25. 6. Pūruşārthasiddhyupāya, 166. 7. Pujyapäda on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.21. 8. Ratnakarandastāvakācāra, 102, Also Kārtikeyānuprekṣā, 357. 9. Kārtikeyānuprekṣā, 352, 10. Ibid., 353 Page #151 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 134 Jaina Ethics sāmāyika could be performed thrice a day1 or at least twice a day. In fact, it may be performed as many times as possible. The day of fasting is specially suited for sāmāyika.1 The duration should be gradually increased as one gets prac tised to it. As for postures, any sitting or standing posture which is convenient is good for sāmāyika.5 Adopting humble and surrendering gestures, the aspirant should either repeat some devotional hymn or should get absorbed in self-meditation." He should show forbearance under adverse circumstances and should keep his body, mind and speech steadfast." Transgressions of sāmāyikavratas The five transgressions of sāmāyikavrata are ; 1. Misconduct of speech (vāgduṣpraṇ dhāna) 2. Misconduct of body (kayaduspraṇidhāna) Misconduct of mind (manoduspraṇidhāna) 3. 4. Lack of interest in sāmāyika (anādara) 5. Forgetfulness in due observance of sāmāyika (smṛtyanupasthāna).8 1. Vagduspranidhana: It means hasty recitation of text without understanding its meaning.9 2. Kayaduspraṇidhāna: This means that parts of body should be kept steady.10 3. Mānoduspraṇidhāna: Anger, avarice, deceit, pride, envy and other such feelings, if entertained at the time of sāmāyika, constitute this aticara.11 Camunḍaraya says that absentmindedness at the time of sāmāyika constitutes this aticara.12 1. Kartikeyanuprekṣa, 354. 2. Puruşarthasiddhyupāya, 149. 3. Ibid., 149, Also Sagaradharmamṛta, 5.29. 4. Ratnakaranḍaśrävakācāra, 100-101. 5. Kartikeyanuprekṣā, 355. 6. Ibid., 355-356. 7. Ratnakaranḍaśrāvakācāra, 103. 8. Tattvärthasutra, 7.28. Also Upasakadaśänga, 1.53. 9. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvärthasutra, 7.28. Also Caritrasära, p. 20. Ibid., 7.28. Also Ibid., p. 20. 10. 11. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvärthasutra, 7.28. 12. Caritrasara, p. 20. Page #152 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 135 4. Anādara : It is explained as lack of zeal in the performance of sāmāyika. 5. Smrtyanupasthāna: This means forgetfulness in sāmāyika; one may forget whether he has performed it or not. This type of forgetfulness is condemned for a man who wants to attain liberation 2 Prosadhopavāsavrata : Almost every religion prescribes some type of control over food. Fast is considered to be a means of self-purification. Gāndhīji used fast as a self-purificatory measure in modern times, even to remove social evils as untouchability. With the Jainas, whether a householder or a monk, fast is a common practice. Under proșadhopavās avrata, a Jaina householder is expected to fast on aştami, caturdaši and pūrnimā.3 Fasting includes not only abstinence from food, but also avoidance of bath, perfumes, physical adornment, use of ornaments and sinful activities and observance of brahmacarya.4 Pūjyapāda has laid emphasis on abstinence from the pleasures of senses, so much so that even sounds which give pleasure to ear are to be avoided.5 Āśādhara, 6 Vasunandin,? Amrtacandra8 and others have prescribed the procedure for fasting. Though having some differences in details, it is almost the same in its moral contents. Meditation, study of the scriptures, worship of Jina, saluting and feeding the sādhus, vigilance in conduct, and thinking of anuprekşās are some of the duties of the aspirant while fasting.' He should sleep on a mat on ground and should avoid sinful activities. 10 1. Cāritrasāra, p. 20. 2. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.28. 3. Ibid., 7.16. 4. Umāsvāti on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.16. Also Kartikeyānuprekṣā 358; Ratnakarandaśrārakācāra, 107-108; Amitaga tiśrävakācāra, 6. 89. 5. Pujyapāda on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.21. 6. Sāgāradharmāmặta, 5. 36-38. 7. Vasunandiśrāvakācāra. 280-289. 8. Puruşārthasiddhyupāya, 152-157. 9. Sāgāradharmāmsta, 5-36-38. 10. Puruşārthasiddhyurāya, 153-154 Page #153 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 136 Transgression of proșadhopavāsavrata Tattvärthas ūtra gives the following five aticāras of prosadhopavāsavrata : 1. Apratyavekṣitāpramarjitotsarga: This means that bodily discharge should not be thrown on a spot which is not wellexamined and swept.1 2. Apratyavekṣitāpramārjitādānanikşepa: Similar care should be taken while picking up or laying down any object like sticks, etc.2 Pujyapāda includes careful handling of objects used for Jinapūjā or in obeisance to the guru.3 3. Apratyavekşitäpramärjita-samstara: The same care should be taken in handling one's bed, which should be made of kusā or blanket.4 4. Anādara : It means lack of zeal in performing the necessary duties.5 What is desirable is withdrawing oneself from food and worldly enjoyments, not only outwardly but inwardly also. 5. Smrtyanupasthana: This aticara corresponds to the last aticara of sāmāyika. It means forgetfulness about the observance of proṣadhopavāsa. It also means lack of concentration of mind in observing the fast." Atithis amvibhāgavrata Samantabhadra extends the scope of this vrata, by calling it Vaiyyavṛtya, which means any physical service including removal of ailments or massaging of feet of the monk.8 Kartikeya defines atithisamvibhāgavrata as offering of four kinds of gifts to the three kinds of recipients in conformity with the nine-fold process. Tattvārthas utra mentions the 1. Pujyapada on Tattvārthasutra, 7.34. 2. Ganin, Siddhasena on Ibid., 7.29. Jaina Ethics 3. Pujyapada on Ibid., 7.34. 4. Ganin, Siddhasena on Ibid., 7.34. 5. Ibid., 7.28-29. 6. Ibid., 7.28-29. 7. Sāgāradharmāmṛta, 5.40. 8. Ratnakaraṇḍaśravakācāra, 112. 9. Kartikeyanuprekṣā, 360-361. Page #154 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 137 following four factors to be considered in dānal: (i) The manner of giving (dānavidhi). (ii) The object which is given (dātavya). (iii) The giver (dāt;). (iv) The recipient (pātra). Vasunandin adds the result of giving dāna as the fifth factor to this list.2 The three kinds of recipients are : (a) The best recipient, which means a Jaina ascetic. (b) The second best recipient, which means an aspirant, who is ascending the ladder of the Pratimā. (c) The least satisfactory recipient, which means a man with right faith but not observing the vows. The recipients of gift are classified into three other categories of kupātra, apātra, karuņāpātra. A man who observes the moral laws but is devoid of samyagdarśana is cailed kupātra. 4 In this connection, we have already discussed the importance samyagdarśana. Worse is apatra, who has neither samyagdarśana normoral virtues. Children, old and destitute persons are considered to be karunāpātras. As for the giver. he must be possessed of the following seven virtues? : (1) Faith (śraddhā) regarding the result of almsgiving (2) Devotion (bhakti) towards the virtues of the recipient. (3) Pleasure (tuşļi) in giving (4) Knowledge (vijñāna) of the propriety of gifts for different types of recipients. (5) Unattachment (alaulya) towards worldly rewards. (6) Forbearance (kşamā) even in the face of instigation. (7) Enthusiasm (sakti) for almsgiving even if one is not so rich. 1. Pujyapāda on Tattvārthas ülra, 7.39. 2. Vasunandiśrāvakācāra, 220. 3. Ibid., 221-222. Also Puruşārthasiddhyupāya, 171; Amitagatisrāvakācāra, 10.4; Sagaradharmāmta. 5.44. 4. Amitagatistāvakācāra, 10.34-35, Also Vasunandiśrārakācāra, 223. 5. Ibid., 10.36-38. 6. Vasunandiśrävakācāra, 235. 7. Amitagatisrāvakācāra, 9.3-10. Also Vasunandiśrärakācāra 224; Sagara dharmāmặta, 5.47. Page #155 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 138 Jaina Ethics The Tattvarthabhāṣya gives a slightly different list 1 (1) Absence of ill-will (Anasuya) towards the recipients. (2) Absence of defection (avisāda) in giving. (3) Absence of condescension (aparibhāvitā) towards the recipient. (4) Joy (pritiyoga) in giving. (5) Purity of mind (kusalabhisandhita) (6) No desire for worldly result (dṛṣṭa-phalanapekṣitā). Straightforwardness (nirupādhitva). (7) (8) Freedom from desire of rebirth in heaven, etc. (anidānatva). As for things worthy of gifts, the following four kinds of gifts have been recognised: food, medicine, books and fearlessness.2 Camunḍaraya adds to these the place of shelter.3 All these things should be conducive to observance of austerities and study and should be such as do not bring about attachment or aversion.4 The method of giving is as important as the giver, gifts and the recipient. The following nine modes have been recommended5 : 1. Reception (pratigraha) to the monk with the words 'namo'stu'. 2. Offering a high seat (uccāsana) to the monk. 3. Washing of feet (padodaka ). 4. Adoration (arcana) of the monk. 5. Salutation (praṇāma) to the monk. 6-8. The giver should be possessed of purity of mind (manaḥsuddhi), speech (vacanaśuddhi) and body (kayasuddhi). 9. The food to be offered should also be pure (āhāraSuddhi). Transgressions of Atithisamvibhāgavrata Regarding the five aticāras of atithisamvibhāgavrata, the Svetämbara and Digambara traditions agree, except that the third of these aticāras is called anādara by Samantabhadra. I. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvarthasutra, 7.34. 2. Vasunandiśravakācāra 233-238 Also Kartikeyanuprekṣā, 362. 3. Caritrasāra, p. 27. 4. Puruşarthasiddhyupaya, 170. 5. Subhacandra on Kartikeyanuprekṣā, 360-361. Page #156 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 139 1. Sacittaniksepa: As a monk cannot accept the food which is associated with something sentient, the giver commits a transgression if he places food on a green leaf.1 Siddhasena says that one may purposely do so because then the food would not be accepted by the Sadhu and the householder will be benefitted.2 2. Sacittapidhāna: Covering of food with a sentient thing, like leaf, constitutes this aticāra.3 3. Kālātikrama: This means offering of food at inappropriate time. The Svetambara tradition ascribes intention of avoiding almsgiving by asking a Sadhu to accept food at such time when he is not allowed to take food.4 4. Paravyapadesa Pujyapada explains this as offering alms of others as if they were one's own. 5 Siddhasena says that it means telling the monk that the objects of alms do not belong to him and that the monk should ask somebody else for the same." 5. Mātsarya: It means lack of respect for the monk.7 Siddhasena thinks that anger shown to soliciting monk, or envy at some rich neighbour who offers rich alms, constitutes this aticāra.8 Sallekhanavrata Samantabhadra, 9 Vasunandin,10 and Asadhara11 give a detailed description of this ritual of voluntary death. The nature of Sallekhanā is such that one is likely to confuse it with suicide. The Jaina ācāryas have, therefore, tried to distinguish it from suicide. Pujyapada says that rāga, I. Pujyapada on Tattvarthasutra, 7.36. 2. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvärthasutra, 7.31. 3. Pujyapada on Tattvärthasutra, 7.36. 4. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvärthasutra, 7.31. 5. Pujyapada on Tattvarthas utra, 7.36. 6. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvrathasutra, 7.31. 7. Pujyapada on Tattvarthasutra, 7.36. 8. Ganin, Siddhasena on Tattvärthasutra, 7.31. 9. Ratnakaranḍaśrāvakācāra, 122-129. 10. Vasunandiśravakācāra, 271-272. 11. Sägaradharmamɣta, 8.1-110. Page #157 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 140 Jaina Ethics which underlies suicide, is absent in sallekhanā.1 Sallekhanā, therefore, is justified if the body becomes incapable of observance of vratas. Similarly, Asadhara defends sallekhana for the protection of dharma." He says that what a man does at the last moment is very important. Hemacandra says that sallekhana is a sort of udyapana, as it were, for the śravaka dharma.4 In view of what has been said above, sallekhana has been recommended when someone is confronted with calamity, famine, senility, disease, and when the sustenance of spiritual practices is endangered.5 Sallekhana can also be practised at a time when the natural death is known to be at hand." It is better to die a voluntary death with self-control than try to save the body in vain, when it ceases to respond to medical treatment.? The idea underlying sallekhanā is not mere flagellation of the body but denial of passions also.8 Voluntary death is not so difficult as upholding self-control, when the vital forces leave the body. If the mind is not pure at the last moment, the life-long self-control, study, austerity, worship and charity become futile, just as a king, well-versed in weapons, is no good if he faints in the battle-field.10 It is repeated by every ācārya that renunciation of attachment and aversion is a necessary corollary of sallekhanā. Thus Samantabhadra says that one performing sallekhanā should put aside all affection and enmity, should ask for forgiveness to all and should himself forgive all. He should make an honest confession of his misdeeds, kṛta, kārita or anumata. 1. न सल्लेखनां प्रतिपन्नस्य रागादयः सन्ति ततो नात्मवधदोषः । -Pujyapada on Tattvärthasutra, 7.22 Also Sāgāradharmāmṛta, 8.8 Sāgāradharmāmṛta, 8.7. 2. 3. Ibid., 8.28. 4. श्रावकः किल सकलस्य श्रावकधर्मस्योद्यापनार्थमिवान्ते संयमं प्रतिपद्यते । -Hemacandra on Yogaśastra, 3.149 (p. 272b). 5. Ratnakaraṇḍaśrāvakācāra, 122. 6. Sāgāradharmāmṛta 8.20. Also Amitagatisravakācāra, 6.98. 7. Sāgāradharmamṛta, 8.7. 8. Ibid., 8.22. 9. Ibid., 8.24. IO. Handiqui, K.K., Yasastilaka and Indian Culture, p. 287. . Page #158 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder He should abandon all dissatisfaction, sorrow, fear and turpitude. Then he should renounce, in the first stage, intake of solid food and then of fatty liquids and acid in liquids, respectively.1 Vasunandin does not think it necessary to assume mahāvratas2 while performing sallekhana, whereas Asadhara and Samantabhadra think it obligatory and recommend nudity not only for men but even for women at this last moment of life.3 Transgressions of Sallekhnavrata Tattvärthasutra gives the following five transgressions of sallekhanävratas :4 1. Desire to live (jivitāśamsā) 2. Desire to die (maraṇāśaṁsā) 3. Remembrance of friends (mitrānurāga) 4. Revival of past pleasure (sukhānubandha) 5. Expectation of future prosperity (nidana) Samantabhadra replaces the fourth aticara by fear'.5 Upasakadaśānga gives the following five aticārasR : 1. Longing for this world (ihalokāśaṁsā) 2 Longing for the next world (paralokāśaṁsā) 3. Longing for life (jivitāśāṁsā) 4. Longing for death (maraṇāśaṁsā) 5. Longing for sensual pleasures (kāmabhogāśaṁsā). We explain below the aticaras of sallekhanavrata : 1. Jivitāśamsa: Pujyapāda explains it as reluctance to leave this body." Asadhara thinks that the desire to listen to one's own praise from those who surround the dying man constitutes this aticăra. 1. Ratnakaranḍaśrāvakācāra, 127-128. Cf. Vasunandiśravakācāra, 271-272. 141 2. 3. Sägaradharmāmṛta. 8.35-38. 4. Tattvärthasutra, 7.32; Also Puruṣārthasiddhyupāya, 195; Amitagatisrāvakācara, 7.15 and Sagaradharmamṛta, 8.45. 5. Ratnakaranḍaśravakācāra, 129. 6. Upāsakadaśānga. 1.57. 7. Pujyapada on Tattvärthasutra, 7.37. 8. Sägäradharmāmṛta, 8.45. Page #159 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 142 Jaina Ethics 2. Maraņāśāṁsā : Pūjyapāda explains it as desire for quick death.1 3. Mitrānurāga : This includes remembering one's friends, games of childhood, merry festivities etc. The Svetāmbaras do not recognize this aticāra. 4. Sukhānubandha : This means recollection of past comforts and pleasures.3 5. Nidāna : One should not desire sensual satisfaction in the next life as a reward for performance of sallekhanā. The Pratimās Kundakunda,5 Kārtikeya, Samantabhadra? and Vasunanding refer to Pratimās whereas Umāsvāti and Amrtacandra do not. All Digambara ācāryas, except Svāmi Kārtikeya, speak of twelve pratimās;' and Upāsakadaśārgalo speaks of eleven pratimās. Svāmi Kārtikeya, in fact, thinks samyagadarśana and avoidance of gross faults as two separate pratimās whereas other ācāryas combine these two into one, viz. darśanapratimă. Somadeva, here as elsewhere, has a way of his own. In the first place, he changes the order of the pratimās and then replaces rātribhuktivirati by divāmaithunavirati (divābrahma).11 1. Darśanapratimā In the first stage of spiritual development, the Srāvaka is required to give up the use of meat, wine, etc. According to Vasunandin, in this pratimā the śrāvaka should abandon the use of five udumbara fruits, and should also refrain from gambling, meat, wine, honey, hunting, prostitution, adultery, and stealing, 12 He also thinks it proper that the śrāvaka, even in this first stage, should renounce eating at night. 1. Pūjyapāda on, Tattvārthasütra, 7:37. Caritrasāra, p. 50. 3. Ibid., p. 50. 4. Ibid., p. 50. 5. Caritràpāhuda, 22. 6. Kārtikeyānupreksā, 305-306. 7. Ratnakarandaśrāvakācāra, 137-147. Vasunandiśrāvakācāra, 4. 9. Kārtikeyānuprekṣā, 305-306. 10. Upāsakadašānga, 1.71. II. Vasunandiśrāvakācāra, prastāvanā, p. 50. 12. Vasunand išrāvakācāra, 59. Page #160 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 143 The Mūlagunas are also attached to darśanapratima; and Somadeva calls this pratimă as mūlavrata. Samantabhadra and jinasena include five small vows in mūlaguņas whereas Somadeva does not. Vasunandin follows the middle path by saying that a Śrāvaka should renounce seven vyasanas in this pratimā,1 as these seven vyasanas indirectly include four out of five sins, viz. violence, falsehood, stealing and unchastity. 2. Vratapratimā : Samantabhadra 2 and other Digambarācāryas think that in this stage, a śrāvaka should observe the twelve vratas mentioned in this chapter. 3-4. Sāmāyika and Proşadhapratimā : It may be noted that sāmāyika and prosadhopavāsa are enjoined as separate pratimās, whereas they are included in the second pratima also. Āsādhara tries to explain this position by saying that sâmāyika and proşadhopavāsa as śikṣāvrata are meant for safeguarding the five anuvratas and, therefore, occupy only a subservient position, whereas in pratimās they assume the position of an independent vrata.3 Vasunandin had perhaps this duplication in his mind when he excluded sāmāyika and proșadhopavāsa from the list of sikşāvratas and represented them as pratimās only. Kundakunda and Kārtikeya, on the other hand, have preferred to enumerate them, both as pratimās and fiksāuratas, perhaps to show their importance for spiritual progress. We have already dealt with Sāmāyika and proșadhopavāsa while dealing with sikşāvratas. 5. Sacittalyāga pratinā This pratinā consists in abandoning the use of animate articles like roots, fruits, seeds, etc. without getting them sterilized by boiling etc.4 The Srāvaka in this pratimā is required not to feed others by such objects as he himself has renounced.5 1. Vasunandi-śrāvakācāra, 57. 2. Ratnakarandaśrāvakācāra, 138. 3. Sāgāradharmāmsta, 7.6. 4. Kārtikeyānupreksā, 379. 5. Ibid., 380. Page #161 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 144 6. Ratribhuktivirati pratimā Kundakunda,1 Kartikeya,2 and Samantabhadra take this pratimă to mean abstinence from taking of food at night. Amitagati, Vasunandin5 and Somadeva represent the other school and call this pratima by the name of divāmaithunavirati i.c. abstinence from sexual intercourse during day. Asadhara is here influenced by Hindu conception of brahmacarya and says that a śrāvaka in this pratimā renounces all intercourse except during rtu for the sake of progeny The first school distinguishes abstinence from taking food in the night in the first pratima from this pratima, in as much as here the frāvaka is required not to offer food to others also at night. 7. Brahmacarya pratimā It implies absolute continence. It covers not only intercourse but all types of contacts with women. It also includes avoidance of decorating one's body." 8. Arambhatyaga pratimā It signifies the renunciation of all worldly occupations as service, cultivation and business. The aspirant under this pratima should neither ask others to do such jobs nor give his consent for doing such jobs.10 9. Parigrahatyaga pratimā It means abandonment of all kinds of parigraha, except limited clothes.11 Parigraha here includes external possession as well as inner faults, perverted attitude, sex, humour, passion, attachment and aversion.11 1. Caritrapahuḍa, 22. 2. Kartikeyanuprekṣā, 382. 3. Ratnakaranḍaśrāvakācāra, 142, 4. Amitagatisravakācāra, 7.72. 5. Vasunandiśrāvakācāra, 296. 6. Vasunandiśravakacara, prastavana, p. 50. Jaina Ethics 7. Sāgāradharmamṛta, 7.14. 8. Kartikeyanuprekṣā, 382. 9. Sāgāradharmamṛta, 7.27; Also Kartikeyanupreksa, 385. 10. II. Vasunandiśravakācāra, 299. Subhacandra on Kartikeyanupreksā 386. Page #162 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Householder 10. Anumatityāgapratimā Under anumatityāga, a śrāvaka should also withdraw himself from all worldly affairs and should leave everything worldly to fate.1 Svetambaras call it 'presyatyāga' pratimā and its description includes both parigrahatyāga and anumatityāga. 11. Uddiṣṭatyāga Under this pratimā, the Śrāvaka does not take any food specially prepared for him.2 Vasunandi mentions two divisions of this pratima, which are called 'ksullaka' and 'ailaka'.4 145 This difference between 'kṣullaka' and 'ailaka' is mainly in their dress. The kṣullaka has an upper garment also whereas the ailaka has only a loin cloth. The former applies instruments for cutting his hair, keeps a broom in place of picchi, takes his meals once a day either in the palm of his hands or in some pot in a sitting posture, and observes fast on every parvan day. The latter pulls out his hair (this act is called luñcana) and takes his meals in the palm of his hands.5 Conclusion Thus we see that in Jainism the conduct of a householder occupies a subserviant position to that of a monk. In ' fact, the life of a householder is just a stepping-stone to the life of a monk. We find that Jaina ācāryas have covered almost every quality of good and honest citizens while giving the details of transgressions of different vows. The minuteness with which they describe these aticāras show their close familiarity with the working of human mind, which generally inclines towards evil under some excuse or the other. 1. भवियव्वं भावंतो अणुमण विरओ हवे सो दु । -Ibid., 388. 2. Ibid., 390. 3. Vasunandiśrāvakācāra, 301. 4. For the history of this division, see introduction to Vasunandiśravakācara, pp. 60-64. 5. Vasunandiśravakācāra, 302, 303, 311, Page #163 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 146 Jaina Ethics It may also be pointed out that the descriptions of the conduct of a householder by different ācāryas differ in detail, but the fundamental spirit behind these rules has remained unchanged through ages. Page #164 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CHAPTER VI THE CONDUCT OF A JAINA MONK Position of an ascetic in Jainism Jainism is an ascetic religion from the very beginning whereas the institution of samnyāsa is most probably of later origin in Brāhmaṇism. The grhastha stage occupies the place of pride in Brāhmaṇism, whereas in Jainism ghastha stage is only a means to the higher goal of monkhood. Later on, in Hinduism also, the division of life (aśrama) into four stages accorded a proper place to asceticism. It may also be pointed out that Jainism has retained its ascetic character till modern times. Brāhmaṇism, on the other hand, has been influenced by such ascetic religions as Jainism and Buddhism. The Hinduism of the Purānas shows greater inclination for samnyāsa than that of the Vedas. In Sāntiparva of the Mahābhārata, we find this conflict of the older Vedic religion of activity with the newer Hindu religion of renunciation.2 It is due to this, that in Jaina tradition even a śrävaka is taught yatidharma prior to śrāvaka dharma, so that he is attracted by the life of a monk rather than remain attached to householder's life.3 It is in contradiction to Hinduism where the study of Vedas, which are books of action (karmakānda), precedes the study of Vedānta, or jñānakāņda. There is every reason to believe that the ascetic tendency of later systems of Hindu philosophy is due to the influence of Buddhism and Jainism. The conduct of a Jaina Monk The whole moral code for a Jaina monk should be viewed from a particular angle. Here the aspirant has decided to 1. Manusmrti, 3.77-78. 2. Cf. Samkşipta Mahābhārata, (ed.) C.V. Vaidya, Bombay, 1921, pp. 408-412. 3. Byhatkalpabhâsya, Bhayanagar, 1933, Vol. II, Gāthā 1139... Page #165 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 148 Jaina Ethics devote himself absolutely to spiritualism. Even though depending on society for such bare necessities of life as food, he is above all social obligations. His goal is transcendental morality which is beyond good or bad in the ordinary sense of the words. His life is predominated by niscayanaya or real point of view rather than by vyavahāranaya or practical point of view. In order to attain perfection, he has to avoid even smallest defects in his conduct even though this may make his living odd and inconvenient from a worldly point of view. ĭ The institution of Jaina monkhood has been traced to pre-Vedic periods.1 The description of Rsabhadeva in the Bhāgavata very much resembles the description of Jaina monk.3 Even though there has been some modification in the moral code of a Jaina monk, which will be noted at places in this chapter, it may be pointed out that the mode of living of a Jaina monk has essentially remained unchanged for all these ages. The study of the conduct of a Jaina monk, therefore, forms a unique chapter of Indian civilisation because here we can see the continuity of a great tradition for a considerably long period i.e. from pre-vedic age down to modern times. Qualifications for initiation into monkhood Originally, Jainism revolted against casteism. Harikesin, who was a Pariah, was taken into the order and thus the privilege given to particular castes for entering monkhood was extended to others also.3 Sthānangasūtra mentions that a eunuch, a sick person and a timid person should not be initiated and the commentary adds that the following categories of persons do not qualify for initiation (1) A child under eight years, (2) a person who is old and infirm, (3) devoid of limbs, (4) dull, (5) robber, (6) offending the king, (7) mad, (8) blind, (9) slave, (10) wicked, (11) stupid, (12) in debt (13) attendant, (14) kidnapped, (15) a pregnant woman (16) and a woman with a child.4 1. Anekanta, Varsa 10. Kirana 11-12, pp. 433-456. 2. Srimadbhāgavatapurana, 5.3, 4, 5 and 6. 3. Uttaradhyayana, 12.1. 4. Cf. Deo, S.B., History of Jaina Monachism, Poona, 1956, p. 140, footnote 3. Page #166 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 149 The Conduct of a Jaina Monk So far, we do not come across any restrictions of caste or birth and the conditions laid down are of a universal nature. But a glance at the following conditions, laid down by Dharmasamgraha, will prove that distinction of caste pres cribed by Brāhmaṇism entered Jainism too. According to Dharmasamgraha, a person who wants to take to monkhood, must (1) be born in an Aryan country, (2) belong to a higher caste, (3) be free from gross sins, (4) have a pure intellect, (5) know the transitory nature of worldly pleasures, (6) be detached from the world, (7) be mild in passions, (8) have semi-passions only, (9) be grateful, (10) be humble, (11) not be a political rebel or criminal, (12) be friendly to all, (13) have his body intact, (14) be faithful, (15) be steadfast, (16) and be anxious for initiation.1 Besides, Pravacanasaroddhära also prohibits initiation of an old man, of an effeminate person, of a person who is dumb or fattish or diseased and of those who practise condemnable professions or those who are not allowed by their relatives to renounce the world.2 Thus some of the conditions laid down for initiation refer to the physical fitness of the aspirant, while others refer to his moral fitness. But some of the conditions-that of birth in an Aryan country or a higher caste-are due to Brāhmaṇical influence. It should also be interesting to note that Nāradaparivrajakopanisad, a text for the Hindu Samnyasi, mentions almost the same conditions for initiation into Samnyāsa. Of course, it contains some sectarian references which are irrelevant for a Jaina monk. Types of monks Svetambara tradition mentions two types of Sādhus : (1) Jinakalpa; and (2) Sthavirakalpa. Jinakalpa Sadhu is supposed to be above the rules of monastery. He remains 1. Dharmasamgraha, 3.73-78 (p. 1) quoted from Sri Jaina Siddhanta Bola Samgraha, Vol. V, Bikaner, Vik. Sam. 2005, p. 158-161. 2. Pravacanasaroddhāra, Bombay, 1922, Gāthās 790 791 (p. 228a). 3. Minor Upanisads, Madras, 1912, Vol. I, pp. 136-137. 4. Visesavasyakabhāṣya, Ratalam, 1936, 7. Page #167 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 150 Jaina Ethics naked and eats in the hollow of his hands.1 Bṛhatkalpabhāṣya says that a Jinakalpa eats food within one 'porisi' of obtaining it,2 and does not go beyond the chief garden for begging his food.3 Sthavirakalpa monk resides in Samgha and is bound by its rules. He wears clothes and has requisites with him than Jinakalpa. a greater number of In The distinction of Jinakalpa and Sthavirakalpa cannot apply to Digambara monks, all of whom remain naked. Hinduism, of course, we can compare Jinakalpa with 'paramahamsa', 'turiyātita' or 'avadhuta' types of Sadhus whereas the sthavirakalpa can be compared to 'kuticaka', 'bahüdaka' and 'hamsa' types of ascetics.4 Among other classes of Jaina monks, sthānanga makes a mention of the following types: 2. 1. Pulāka who lacks a higher degree of mental purity. Bakufa who is slightly attached to his possessions. 3. Kuśila-who, though observing the primary rules of conduct, transgresses the secondary rules.5 All these types refer to such Sadhus as are a little inferior to real Sadhus and fall short of that high standard. There is another classification which mentions pseudo Sadhus of various types. 1. Pārsvastha-who try to earn their livelihood by religious observances. 2. Samasakta-who practise magic. 3. Avasanna-who, though outwardly observing all the rules of conduct, are devoid of right attitude and knowledge. 4. Mrgacaritra-who dissociate themselves with the Samgha and show looseness in character." Essential qualities of a monk : Mulācāra, the basic text for the conduct of a Digambara I. Max Müller, Sacred Books of the East, Vol. 22, p. 57, f. n. 2. 2. Bṛhatkalpabhāṣya, Vol. V. 5264-5267. 3. Ibid., Vol. V, 5290. 4. Cf. Sharma, Har Dutt, Contribution to the History of Brāhmaṇical Asceticism, Poona, 1939, pp. 30-31. 5. Sthananga, Ahmedabad, 1937, 5.3.445. 6. Jaina, C.R., Samnyasa Dharma, London, 1926, p. 23. Page #168 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Jaina Monk 151 monk, gives the following twenty-eight qualities of a monk. These qualities are known as Mūlaguņas. 1-5. Five great vows (pañcamahāvratas). 6-10. Five-fold path of vigilance (Pañcasamitis). 11-15. Control of five senses (Indriyajaya). 16-21. Six essential duties (Saḍāvasyakas). 22. Pulling out of the hair (Keśaluñcana). 23. Nudity. 24. Non-bathing. 25. Sleeping on the ground. 26. Not cleaning the teeth. 27. Taking food in standing posture. 28. Eating only once in twentyfour hours (Ekabhakta).1 The Svetambara tradition, as already shown, does not take nudity to be an essential quality of a monk. Besides this, the last two qualities also do not find a place amongst essentials of a monk in the Svetambara tradition. Both the sects claim antiquity for their respective traditions. The Svetämbara tradition enumerates the following essentials for a monk2 : 1. 1-5. Five great vows. 6. Not taking food in the night. 7-11. Controlling the five senses. 12. Inner purity. 13. Purity of possessions of a monk. 14. 15. 2. Forgiveness. Detachment. 16. Mental goodness. 17. Vocal goodness. Now, before coming to the outfit of a monk, which constitutes his secondary attributes, we shall deal with these primary qualities. 18. Physical goodness. 19-24. Protection of the six types of living beings. 25. Threefold discipline. 26. Forbearance. 27. Sallekhanävrata. Mülācāra, 1.2-3. Also Pravacanasara 3.8, 9; 9.84, 85. Sri Jaina Siddhantabolasaṁgraha, Vol. VI, pp. 228-230. Anagaradharmāmṛta, Page #169 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 152 Jaina Ethics The five great vows : The five great vows of a Jaina monk correspond to the five small vows of a Jaina householder. The five small vows have been framed keeping in view the social obligations of a householder. The great vows, however, are unconditional and absolute. It may be noticed that the earlier Anga literature lays more emphasis on these moral virtues than on the details about monastic life which comes under the jurisdiction of post-canonical literature. Even though the niryuktis and cūrņis take a liberal view of these vows, especially in case of emergency, the basic idea of these five great vows has remained intact through ages. Great vow of non-violence : The Jainas believe in the equality of all life. Therefore, the vow of non-violence includes abstinence from taking the life of any superior or inferior being in any form. Not only the 'trasa', or mobile forms of life, are not to be destroyed; but any violence to 'sthāvar a' or immobile, such as vegetables, fire, air, water and earth, is also to be avoided. Friendship for all, and subjugation of passions are necessary for ahiṁsā mahāvrata. We shall see how Jaina ācāryas have taken care in prescribing rules for movement, speech, thinking, handling of things and food, while we discuss five samitis.2 In reality, deviation from the path of self-realisation is violence.3 Attachment is suicidal for the aspirant. It is against this background of detachment that the vow of nonviolence is to be interpreted. The epigraphical records show that Jaina monks have shown remarkable vigilance in observing non-violence. Aryadeva is said to be so careful that he removed a straw from his ear very gently even while he was sleeping. The straw was placed 1. Jħānārņava, 8.11. 2. Mülācāra, 5.140; Also Anāgāradharmāmsta, 4.34; Tattvārthasūtra 9.5; Bhagavati Aradhana, 1206. 3. Amrtacandra on Pravacanasāra 3.16, and Jayasena on Pravacanasära, 3.17 4. Pañcādhyāyī, 2.756. Page #170 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Jaina Monk 153 in his ear by others to test him and was taken to be a worm by him.1 Nevertheless, there are references in the post-canonical literature to show that some concessions were made for the Jaina monk in this matter, as in others, in later periods. Great vow of truthfulness: The monk leaves all worldly activities and, therefore, for him truth carries a deeper meaning than mere statement of facts. Truth means a considerate mode of expression, a thoughtful speech which is beneficial for all. Truth and all other vows being subservient to cardinal virtue of non-violence, a speech that may cause pain should be avoided even though it may be objectively true. Truth, therefore, in its wider sense is not only a negation of lie but a negation of all which is injurious. This is clear from the following classification of non-truth.2 1. Lie (Alikavacana). 2. Insulting speech (Hilitavacana). 3. Teasing speech (Khimsitavacana). 4. Harsh speech (paruşavacana). 5. Speech used by householders, calling relatives by their relations as father, mother etc. (gṛhasthavacana). 6. Exciting speech (vyavasamitavacana). Mulācāra asks a monk to avoid all words under influence of attachment, aversion, jest, fear, anger and greed.3 Nisithas utra lays down that a monk should be modest, true and gentle in his speech and should not talk about worldly affairs or past quarrels.4 The study of Bṛhatkalpabhasya reveals some interesting facts regarding the observance of this vow by the monks. A Gitärtha, meaning an old monk, pretended to have used pure water (meaning water which has been rendered acitta) for I. Epigraphia Carnatica, Bengalore, 1923, Vol. II, 67(54), 1129 A.D. (pp. 23-30). 2. Sthänängas útra, 6.3.527. Also Pravacanasaroddhāra, 235.1133. 3. Müläcära, 5.141. Also Anāgāradharmamṛta, 4.45; Acarasara 5.41 and Bhagavati Aradhanā, 1207. 4. Nisitha, Agra, 1957, Vol. II, 2.18-19. 5. Bṛhatkalpabhäşya, Bhavanagar, 1936, Vol. III, 2882. Page #171 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 154 Faina Ethics washing clothes before a novice, even though the water was actually not acitta. For this purpose the Gitārtha monk used gulikā (explained as tubaravyksaguţikā) or khola, meaning a cloth dripped in milk. Both these were used to conceal the fact that sacitta water had been used to wash the cloth. Obviously, the intention of the Gitārtha was to avoid indulgence of the novice in improper behaviour. Nevertheless, it must be conceded that the Gitārtha lacked the moral courage to tell the truth to the novice. Similarly, we find the mention of a Jaina monk wearing the apparel of a heretic in order to seek food and drink. The vow of non-stealing The great vow of non-stealing is much more exhaustive than the smaller vow of non-stealing. Whatever little possession a monk has, is acquired by him by begging of the householders. No object, howsoever small, should be acquired or used by the monk without an express permission of the owner. The monk should refrain from taking any thing without being offered, not only in a village or a town, but also in a forest.2 Books etc. are also to be taken with permission. One should have an attitude of detachment towards one's possessions. Rules for obtaining food, which we shall mention separately, should be observed.5 Tattvārthasūtra speaks of certain rules for choosing one's residence also. It says that : 1. The monk should stay in a solitary place. 2. Or he should stay in a deserted place. 3. He should not deny other persons the right to stay where he is staying The idea is that he should not claim his residence as his personal property even for a limited period during his stay. This vow also implies that the monk should not quarrel with his fellow monks over any of his possessions.? 1. Brhatkalpabhāsya, Bhavanagar, 1936, Vol. III, 2882. 2. Mülācāra, 5.290. 3. Vasunandi on Mülācāra, 5.142. 4. Ibid., 5.142. 5. Infra. pp. 171-174. 6. Pujyapāda on Tattvārthasūtra, 7.6. 7. Ibid., 7.6. Page #172 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Jaina Monk 155 A study of prāyaścittas for transgression of this vow reveals some facts about the actual observance of this vow. There is prāyaścitta for an ācārya for stealing some requisites of his co-religionist, and also for a monk who secretly gathers extra requisites, or who has a duplicate set of requisites, or who refuses to give the requisites to his fellow monk on being asked to do so. It is also mentioned that it is a more serious sin to take away the requisites of a monk of a rival sect than that of one's own sect.? Vow of celibacy and sexual control The monk, being a celibate, should be absolutely free from any type of sexual desire. He is to abstain not only from intercourse but also from bodily decoration, sense indul. gence, exciting food, excessive food, songs and dance, association with women, exciting surroundings, passionate thinking, recalling past sexual enjoyment, and planning for future sexual enjoyment.3 Monks should have no connection with women. Even in emergencies like famine, political upsurge, or in uncongenial society, he should keep his senses under control.5 TattvārthaSūtra states the monk should avoid the following 6 : 1. Stories relating to attachment to women. 2. Looking at beauty of women. 3. Recalling past sexual enjoyments. 4. Rich delicious foods. 5. Decoration of the body. The list of prāyaścittas for transgression of this vow suggests that even monks sometimes yielded to the desire of the flesh.” The guiding principle before Jaina ācāryas, while fixing the rules of behaviour of a monk in relation to a nun, has been this vow of celibacy. 1. Byhatkalpabhāsya. Vol. V, Bhavanagar, 1938, 5064-5087. 2. Ibid., Vol. V, 5088. 3. Mülācāra, 10.105-106. Also Uttarādhyayana, 16.1-10; Bhagavati Arā. dhanā, 879-880; Anāgāradharmamặta, 4.61 and jñānārņava, 11.7-9. 4. Sūtrakrtānga, p. 272 (1.4.1.5). Also Uttarādhyayana, 16.1-10; Daśavaikälika, 2.9. 5. Bịhatkalpabhāsya, Vol. V, 4955-58. 6. Pūjyapāda on Tattvārthasūtra. 7.7. 7. Bịhatkalpabhâsya, Vol. III, 2258-2262. Page #173 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 156 Faina Ethics Vow of non-possession : Parigraha has been defined as mūrcchā or attachment. Attachment to anything is the cause of bondage and, therefore, should be avoided. In the state of meditation, a monk is self-absorbed and requires no paraphernalia. At other times, he requires certain objects for reasons of piety and decency, but he should not have any desire or attachment for such objects.2 Mülācāra, therefore, defines aparigraha as renunciation of sentient and insentient paraphernalia and nonattachment towards such objects as are allowed by the 'scriptures.3 As far as the definition of parigraha is concerned, both the Digambaras and the Svetāmbaras agree. But it would be observed that, as regards the objects which are allowed for a a monk, there is much difference of opinion between the two sects. Even amongst Svetāmbaras, the number of articles allowed for a monk seem to have increased by the passage of time. The main difference between the two sects is regarding the question of possession of clothes by a monk. We need not go into the details of this sectarian question, but it may be pointed out that this difference regarding the mode of living of a Jaina monk is a very old one and is referred to by Uttarādhyayana also.5 Kundakunda seems to have noted this difference, and according to tradition, he is also said to have had some debates with Svetõmbaras on this point. According to the Digambara tradition, a monk's possessions are classified under three heads : 1. Jñāno pādhi-or means of attaining knowledge. This includes Šāstras. 2. Samyamo pādhi—or means of observance of vows. This includes a broom of peacock feather. This broom helps in observing non-violence, because the monk can gently remove 1. 7997 qfaret a -Dasavaikälika, 6.20. 2. Daśvaikālika, 6.21. 3. Mülācāra, 1.9. 4. Cf. Tattvärthasūtra, 7.16. and Daśavaikälika, 6.20. 5. Uttarādhyayana, Lecture XXIII. 6. Mülācāra, 1.14. Page #174 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Jaina Monk 157 small insects with its help while handling something or while himself making movements. The peacock-feather broom does not get soiled either with dust or with sweat, it is soft and non-injurious, tender and light.1 3. Saucopādhi-or means of purity. It includes a kamandala in which acitta water can be carried for the purpose of of bodily cleanliness. The Acārāngas ūtra in the Svetāmbara tradition makes mention of four possessions of a monk : (1) Clothes (2) Alms-bowl (3) Blanket (4) Broom. The Mülasūtras are silent about the measurements etc. of these possessions. Chedas ūtra and Niryukti furnish us with these details. In post-canonical literature some new requisites for a monk were also allowed. To alms-bowl, for example, the following requisites were also added : 1. Pātrakabandha—a string to bind the pot. 3. Pātrakasthāpana-a base for the pot. Gocchaka-a small broom to clean the pot. 4. Pátrakasarikā—-a small piece of cloth for cleaning the pot. 5. Patala—a small piece of cloth to cover the pot. 6. Rajastrāna—a piece of cloth to wipe the pot.3 Besides, the monk can have : (1) a mukhavastrika to be tied over the mouth to prevent small insects from going in, (2) a staff (danda), (3) a bed-sheet, (4) an umbrella and (5) a piece of cloth to wipe the mud off one's feet in the rainy season. These paraphernalia are called ogha or essentials. Besides, a list of what a monk may occasionally require is also given. These are called Uvaggahiya (aupagrāhika). Amongst others, they include (1) needle (2) razor (3) nail-cutter (4) earcleaner.6 The following list, taken from Byhatkalpasūtra, shows 3 1. Bhagavati Ārādhanā, 98 and Mülācāra, 10.19. 2. Acārāngasutra, 1.2.5-3. 3. Deo, S.B., History of Faina Monachism, pp. 269-271. 4. Ibid., pp. 273-277. 5. Nisitha, 1.15-38. Page #175 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 158 Jaina Ethics that in cases of emergency a tendency to keep many things, even against the precepts of the Mülasūtras, did develop :1 1. Tālika-shoes to protect oneself from thorns. 2. Puțaka-shoes to protect oneself from cold. 3. Vardhna-stitching instruments to bind the torn soles of the shoes. 4. Košaka--protector of nails. 5. Kștti— a piece of skin to be worn if clothes were stolen.. 6. Sikkaka-pingoes for hanging the alms-bowl. 7. Kāpotikā-carrier of ill monks. 8. Pippalaka-razor. 9. Sūci--needle. 10. Arika-to stitch the soles of shoes. 11. Nakharadana-nail-cutter, 12. Sastrakośa—an instrument to mark the nerves etc. 13. Nandibhājana-pot for begging. 14. Dharmakaraka—a pot with straining arrangement for water. 15. Paratirthakarana-apparel of heretics to be used in emergency. 16. Gulikā—already explained under satya. 2 17. Khola—already explained under satya. The inscriptions bear testimony to the fact that Jaina monks were even granted gifts of land by their royal patrons.3 ild not prevent us from appreciating the high standards of the Faina code of morality under the vow of non-possession for a monk. The monk is to abandon not only possession of external objects but also of such ideas as, being alien to the nature of the self, may be termed as inner possessions. Such possessions are fourteen in number : (i) False belief (ii-iv) Three sex passions (v) Laughter 1. Byhatkalpabhāsya, Vol. III, 2883-2892. 2. Supra, p. 153-154. 3. Epigraphia Indica, pp. 232-240. (1088 A.C.) Page #176 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Jaina Monk 159 (vi) Liking (vii) Disliking (viii) Sorrow (ix) Fear (x) Disgust (xi-xiv) Four kaşāyas.1 Eight essentials (pravacanamātīkās) of the conduct of a monk : Self-control and vigilance in conduct are the two chief moral virtues. Self-control is three-fold : physical, mental and vocal. Vigilance in conduct is classified under five heads : vigilance in moving, speaking, taking food, keeping and receiving food and evacuating bowels. Three-fold selfcontrol is mainly negative in its implication while the five-fold vigilance is positive. These eight together protect the Ratnatraya of a monk just as a mother protects her child; and are, therefore, called pravacanātrkā.3 The five vows, discussed above, are the guiding principles of morality, whereas these pravacanamāt,kās are the means to put those principles into practice. The three 'guptis' The guptis' (the word is derived from the root 'gup') protect the monk from sin. The ātman receives a shelter in these guptis against the mundane circle of birth and death." Mano-gupti means freedom from thought of passions, delusions, attachment, aversion and such other impure thoughts. Vāggupti means avoidance of talks about women, politics, theft, food, etc. and refraining from telling a lie. Kāyagupti means renunciation of such violent actions as piercing, beating, contracting, expanding, etc.? 1. Puruşārthasiddhyupāya, 116. 2. Uttarādhyayana, 24.26. Also Pūjyapada on Tattvārthasūtra. 9.4-5. Mülācāra, 5-39. 4. A: FATTAI RUTTETTHET! Than Hafa i -Pujyapāda on Tattvārthasūtra. 9.2. 5. Niyamasāra, 66. 6. Ibid., 67. 7. Ibid., 68. Page #177 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 160 Five Samitis The word Samiti, coming from the root Vi (to go) with 'sam' prefix, means vigilance in behaviour.1 Negligence (pramāda) lies at the root of all sins and, therefore, constant vigilance is necessary to avoid them. Here again, it is emphasised that the best and perfect form of vigilance, from niscaya point of view, is the state of trance where the self becomes identical with its own nature; but from vyavahāra point of view, vigilance is five-fold : Jaina Ethics 1. Iryāsamiti While moving, the monk should be careful about the following five points2 (1) He should traverse only that path which is free from ants, seed, green vegetables, mud, etc. The path which is repeatedly trodden by vehicles and by other people or which is scorched by the sun or which is ploughed should be regarded fit for movement.4 (2) He should move about only in day-light.5 Moonlight or artificial lights of lamps etc. are not capable of properly showing small insects which may be lying in the path. (3) The monk should abstain from the objects of five senses and should devote his full attention towards his steps, while moving, so that no living being is injured through carelessness." (4) The monk should not move about for purposes other than religious. He should move for a pilgrimage, for a visit to the teacher, for religious discussion and for preaching of dharma only.8 (5) The monk should move always looking forward on 1. Jayasena on Pravacanasara, 3.40. 2. Mulacara, 5.106. Also Bhagavati Ārādhanā, 1191; Uttaradhyayana, 24.4; Tattvärthasara, 6.7. 3. Aparajita and Āśādhara on Bhagavati Ārādhanā, 1191. 4. Mülācāra, 5.108-109. 5. Mulācāra, 11. Also Niyamasāra, 61 and Uttaradhyayana, 24.5. 6. Aparajita on Bhagavatī Ārādhanā, 1191. 7. Aparajita and Asadhara on Bhagavati Ārādhanā, 1191; Also Uttaradhyayana, 24.5. 8. Aparajita on Bhagavati Ārādhanā, 1191. Page #178 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Jaina Monk 161 the ground to the extent of four cubits. He should not run, jump or look in other directions.2 Thus the idea of iryasamiti is to avoid all purposeless movements and to regulate all necessary movements in such a way that no living being is injured through carelessness. 2. Bhāṣāsamiti This is supplementary to the vow of truthfulness on one side and to the vacanagupti on the other. Superfluous and harsh speech is to be avoided. Concise and salutary speech, is to be adopted, avoiding anger, pride, deceit, greed, laughter, fear, loquacity and gossip.3 Backbiting, ridiculing others, and self-condemnation are to be abondoned." 3. Eṣaṇāsamiti The monk does not cook for himself; and, therefore, he has to beg his food to keep his body and soul together. His purpose in taking food is just to sustain life. There is therefore, no question of overeating or eating for the sake of taste. Moreover, he should keep the convenience of the house- * holder in view. He should take only that food which is neither prepared, nor suggested, nor approved by him. The food should be, moreover, pure and wholesome and should be such as offered with devotion. Right handling of sinless paraphernalia, and proper sweeping of sitting and sleeping places are also included in eşaņāsamiti. For a monk, the aim of taking food should not be fostering strength, increasing longevity, gratifying relish, or attaining healthy and bright look but sustenance of life for constant study of scriptures, for exercise of self-control and for performance of meditation. He takes food for satisfying hunger, for doing service to other monks, for preserving his pranas and 1. Niyamasara, 61. 2. Lingapahuḍa, 15-16. 3. Uttaradhyayana, 24.9-10. 4. Mülācāra, 1.12, 5. Ibid., 6.62. Page #179 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 162 Jaina Ethics self-control and for observing six essentials and ten dharmas.1 He should be completely detached towards this world and the next.2 As regards the quantity of food, only two portions of stomach out of four, should be filled with food and the remaining two should be left for water and air.3 The monk should not take food if he finds any one of the following fourteen impurities : nails, hair, insects, bones, chaff, grain particles, pus, skin, blood, flesh, seeds, fruits, bulb and roots.4 A monk should not go out for food when he suffers from disease, or when some misery befalls him, or when he wants to defend his celibacy or when he wants to refrain from causing injury to living beings or when he is desirous of renouncing the body.5 We shall deal with the rules of begging separately while discussing the food of a monk. 4. Adānanikşefaņāsamiti " It means that the monk should carefully lift and put his articles. He should use his picchi or rajoharaņa to remove insects before placing it at any place.? He should avoid injury to any living being in this way. 5. Pratisthāpana-samiti or utsarga-samiti While answering the call of nature, throwing away excrements,& urine, saliva, mucus, or any other uncleanliness of the body, pieces of food, waste things, torn clothes, dead bodies or other useless things, the monk should properly scrutinise the place and should throw away such wastes only in a place which is burnt, ploughed, used for cremation, 1. Mulācārā, 6.60. Pravacanasāra, 3.26. 3. Mülācāra, 6.72. 4. Ibid., 6.65. 5. Ibid., 6.61. Also Uttarādhyayana, 26.35. 6. Niyamasāra, 64. Also Mülācāra, 1.14. 7. Mülācāra, 5.123. Also Uttarādhyayana, 24.14. 8. Niyamasāra, 65. Page #180 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Jaina Monk unobjected, spacious, devoid of insects and seeds, not covered with grass or leaves, not perforated by holes, situated at a distance, neither frequented nor seen by other people, and having an acitta (inanimate) surface layer.1 These samitis, giving detailed rules of behaviour, show with what exactness and solemnity a monk is required to be vigilant in the observance of moral virtues. It may also be noted that these samitis, which have been framed to guide the conduct of a monk, should be taken as upalakṣaṇa only that these imply that all aspirants to liberation should keep constant vigilance in all walks of life. The Excellent qualities A monk should cultivate ten cardinal virtues in himself: (1) Forgiveness, (2) Humility, (3) Straightforwardness, (4) Contentment, (5) Truth, (6) Restraint, (7) Penance, (8) Renunciation, (9) Detachment, (10) Celibacy.2 As all these qualities are prefixed with the epithet "uttama" these are to be cultivated with the purpose of spiritual development and not with some worldly purpose. The fact is that a true monk will automatically be possessed of the above-mentioned qualities. He should employ his will-power against the tendency of transgressing these qualities. The list of these qualities repeats many moral virtues which are already covered by the five great vows, guptis and samitis; but since they are specially helpful in stopping the inflow of karmic matter, the sutra on samvara has enumerated these qualities separately. The Rajavartika commentary on Tattvärthas utra tries to explain the difference of dasalakṣaṇadharma and vratas, guptis and samitis. In any case, it must be admitted that there is much of repetition. It seems that the tradition in Hinduism of having ten cardinal virtues prompted Jaina thinkers also to have ten virtues as the basis of their religion.4 163 1. Mūlācāra, 5.125-126 Also Uttarādhyayana, 24.15, 17-18. 2. Tattvärthas ütra, 9.6. See Schubring, W., The Doctrine of the Jainas, pp. 305-306 for different lists given by different Svetambara sects. 3. Bhaṭṭa Akalanka on Tattvärthasutra, 9.6. (p. 958). 4. Manusmrti, 6.92. Page #181 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 164 Faina Ethics Repetition apart, the qualities of humility (mārdava ) straightforwardness (ārjava) and contentment (sauca) are essential for a monk. In fact, the ten cardinal virtues leave out hardly any virtue which may be required of a monk. The attitude of a monk towards hardships The path of asceticism is full of hardships which a monk is expected to overcome with detachment and forbearance.? The monk should get rid of the false impression of identity of body with soul and should understand the transitory nature of physical pains and pleasures.3 While the worldly man tries to avoid these hardships and counteracts them by various means, the monk welcomes these hardships and faces them with fortitude. Parişahajaya or victory over these hardships is a part of tapaścaryā or penance; the difference between the two lies in the fact that the former refers to remaining calm amidst such hardships as befall a monk by chance, whereas the latter refers to remaining steadfast amidst self-inflicted hardships. By facing these hardships boldly, the monk acquires a resolute will that no difficulty could bend. The path of salvation is not an easy one. It necessarily involves denial of comforts to the body, which being only a means and not the end, should not be unduly pampered and coddled. The hardships that a monk may have to face are roughly twenty-two in number:5 (1) Hunger, (2) Thirst, (3) Cold, (4) Heat, (5) Insectbites, (6) Nakedness, (7) Discontentment, (8) Woman, (9) Fatigue from walking, etc. (10) Disturbance by animals, (11) Sleeping or sitting on hard earth, (12) Abuse, (13) Beating, (14) Begging, (15) Failure to get alms, etc. (16) Disease, (17) Contact of thorny shrubs, etc. (18) Discomfort from dirt, (19) Respectful or disrespectful treatment, (20) Pride of knowledge, (21) Lack of knowledge, (22) Failures in religious practices. dio 1. Aparājitas üri on Bhagavati Ārädhanā. 1171. 2. Cf. Pujyapāda On Tattvārthas ütra, 9.9. Cf. Ibid., 9.9. 4. Gogortafarfast: qfa: 1 Fauna: TTFSOT: 1 Ibid., 9.19. Also Bhatta Akalarka on Tattvārthasūtra, 9.19. (p. 1082). 5. Uttarādhyayana, 2.1. Also Tattvärthas ütra, 9.9. Page #182 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Jaina Monk 165 The list shows that the monk may have to face not only physical pains but mental hardships also. In any case, he should be impervious to pain. Though these hardships are likely to be faced by a monk, a householder is also expected to become not too soft, hyper-civilised and a slave to luxuries. Any aspirant to liberation should never look for worldly comforts and should not be afraid of discomforts and privation. Pañca cāritra or five types of couduct The monk should have equanimity and should avoid all sinful activities. This is called sāmāyika cãritra.? If he infringes the moral law through negligence, he should again engage himself in the pursuit of righteousness. This is called chedopasthāpana.? A gathā of Jivakānda of Gommațasāra says that a person who, from the age of 30 to the age of 38, serves the Tirtharkara, developes parihāravifuddhi, i.e. his physical activities become perfectly free from injury.3 The monk having only very minute passions is called to have sūksmasāmparāja cāritra. When all passions are shed away, the ideal position of a kevali is called yathākhyātacāritra.5 We shall deal with these various stages of conduct in detail while dealing with the gunasthānas in a separate chapter. In this manner, we have dealt with the primary moral qualities required of a monk. These qualities help him in checking the inflow of kārmic matter. The monk should also perform penances which are the means of shedding of the kārmic matter. On account of the importance of penances in the moral system of Jainism we shall deal with this subject in a separate chapter, where we shall have the occasion to dwell upon the important subject of meditation also, which is one of the most important internal penances. Now we turn to some other important aspects of a Jaina monk's life. 1. Gomma fasāra, Jivakânda, 470. 2. Ibid., 471. 3. Ibid., 472-473. 4. Ibid., 474. 5. Ibid., 475. Page #183 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 166 Şaḍāvasyakas The word avasyaka comes from avaśa, which means independence from kaşayas. A monk who depends on others cannot, therefore, be said to have performed avasyaka karma.2 The traditional six avasyakas as enumerated in Mülācāra and Uttaradhyayana are as follows : 1. Sāmāyika 2. Caturvimŝatistava 3. Vandanā 4. Pratikramana 5. Pratyakhyāna 6. Kayotsarga.3 Kundakunda gives a slightly different list: 1. Pratikramaṇa 2. Pratyakhyāna 3. Alocană 4. Prayaścitta 5. Paramasamādhi Paramabhakti.4 6. It seems that no later author followed the tradition of Kundakunda Sāmāyika: Sāmāyika means equanimity of mind. Mūlācāra defines it thus: Sāmāyika is equanimity in life and death, profit and loss, union and separation, relative and enemy, and happiness and misery.5 It further adds that framana is one who is equally disposed towards one's own and others, who regards every woman as his mother and is equanimous in favourable and unfavourable circumstances. It is thus that he is said to perform sāmāyika. Jaina Ethics Niyamasara says, "What is the good of residing in forest, mortification of body, observance of various fasts, study of 1. Niyamasara, 142. Also Mülācāra, 7.14; Anāgāradharmāmṛta, 8.16. 2. Niyamasāra, 143. 3. Mülācāra, 7.15. Also Uttaradhyayana 26, 2-4. Introduction to Pravacanasära, p. XLII. 4. 5. Mülācāra, 1.23. 6. Ibid., 7.20. Page #184 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Jaina Monk 167 scriptures, and keeping silence, etc., to a saint, who is devoid of equanimity ?"1 Mūlācāra lays down the following conditions for sāmāyika: detachment, faith in scriptures, abstention from vices, three guptis, control over senses, austerity, victory over kaşayas and objects of enjoyment, abstention from arta and raudra dhyana, and devotion to dharma and śukla dhyāna.2 Anāgāradharmāmṛta has classified sāmāyika as well as other avasyakas into six categories :3 1. Nāma-detachment from good or bad names. 2. Sthapana-detachment from things placed proportionately or otherwise. 3. Dravya-detachment from good or bad material. 4. Ksetra-detachment from good or bad place. 5. Kala-detachment from good or bad time. 6. Bhāva-detachment from good or bad ideas. Caturviṁśatistava This includes offering prayers to twenty four Tirthankaras. These Tirthankaras are possessed of the following six qualities: 1. They spiritually illuminate the lokas.5 2. They pacify afflictions, destroy desire, and remove mental pollution and are, therefore, dravyatīrthas.® They are possessed of faith, knowledge and conduct and are therefore, bhavatirthas." 3. They have conquered the kaşayas.8 4. They have destroyed karmans.9 5. They are to be worshipped by all.10 6. They are possessed of kevalajñāna.11 1. Niyamasara, 124. (Translation from The Sacred Books of the Jainas, Vol. IX., p. 57). 2. Mülācāra, 7.22-32. Also Anāgāradharmamṛta 8.18. 3. Ibid., 7.17. 4. Ibid., 8.19-26. 5. Ibid., 7.59. 6. Ibid., 7.62. 7. Ibid., 7.63. 8. Ibid., 7.64. 9. Ibid., 7.64 10. Ibid., 7.65 II. Ibid., 7.67 Page #185 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 168 Faina Ethics These Tirtharkaras are to be requested to bestow liberation, knowledge and samādhimarana. But this is an asatyamışa and merely a devotional language, because, in reality, the Jinas being free from attachment and aversion, cannot impart any knowledge or sanādhimarana. They have already imparted us the knowledge of the path of liberation and this is all that they could do for us. Their devotion, of course, annuls previously accumulated karmans. Attachment to Athantas, dharma, scripture, ācārya and sages is but an auspicious type of attachment,5 because it is free from mundane desire. According to Anāgār adharmāmsta, one should think of the meaning of 1008 names of Arhantas.? It also lays emphasis on thinking of the physical beauty of Tirtharkaras,& going on pilgrimage, and contemplation of the knowledge of Tirthankaras.10 Vandana Vandanā means paying respect to the preceptor, to superiors, images of Athantas and Siddhas, and to those who are seniors in austerity, the study of scriptures and knowledge. Those who are seniors in other qualities or have been initiated for long, should also be paid respect.11 A monk is not to pay respect to those who do not observe vows. This includes parents, loosely disciplined guru, king, non-Jainas, Śrāvakas, gods and pseudo-saints.12 Vandanā should be free from thirty-two faults, which include, amongst others, disrespect, 1. Ibid., 7.69 2. Mülācāra, 7.70. Ibid., 7.71 Ibid., 7.72 5. Ibid., 7.74-75. (Verse No. 75 is wrongly numbered as 74 in the printed text). 6. Ibid., 7.76. (This verse is not numbered in the printed text.). 7. Anāgāradharmā mộta, 8.39. 8. Ibid. 8.41 9. Ibid., 8.42 10. Ibid., 8.44 11. Mūlācāra, 25. 12. Ibid., 7.95 Also Anägäradharmāmặta, 8.52. For pseudo-saints see supra, p. 150. Page #186 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 169 The Conduct of a Faina Monk pride, fear, ambition and deceit.1 Besides this, one should observe the common etiquette by not paying respect to one who is lecturing, invigilant, taking food or excreting bowels. Pratikramaņa Pratikramaņa consists in self-criticism (nindā) censuring before guru (garhā) and confession (ālocanā) of the moral transgressions. It is to be performed in day, at night, for negligence of movements, fortnightly, four-monthly, yearly and for the whole life.4 Pratikramaņa is to be performed for wrong attitude, absence of self-control, passions, and inauspicious activities. There should be no sense of pride, while performing pratikramana. There should be no delay in reporting one's faults to the guru.? Besides the above-mentioned self-criticism, censuring, and confession, which are called bhāva-pratikramaņa, the reciting of Pratikramaņa Sūtra is called dravya-pratikramana. 8 Both of these should go together. Kundakunda has also made a distinction between vyavahāra pratikramana and niscaya pratikramana. From niscaya point of view, meditation is the pratikramana for all trangressions.10 Kundakunda has included self-contemplation, conduct, righteousness, freedom from crookedness, thorns (Salya) of mind, self-discipline, avoidance of ārta and raudra dhyāna, and triple jewels of right attitude, knowledge and conduct, in pratikramana so as to make it all-comprehensive. 11 This may also be pointed out that pratikramana was required to be performed for those transgressions alone which were actually committed in the time of all Tirtharkaras, except 1. Mūlācāra, 7.106-111. 2. Ibid., 7.100. Also Anāgāradharmāmsta, 8.53. 3. Ibid., 1.26. 4. Ibid., 7.116. 5. Ibid, 7.120. 6. Ibid., 7.121. 7. Ibid., 1.125 8. Ibid., 7.126. 9. Ibid., 7.128. 10. Niyamasāra., 92, 93. II. Ibid., 83-91. Page #187 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 170 Faina Ethics the first and the last in whose time one was required to perform pratikramaņa for all transgressions. This difference is attributed to the firmness, concentration of mind and absence of infatuation in the monks of the times of the intervening period, and fickleminedeness and infatuation of the monks of the times of the first and last Tirtharkaras. 2 Pratyākhyāna Pratyakhyana means determination to avoid sinful activities. Pratikramana is connected with the sinful activities of the past whereas pratyākhyāna is related to the activities of the future. Pratyākhyāna can be easily practised by a person who is free from passions, self-controlled, brave, enterprising and afraid of the dangers of transmigration.3 Mūlācāra recommends modesty, correct following of the teacher in the recitation of the sūtra, observance of the vows even in emergency and detachment, as necessary for Pratyakhyāna. It specially connects pratyākhyāna with fasting and classifies it into the following ten categories : 1. Keeping a fast earlier than the due time. 2. Keeping it later. 3. Keeping it according to one's capacity. 4. Keeping it at proper time. 5. Doing penances with concentration on constellations. 6. Doing penances at will. 7. Fasting for varying periods. 8. Keeping fasts by renouncing all foods throughout the life. 9. Fasting while crossing a forest, etc. 10. Fasting with some purpose.5 Kāyotsarga It means devotion to auspicious meditation, keeping the feet at four-angula distance, without moving the body and 1. Mūlācāra, 7.129-131. 2. Ibid., 7.132-1333. Ibid., 2.104. 4. Ibid., 7.145. 5. Ibid., 7.140-141. Page #188 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Jaina Monk 171 without having any attachment to it.1 Only a person who aspires for liberation, has conquered sleep, is expert in the meaning of the sūtras, pure in thoughts, strong in body and spirit, and pure in spirit, is capable of performing kāyotsarga. 2 The kāyotsarga is practised for different lengths of time on different occasions.3 Mülācāra gives twenty three faults of kāyotsarga, which we need not enumerate here. We may simply summarise by saying that one should stand properly without spoiling the posture by such acts as bending one leg, shaking the body, taking the support of something like a wall, looking on all sides, or by any such unbesitting action. The kāyotsarga is of four kinds, according to postures and the types of meditation : 1. Dharma and śukla dhyāna in a standing posture is utthitotthita. 2. Arta and raudra dhyāna in a standing posture is utthitanivista. 3. Dharma and śukla Dhyāna in a sitting posture is upvisļotthita. 4. Arta and raudra dhyāna in a sitting posture is upavistopavisța.5 Food of the monk Out of many fundamental necessities of human life, food is the most elementary. Even a monk cannot get rid of this necessity. The Digambara sect holds that a Kevali requires no food; but, according to Svetāmbara sect, he does. In any case, the monk must reduce this basic necessity also to the minimum. We have already pointed out while discussing eşnā samiti that he should take only to allay the afflictions of hunger and should not develop any attatchment to it. He should beg his food in such a way that the householders are put to the least possible difficulties. Hindu scriptures also ordain the monk to take food like a medicine and not to relish it, 1. Mülācāra, 1.28 and 7.153. 2. Ibid., 7.154 3. For details cf Ibid., 7.159-164. 4. Ibid., 7.171-173. 5. Ibid., 7.176.180. 6. Sharma, Hardutta, Contribution to Brāhmaṇical Asceticism, p. 41. Page #189 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 172 Faina Ethics As the monk has very limited sphere of worldly enjoyments, there is every likelihood of his concentrating upon the taste of his food. The Jaina scriptures have laid down very elaborate rules for the monk in this respect. He should not accept food if it involves any transgression either on the side of the giver or on the side of the receiver or in the manner in which it is offered. Below we give the list of these faults1 : The first category of faults The udgama mistakes or mistakes on the part of the giver are sixteen in number. The monk should not accept food 1. if it is specially prepared for him; 2. if some additional food or new item has been cooked on seeing him; 3. if the sterilized or prāsuka food has been mixed with unsterilized food or water; 4. if he is asked to take the food together with layman; 5. if the food is offered to him after being removed from the place of its preparation; 6. if the food is remnant of offerings; 7. if the food is offered at wrong time; 8. if pots containing food are removed from one place to another at the sight of himself, or pots are washed before him, or a lamp is lit; 9. if the food has been purchased; 10. if the food has been borrowed; 11. if the food has been obtained in exchange for some other article; 12. if the food has been brought from another's house; 13. if the food has been kept uncovered; 14. if the food is offered at a place where he can reach only by mounting a ladder; 15. if the food is offered out of fear; 16. if someone has objected to the offering of food. 1. Ācāra sāra, 8.14-57. Also SBE, Vol. XLV, pp. 131 f.n. 7; Anāgå. radharmāmrta, 5.2-38. Page #190 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of Jaina Monk The second category of faults The following sixteen faults pertain to the receiver (utpadanadosa) and should be avoided by the monk. The food becomes condemnable : 1. if it is achieved by teaching the giver the way of looking after the children; 2. if it is obtained by delivering some message; 3. if it is obtained by telling someone about his future, etc; 173 4. if it is obtained by describing one's high lineage or occupation; 5. if it is obtained by flattering the giver; 6. if it is obtained by giving medical advice or medicine; 7. by showing anger; 8. by showing pride; 9. by deceit; 10. by showing greed; 11. by praising the giver in anticipation; 12. by praising the giver afterwards; 13. by imparting occult powers; 14. by imparting mantras for snake-bite, etc.; 15. by imparting some powers for beautification, etc; 16. by imparting secrets for winning over one's love. The third category of faults It consists of the following ten faults concerning the manner of giving. The food becomes candemnable : 1. if there is any doubt about its purity; 2. if it is offered by hands or in utencils which are besmeared with oil or ghee, 3. if it has been placed on unsterilised water or green or green leaves; 5. if the pots are not handled carefully by the giver; 6. if it is unclean; 7. if it is mixed with earth, insects or unsterilized things; 8. if it is not sterilized so as to make it incapable of leaves; 4. if it is covered with unsterilised water Page #191 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 174 Jaina Ethics breeding any living creature; 9. if it is offered from pots or hands besmeared with flour, chalk, and the like ; 10. if it has been thrown away. The fourth category of faults While taking the food, the monk should be free from the following four faults: 1. Mixing up hot things with cold which have ceased to be sterilized, * 2. Over-eating. 3. Having attachment to food. 4. Condemning food while eating it. Besides, the monk should not help in preparing the food at any stage like grinding, crushing, igniting fire, sweeping or drawing of water. This is called ādhākarmadosa. The underlying moral ideas in these rules for food and begging was non-violence and detachment. The monk should neither accept food specially prepared for him nor the food which causes violence to the living beings. The Byhatkalpabhäsya gives various prāyaścittas for violation of the fortysix rules. The Daśavaikālika says that a monk should beg his food just as a bee collects honey from flowers without hurting them or without getting attached to them.2 Samgha organisation The monks have a community of their own. It is possible only for a monk of a high order to remain aloof and endeavour for spiritual development. We have referred to such monks as Jinakalpa. An ordinary monk has, however, to remain under organisation of the samgha. This samgha organisation is headed by ācārya. The ācārya is responsible for the entire organisation of the samgha, from administrative to the spiritual. He should observe the following duties : 1. Sūtrārthasthirikaraña--Decide the meaning of the scriptures. 1. Byhatkalpabhāsya, Vol. I, Bhavanagar, 1933, 532-540. 2. Daśavaikälika, 1. 2-3. Page #192 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Jaina Monk 175 2. Vinaya-Should be humble to all. 3. Gurupūjā--Should be reverential to those who are senior to him in spiritual development. 4. Saikşabahumāna-Should show respect for the aspir ants of spirituality. 5. Dānapatiśraddhāvrddhi --Encourage the giver to give alms. 6. Buddhibalavardhana-Enhance the intellect and capa. city of his students. Besides, the ācārya should also keep in mind the following things : 1. He should be careful in giving any order. 2. He should see that the junior monks behave properly towards senior monks. 3. He should see that the order of reading the scrip tures is not violated by the monks. 4. He should provide proper facilities for those monks who are either diseased or are engaged in penance for studies. 5. He should do every thing in consultation with other monks. 6. He should see that every monk gets the equipment that he requires. 7. He should also take care of the equipments of monks.a The commentary of Pravacanasāroddhāra gives thirty-six qualities of a monk. We need not mention all these qualities here. The essential qualities of an ācārya are that he should have an excellent personality, should be free fr self-praise and crookedness. He should be well-versed in the scriptures and should have good expression. Monks and nuns Monks and nuns in the samgha should observe strict reticence. It is only in case of emergency that they are 1. Abhayadeva on Sthānāngasūtra, 7.3.570. 2. Sthānāngas ūtra, 5.1.399 and 7.3.544. 3. Pravacanasároddhāra, 64th dvāra (pp. 128-131). Page #193 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 176 Faina Ethics allowed to share a common quarter. They may talk to each other only for asking the way and showing it. The monk can touch a nun only to protect her against some harm. Thus full care should be taken against any chance of transgressing the right path of chastity. Behaviour of a monk towards his fellow monks The society of monks is guided by what is called Sambhoga. The rules of Sambhoga are twelve in number : 1. Upādhisambhoga—The possessions of a monk are called Upādhi. The monks should exchange these Upādhis with other monks with care. 2. Srutasambhoga-The monk should instruct other monks with regard to the scriptures. 3. Bhaktapāna—The food given to other monks should be pure. 4. Añjalipragraha—The monk should pay due respect to other monks. 5. Dānasambhoga—Pupils can be exchanged with the other monks of the same group. 6. Nimantraña--A monk can invite another monk of the same group for exchange of food, possessions and pupils. 7. Abhyutthāna—The monk should pay due respect to other monks of the same group by giving them seat etc., and by standing from his seat on their arrival. 8. Kịtikarma--Should give proper salutation, etc. 9. Vaiyyāvịtya—The old, diseased, and disabled monks should be served with due respect and care. 10. Samavasarana-They should join the assembly at the time of religious discourse. 11. Sannișadyā—The monk can share his seat with the monk of his own group but not with the nun. 12. Kathā-prabandha—He should discuss various religious matters with fellow-monks.2 1. Schubring, W., The Doctrine of the Fainas, p. 251. 2. Sri Jaina-siddhanta-bola-sangraha, Vol. IV, pp. 292-296. Page #194 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Faina Monk 177 Secondary duties af the monk (Uttaraguna) We have dealt with the cardinal moral virtues of a monk. He must also possess some minor virtues which are corollaries of the main virtues. The monk is expected to be friendly to all. He should be punctual, indifferent to pains and pleasures, and should not give way to anger at being condemned. He should not be proud and should love loneliness.1 Daśavaikālika lays down that a monk should not reside at one place. He should not take food daily from the same houses. He should not move about in the four months of rainy season; but should not stay for those four months at the same place. Thus he avoids attachment to a particular place. Sallekhanā We have already referred to this practice of voluntary death in the foregoing chapter. Deaths have been classified under five heads :3 (1) The wisest or 'Pandita-paņdita' death is the death of a kevali who leaves his body after exhausting his karmans and, therefore, need not take any birth after death. He has attained the summum bonum of life. (2) The wiser or 'Pandita' death is the death of a monk who dies in tranquillity. He has performed his spiritual duties to the best of his capabilities in this life but unfortunately could not attain his ultimate end and is, therefore, leaving this body voluntarily to continue his aspirations in another body where he will have better chances to fulfil his aim. (3) The wise or 'Bāla-pañdita' death is the death of a householder who could not take to monk's life but practised partial self-control while staying at home. (4) The foolish or 'Bāla' death is the death of an uncontrolled right believer. Though he had the seed of salvation in him, his life could not be a success since he practically lost this life in enjoyment of worldly pleasures and did not practise any self-control. (5) The worst or 'Bālabāla' death is the death of a wrong believer, who has 1. Cf. Uttarādhyayana, Lecture. XXI. 2. Daśavaikālika, cūlikā, 2. Also Uttaradhyayana, Lecture XI. 3. Jaina, C.R., Samnyāsadharma, pp. 121-122. . . Page #195 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 178 Jaina Ethics no chance of salvation. The true life, from the spiritual point of view, begins only at the dawn of right faith. It is only when a monk is certain of his death that he is allowed to adopt Sallekhana. The following passage from Bhagavatiarādhana clarifies it : Bhaktapratyakhyāna (samādhimarana) is not proper for him who has many years of saintly life before him, who has no fear of starvation from a great famine, who is not afflicted by an incurable disease, and who is not faced by any sudden cause of death. Whoever desires to put an end to his life, while still able, with his body, to observe the rules of the dharma and of the order properly, falls from the true path.1 When a monk takes sallekhanavrata, the fellow monks and the ācārya should carefully see that the concerned monk is not led to consider the sallekhana as a burden on him. He is to be carefully looked after and should be kept firm on the right path by means of constant inspiration from religious discourses. The ācārānga gives the following four types of death: 1. Bhaktapratyākhyāna-This means total abstinence from food and drink. The monk lies on a bed of straw and waits for death even without moving his limbs.2 2. Ingitamarana-The monk lies on a bare piece of ground and abstains from food and drinks although he can move according to the rules of gupti and samiti.3 3. Padopagamana-The monk stands motionless like a tree till death comes.4 4. Sallekhana-This means a planned scheme of fasting and mortification; the maximum period of mortification being twelve years and the minimum six months. 1. Quoted from Samnyasa Dharma, p. 128. 2. Acarängasútra, 1.7.8.7-10. 3. Ibid., 1.7.8.11-18 (pp. 76-77). 4. Ibid., 1.7.8.19-23 (p. 77). Page #196 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ The Conduct of a Jaina Monk Conclusion A study of the rules laid down for a Jaina monk would show that social conditions were also given due consideration in framing them. Secondly, every attempt has been made to preserve the puritanic form of monastic life. Thirdly, if a monk transgressed some law, the punishment given to him was of a reformative nature. Fourthly, the rules, though rigidly followed in normal circumstances, were flexible enough to make allowance for exceptional circumstances. 179 Page #197 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CHAPTER VII PENANCES The path of self-realisation is not an easy one. The demands of flesh and extrovert lower tendencies are so deeply rooted in our nature that any attempt to get rid of them is not likely to succeed without a tough struggle. These natural impulses, which when satisfied are the source of worldly pleasure, should be completely controlled by an aspirant to spiritualism. In fact, every progress involves some struggle. An aspirant is required not only to endure the hardships patiently but also to invite such hardships voluntarily. This process compels the soul to put forth its whole strength. It is, as it were, challenging the flesh. So far we have spoken of these moral virtues which a householder or a monk imbibes mainly to avoid sins. This is a form of saṁvara. But this alone is not sufficient. Previously accumulated karmans are also to be annihilated by penance, No doubt, those karmans, if left alone, exhaust themselves automatically after yielding their fruits (savipāka nirjarā); but an ardent aspirant cannot wait for such a long period. To strengthen the vitality of soul, therefore, he willingly challenges such natural instincts and fights against them. This appears to involve a lot of hardship and pain to casual observer, but to a true aspirant it is a source of great inspiration. It is here that he has a chance of trengthening his will-power against the allurements of worldly pleasures. The quality of tapas has been held very high in all the systems of Indian philosophy. The word āśrama, which indicates the four stages of life in Brāhmaṇism, comes from the root Srama, which means 'to toil. The word sramaņa, which indicates Jaina and Buddhist monks alike, also comes from the 1. THT FASTET # -Tattvārthasūtra, 9.3. Page #198 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Penances 181 same root. This shows the basic attitude of Indian philosophy towards the relation between austerities and spiritual progress. The Atharvaveda says that wise men conquer death by means of tapas.1 The Chăndog yopanişad draws a distinction between devayāna and pitryāna. Those who follow Deayāna attain liberation. The devayāna is characterised by performance of penances.3 Both, Mundaka4 and Praśnopanişad,5 mention tapas as a means of self-realisation. The Mahābhārata makes a mention ofrșis standing on one leg or devoured by vermin, adding at the same time that without inner purity, external austerities alone do not lead to salvation. The Manusmrti lavishly praises tapas.? The Gitā gives in detail the austerities of body, mind and speech.8 These penances are classified by the Gitā into rājasika and tāmasika.' Place of tapas in Jainism Umāsvāti describes tapas not only as a means of stopping the inflow of karmic matter but also as a means of annihilation of the previous Karmans. 10 In Satkhandāgama it is said that tapas means extirpation of desire in order to strengthen the three jewels of right attitude, right knowledge and right conduct. 11 The Uttarādhyayana praises tapas in these words : "As a large tank, when its supply of water has been stopped gradually, dries up by the consumption of water and by evaporation, so the karmans of a monk, which he has acquired in crores of births, is annihilated by austerites, if there is no 1. Atharvaveda, 11.5.19. 2. Chandog yopanişad, 5.3.2. 3. Ibid., 5.10.1. 4. Mundakopanisad, 1.2.11. 5. Prasnopanişad, 1.2. 6. Mahābhārata, Santiparva, 174.48, 177.49. Also eight-fold path in Viduraniti. 7. Manusmrti, 11.34-44. 8. Gitä, 17. 14, 15, 16. 9. Ibid., 17. 17-19. 10. Tattvārthas ütra, 9.3. 11. Virasena on Satkhandagama, 5.4.26 (Vol. XIII, p. 55). Page #199 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 182 Jaina Ethics influx of bad karman'. It further says: 'Penance is my firekarman is my fuel'. It is penance which makes a man respectable. It is on account of penance that a man is called Brāhmaṇa.* 3 penances should world or to the Sthānanga Sutra makes it clear that all be devoid of any desire pertaining to this next world. Tapas devoid of spiritualism is called Balatapa. Pravacanasara says that those who are spiritually endowed, get their karmans destroyed much more earlier than those who are not endowed with spirituality, even though they may perform external austerities." Even though the inner aspect of penances is duly emphasised in Jainism, yet the importance of external penances is also not underrated. Penances are classified under two heads external and internal.' External austerity involves physical endurance and renunciation of something perceptible, whereas the internal austerity involves control of mind. The external austerity being something physical can be pursued even by a man who is not possessed of right attitude.9 External austerities There are six types of external austerities: 1. Fasting (Anasana), 2. Eating less than one's fill (Avamaudarya), 3. Taking a secret vow to accept food from a householder only if certain condition is fulfilled (Vṛttiparisamkhyāna), 4. Abstention from one or more of the following six objects of taste (Rasaparityaga): (i) Ghee,, (ii) Milk, (iii) Curd, (iv) Sugar, (v) Salt, (vi) Oil., 5. Sitting and sleeping in a lonely place I. Uttaradhyayana, 30.5, 6. SBE Translation. 2. Uttaradhayana, 22.44. 3. Ibid., 12.37. 4. Ibid., 25.22. 5. Cf. Sthananga, 10.1.759. 6. Pravacanas āra. 3.38. 7. Virasena on Satkhanḍāgama, 5.4.26 (Vol. XIII, p. 54), Also Tattvarthasutra, 9.19-20. 8. Pujyapada on Tattvärthasutra, 9.19-20. 9. Virasena on Satkhanḍāgama, 5.4.26 (Vol. XIII, p. 59). Also Anagaradharmamṛta, 7.6. Page #200 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Penances .183 (Vivikta Sayyāsana), 6. Mortification of the body (Kāya kleśa).1 1. Anaśana : The food may he abandoned either for a limited period or till death.2 Pūjyapāda says that penance is performed for the sake of self-control, exterminating attachment, annihilating Karmans, performing meditation and acquiring scriptural knowledge; and not for any worldly purpose.3 Mere maceration of body should be distinguished from fasting, where detachment from food is essential.4 2. Avamaudarya : Normally the full quantity of food for an ascetic is thirty-two morsels in the case of a monk and twenty-eight in the case of a nun. Any reduction in this quantity constitutes this tapas. Mūlācāra says that it helps control of senses and sleep, in practising Dharma, and in the performance of six essentials. 3. Vrttiparisamkhyāna : Like the first two types of penances, this type also involves control of food. The ascetic decides regarding the number of houses to be visited, the manner of taking food, the type of food and the qualification of the giver of food, before going out to beg food.? If he finds that his conditions are fulfilled he would accept the food, otherwise he would go without it. Sometimes the conditions are too difficult to be normally fulfilled and the monk has to go without food for a very long period. This helps him in uprooting the desire for food.8 4. Rasaparityāga : This again is connected with food. The monk should eat to live and not live to eat. This means a control of palate. He should, therefore, renounce one or more of the six objects of taste viz. milk, curd, ghee, oil, sugar and salt and also one or more of the following types of 1. Tattvärthasūtra, 9.19. 2. Mülācāra, 5.151-152. Also Uttarādhyayana 30.9 and Bhagavatiārādhana, 209 Pūjyapāda on Tattvārthasūtra, 9.19. 4. Satkhandāgama, 5.4.26 (Vol. XIII, p. 55). 5. Mülācāra, 5.153. Also Bhagavatī ārādhana 211, 212; Uttarādhyayana 30.15 and Virasena on Satkhaņdāgama, 5.4.26 (Vol. XIII, p. 56). 6. Mūlācāra, 5.153. Also Anāgāradharmāmýta, 7.22. 7. Mülācāra, 5.158. Also Bhagavati Ārādhana, 218-221; and Virasena on Satkhaņdāgama, 5.4.26 (Vol. XIII, p. 57). 8. Anāgāradharmāmsta, 7.26. Page #201 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 184 Jaina Ethics tastes acrid, bitter, astringent, sour and sweet. The purpose of this tapas is emasculation of the senses, subduing sleep, and unobstructed pursuance of study.2 5. Vivikta sayyasana: The monk should choose a secluded place for his residence. It should not be frequented by women, eunuch, she-animals, and depraved house-holders. It helps in celibacy, self-study and meditation.* 6. Kaya klesa: It means inflicting some pain on the body by adopting certain postures or by exposing it to the vagaries of weather just like remaining in the hot sun in summer season.5 The purpose of this tapas is to endure physical hardships and to alleviate attachment to pleasure.& Mülācāra makes it clear that external penances should not engender mental disquietude, or abate the zeal for the performance of disciplinary practices of ethical and spiritual nature but should rather enhance spiritual conviction." Samantabhadra also emphasises the inner aspect of penance and says that external austerities are means for spiritual austerity.8 Internal austerities The internal austerities are also classified under six heads. They are as follows: 1. Expiation (Prayaścitta) 2. Reverence (Vinaya) 3. Service (Vaiyyavṛtya) 4. Study (Svadhyaya) 5. Detachment (Vyutsarga) 6. Meditation (dhyāna). 1. Mūlācāra, 5.155. Also Uttaradhyayana, 30.26; Bhagavatiārādhanā, 215; and Virasena on Satkhandagama, 5.4.26 (Vol. XIII. p. 57). 2. Pujyapada on Tattvarthasutra, 9.19. 3. Mulācāra, 5.160. Also Virasena on Satkhaṇḍagama, 5.4.26 (Vol. XIII, P. 57). 4. Pujyapada on Tattvarthasutra, 9.19. 5. Uttaradhyayana, 30.27; Bhagavati- Aradhana 222-227; and Virasena Satkhandagama, 5.4.26 (Vol. XIII, p. 58). 6. Pujyapada on Tattvärthasutra, 9.19. 7. Mūlācāra, 5.161. Also Bhagavati-Aradhana, 236. 8. बाह्यं तपः परमदुश्चरमाचरंस्त्वमाध्यात्मिकस्य तपसः परिबृंहणार्थम् । -Svayambhustotra, 83. on Page #202 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Penances 185 1. Expiation (the sense of guilt) The Prāyaścitta samuccaya says that without prāyaścitta here cannot be any conduct, without conduct no piety, withput piety no detachment, and without detachment all vows ire futile.1 It is said that one should not try to conceal his defects from a benevolent king, doctor and teacher.2 While prescribing a prāyaścitta, time, place, availability of food, and individual capacity are to be kept in view.3 In fact, there are as many prāyaścittas as there are shades of faults and, therefore, no body can draw up an exhaustive list of all the prāyaścittas. 4 It should also be kept in mind while prescribing a prāyaścitta whether the sinner has transgressed the law under some pressure or wilfully, once or repeatedly, follow the teaching of (truth) or otherwise, and whether resisting the temptation for sin or not.5 Prāyaścitta includes the following ten :-6 1. Self-criticism (ālocanā) 2. Self-repentence (pratikrmana) 3. Both, confession and self-repentence (tadubhaya). 4. Renunciation of a bad thing (viveka). 5. To engage oneself in Vyutsarga (kāyotsarga). 6. Fasting or external penances (tapas) 7. Cutting short the life of monkhood (cheda ) 8. Reordainment in monkhood (mūla) 9. Expulsion from monkhood (parihāra) 10. Re-establishing belief in the true order (Sraddhāra) The Tattvārthas ütra enumerates only nine of these eliminating fraddhā the last and mentioning the eighth as upasthāpana.? Alocanā (Self-criticism) Alocanā is meant for lapses in the movements of body, 1. Prayascittasamuccaya, 5. 2. Cülika (Prāyaścitta), 163. 3. Prayascittasamuccaya, 130-180. 4. Cālikā, 163 5. Prāyaścittasamuccaya, 18-22. 6. Mülācāra, 5.165; Virasena on p. 60). 7. Cf. Tattvārthasūtra, 9.22. Satkhandāgama, 5.4.26 (Vol. XIII, Page #203 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ · 186 Faina Ethics mind and speech, and in iryāsamiti2 as also for lapses while away from the community and while visiting other party of saints.4 The transgression should be expressed and confessed before the guru avoiding the following ten defects ( doşas) 5 : (i) Akampita doşa : The monk should avoid serving the Guru, or offering him things, with the object he may prescribe a milder type of prāyścitta. This is known as akampit adoșa. (ii) Anuk ampita or anumānita doșa : To plead one's ill health so that the guru may prescribe a milder prāyścitta out of compassion is anukampita dosa. Or inferring guru attitude towards lesser punishment is anumānita doșa.7 (iii) Yaddısta : It means expressing only those faults which are perceived by others. 8 (iv) Bādara doşa : It means concealing minor faults, disclosing only major faults.' (v) Sükşma doșa : It is just opposite of the previous fault. It means disclosing only minor faults and concealing major ones. 10 (vi) Channa dosa : If the monk asks prāyaścitta for a hypothetical case and then expresses his own fault, it is called channadoşa 11 (vii) sabdākulita doşa : If the monk expresses his faults indistinctly amidst great noise, it is called sabdākulita doşa.12 (viii) Bhūrisūri doșa : It results from asking many people regarding the propriety and authenticity of the prājascitta prescribed by the guru.13 1. Prāyaścittas amuccaya, 184. 2. Ibid., 185. Ibid., 187. 4. Ibid., 188. 5 Pujyapāda and Bhatta Akalarka on Tattvārthas ütra, 9.22. 6. Bhagavati-Ārādhanā, 563. 7. Ibid., 569-573. 8. Ibid., 574 9. Ibid., 577. 10. Ibid., 581. 11. Bhagavatiārādhanā, 586. 12. Ibid., 590. 13. Ibid., 596. Page #204 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Penances 187 (ix) Avyakta dosa : To express one's fault before a person who is devoid of the three jewels is called avyakta. (x) Tatsevita doșa : It means asking for prāyaścitta from a person who himself is involved in the same type of lapses for which prāyaścitta is to be prescribed.? Pratikramana : This means self-condemnation for a transgression. The transgression may be in connection with speaking lie under the influence of sex,3 throwing bodily excrements in prohibited areas, 4 forgetting about vaiyyāvrtya or service of the saints5 and being excited sexually.. Tadubhaya It means performing both ālocanā and pratikramaņa for such faults as are committed unintentionally, i.e. bad dreams etc.? Viveka It means renunciation of an objectionable thing. Prāyaścittasamuccaya gives the following conditions for giving up an object : 1. When it is objectionable. 2. When there is doubt about its purity. 3. When a part of it is objectionable. 4. When impure thoughts have become associated with it, even though it is pure. 5. When one intends to take food at night for fear of illness or famine. 6. When objectionable food has been served or a part of it has been put in the mouth.8 1. Bhagavati-Ārādhanā 599. 2. Ibid., 602. 3. Prāyaścittasamuccaya, 48. 4. Ibid., 48. 5. Ibid., 191. 6. Prāyaścittasamuccaya, 192. 7. Virasena on Satkhandāgama, 5.4.26., Vol. XIII, p. 60. Also Pújyapāda on Tattvārthasütra, 9.22. 8. Prayascittasamuccaya, 196-202. Page #205 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 288 Jaira Ethics Kāpotsarga It means to engage oneself in vyutsarga." It is practised for 1. Such common unavoidable slight faults as walking, eating etc. 2. Touching some living bodies, itching and contracting the body, and discharging bodily excrements in an improper place. 3. Pulling threads or straws to pieces, causing slight agitation, employing hands in some action, thinking of completing an accessory (upakarana) like a book or a feather within a certain number of days. 4. Rubbing one limb against another, or against clay, - hard seeds, green grass or insect life.? Tapa It means fasting or engaging oneself in external austerity. Many elaborate details are given concerning this type of penance. Control over the sense of taste is considered to be the main concern of the aspirant and hence there is much emphasis on fasting. There are many methods of controlling the sense of taste e.g. one may resort to ācāmla, which means taking food prepared by one kind of grain with water; orekasthāna, which means either eating only what is offered at one time or eating only as long as one does not change his position; or nirvikyti, which means taking food devoid of six castes of milk, curd, ghee, oil, sugar and salt (called rasas); or upavāsa, which means totally abstaining from food for 24 hours, or purumandala which means abstaining from food till after the mid-day sāmāyikasi.e. upto 1.15 P.M.) or kalyāņaka, which means one each of the quintet of the above five. Four such kalāyāņakas are termed as bhinnamāsa, five as gurumäsa and five kalyānakas without ācāmla, nirvikrti, and upavāsa as laghumāsa. There are various combinations of these tapas which are prescribed for various types of transgressions. 1. Pujyapäda on Tattvärthasūtra, 9.22. cf. infra, p. 193. 2. Prāyaścittasamuccaya, 28-31. Page #206 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Penances 189 Cheda : It means cut in the period of monkhood. It is prescribed for: (i) leaving the samgha and roaming about alone. (ii) being loose in one's saintly character, (iii) failing to apologise for a fault. (iv) leaving the samgha without apologising for one's faults. It may be noted that the period of cheda for an ācārya is thrice and for a learned monk twice the period for an ordinary monk. (ii) Müla : It is meant for such faults as are too grave to be cured by cheda but not so strong as to merit parihāra (expulsion ). The monk is re-ordained in the samgha as a novice and loses his seniority completely. It is meant for(a) (i) losing the faith, conduct and principal vows, non-observance of six essentials of a monk and ordaining a pregnant woman or an important person into sainthood. propounding teachings contrary to the faina scriptures. (iii) leading the life of a false monk. (iv) adopting non-Jaina mode of living. (v) committing sins against mūlagunas.3 Parihāra : It means expulsion from the samgha. It is of two types-(1) anupasthāna or anupasthāpana and (2) pārañcika. Under first type of expulsion, a monk is allowed to remain in his own gana and has to respect ev He is to observe a fast in which he is allowed meals only 1. Pujyapāda on Tatträrthas ütra, 9.22. 2. Satkhandägama, 5.4.26. Vol. XIII. p. 62. Also Anāgāradharmāmpta, 7-55. 3. Prāyaścittasamuccaya, 239-240 4. Pujyapäda on Tattvärthasūtra, 9.22. Page #207 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 190 Jaina Ethics after five days in cases of mild punishment and even after six months in cases of hard punishment, though such hard punishments are rarely allowed in modern age when human capacity is limited.1 Even so, some persons undertaking long fasts are mentioned. The penance may continue for twelve years. Under second type of expulsion (pārañcika parihāra) the monk has to live outside the samgha and observe such hard fasts as mentioned above. But such punishment is awarded only in cases of the worst sins like abduction of a monk of another faith, of a layman, a woman, a child, or the pupil of a saint and for assaulting a saint with a stick.3 Sraddhāna : It means that a monk, who had been misled again joins the samgha.4 2. Vinaya (reverence) : Vinaya means control over passions and senses and proper humility towards reverential personalities. All knowledge is futile without vinaya. Humbleness is shown for five reasons : (1) Imitation (2) Wealth (3) Sex (4) Fear and (5) Liberation.? We are not concerned here with the first four types of vinaya. The last-mentioned type of Vinaya is again classified under five heads : (1) Darsana (2) Jñāna (3) Căritra (4) Tapa and (5) Upacāra. (1) Darsana vinaya : One who has faith in the nature of things as taught by Jinas is said to have shown darśana vinaya.' It means having right faith with all its constituents and avoidance of its five faults.10 (2) Jñāna vinaya : A person who attains or knows 1. Prāyaścittasamuccaya, 157. 2. Bệhatkalpabhāsya, Vol. II, 1283-1284, Vol. V, 4492. 3. Prāyaścittasamuccaya, 244. Virasena on Satkhan dägama, 5.4.26 (Vol. XIII, p. 63). Also Anāgāradharmāmsta, 7.57. 5. Anāgāradharmāmrta, 7.60. Bhagavatiārādhana, 128. 7. Mülācāra, 7.83. 8. Ibid., 7.87. 9. Ibid., 7.88. 10. Bhagavati-Arādhanā, 114. 6. Bhaga Page #208 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Penances 191 liberation, avoids sins, does not acquire new karmans, and acts with knowledge is said to have performed jñāna vinaya. Acārya Sivakoți says jñāna vinaya has eight varieties? : (i) Kalavinayait means reading the scriptures at proper time, (ii) Vinaya—it means devotion towards scriptures and those who are wellVersed in them, (iii) Upādhāna vinaya-it means taking a vow of fast unless a particular scripture is finished, (iv) Bahumāna vinaya—it means reading with purity and with folded hands with concentration, (v) Anihnava vinaya—it means not proclaiming the name of the ācārya other than the one from whom one has actually studied, (vi) Vyañjana vinaya—it means proper recitation of the scriptures, (vii) Artha vinaya—it means proper understanding of the meaning of the scriptures, (viii) Tadubhaya vinaya—it means proper recitation and properunderstanding of the scriptures. 3 (3) Cāritra vinaya : it means annihilating previously accumulated karmans and stopping the accumulation of new karmans. This includes three guptis, five samitis and control over senses and passions.5 (4) Tapa vinaya : It means dispelling darkness by penance. It also means devotion to penance and to those who are devoted to penance. One should not insult those who perform less penance but are possessed of knowledge.? (5) upacūra Vinaya : It means paying proper respect physically, vocally and mentally. To stand up to salute, to bow down with hands folded on one's forehead, and to follow the sage while bidding him farewell - all these are included in physical Upacāra vinaya.8 One should keep his seat lower than that of a senior and should also offer place and seat to him. ܘ̇ܗ̇ ܛܲ ܗ̇ ܗ̇ ܝܿܕ 1. Vasunandi on Mülācāra, 7.89. Bhagavati-Ārādhana, 113. 3. Aparājitas üri on Bhagavati-Arādhanā, 113. 4. Mülācāra, 7.90. Bhagavati-Aradhana, 113. 6. Mülācāra, 7.90. 7. Bhagavati-Arādhanā, 117. 8. Ibid., 119. 9. Ibid., 120. Page #209 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 192 Faina Ethics Vocal upacāra vinaya includes respectful, beneficial, limited, sweet and non-harsh speech. The speech should be calm, unconnected with worldly affairs and non-insulting.2 Mental upacāra vinaya means controlling the mind against vices and diverting it to virtues. All these vinayas should be observed whether the teacher sees it or not.4 3. Vaiyyāvrtya : .: It means rendering service to monk with one's own body or some other object when he is in misery such as disease, Parişaha or perversity or attitude. This service may be rendered to the following ten : (i) ācārya, (ii) upādhyāya, (ii) one who performs some great penance, (iv) teacher, (v) diseased, (vi) old monks (vii) students of one's ācārya, (viii) the monks of one's samgha, (ix) a monk with long standing and (x) a popular monk. This type of service expresses non-abhorrence for dirt and love for the religious path.? 4. Svādhyāya : The scriptures should be studied for excellence of intelligence, good engagement, detachment, argumentation of penance, and purification of transgressions of vows.8 Svādhyāya has five varieties : 1. Vācanā, which means teaching the scripture and its meaning. 2. Prcchanā, which means asking others for removing the doubt or for ascertaining the meaning. 3. Anupreksā, which means contemplating on the scripture which has been read. 4. Āmnāya, which means correctly revising a scripture. 5. Dharmopadeśa, which means giving religious sermons." I. Bhagavati-Arādhanā, 123. 2. Ibid., 124. 3. Ibid., 125. 4. Ibid., 127. 5. Pūjyapada on Tattvārthas ütra, 9.24. 6. Tattvārthasūtra, 9.24. 7. Pujyapāda on Tattvārthasütra, 9.24. 8. Ibid., 9.25. 9. Ibid., 9.25. Page #210 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Penances 193 5. Vyutsarga : It means renunciation of external and internal possessions. Property etc. are external possessions whereas anger etc. are internal possessions. This penance enhances detachment, fearlessness and indifference towards one's life.1 6. Dhyāna : After dealing with the above five kinds of internal penances, we come to the sixth kind, dhyāna, which occupies the most important place in the scheme of Jaina ethics and is, therefore, dealt with in some detail herebelow. The position of dhyāna in Indian Philosophy As a means to self-realisation, meditation holds the supreme position. In fact, all ethical discipline aims at perfect state of meditation. The conception of the state of meditation differs from one system to another, but they all agree regarding the importance of meditation. The Kathopanişad declares : "He who has not turned away from frivolity, who is restless and uncollected, who does not have a peaceful mind cannot through searching realise the self."2 The Svetāsvataropanişad says : “By practising churning in the form of meditation, one should realise God as one would find out something hidden.”3 Lord Buddha declared in Dhammapada“ that those in whom wisdom and meditation meet are not far from salvation'. Patañjali says in his Yogas ütra that the action of meditation is free from vehicles. Nyāyasūtra recommends meditation as a means of knowledge. 8 Dhyāna in Jainism Tattvārthas ātra defines Dhyāna as concentration of mind on a particular object. This concentration is possible only 1. Pūjyapāda on Tattvārthasūtra, 9.26. 2. Kathopanişad, 1.2.24. 3. Svetāśvataropanişad, 1.14. 4. Dhammapada, 25:13 5. rogasūtra, 4.6. 6. Nyāyasūtra, 4.2.38. Page #211 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 194 Jaina Ethics for a period below forty-eight minutes (antarmuhūrta) and can be practised by a person possessed of the best type of body. 1 Types of Dhyāna : Tattvārthas ūtra has classified Dhyāna into four categories : 1. ārta, 2. raudra, 3. dharmya and sukla. The first two are inauspicious and the other two auspicious. 3. The last two types of dhyāna are said to lead to liberation. The arta dhyāna : The ārta dhyāna has been further classified under four heads : (i) anista samyogaja, (ii) įsta viyogaja, (iii) vedanā janita, (iv) nidāna janita. As is clear from the names of these types of ārta dhyāna, all of them are connected with worries emanating from worldly objects. Anista samyogaja relates to anxiety to remove the undesirable objects like poison, thorn, enemy, weapon, etc. The opposite of it is ista viyogaja where one thinks of means of attaining such desirable objects as son, wife or wealth in their absence.6 Vedanā janita ārta dhyāna is connected with anxiety for finding devices to remove the physical diseases.? Nidāna janita means concentrating on the means of obtaining the worldly pleasures by a person who yearns for them.& iñānārnava includes in this type of ārta dhyāna, the desire to attain the status of Tirthankara or god by performing meritorious actions." The ārta dhyāna, though agreeable in the beginning, yields bad results in the end.10 It continues upto the sixth stage of spiritual development. The last type of this dhyāna, however, continues only upto the fifth stage.11 From the point 1. Tattvärthasūtra, 9.27, 28. Also jñānārnava, 25.15. 2. Tattvārthas ütra, 9.28. 3. Pujyapada on Ibid.. 9.28. Also jñānārnava, 25.20. 4. Tattvārthas ütra, 9.29. 5. Pūjyabāda on Tattvärthasūtra, 9.30. Also Jñanārnava, 25.25. 6. Ibid., 9.31. Also Ibid., 25.29. 7. Ibid., 9.32. Also Ibid., 25 32. 8. Ibid., 9.33. Also Ibid., 25.34. 9. Jñānārņava, 25.35. 10. Ibid., 25.38. 11. Ibid., 25-39. Page #212 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Penances 195 of view of lesyas, arta dhyana is the result of the three inauspicious lesyas.1 The arta dhyana requires no efforts but proceeds spontaneously from the previous impressions of karmans. Its signs are: doubt, sorrow, fear, negligence, dispute, confusion, intoxication, eagerness for mundane pleasure, sleep, fatigue, and unconsciousness.3 The randra dhyana : The raudra dhyana is even worse than arta dhyāna. arises from relishing ideas about sinful violence, falsehood, theft, and preservation of objects of enjoyments; it is found only upto the fifth stage of spiritual development.4 The first type, raudra, called himsānandi means taking delight in killing, crushing, or destroying the living beings either by self or through others. It includes skill in violent actions, advising sins, and association with cruel people." Desire of killing in the battle; taking delight in hearing, seeing or remembering the miseries of sentient beings; being envious of other's prosperity are all included in this type of Raudra dhyāna. Mrşanandi raudra dhyana includes falsehood,10 composing deceptive literature for one's own pleasure,11 collecting wealth by deceit12 and deceiving the simple-minded.13 Cauryanandi raudra dhyāna includes not only the act of theft but also preaching dexterity in theft.14 Vişayanandi raudra dhyana includes desire to take posses 1. Jñānārṇava, 25.40. 2. Ibid., 25.41. 3. Ibid., 25.43. 4. Tattvärthasutra, 9.35. Also Jñänarnava, 26.3. 5. Jñänärṇava, 26.4. 6. Ibid., 26.6. 7. Ibid., 26.9 8. Ibid., 26.10. 9. Ibid., 26.13. 10. Jñānārṇava, 26.16. 11. Ibid., 26.17. 12. Ibid., 26.18. 13. Ibid., 26.19 14. Ibid., 26.24. . It Page #213 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 196 Jaina Ethics sion of all good things of the world1 and thinking of fighting ferociously for attainment of the objects of enjoyment.2 It is obvious that only a man who is fully disciplined can avoid raudra dhyāna which persists upto the fifth stage of spiritual development.3 Pūjyapāda has, however, pointed out that the raudra dhyāna of a person with right attitude is of less intensity and cannot lead to hellish existence.* Sometimes this dhyāna occurs in the monk also on account of the force of previously accumulated karman. The raudra dhyāna is characterised by cruelity, harshness, deceitfulness, hard-heartedness and mercilessness. The external signs of raudra dhyāna are red eyes, curved eyes-brows, fearful appearance, shivering of body and sweating.? The auspicious types of dhyāna The above-mentioned inauspicious types of Dhyāna require no effort and are spontaneous.8 They do not lead to liberation. It is only the auspicious types of dhyāna viz. dharma dhyāna and sukla dhyāna which lead to liberation. Requirements for dharma dhyāna : The aspirant should be possessed of knowledge and detachment, self-control, firm desire for liberation, should be active, calm and steadfast. Place for dharma dhyāna : Whether crowded or lonely, any place is fit for meditation, if the mind is firm.10 But the surroundings also influence the mind.11 Therefore, that place should be avoided which is inhabited by low people, ruled by a wicked king, and surrounded by hypocrites, highly perverted persons, Kaulas and Kāpālikas, gamblers and drunkards.12 In short, all such. 1. Ibid., 26.29. 2. Ibid., 26.30-35. 3. Ibid., 26.36. 4. Pujyapāda on Tattvārthasūtra, 9.35. 5. Jñānārņava, 26.42. Ibid., 26.37. Ibid., 26.98 Ibid., 26.43 Ibid., 27-3. 10. Ibid., 28.21. II. Ibid., 28.22. 12. Ibid., 27.22. cinco no 9. Page #214 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Penances 197 places, where disturbances may be caused by people of reprehensible profession, bad character, women, or animals, should be avoided. 1 On the other hand, a place which is sanctified by the association of great persons, and is lonely like sea-shore, forest, mountain, island, etc., should be chosen.3 The place for meditation should not have disturbance by noise, rain or wind.4 Postures for dharma dhyīna : Every place and every posture is suitable for meditation for him, who is detached, steadfast, firm and pure.5 Yet postures have importance of their own. Subhacandra mentions seven pastures : 1. paryarkāsana, 2. ardhaparyankāsana, 3. vajrāsana, 4. vīrāsana, 5. sukhāsana, 6. kamalāsana, 7. kāyotsarga. The first and the last of these seven, are specially suitable for the modern age, when people lack energy.? The aspirant should face east or north, though there is no such fixed rule.9 One who has controlled his posture becomes immune from the clemencies of nature.10 Sitting cross-legged, one should place his left hand on the lap, 11 concentrating his sight on the tip of the nose, 1a and making his face as motionless as the lake with fish asleep.13 Other auxilaries of dhyāna : In Pātañjala yoga, much import ince has heen attached to prāņāyāma. In Jainism also, Subhacandra considers control 1. Jñānārnava, 27.28-33. 2. Ibid., 28.1. 3. Ibid., 28.2-4. 4. Ibid., 28.5-7. 5. Ibid., 28.21. 6. Ibid., 28.10. 7. Ibid., 28.12. 8. Iibd., 28.23. 9. Ibid., 28.24. 10. Ibid., 28.32. 11. Ibid., 28.34. 12. Ibid., 28.35. 13. Ibid., 28.36. Page #215 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 198 Jaina Ethics over breath of much importance for control over mind.1 At the same time he also says that controlling the breath may lead to ārta dhyāna.2 Still Subhacandra has devoted a full chapter to describing prāņāyāma of three types, pūraka, kumbhaka and recaka. The main purpose of these prānāyāmas is to control the mind, and they give power to know the whole world also.4 Better than prāņāyāma is pratyāhāra, which means concentrating on forehead by withdrawing the senses. Besides, one can concentrate on the eyes, the ears, the tip of the nose, the mouth, the naval, the head, the heart and the place between the two eyebrows. The object of dharma dhyāna : Leaving attachment and infatuation, one should cut, as it were, the enemy of karmans by the sword of dhyāna.? The chief object of dhyāna is ātman.8 Atman should strive for the attainment of paramātmahood. All these yonis are the result of karmans, the real self is siddha. "O Self is possessed of the four infinitive qualities of energy, knowledge, perception and bliss. 11 Amongst the objects of dhyāna are the sentients and the insentients, their triple nature of continuance, birth and destruction, arhants and siddhas 12 What is necessary is to distinguish the self from the body.13 The self should think that he is simply a light which has no foe or friend.14 He should know that he himself is the object of worship.16 There 1. Jñānārnava, 29.2. 2. Ibid., 30.9. Ibid., 29.28.77. Ibid. 29.80-98. 5. Ibid., 30.3-4. 6. Ibid., 30-13 7. Ibid., 31.3. 8. Ibid., 31.4; 32.1-4. 9. Ibid., 31.9. For the nature of paramätman sce jñānärnava, 31.22.41. 10. Ibid., 31.12. II. Ibid., 31.13. 12. Ibid., 31.17. 13. Ibid., 32.21-24. 14. Ibid., 32.32. 15. Ibid., 32.45. Page #216 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Penances 199 by he should leave all desire for beauty, age, strength, wealth etc.1 Types of dharma dhyāna : Tattvārthasūtra mentions four types of dharma dhyāna. (i) ajñānavicaya dharma dhyāna; (ii) apāya vicaya dharma dhyāna; (iii) vipāka vicaya dharma dhyāna; and (iv) saṁsthāna vicaya dharma dhyāna.? (i) Ajñāna vica ya dharma dhyāna :--Ajñāna vicaya dharma dhyāna means having firm faith in the nature of things as taught in the scriptures composed by the omniscients. It becomes necessary when there is no teacher, one's own intellect is not so subtle, when there is rise of karmans and the objects are subtle and when one does not find proper causes and illustrations.3 Or, the person, who has himself grasped the nature of things, uses naya and pramīņa for supporting the truth, is also said to have performed ajñāna vicaya dharma dhyāna. All studies of scriptures constitute this type of dharma dhyāna.5 (ii) Apāyavicaya dharma dhyāna :- To think that the per-, verted souls are opposed to the path of the omniscient, or to ponder over the ways and means of releasing preachers from wrong belief, knowledge and conduct, constitutes apāya vicaya dharma dhyāna. To contemplate on seven tattvas is also apāya vicaya dharma dhyāna.? (iii) Vipāka vicaya dharma dhyāna :---It means thinking of the various effects of the karmans on the creatures. All pleasures and pains are the result of one's own actions which should be regulated and controlled. All reflections on this aspect are included in this type of dharma dhyāna. (iv) Saṁsthāna vicaya dharma dhyāna :-It means reflect I. Jñānārnava, 32-55. 2. Tattvärthasūtra, 9.36. Also jñānāınava, 33.5. 3. Pujyapāda on Tattvārthas ütra, 9-36. 4. Ibid., 9.36. 5. jñānārnava, 33.9. 6. Pujyapāda on Tattvärthasūtra, 9.36. 7. jñānārņava, 34.11. 8. Pūjyapāda on Tattvärthasūtra. 9.36. Also jñānārņava, 35.1. Page #217 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 200 Jaina Ethics ing over the nature and form of the universe with a view of attaining detachment. It includes reflection over the shape of the universe,2 the seven hells and their miseries,3 the middle region, the sixteen heavens and their pleasures, and the Siddha sila or the place where liberated souls reside." Samsthana vicaya dharma dhyana is again of four types: (A) pindastha; (B) padastha; (C) rupastha; and (D) rüpātīta." (A) Pindastha dhyāna : Pindastha dhyana means concentration based on the body. It is possible in the following five ways .8 (i) Pārthivi dhāraṇā: In this state one has to imagine a peaceful, noiseless and all-white ocean. In the ocean, he imagines a hundred petalled lotus, as wide as Jambudvipa, and of golden colour. The lotus has the pollen of attachment and attracts the bee of mind. It has the pericarp of yellow colour, on which is made a royal seat. One should imagine himself seated on that seat and should believe that he is capable of destroying all karmans." (ii) Agneyi dharaṇā: After pārthivī dhāraṇā, the aspirant should think of a beautiful sixteen petalled lotus in his navel, each petal having one of the sixteen vowels from 'a' to 'ah' (to :). He should imagine the pericarp of the lotus with an illuminating 'rham' () inscribed on it. He should think of a line of smoke arising from the stroke of 'r' () above the 'ha' (). The fire, then, should be imagined as burning an eight-petalled lotus in the region of heart. This lotus, representing the eight karmans, is reduced to ashes. This fire reduces everything, including the body, to ashes and then extinguishes itself.10 1. Pujyapada on Tattvärthasutra 9.36. 2. Jñānāṛṇava, 36.1-9. 3. Ibid., 36.10-81. 4. Ibid., 36.82-87. 5. Ibid., 36.88-181. 6. Ibid., 36.182-185. 7. Ibid., 37.1. 8. Ibid., 37.2. 9. Ibid., 37.4-9. 10. Ibid., 37.10-19. Page #218 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Penances 201 (iii) Māruti dhāraņā : The ashes of the body should be imagined to be carried away by a powerful wind, which moves everything, the army of the gods, Meru mountain, clouds, and oceans. Afterwards the wind should be imagined to be peaceful and calm.? (iv) Vāruri dhāraņā : Afterwards, the aspirant should think of a sky overcast with clouds having rainbow, lightning and thundering. Then follows, in imagination, a downpour of raindrops as big as pearls. These raindrops wash away the remnants of the ashes of the body.2 (v) Tattvar ūpāvati dhāraņā : This includes imagining one's soul to be omniscient, bereft of seven elements of the body. One should think himself to be possessed of all the glories of a Siddha. He should think that all his karmans have exhausted. 3 2. Padastha dhyāna : It means concentrating on the syllables of certain mantras. Many of the letters are to be imagined inscribed on the various petals of the lotus 4 The bija letter ‘Rha' () carries a special significance and Subhacandra gives a detailed process of meditating on it.5 Similarly, japa of praňava, 6 namokāramantra,? sodasāksara mantra,8 and many other mantras of different syllables have been prescribed. The japa of these mantras may lead to the attainment of supernatural powers' as well as omniscience.10 3. Rūpastha dhyāna : It means concentrating on the spiritual qualities of arhants. This type of dhyāna leads to the realisation of the 1. Jñānārņava, 37.23. 2. Ibid., 37.24-27. 3. Ibid., 37.28-30. 4. Ibid., 38.2-6. 5. Ibid., 38.7-30. 6. Ibid., 38.31-37. 7. Ibid., 38.38-47. 8. Ibid., 38.48-50. 9. Ibid., 38.92. 10. Ibid., 38.93. Page #219 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 202 Jaina Ethics ideal on which one concentrates. Here Subhacandra has given a detailed description of the qualities of arhants. 2 4. Rūpātita dhyāna Rūpastha dhyāna implies concentration on embodied liberated souls, Arhants; whereas rūpātīta dhyāna implies concentration on disembodied liberated souls, Siddhas. Here Subhacandra gives a detailed description of Siddhas. 3 The fruits of dharma dhyāna : The first signs of joga are non-sensuality, health, softheartedness, agreeable smell, scantiness of excretion, glory, blissfulness, and clarity of voice.4 Dharma dhyāna leads directly to heavenly pleasures and indirectly to liberation.5 Sukla dhyāna : In dharmadhyāna, the consciousness of the distinction between subject and object of knowledge persists; whereas in sukladhyāna all conceptual thinking ceases gradually. Sukladhyāna is so-called, because it emerges when the filth of passions has been destroyed or has subsided.? Sukla dhyāna is possible only for a person with a body of of the best order (vajravrşabha nārācasamhanana) and for one who has the knowledge of the eleven angas and fourteen pūrvas.8 Stage of Sukladhyāna : With gradual disappearance of conceptual thinking, the sukladhyana has following four stages, the first two of which occur upto the twelfth gunasthāna and the last two only to an omniscient : 1. Prthakatva vitarkasavicāra 1. Jñānārņava. 39.32. 2. Ibid., 39.1-31. 3. Ibid., 40.22-31. Ibid., 41,15 (1). Also cf. Svetāśvataropanisad. 2.13. Ibid., 41.16-27. 6. Ibid., 42.4. Ibid., 42.6. 8. Ibid., 42.5 Page #220 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Penances 203 2. Ekatva vitarkavicära 3. Sūksmakriyā pratipatti 4. Vyuparatakriyānivrtti.1 1. Pịthakatva vitarkavicāra : In this stage, all the three types of activities of body, speech and mind (yogas) continue and the aspirant shifts from one kind of activity to another, 2 from one substance to another, and from one modification to another.3 All these stages of thinking depend on the scriptural knowledge. 4 In spite of the fact that the object of thinking changes here, it is called dhyāna, because many dhyānas together also form dhyāna,5 2. Ekatva vitarkavicāra : Here only one of the three yogas persists and there is no shifting from one object of thinking to another. In this stage also, thinking depends on scriptural knowledge.? After this stage, the aspirant becomes omniscient, and all the obscuring karmans are destroyed. 8 3. Sūkşmakriyāpratipatti : Now only the subtle activities of body persist, and all types of vocal and mental and gross type of physical activities cease. Only the four non-obscuring karmans, viz. agedetermining, feeling-determining, name-determining and family-determining karmans, remain. Now, if the age-determining karman has the same length as other three karmans, the aspirant attains liberation, but if other karmans exceed age-determining karman, they are brought in line with the lastmentioned karman by means of samudghäta.' Subhacandra says 1. Pūjyapāda on Tattvārthas ütra, 9.39. 2. Ibid., 9.40. Also jñānārnava, 42.12. 3. Ibid., 9.44. Also Ibid., 42.16-17. 4. Ibid., 9.43. 5. Ibid., 9.44. 6. Ibid., 9.40. 7. Ibid., 9.41. 8. jñānārņava, 42.29. 9. Cf. Pūjyapāda on Tattvārthas ütra, 9.44. Page #221 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 204 Jaina Ethics that all Kevalins, who have an age-determining karman of a length of less than a period of six months, have to perform samudghata, whereas other Kevalins may or may not perform it.1 He also gives the process of eliminating the yogas. While resorting to gross physical activities, he makes the gross vocal and mental activities subtle; and then resorting to the later, he makes the former also subtle. Resorting to the subtle physical activities, he stops other two activities completely.2 4. Samucchinnakriyā: Here all activities stop completely. The soul shines forth in its intrinsic lustre, all karmans exhaust, and he leaves his body in the time taken for pronouncing five small letters.3 Conclusion: We have given the description of different varieties of external as well as internal penances in this chapter. In conclusion, we may note the following points: 1. Jainism lays emphasis on penance; but it must be characterised by spiritual awakening, or else it becomes a mere torture of the body (balatapa). 2. Jainism prescribes voluntary infliction of physical pains to a greater extent than other religions. In this respect, it remarkably differs from Buddhism which holds such penances as futile. 3. The transcendental morality culminates in meditation which should never be used as a means for attaining supernatural powers. 4. Prāṇāyāma, āsana etc. do not form an essential part of Jaina Yoga and are even condemned sometimes from spiritual point of view. I. Jñānārṇava, 42.42. 2. Ibid,, 42.48-50. 3. Pujyapada on Tattvārthas ūtra, 9.44. Also Jñānārṇava, 42.53-59. Page #222 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CHAPTER VIII STAGES OF SPIRITUAL DEVELOPMENT Introduction : From the first stage of impulsive life, which is comparable to animal existence, to the ultimate end of liberation, where one attains perfection, the aspirant passes through many stages. Fighting against karmans, which have held the soul in check from beginningless time, the aspirant continues his moral struggle till he achieves the state of supramoral existence of complete harmony. Strictly speaking, the stages through which an aspirant passes differ from moment to moment and are therefore innumerable; yet for the sake of convenience and for a better understanding of the process of spiritual development, the Jaina ācīryas have described fourteen stages of the spiritual journey, called gunasthānas, which we propose to deal with in the present chapter.1 It may be pointed out these fourteen stages of developments do not imply any mechanical process. They merely afford a complete picture of spiritual development from the beginning to the end. Some of these gunasthānas, for example 7th, 8th, 9th, 10th and 11th, last for a short duration, not more than a fraction of 48 minutes. This classification is, therefore, more important for reading the psychology of an aspirant in different places of his spiritual sādhanā. Many details regarding these guņasthānas belong to the sphere of karaṇānuyoga rather than to caraṇānuyoga. As we are here concerned only with the ethical implications of these gunasthānas, we will not go into details of such particular as are not connected with our subject. 1. Cf. यावन्तः परिणामास्तावन्त एव गुणा किन्न भवन्तीति चेन्न, तथा व्यवहारानुपपत्तितो द्रव्याथिकनयसमाश्रयणात् । -Virasena on Șațkhandāgama, 1.1.17 (Vol. I, p. 184). 2. Cf. Pujyapada On Tattvärthas ūtra, 1.8. (pp. 32-33). Also Virasena on Satkhandāgama, 1.5.19-22 (Vol. IV, pp. 350-355). Page #223 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 206 Jaina Ethics It may also be pointed out here that there are examples of aspirant, like Bharata, who attained liberation within no time of attaining the samyaktva. This proves that liberation is not necessarily a slow process. The speed depends on the intensity of the previously accumulated kurmans on the one hand, and the intensity of earnestness of the aspirant on the other. The great obstacle 'delusion' (moha): Before we proceed to describe the stages of development, let us state it clearly that the main enemy of the spiritual progress is delusion (moha). It has two aspects : (1) that which perverts-attitude of soul (darśanamohaniya) and (2) that which obstructs right conduct in the form of mental pol. lution (cāritra mohaniya). Once the first type of delusion is removed, the aspirant is bound to get rid of the second type of delusion also. We have already referred to the various sub-varieties of darśanamohanīya and cāritramohaniya. It is after subsidence or annihilation of all the three types of darśanamohaniya and attainment of the first degree of intensity, anantānubandhi, of four kaşāyas that the aspirant comes to the fourth stage of development from where his real struggle begins. The threefold division of ātman : Broadly speaking, the ātman can be divided into the following three categories according to the position occupied in the laddar of spiritual development : 1. Extrovert soul (bahirātman) 2. Introvert soul (antrātman). 3. Super-soul (paramātman). Extroversion is to get rid of. Introversion is the means to the goal of the supra-ethical stage, which is the paramātman. Bahirātman : This is a state of impulsive life of lust and worldly en 1. Adipurāņa, 47-395. 2. Paramātamaprakāśa, 1.12. Also Jñānārņava, 32.10. 3. Mokşapāhuda, 5-8. Page #224 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Stages of Spiritual Development 207 joyments. The soul is absolutely ignorant as to its true destiny. It is at animal plane of existence, where indiscrimination and wanton activities predominate. This state can be compared to saṁsāraprāgbhāra of Yoga and prthagjana of Buddhism. A person, identifying himself with the body,' relatives and possessions, 2 is afraid of self-destruction at their separation. Even if he performs penances, it is with a view to attain worldly pleasures. The first three guṇasthānas consist of extrovert souls. Subhacandra, while commenting upon Kārtikeyānuprekṣā, says that the jivas in the first, second and third guṇasthānas are called utkrsța, madhjama and jaghanya, bahirātmans respectively.5 2. Antarātman : With this stage begins the dawn of moral consciousness. Licentious activities are checked by voluntary regulations. This state corresponds to kaivalyaprāgbhāra of Yoga and srotāpanna of Buddhism. Here the aspirant distinguishes between the self and the non-self. He relinquishes all the eight types of pride.? This stage is also classified under three categories. The best type of antarātman includes those who observe the five great vows, are steadfast in dharma and sukladhyāna and overcome all types of pramādas. This includes stages from the 7th gunasthāna (apramattasamyata) to the 12th guṇasthāna (kṣīņakaṣāya).8 The next best type of antarātaman includes those who observe the vows of a householder and a stage in the 6th guṇasthāna. The lowest type of antarātman is of those who, though possessed of right attitude, are devoid of observance of any moral vow.10 ܛܼ 1. Kārtikeyānuprekşā, 193. 2. Jñānārņava, 32.17, 21. 3. Ibid., 32.18. Samadhisataka, 42. Subhacandra on Kārtikeyānuprekşā, 193. 6. Mokşapāhuda, 17. 7. Kārtikeyānupreksā, 194. 8. Ibid., 195. Also Subhacandra on it. 9. Ibid., 196. 10. Ibid., 197 Page #225 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 208 Jaina Ethics Parmātman : This stage is the goal of all spiritual exertion. Here all conflicts disappear and the soul shines forth in its natural qualities. This is a state of complete harmony. This state is comparable to jivanmukta and mukta of Hinduism and anāgāmin and Arhat-ship of Buddhism. The jivanmukta state can be compared to Arhat, who is an embodied Paramātman; whereas the Siddha state is the state of disembodied liberation. We have already dealt with the nature of liberated soul in the second chapter. This stage is free from birth, old age and death, where the four infinitive qualities of soul shine forth on account of freedom from all the four ghāti karmans in the case of an ar hant and of all the eight karmans in the case of a Siddha.? Five labdhis A soul before attaining right attitude in the fourth gunasthāna passes through stages which are five in number. The first four of them are possible even without right attitude. Therefore, they do not indicate any real spiritual progress. They are ethically important only if they lead to right attitude through the fifth labdhi. 1. The first labdhi is called kṣāyopasama, which means destruction-cum-subsidence of the kārmic matter.4 This labdhi is not the result of any conscious effort on the part of the aspirant but occurs automatically in the normal course of time. 2. As a result of first labdhi, the self inclines towards auspicious types of actions which lead to happiness. This is called visuddhi labdhi.5 3. The third labdhi, desanā labdhi, means obtaining a teacher who initiates and leads into the nature of six dravyas and nine padārthas. If no such teacher is available in hell, 1. Kārtikeyānupreksā 198. 2. Niyamasāra, 176. 3. Labdhisāra, Bombay, 1946, 3 4. Ibid., 4. 5. Ibid., 5. 6. Ibid., 6. Page #226 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Stages of Spiritual Development 209 then this labdhi means inclination towards the true nature of things on account of the impressions of previous births.1 4. The fourth labdhi, prayogya labdhi, means the capacity to so reduce the duration of all karmans, except āyuḥ karman, that they are squeezed in the time of crore into crore (koțākoți) years and this labhdi is possible for bhavyas and abhavyas alike.2 5. The first four labdhis are important only if they lead to the fifth, karaña labdhi. The karana labdhi is attained by a bhavya jiva only. The karaņa labdhi consists of the following three karaņas. Three karanas : The soul, through its wanderings, feels sometimes inclined towards self-realisation, but because of the eternal force of passions it is wavering between the right path and the wrong path. This is called yathāpravsttikaraņa.4 During this process, whenever the intensity of the bondage of karnan is lessened the soul faces what is called granthi. Once the granthi is broken asunder, the soul is sure to get liberation.6 This process is called granthibheda or cutting of the Gordian knot. Some souls come out victorious from this struggle; some accept defeat; and some others remain engaged in the struggle for a considerable period. This struggle is the cause of development. The soul, if successful in this struggle, realises the emptiness of worldly enjoyments and a sense of dissatisfaction with them. The struggle continues in the I. Keśavavarni on Labdhisära, Calcutta, 1916,6. 2. Labdhisāra, 7. 3. Gommațasāra, Jivakānda, 651. 4. Kotyācārya on Višeşāvasyakabhāsya, Ratalam, 1936, 1207. 5. गंठित्ति सुदुबोओ कक्खडघण रूढगंठिव्व । जीवस्स कम्म जणिओ घण रागद्दोसपरिणामो ॥ –Višeșāvasyakabhāsya, 1200. Also तीइ वि य थोव मित्ते खविए इत्थंतरम्मि जीवस्स । हवइ हु अभिन्नपुव्वो गंठी एवं जिणा बिन्ति ॥ ---Srāvakaprajñapti, Bombay, Vik. Sam. 1961, 32. 6. भिन्नमि तंमि लाभो जायइ परमपयहेउणो नियमा। -Ibid., 33 Page #227 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 210 Jaina Ethics apūrvakarana, but this time consciously. As this has never happened before, it is known as apūrvakarana.1 If yathāpravritikarana, is not followed by apūrvakaraña and anivsttikarana, it is futile. Even abhavyas experience yathāpravrttikarana, but without any use. The apūrvakarana further reduces the duration and intensity of karmans. This is made possible by the following five processes : (1) sthitighāta-destruction in the duration; (2) rasaghāta-destruction of the intensity; (3) gunaśreņi-conversion of karmans of longer duration into those having a duration of not more than a muhūrta; and (4) gunasaṁkramaņa---conversion of the karmans of intensive degree into those of milder degrees. The third step is anivrttikaraṇa. Here the struggle ends in favour of the aspirant. The most intense type (anantānubandhi) of passions and vision-deluding karmans are annihilated and the aspirant reaches the fourth stage of spiritual development. Two śreņis : Before coming to the description of gunasthānas, it will be in the fitness of things to mention that the aspirant ascends the stages of spiritual development either by subsidence (upaśama) or by annihilation (kşaya) of karmans. These are called two ladders (śreņis) of spiritual development. The aspirants belonging to the first śreņi are those who subside their delusion. The dirt in the bottom comes up in the water, similarly the delusion gives a defeat to the aspiring spirits and they fall down from the arduously attained height. These aspirants cannot go beyond the eleventh stage of development. The other aspirants are those who rise through destruction of delusion. One can climb the ladder of subsidence only twice in one life. According to the Karmagrantha, a person who has climbed 1. Virasena on Satkhan dagama, 1.1.16 (Vol. I, p. 180). 2. Ibid., 1.9-8.5. (Vol. VI, p. 222). 3. Ibid., 1.9-8.5. (Vol. VI, p. 221). 4. 'Ibid., 1.9-8.14 (Vol. VI, p. 317). 5. Cf. Pravacanasāroddhāra, 700-708. 6. Cf. Ibid., 694-699. Page #228 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ wwwgt inte tyek Stages of Spiritual Development 211 only once the ladder of subsidence can attain liberation in that very life through the ladder of annihilation. But a person, who has climbed the ladder of subsidence twice, has no chance of liberation in that life. According to Canons, however, a soul can climb only one of the two ladders in one life,1 Mithyadrsti guṇasthāna:2 This is a state of absolutely perverted attitude. A person in this guṇasthāna may even attain heaven, but is far away from liberation. The soul has been rotting in it from time immemorial without knowing the real path. Though any man with a perverted attitude is equally away from the goal, whatever his external conduct, yet a distinction has to be made between one soul and the other, even in the first guṇasthāna. Muni Śrīyaśovijaya, in his Yogavatāradvātriṁśikā classifies souls into eight mitrā, tārā, balā, diprā, sthirā, kāntā, prabhā and parā.3 The first four of them belong to first gunasthāna.4 In the very first stage called mitrā, the soul gets the first indistinct enlightenment. He serves the ascetics, worships the founders of religion, performs good deeds and shows a sympathy towards the suffering but without making any real distinction between self and non-self. As his desire to know the truth becomes more earnest, the soul enters the second stage of tārā. Here the soul is more steady and conscious of its shortcomings. In the third stage, called balā, the evil desires cease and the enlightenment becomes clearer. The fourth stage, called diprā, where the soul, though having a verbal knowledge of the truths of religion, does not understand its reality. He has not as yet come face to face with the reality. The next four stages belong to a soul who has realised the self. Thus we see that even the unveiling of vision-deluding Sri Jaina Siddhantabola samgraha, Vol. V, pp. 83-84. Virasena on Satkhandagama, 1.1.9. Also Gommatas āra, Jivakända, 8-18. 3. Yogavatäradvātrimšika, 25. Quoted by Pt. Sukhalala, Jaina dharma aura darśana, Ahmedabad, 1957, p. 268. 4. Ibid., 28. ff. I. 2. Page #229 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 212 Jaina Ethics karmans is not a sudden phenomenon. It may be noted here that the conduct of a person in these four stages can not be termed as right as it does not necessarily lead to liberation. It is only after cutting the Gordian knot (granthibheda) through anivịttikaraņa that one attains the real spiritual insight.2 Till then, we can compare his condition with that of a wanderer who is sometimes nearer the real path sometimes away from it. But in no case does he find it. His coming nearer the real path is useful only if he finds it; otherwise he is again lost in the thickness of the jungle. We have spoken of the types of mithyātva in the second chapter. It may be interesting to note here that amongst those who get liberation even anyalingasiddhas or those wearing the dresses of other religions are included. Commentaries on karmagranthas, however, make it clear that every word of the Jaina scriptures must be believed by a samyagdrsti.4 For those souls who are abhavya or jātibhavya and will never get liberation,5 the first punasthāna has neither beginning nor end; for those who get liberation it has no beginning but end and for those who having broken the knot, again descend to first stage, it has a beginning as well as an end. As every soul has some element of purity in it, this stage, though of complete darkness, is also considered to be guņasthāna in as much as it has also a ray of purity, just as even though the rays of the sun and the moon are completely obscured by clouds yet we cannot say that the light has been completely destroyed. If there had been a complete destruc 1. Uttarādhyayana, 28.30. Also Gomma ļasāra, Jivakānda, 12. 2. Supra, p. 209. 3. Sri Jaina Siddhāntabola saṁyraha, Vol. V, p. 119. 4. यतो भगवदर्हत्प्रणीतं सकलमपि द्वादशाङगार्थमभिरोचयमानोऽपि यदि तद् गदितमेकमप्यक्षरं न रोचयति तदानीमप्येष मिथ्यादृष्टिरेवोच्यते । --Karmagranthaţikā, Vol. II, Quoted by Muni Nathamala, Faina darśana ke maulika tattva', Vol. II, p. 449. 5. Cf. Virasena on Satkhandāgama, 1.1.141. (Vol. I, p. 394). Also Srāvakaprajñapti, 66-67. 6. तथाहि समुन्नतातिबहलजीमूतपटलेन दिनकररजनीकरकरनिकरतिरस्कारेऽपि Aaaa ACTHAIST: pt...." - Karmagrantha, Vol. II, Quoted by Muni Nathamala, Jaina darśana ke maulika jñaptitattva'. Vol. II. p. 449. Page #230 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Stages of the Spiritnal Development 213 tion of knowledge Jiva would have become ajiva. 2. Sāsvādana-samyag drsți-gunasthāna? : The soul while falling from fourth gunasthāna to the first makes a sojourn through this guņasthāna. This is a stage not of development but that of degradation. A soul which has attained Aupa śamikasamyaktva (i.e. subsided vision--deluding karman temporarily), at the rise of life-long, intense types of four passions, falls to the first stage. In this process of degradation, he passes through this stage. He has an indistinct idea of samyaktva for a very short period (one samaya to six ävalis) before he reverts to mithyātva. The soul in second stage invariably falls down to the first stage. But this stage has an indistinct element of samyaktva and, therefore, is considered to be higher than the first gunasthāna. Just as a person who has tasted something sweet (like khira etc.) and then vomitted it out feels a strange taste of sweetness, similarly the soul in this stage has a strange feeling of samyaktva. Because of the existence of this taste it is called sāsvādana.3 The BỊhatkalpabhâsya gives another two examples. Just as a person falling from a ladder stays for sometimes in the vaccum, before coming to the earth, a person falling from samyaktva to mithyātva also experiences an admixture of the two for some time. Another example is that of a person who has tasted sugar. He goes to sleep but has not completely slept. In that state, he still feels the sweetness of sugar indistinctly. Similar is the case with the soul in the second guṇasthāna.5 3. Samyag mithyādršți guṇasthāna: This is a stage of uncertainty and tension. Due to the 1. Karmagrantha, Vol. II, Quoted by Muni Nathamala Jaina darśana ke Maulika tattva Vol. II. p. 449. 2. Virasena on Satkhandāgama, 1.1,10 (Vol. I, p. 163). Also Gommațasära, Jivakānda, 19-20. 3. Bohatkalpabhäşya, Vol. I, 128. 4. Ibid., 126. Also Gommatasara, Jivakända, 20. 5. Ibid., 128. 6. Virasena on Saļkhandāgama, 1.1.11 (Vol. I, p. 166). Also Gommațasāra, Jivakānda, 21-24. Page #231 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 214 Faina Ethics rise of miśramohaniyakarmans, the soul remains indifferent to truth. It neither believes nor disbelieves it. After this stage, a soul may ascend to true belief or may descend to false belief. Either a person may ascend to this third stage or a person may descend from some higher stage to this stage. It is, therefore, a stage of development as well as of degradation, according to circumstances. This stage has been compared to curd mixed with sugar which has sour as well as sweet taste.1 4. Aviratasamyagdrsţi gunasthāna : An aspirant having firm belief in truth attains this stage. The anantānubandhi category of passions is subdued and only the weak form, called apratyākhyānavarni kaşāya, remains which does not last more than a year. We have already dealt with the character of an aviratasamyagdışți. In this gunasthāna on account of apratyākhyānakaṣāya, the existence of the aspirant is not able to observe any moral vows. Therefore, he is called avirata. Here the aspirant realises for the first time that the sensual pleasures, for which he strives so much, are only temporary, finite and painful in the end. Still he cannot leave them.3 The moral condition of an aspirant in the fourth stage can be compared to the state of Duryodhana, who said, "I know the truth but I cannot follow it; I know the falsehood but I cannot shun it." Morally, a man in the fourth stage is still not mature, yet this stage is very important in as much as it indicates the beginning of real spiritual exertion. 5. Deśasamyata gunasthānas : Here the stoppage of karmans begins. With the removal. 1. Gommațasāra, Jivakānda, 22. 2. Virasena on Satakhandägama,, 1.1.12 (Vol. I, p. 170), Also Gommațasāra, Jivakānda, 27-29. 3. Gomma tasara, Jivakānda, 29. Cf. Muni Nathamala, Jaina darśana ke maulika tattva, p. 301. 5. Virasena on Satkhandāgama, 1.1.13. (Vol. I, p. 173), Also Gomma fasāra, Jivakānda, 30-31. Page #232 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Stages of the Spiritual Developemnt 215 of apratyākyāna kașāya the aspirant takes partial vows. This gunasthāna includes not only those persons who inhabit the houses but also the person who leaves the house but cannot take to monkhood. Thus the highest type of a śrāvaka is he who neither does, nor makes others do, any prohibited action. We have already dealt with the eleven stages of this gumasthāna at the end of the fifth chapter. 6. Pramatta samyata gunasthānal : After subduing the third degree of passion viz. pratyā. khyānavarana,? when only sanjvalana type remains, the aspirant joins the order of mendicants. He observes complete restraint but is still open to such negligences as pride, enjoyments of senses, passions and sleep. The partial peace that one gets in the fifth stage of spiritual development inspires him to adopt complete self-control and to proceed towards self-realisation. Now he relinquishes all social obligations and joins the order of mendicants to devote his entire time and energies to the supreme goal. He abstains not only from killing harmless animals but even harmful animals. He does not take even a trivial things without the permission of the owner. He does not hold any property at all. Thus, even though self-controlled, he is not free from negligence. There is no appearance of Pratyakhyānavarana kaşāya and only samjualana form of kasāya remains. Due to samjvalana form of kaşāya and existence of negligence, the energy of the soul is not fully expressed. We have already dealt with the conduct of a monk, who begins his life from this guṇasthāna, in the sixth chapter. 7. Apramattasamyata guṇasthānaa : When negligence, which is the cause of small defects in the sixth stage, is removed, the soul ascends to the seventh gunasthāna. In this stage, the aspirant wins the three stronger types of sleep, viz. nidrānidra, pracatāpracata and styānagyddhi. He 1. Virasena on Satkhandägama, 1.1.14 (Vol. I, p. 175), Also Ibid., 32-33. 2. Ibid., 1.1.15 (Vol. I, p. 178), Also Gomma fasāra, Jivakānda, 45-48. Page #233 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 216 Jaina Ethics tries to overcome the milder types of passions also and is always struggling against them. His condition is comparable to that of a log of wood moving up and down with the rise and fall of the waves. 8. Nivrttibādara gunasthānal : Here the soul comes out successful in the struggle going on in the seventh gunasthāna. The soul ascends positively either of the two śreņies described in the beginning. Uptil the seventh stage the soul follows the path of ksayopaśama. This means that anantānubandhikaṣāya etc. are neither completely repressed nor destroyed uptil the seventh stage. These kaşāyas do rise in the previous gunasthānas but without the fruit-giving potency. Thus the soul is able to reduce the effect of karmans in the four ways mentioned earlier in the beginning of this chapter. In the eighth gunasthāna, the soul adopts apūrvakarana. Those who are in the upašama śreņi, remain in the eighth guņasthāna minimum for a samaya and maximum for antarmuhurtta; and those who are in the kșapakaśreņi for antarmahūrtta. Here anger and pride disappear. 9. Anivrtti-sāmparāya gunasthāna? : Through the four ways mentioned above, the progress becomes automatic and uniform in cases of all aspirants Anger and pride have already disappeared; now deceit disappears and three types of sexual desires also subside. In this stage, the struggle for spiritual progress comes to an end in the sense that the aspirant has not to make any conscious efforts for progress. His progress becomes automatic. Here the soul performs the process of anivrttikarana. In this stage, there is still a fear of attack of gross passions. Therefore, this is called bādarasāmparāya in contradistinction to the next stage, -sūksma sāmparāya, where only subtle types of greed can occasionally disturb the peace of soul. . 1. Virasena on Sațkhandāgama, 1.1.15 (Vol. I, p. 183). Also Gommatasāra, Jivakānda, 50-54. 2. Ibid., 1.1.17 (Vol. I, p. 183). Also Ibid., 56-57 Page #234 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Stages of the Spiritual Development 217 10. Sūksmasāmparāya guṇasthānal : As indicated already, only subtle form of greed remains in this guṇasthāna. This greed means the subtle attachment of the soul with the body. Here the soul, following the upaśama śreņi, ascends to the eleventh gunasthāna and those following the kșapakaśreņi directly ascend to the twelfth gunasthāna. 11. Upaśāntamohaniya gunasthāna: This is the highest stage which can be reached on the upaśamaśreņi. Only the upaśamakas ascend this guṇasthāna. It lasts minimum for one samaya and maximum for antarmuhürtta The soul in this guṇasthāna does not go further. As aspirant from this guņasthāna, descends either to the sixth or fifth or fourth or first gunasthāna. But, ultimately within a period of ardhapudgalaparāvarta he again becomes a kşapaka and attains liberation. 12. Kșiņakāṣāyachadmastha vitarāga guṇasthāna3 : Here the mohaniya, which is the main obstruction, is completely destroyed. The ksapaka comes directly to this stage without going to the eleventh stage. After remaining antarmuhürtta in this stage, he becomes omniscient without fail and ascends to the thirteenth stage. In the penultimate samaya, the first two kinds of sleep (nidrā and pracalā) are eliminated. In the last samaya of this stage, five types of Jñānāvarani, daršanāvarasi and antarāya karmans are completely annihilated. 13. Sayogakevali gunasthāna :* As soon as the ghātikarmans are destroyed at the end of the twelfth guṇasthāna, the four infinities (anantaj ñāna, ananta 1, Virasena on Satkhandāgama, 1.1.18 (Vol. I, p. 187), Also Gommațasāra, Jivakānda, 58-60. 2. Ibid., 1.1.19 (Vol. I, p. 188). Also Ibid., 61. 3. Ibid., 1.1.20. (Vol. I, p. 189). Also Ibid., 62. 4. Virasena on Satkhandägama, 1.1.21 (Vol. I, p. 190). Also Gommațasāra, Jivakānda, 63, 64. Page #235 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 218 Jaina Ethics virya, ananta darśana and ananta sukha) are obtained. It may be mentioned that it is only in this gunasthāna that the jñānāvaraṇīkarmans are removed. The actual struggle consists of conquering the passions. Hence the importance of conduct rather than that of knowledge in Jainism. Here only the Yoga, out of the four causes of bondage, remains. But the bondage lasts only for two samayas; and that bondage relates only to four aghāti karmans viz. vedaniya, āyuş, nāman and gotra. Due to the existence of these karmans, the soul has bodily existence and can be compared to jivanmukta of Vedanta. 14. Ayogakevali gunasthāna:1 At the end of the thirteenth stage, the aspirant prepares himself for salvation. In case the duration of Vedaniya, naman and gotra is longer than that of ayus, he equalises these karmans by a process called samudghāta. Then the soul proceeds to check the three yogas also. This is done in the following order. The gross mental and vocal activities are checked by gross physical activities, which are checked by subtle physical activities in turn. Subtle physical activities also check subtle mental and vocal activities. The subtle physical activities are checked by sukṣmakriyānivṛtti type of sukladhyāna. Here the subtle activity of body is checked by itself. This dhyāna also makes the soul contract and fill up the cavities of body. The soul is thus reduced to two-third of its previous volume. Then the soul enters the last type of sukladhyāna which is called samucchinna kriyātipāti, which stops all activities and leads to what is called failesikarana i.e. a state of complete motionlessness. This state lasts for only as much time as is required to pronounce five short vowels. At the end of this period the soul leaves the embodied state for ever and goes straight above, to the end of the universe, to enjoy its inherent blissfulness for ever. 1. Virasena on Satkhaṇḍāgama, 1.1.22. (Vol. I, p. 192). Also Ibid., 65. Page #236 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Stages of the Spiritual Development Conclusion: In Jainism the spiritual progress begins from right faith. Right faith leads to avoidance of sins. Avoidance of sins makes a man vigilant. Vigilance leads to passionlessness and passionlessness leads to cessation of karmans. This, in short, is the path to liberation. 219 Page #237 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CONCLUSION We have studied in the foregoing chapters the ethical principles of Jainism and compared them with those of Hinduism and Buddhism, with which it came into close contact. We find that the 'unity in diversity' found in Indian culture, is as much true in the sphere of ethics also. There has been much give-and-take between these religions; and the virtue of non-violence may be mentioned as the greatest contribution of Jainism to the current of Indian thought. The history of Jaina ethics is a fine example of what the Jainas hold to be the nature of reality, viz., continuity in change. We have noticed during our study that the fundamentals of Jaina ethics have remained unchanged through all these years, though the rules of code of conduct have shown some modification, which we have noted here and there, specially while dealing with the conduct of a house-holder and a monk. It may also be noted here that though the rules of conduct as prescribed by Jainism and recorded by us appear to be too elaborate and sometimes even superfluous, yet the basic idea behind these rules is that of self-realisation. When there is a feeling-realisation of the true nature of the self and when one is completely lost in the bliss of self-meditation, the observance of all the moral rules becomes spontaneous, coming from within and not being an imposition from without. Though we have already recorded our conclusions at the end of every chapter, and sometimes even at the end of our discussion of a particular topic, yet no ethical study could be useful unless it provided an answer to the problems with which our lives are beset. We are, therefore, tempted to conclude our discussion with a few observations on how the principles of Jaina ethics could be helpful in solving the problems of humanity at large. The problems of human life arise out of various factors, which can be classified under the following broad heads : Page #238 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Conclusion 221 1. Scarcity. 2. Injustice. 3. Ignorance. 4. Selfishness. Scarcily In spite of the great strides of science and technology, we know that humanity suffers from scarcity. Science tries to solve this problem in its own way by inventing tools for increasing production, by improving means of comforts and luxuries, and by developing new means of fighting against the furies of nature. But we know that apart from the scarcity caused by natural circumstances, there is also an artificial scarcity created by indulgence into such selfish tendencies as hoarding and profiteering not only by individuals but by nations also, trying to expand and wanting to occupy others' territories by force. "The greater the possessions, the greater the happiness' is the motto of many. Jainism teaches us quite the opposite : 'the lesser the possessions the greater the happiness'. Happi. ness comes from what we are and not from what we possess. We should realise the blissful nature of the self, become free and be not the slaves of worldly objects. This puts an end to the struggle for wealth and other possessions. For those who can reach the highest stage of monkhood, scarcity becomes a self-imposed virtue followed voluntarily in pursuance of complete freedom from bondage; for those who cannot attain that height, limitations of possession, coupled with a sense of detachment towards what one has, is recommended. The idea behind the vow of non-possession is not a morbid feeling of self-mortification but a sense of, and belief in, the inherent bliss of the self. The answer of Jainism to the problem of scarcity is : Be not attached to the worldly objects; be not their slaves; turn to the self within wherefrom comes the true happiness. This does not imply a life of inertia, but that of contemplation and contentment. What is true of the individual is true of the nations. The glorification of a king who desires to conquer others' territory (vijigīșu), though very common in other ancient Page #239 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 222 Jaina Ethics Indian literature, is foreign to Jaina literature; the greed for expansion is unmistakably condemned in the too well-known story of Bharata and Bāhubali. Injustice The bigger fish swallow the smaller ones. The mighty and the aggressive prosper, the humble and the meek suffer. The result is the rule of jungle. In the sphere of politics we kill and crush in the name of caste, creed and colour. The result is war and bloodshed. Jainism brings us hope of justice in the form of doctrine of karman. As we sow, so shall we reap. Though there is no God who sits upon judgment on us, there is a law, based on the theory of cause and effect, which works automatically and unfailingly. All life is equal and the stronger have no right to do any injustice to the weaker; and if they do, they do not harm anybody but themselves. Ill-feeling vitiates our moral structure first; it harms anybody else afterwards. To kill a man with a hot rod of iron, the killer will burn his own hands first before he can kill the other. It is not so much out of regard for the life of others that we are forbidden to kill, as out of regard for our own selves. We should meet an injustice not with force but with forbearance. Enmity leads to enmity: but if we do not retaliate it, it subsides. The attitude of equanimity of Pārsva to Dharanindra and Kamatha, when the former tried to save him from the latter who tried to kill, beautifully illustrates the Jaina attitude. Jainism has also opposed from the beginning any social injustice arising out of casteism or racialism. 'Mankind is one community', says Jinasena.1 Mahātmā Gāndhi successfully applied the creed of nonviolence to redress the injustice of one nation against another. The creed of non-violence, if applied to the international problems, has the potentiality of wiping out the institution of war from the surface of earth. 1. Caral --Adipurāna, 38.45. Page #240 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Conclusion 223 Thus the answer of Jainism to the problem of injustice is four-fold : doctrine of karman, equality of life, non-violence and equanimity. Ignorance In spite of the spread of education in modern times, the problems of life seem to multiply rather than decrease. Of what use is knowledge which binds us rather than liberate ? Jainism teaches us that all knowledge is relative and corelated. Let us be receptive to every thought. Let us not assume the attitude of finality about our knowledge. One-sided attitude only complicates problems rather than solve them. It does not give us any solution to such ethical questions as determinism' and 'freedom of will'. Non-absolutism shows us the path of synthesis among fate and human effort; faith, knowledge and action; and supra-moral plane of life and practical code of morality. The answer of Jainism to the problem of knowledge is represented in its doctrine of non-absolutism. Much of misunderstanding between one nation and the other could be solved if we could adopt the attitude of nonabsolutism on political problems. Selfishness Selfishness lies at the root of all problems. All immoral practices arise out of selfish nature of man. Selfishness can be overcome by realising the true nature of self. According to Vedānta, the individual se identical with the universal self (brahman); and the summum bonum of life is to realise this identity. This broadens our outlook and lifts us above selfishness. Buddhism, on the other hand, asks us not only to destroy our ego but also to believe that the self, for which we struggle so much, is a non-entity. Both of these views represent idealism, whereas Jainism is a realistic system. It propounds that the self is a real, permanent entity and that each soul has a distinct existence. What Jainism lays down is neither a belief in the unity of life nor in the non-entity of the self, but a distinction between the self (jiva) and the non-self (ajiva) and a victory over passions Page #241 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 224 Jaina Ethics which are based on a false conception of the identity of the two. An ordinary Jaina (samyagḍrşți) is not allowed to indulge in feelings of anger, pride, hypocrisy and greed continuously for more than a year, a householder at an advanced stage (śravaka) for more than four months, and a monk for more than fifteen days. Perfection or liberation is attained when these feelings are completely overcome; and not, as the Vedanta will have us believe, when the self merges into the universal self; or, as the Buddhism believes, when it is annihilated. We need not discard commonly experienced, separate, existence of the self. The above ethical idea, which Jainism gave with reference to individual sadhana, could be interpreted afresh in the con text of modern day problems to suggest that all nations could also maintain their individuality, and yet live in peace and harmony if negative ideas of anger, pride, hypocrisy and greed could be renounced. It could, thus, teach the possibility and utility of co-existence in modern times and bring the hope of a brighter future for war-ridden humanity of to-day. If Jaina ethics could bring home to us that alone, its purpose will be more than achieved. Page #242 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ APPENDIX ETHICAL LITERATURE OF THE JAINAS The history of the Jaina literature begins from Mahāvīra. The tradition mentions that a bulky literature classified under fourteen heads, called Purvas, existed even before Mahavira,2 but unfortunately that literature became extinct as early as 182 B.C. according to Digambara tradition, and in 473 A.D. according to Svetämbara tradition.4 The post Mahavira literature can be classified under two heads (i) canonical literature; and (ii) non-canonical literature. The canonical literature can again be classified into two categories : (i) Angapravista, which consists of the twelve Angas, the essence of which is claimed to have been imparted to his eleven principal disciples, known as ganadharas,5 by Lord Mahāvira himself. (ii) Angabahya, which includes the composition by later ācāryas also and consists of twelve Upangas, six Chedasūtras and four Mulas utras. The Digambaras disown the extant canonical literature, which, according to them, was gradually lost by 156 A.D. Besides the canonical literature, there is a vast non-canonical literature of both the sects of Jainism. The whole of the Jaina literature, is, again, classified under four anuyogas, based on the subject-matter with which each one deals,8 1. Nandis ütra, Rajakota, 1958, p. 634. Also Siddhāntasärādisaṁgraha, Bombay, Vik. Sam. 1979, Angaprajñapti, 2.1-117. 2. Jaina, H.L., Bharatiya samskṛti mem Jainadharma kā yogadāna, Bhopal, 1962, pp. 51-53. 3. Satkhanḍagama, Amaravati, 1939, Vol. I, prastāvanā, p. 26. 4. Bhagavatis utra, Ahmedabad. Vik. Sam., 1988, 20.8.9. 5. Nandicürni, Ratalam, 1928, p. 6. 6. Nandis ütra, pp. 524-547. 7. Kaşayaprabhṛta, Mathura, 1944, Vol. I, prastāvanā, p. 49. For canonical literature of the Digambaras, see further. 8. Bhadrabahu on Daśavaikālikas ātra, Ahmedabad, 1932, gāthās, 3-4, Page #243 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 226 Jaina Ethics (i) The literature dealing with ethical aspect is called Caraṇakaraṇānuyoga. The Digambaras call it simply as Caraṇā nuyoga. (ii) The literature dealing with metaphysical problems is called dravyānuyoga. (iii) The biographies of religious personalities are included in dharmakathānuyoga or prathamānuyoga. (iv) The works dealing with mathematics are called ganitanuyoga. The Digambaras have karaṇānuyoga, as the fourth anuyoga. Karaṇānuyoga deals with the details of doctrine of karman. It would be interesting to know that Caraṇānuyoga, which has a direct bearing on ethics is given the highest place and the other anuyogas are considered only subsidiary to it.1 The Anga literature The Angas, composed in Ardhamagadhi language and twelve in number, are supposed to have been passed down from generation to generation by oral transmission till Bhadrabahu, who belonged to the 8th or 7th generation following Mahavira, and died 1703 or 1624 years after him (357 B C. or 365 B.C.) according to Svetambara and Digambara tradition, respectively. Redaction of Agamas Council of Pataliputra (4th Cent. B.C.): The Curni on Avasyaka informs us that at the time of Bhadrabahu, there was a wide-spread famine, lasting for twelve years. This meant a disturbance in the study of Jaina scriptures. After the end of the said famine, the monks of Jaina Samgha assembled at Pățaliputra and recollected the first eleven Jaina Angas but could not recollect the twelfth 1. चरणकरणानुयोगश्चाचारादिकः, स च प्रधानतमः शेषाणां तदर्थत्वात् । -Silänka on Acărängas ütra, Calcutta, Vik. Sam. 1936. p. 3. Vide infra, p. 229. 2. 3. Parisistaparva, Bhavanagar, Vik. Sam. 1968, 9.112. 4. Satkhandagama. Vol. I, Prastāvanā, p. 26. Page #244 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 227 Ethical Literature of the Jainas Anga, dışțivāda. Bhadrabāhu, who was practising Mahāprāņa penance at Nepāla, knew drsțivāda and agreed to teach it, at the instance of Samgha, to 500 Sādhus, only Sthūlabhadra among whom could stay to the last. But even he, out of 14 pūrvas, which formed part of the last Arga, could learn only 10 pūrvas completely; the last four pūrvas were taught to him verbally, without giving their meanings. With the death of Sthūlabhadra in 215 Vira Nirvāņa Saṁvat (312 B.C.), the knowledge of these last four Pūrvas was lost for ever, because he was debarred from teaching these by Bhadrabāhu. After this, the knowledge of pūrvas was gradually on decay, and the last ācārya, Vajra, who knew 10 pūrvas, died in 584 Vira Samvat (57 A.D.). According to Svetāmbaras, these pūrvas were completely lost in Vira Samvat 1000 (473 A.D.). According to Digambaras, the last Acārya, who knew 10 pūrvas, was Dharmasena, who died in 345 Vira Samvat (182 B.C.), when the knowledge of the pūrvas was completely lost. According to Digambara tradition, after the death of Dharmasena (182 B.C.), five more ācāryas possessed the knowledge of eleyen Argas for 220 years more (i.e. upto 38 A.D.), after which four ācāryas possessed the knowledge of the first Anga, Ācārānga only, for 118 years more (i.e. upto A.D. 156).6 After this period, only a small part of Argas existed, the rest of it being lost for ever. The Svetāmbara tradition, however, does not agree with it. It holds that though the last Anga, Drsțivāda, was lost in 473 A.D., yet the remaining eleven Angas are available to us. It is, however, true that all the Angas handed down to us are not the result of the first council of Pāțali putra. Council of Mathurā (4th Cent. A.D.) : In the time of Skandila Sūri (Vira Samvat 827 to 840 1. Jinadāsaganimahattar, on Avasyaka, Ratlam, 1928, part II. p. 187. 2. Referred to as "Vira Samvat' hereafter. 3. Muni Kalyāņa, Vijaya Vira nirvāṇa samvat aura Jaina kālagananā, Jalore, Vik. Sam. 1987, pp. 98-103. 4. Kapadia, H.R., A History of the Canonical Literature of the Jainas, Surat. 1941, pp. 73-74. 5. Satkhandägama, Vol. I, prastāvanā, p. 26. 6. Kaşayapāhuda, Vol. I, krastāvanā, p. 49. Page #245 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 228 Faina Ethics i.e. 300 A.D. to 313 A.D.)," there was again a famine for 12 years, after which the monks again met at a council in Mathurā under the headship of Skandila Sūri and recollected Agamas into what is known as Kālikasūtra. Some hold that it was not Sūtra literature but Anuyogas which were in a danger of being lost and were therefore taught by Skandila to others.2 Council af Valabhi (4th. Cent. A.D.): Almost at the same time as that of Skandila Süri, Nāgārjuna Sūri held another council at Valabhi. The recensions of canons codified by this council, many times differed from those of the Mathurā recension.3 Council of Valabhi (6th Cent. A.D.): The fourth and the last council was held under the presidentship of Devarddhi Gani K samāśramana in Vira Samvat 980 (553 A.D.) according to the followers of Skandila, in Vira Samvat 993 (466 A.D.) according to the followers of Nāgārjuna. It was at this council that the Agamas assumed their present form. Thus the story of the redaction of Jaina Canons which represent the direct teachings of Mahāvira, is very interesting. To facilitate the comparison of the traditions of Svetāmbaras and Digambaras, we give below a chart of the ācāryas, according to both of them, in their chronological order : Digambara Traditions Svetāmbara Traditione Lord Mahāvīra (527 B.C.)? Lord Mahāvīra (527 B.C.)? 1. Kapadia, H.R., A History of the Canonical Literature of Jainas, p. 61, footnote 4. 2. Nandic urni, p. 8. 3. Muni Kalyāņa Vijaya, Viranitvāņa Samvat aura Jaina kalagananā, pp. 110-111. 4. Kapadia, H.R., A History of the Canonical Literature of the Fainas, p. 63. 5. Cf (i) Trilokaprajñapti, Sholapur, 1943, part I, 4.1476-1491. (ii) Virasena on Satkhandāgama, 1.1.1. (pp. 65-66). (iii) Virasena on Kaşāyapāhuda, 141. (pp. 84-87). (iv) Tattvānušāsanādisaṁgraha, Srutāvatāra (Indranandi), Bombay, Vik. Sam. 1975, verses 72-83 (p. 80). (v) Ibid., Śrutaskandha, pp. 158-159. 6. Cf. (i) Nandis ütra. Sthavirávali, Gāthās, 25-50. (Contd. on the next page) Page #246 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Ethical Literature of the Jainas A. Kevalins Gautama 12 years1 Sudharma 12 B. Sruta kevalins Jambu Vişnu C. Dasapūrvadharas1 38 years 14 در D Ekādaśāngadhāri Nakṣatra Jayapala Pandu Dhruvasena 7. Year of death. "" "" "" Visakhācārya 10 years Prosthila 19 Śrotriya 17 Jayasena 21 Nāgasena 18 Siddhartha 17 Dhrtisena 18 Vijaya 13 Buddhilinga 20 Deva 14 Dharmasena (182 B.C.) Nandimitra 16 Aparajita 22 Govardhana 19 Sambhūtivijaya 8 Bhadrabahu (357 B.C.) Bhadrabahu 29 (365 B.C.)3 Sthulabhadra (312 B.C.)4 "" "3 در د. دو "" در در در "" A. Kevalins دو Sudharma Jambu B. Sruta kevalins2 20 years 44 Prabhava 11 years Sayyambhava 23 Yasobhadra 50 C. Dasapurvadharas Kalaka 38 Skandila Revatimitra 36 Aryamangu 20 Aryadharmā 24 Bhadragupta 39 Śrigupta 15 Vajra 4. They knew only ten purvas. 5. He was the last to know the ten purvas. 6. Those who knew the eleven Angas. Mahagiri 30 years Suhastin 46 Gunasundara 44 41 .. ". در " ور د. "" ور "" "" دو در 229 در (ii) Muni Kalyāņa Vijaya, ViraNirvana Samvat aura Jaina kālaganana, pp. 119-131. (57 A.D.) 5 (A list of all the ācāryas, after Vajra, is not available. The most important of them in their chronological order are given below : 1. Period for which an ācārya remained as the head of the Samgha. 2. They knew all the twelve angas with fourteen purvas. 3. Though he himself knew all the purvas he was not allowed to teach the last four purvas. Cf. supra, p. 227. Page #247 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 230 Kaṁsācārya (38 A.D.) E. Acārāngadhārī1 Subhadra Yasobhadra Yaśabāhu Lohācārya (156 A.D.)2 Aryarakşita (70 A.D.)3 Puspami'ra (70 A.D.) Skandila (300 A.D.313 A.D.)5 Jaina Ethics Nagarjuniya (about 300 A.D.)6 Devardhi Gani Kşamāśra mana (527 A.D.)? The extant Agamas The Agamas, which were lost according to Digambara tradition gradually by 156 A.D., were put into their final shape in 527 A.D. according to Svetambara tradition. Without going into the sectarian question of the authenticity of these Agamas, we may point out that almost all scholars agree on four points about the extant Agamas: (i) These Agamas do contain, directly and indirectly, some of the teachings of Mahāvīra. (ii) There were certain changes in, and additions to, these Agamas as they were remodelled in the four councils. (iii) Though they took their final shape as late as 527 A.D., yet many of them can be easily ascribed to a period much earlier than that, as early as 3rd cent. B.C. 5. Head of Mathura Council. 6. Head of the first Valabhi Council. (iv) All the Agamas are not the work of ganadharas. For example, Daśavaikālika, is ascribed to Aryasyama; the I. Those who knew the Acaranga only. 2. The Digambaras hold that after him the knowledge of Angas was completely lost. They disown the Angas codified at Valabhi by Devardhi Gani Kşama śramana. 3. He knew nine purvas completely and 24 yavikās of the 10th purva. 4. He was taught the first nine purvas by Aryarakşita but could not remember all of them. 7. Head of the second Valabhi Council. 8. Wintenritz, M., A History of Indian Literature, Calcutta, 1933, Vol. II, P. 434. 9. Max Müller (ed.), SBE, Vol. XXII, Introduction, Oxford, 1884. p. XLIII. Page #248 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Ethical Literature of the Jainas 231 Pindaniryukti and Oghaniryukti to Bhadrabāhu; the third Mülasūtra to Sayyambhava; and the Nandi to Devardhi.1 It is needless to go, here, into such questions of detail, as to whether the number of Agamas is 32 or 45 or 48.2 The extant Agamas include 11 Angas, 12 Upāngas, 10 Prakirņas, 6 Chedas ütras, 1 Nandis ütra, 1 Anuyogadvāra and 4 Mülas ūtra. In this extant literature, apart from the āvasyaka formulae, the most ancient style presents itself in the Acārārga, Sutrakņtārga, the Uttarādhyayana, the old Chedas ūtras, the Rşibhāṣita and in portions of the Daśavaikālika.3 Fortunately for us, these most ancient portions of the Āgamas are those which deal with Jaina ethics primarily. In fact, it is but natural that the Jaina monks, with utmost devotion to conduct, preserved that portion of Agamas with greatest care which dealt with conduct. With these general remarks about the chronology and position of Āgamas, we proceed to present a brief survey of the individual works of Jaina canonical literature, keeping in view their importance as a source-book of Jaina ethics. (i) Ācārāngas ūtra : Acārārga is the first and the most important Agama. It contains pithy sentences which directly touch the soul and appear to be the instruction of Lord Mahāvīra himself. It is the earliest authoritative source-book for Jaina ethics. It's first Srutaskandha, containing nine adhyayanas of which only eight are available at present, is earlier than the 2nd śrutaskandha containing three cūlikās. Silārka in his commentary takes the last but one verse of the first śruta skandha to be the mangala at the end, which shows that he also considered second śrutaskandha to be a later addition. The 2nd śrutaskandha was added to the original Acārānga before Bhadrabāhu wrote his Niryuktion 1. Winternitz, M., A History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, p. 433. 2. Datavaikālika, Calcutta, Vik. Sam. 2020, bhūmikā, pp. 9-12. Schubring, W., The Doctrines of the Fainas, Delhi, 1962, p. 82. Max Müller, (ed) SBE, Vol. XXII, Introduction, p. XLVII. 5. Max Müller, (ed.) SBE, Vol. XXII, Introduction, p. XLVII, Page #249 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 232 Jaina Ethics Acārānga.1 Some hold that the first adhyayana of the first śrutaskandha is the oldest of all.2 As regards the date of Acārānga, Jacobi has placed it in the first part of the 3rd century B.C.3 Among the commentaries of Acārānga may be mentioned Niryukti by Bhadrabahu in about 367 gāthās, Tikā by Silänka (876 A.D.) and Dipika by Jinahamsa. Velankar has mentioned as many as thirteen commentaries.4 (ii) Sūtrakṛtānga: Sutrakṛtānga, the second Anga, is later than Acārānga.5 It has two śrutaskandhas. Jacobi and Winternitz' agree in assigning the second śrutaskandha to a later period. Niryukti by Bhadrabahu is the oldest commentary on Sūtrakṛtänga followed by Silānka's (876 A.D.) commentary on it. Then comes the Dipikā of Harṣapāla (1517 A.D.). Besides Niryukti and Curni, Velankar mentions seven more commentaries. As the purpose of Šūtrakṛtānga according to Samavāyānga, is 'to fortify young monks against the hererical opinions of alien teacher," it is but natural that it must contain, in the main, refutation of heretical sects. Amongst these heretical sects,10 the sects of Purāņa Kasyapa and Makkhali Gosāla are of special ethical interest. (iii) Sthānanga: Sthānānga is divided into ten sthānas. This anga contains 783 sütras. In the ten sthānas, each sthāna gives the name of such objects as can be divided into the same number of classes. The first sthana, for example, enumerates such objects 1. Kapadia, H.R., A History of the Canonical Literature of the Jainas, P. 112. 2. Ibid., p. 114. 3. Max Müller, (ed.) SBE, Vol. XXII, Introduction. p. 43. 4. Velankar, H.D., (ed.), Jinaratnakośa, Poona, 1944, P. 23-24. 5. Max Müller (ed.), Vol. XLV, Introduction, p, XXXVIII. 6. Ibid., p. XXXIV. 7. Winternitz, M., A History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, p. 438. 8. Velankar, H.D., (ed.), Jinaratnakośa, p. 450-51. 9. Max Müller (ed.), SBE. Vol. XLV, Introduction, p. 38. 10. Cf. Sen, Amulyacandra, Schools and Sects, in Jaina Literature, Calcutta, 1931. Also Vide supra. pp. 17-18. Page #250 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Ethical Literature of the Jainas 233 as have one class, and the tenth the objects which have ten classes. Thus, attempts have been made to cover the whole Jaina philosophy under divisions and subdivisions of objects. This anga contains many important facts about things which are not religious. It says, for example, that there are three types of trees, four types of Alarkāras, five types of livelihood, six types of Arya families, seven types of Gotras, eight types of Ayurveda and so on. Abhayadeva's (1063 A.D.) Vrtti is the most important commentary on this anga. Velankar mentions six more commentaries on Sthānānga Sūtra.1 (iv) Samavāyānga : Samavāyānga contains 275 sūtras. This anga is a continuation of the third anga, giving the objects having one to sāgropamakotākoți varieties. This anga is important in giving us the contents of the twelfth anga, drşivāda and fourteen pūrvas which are lost to us. This anga is also important as a source of ancient Indian culture as it contains much material about secular subjects from 246 sūtra to 275 sūtra. Like Sthānānga, this sūtra also helps us in giving the varieties of various moral qualities. Abhayadeva (1063 A.D.) wrote a Vịtti on this sūtra. Velankar mentions two more commentaries on it.2 (v) Vyākhyāprajñapti :: It contains mostly dialogues between Mahāvīra and Gautama, his principle disciple. W. Schubring has pointed out that sections 1 to 20 form the germ of the whole whereas sections 24 and 30 as such and 21 to 23, 26 to 29, 31 and 32, 33 and 34, 35 to 40 form groups of uniform contents.3 Abhayadeva wrote a Vịtti (1071 A.D.) on this Anga. Velankar mentions ten commentaries more on this Anga. 4 1. Velankar, H.D., (ed.), Jinaratnakośa, pp. 454-455. 2. Ibid., p. 420. 3. Schubring, W., The Doctrines of the Jainas, p. 88. 4. Velankar, H.D. (ed.), Jinaratnakośa, p. 290-291. Page #251 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 234 (vi) Jñātādharmakathā : Divided into two śrutakhandas, this Anga gives us stories with a moral purpose behind them. The 8th Adhyayana of the Jñatadharmakatha carries a special significance in describing the 19th Tirthankara as a female. Obviously this goes against Digambara tradition which holds the 19th Tirthankara to be a male and does not accept the possibility of a woman getting liberation. (vii) Upāsakadhyayana : This Anga is supplementary to Acārānga from the point of view of Jaina ethics. The former deals with the conduct of an ascetic whereas the latter deals with the conduct of a house-holder by relating ten stories of righteous house-holders. This work is important ethically as it gives us details about right attitude, and the twelve vows of a householder together with their transgressions. Besides commentary of Abhayadeva (1060 A.D.), Velankar mentions five commentaries more.1 Jaina Ethics (viii) Antakṛtadaśānga : It has eight vargas containing 10, 8, 13, 10, 10, 16, 13 and 10 adhyayanas respectively. It gives the stories of those who attained liberation. This anga gives us Jaina version of the story of Kṛṣṇa. Almost in all stories, we find many descriptions of long penances. We find an interesting account of ten types of penances whose explanation involves mathematical arrangement of numbers, of meals and fast days, in different permutations and combinations. Abhayadeva wrote a Vrtti on this anga also. There seems to be no other commentary on this work. (ix) Anuttara Upapātikadaśā : This anga gives the story of those who have gone to heaven, known as Anuttara Vimāna, from where they will have to assume human body for one time only before attaining liberation. This anga is divided into three vargas, each varga having 10, 13 and 10, adhyayanas respectively. In this anga 1. Velankar, H.D. (ed.), Jinaratnakośa, p. 55-56. Page #252 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Ethical Literature of the Jainas 235 also, we find that full stories are not given. In the first adhyayana of the 3rd varga graphic descriptions of the penances of dhanya have been given. (x) Praśna-Vyākaraṇa : It is divided into two śrutakhandas. Each śrutakhanda has five adhyayanas. The first śrutakhanda deals with āšrava and the second with samvara. These two tattvas, aśrava and samvara, which deal with the inflow of karmans and their stoppage respectively are very important for understanding the moral teachings of Jainism. Besides the țikā by Abhayadeva, Velankar mentions seven more commentaries on this Arga. (xi) Vipākas ātra : The two śrutaskandhas, each having ten adhyayanas, of this Anga give the pleasant and unpleasant consequences of our actions respectively. The first frutaskandha thus brings out the immorality of tyrannising, flesh-eating, egg-selling, sexual indulgence and human sacrifices, etc. The second frutaskandha, on the other hand, praises such qualities as giving of alms. Besides Vrtti of Abhayadeva, Velankar mentions one more commentary on this work.2 (xii) Dršțivāda : As already mentioned, this Anga, together with 14 pūrvas, which formed its part, was lost in 1000 Vira Samvat. Nandis ūtra says that it has five divisions—Parikarma, Sūtra, Pūrvāgata, Anuyoga and Cülikās—dealing with mathematics, Nayas, pūrvas, life-stories of great persons, and mantra vidyā, respectively. The Upāngas The Upārgas, occupy a seco..dary position as compared to the above-mentioned Angas. Some of these Upāngas are works of little ethical interest. Süryaprajñapti and Chandra 1. Velankar, H.D. (ed.), Jinaratnakośa, p. 274-275. 2. Ibid., p. 357. 3. Jain, J.G., Prākrta sāhitya kā itihāsa, Varanasi, 1961, p. 102. Page #253 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 236 Jaina Ethics prajñapti, for example, are works of astronomy. Jambudvipaprajnepti deals with Jaina cosmology. Nevertheless these Upangas sometimes furnish us with ethical material. Aupapātika, for example, gives us stories which elaborate and illustrate the doctrine of karman. Rajapraśniya deals with materialism as against spiritualism; Jivabhigama with categories of jivas. Rest of the Upangas contain many mythological stories. The Chedas ütras : Literally the word 'cheda' means 'cut'. It refers to 'cut' in the period of dikṣā as a sort of punishment to a monk. As a result, he has to pay respects to his juniors. The Chedas utras, six in number, are valuable for the study of Jaina ethics, for though many of them belong to a fairly later age, they deal, in detail, with the rules of conduct of a monk, specially with expiation (prayaścittas) for various violations of moral rules. Besides, these Chedasūtras are important to know the organisȧtion of Jaina monasticism. (i) Nisitha : The word 'Nisitha' means 'night'. The word is perhaps allegorically applied to denote punishment which was treated as secret and not announced in the assembly. It contains 20 uddesas. It is considered to be the second cula of Acārānga. It is also known as Acarakalpa. It gives atonements and penances to be prescribed by the acarya for transgressions of a moral rule by the monks. It is important to know the daily routine of a monk's life. (ii) Mahāniśitha : The original Mahāniśitha is said to be lost; it was restored by Haribhadra Suri. It also deals, together with other sundry matters, with consequences of evil deeds, atonement and confession. (iii) Vyavahāra : Consisting of ten uddeśakas, it is said to have been composed by Bhadrabahu. It gives the rules for ācārya and upadhyaya in detail. It also gives the syllabus for the study of Agamas for a monk. Page #254 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Ethical Literature of the Fainas 237 (iv) Dašaśrutaskandha: It is also said to be composed by Bhadrabāhu, and known by the name of Acāradašā. It has ten adhyayanas and deals with the hindrances in the moral life of a monk. It gives eleven pratimās, the stages of spiritual practices for a householder. The kalpasūtras, forming its 8th section, deal with the life-story of Mahāvīra. (v) Kalpa : Composed by Bhadrabāhu and consisting of six uddešakas, it seems to be a fairly old account of the conduct of a Jaina monk. It deals specially with the regulations regarding food, begging, and mutual co-operation of Jaina monks. It is termed as Brhatkalpasūtra, as distinguished from Kalpasūtras, forming part of the original Dašaśrutaskandha. (vi) Pañcakalpa: The Pañcakalpa Sūtra having been lost, Jitakalpa Sūtra of Jinabhadra gaại kşamāśramana is taken to be the sixth chedasūtra. It deals with the ten traditional prāyaścittas. The Mūlas ūtras The Mülasūtras, four in number, are important to know the fundamentals of Faina ethics. They specially deal with asceticism (i) Uttarādhyayana : Consisting of 36 adhyayanas, it is a sūtra of multiple authorship. Leaving aside the 29th adhyayana and the beginning portions of the 2nd and 16th adhyayanas, the rest of the work is written in verses. Winternitz compares it with Dhammapada, and Suttanipäta. He has rightly called it 'one of the most valuable portions of the canon.'2 Besides the moral teachings which stories like that of Hari Kesin bear, it enunciates such ethical principles as that of forbearance, voluntary death. celibacy, vigilance and penance. It also contains spiritual explanation of sacrifices 1. Winternitz, M., A History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, p. 467. 2. Ibid., p. 466. Page #255 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 238 Jaina Ethics and teaches us that caste is based on actions and not on birth. (ii) Daśavaikälika : The work, a composition of Sayyambhava (429 B.C.), consists of ten adhyayanas and two cūlikās, all of them dealing with the conduct of a monk in a poetical way. The importance of Daśavaikālika can be well imagined from the fact that, after its composition, it took the place of Acārānga in the curriculum of study for monks.1 Its fourth, fifth and seventh Adhyayanas are believed to have been taken from Ātmapravāda, Karmapravāda and Satyapravāda, respectively; the rest of the Adhyayanas have been derived from Pratyākhyānap ürva.2 (iii) Avaśyaka : This deals with the six essential duties of a monk which should be daily performed by him. There is a huge exegetical literature on this Mülasūtra; including Niryukti, Višeşāvašyakabhāsya by Jinabhadra, and ţikās by Haribhadra and Malayagiri. Sisyahitā by Hemacandra Maladhār in is a commentary upon Višeșāvaśyakabhāsya. (iv) Aughaniryukti or Pindaniryukti: There is difference of opinion about the fourth Mülasūtra. Some take both Aughaniryukti and Pindaniryukti to be the fourth Mülas ūtra whereas others accept either of the two as the Mülasūtra. Piņdaniryukti deals specially with the rules regarding begging of food by a Jaina monk. Ten Prakirņakas: There is no uniformity regarding the list of these Prakirņakas. The list of 84 Āgamas includes as many as 30 Prakirņakas. The following ten, however, are mostly included in the traditional list of Prakirņakas : 1. Daśavaikālika, Bh ūmikā, p. 16. 2. Bhadrabāhu on Daśavaikālika, 16-17. Page #256 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Ethical Literature of the Jainas 1. Catuḥsarana, 2. Āturapratyākhyāna, 3. Mahāpratyākhyāna, 4. Bhaktaparijña, 5. Tandulavaicārika, 6. Samstaraka, 7. Gaccha cara, 8. Ganividya, 9. Devendrastava, 10. Marana samadhi.1 These Prakirṇakas contain, respectively, 63, 70, 142, 172, 586, 123, 137, 82, 307 and 663 Gāthās. The first and ninth of these Prakirņakas are attributed to Virabhadra. The first of these Prakirṇakas deal mainly with devotion, Arhanta, Siddha and Sadhus; the second with voluntary death; the third with vow; the fourth again with voluntary death; the fifth with brahmacarya; the sixth with process of voluntary death; the seventh with rules regarding the behaviour of monks and nuns; the eighth with astrology; the ninth with the praises of 24 tirthankaras; the tenth with twelve anuprekṣās and voluntary death. 239 Cülikās ātras: The word 'culikā' means 'appendix'. The two culikāsutras, Nandi and Anuyogadvāra, are the latest parts of the Agamas. Nandi is the work of Deva Vācaka (3rd cent. A.D.). It gives a long list of Sthaviras and classification of Agamas. Anuyogadvara is the work of Arya Rakṣita (5th cent. A.D.) which deals with many secular matters like grammar and politics together with moral material of little originality. Exegetical literature on Agamas We have noted above a view of the important commentaries on the eleven Angas. There are many commentaries on the Angabahya canonical literature, also. Many of these commentaries are no less important than the original as belonging to pre-Christian era. The Samskṛta commentaries are our main help in understanding the original sutras in Ardhamāgadhi. Some of the main commentaries and their authors may be mentioned here : 1. Jaina, J.C., Prākṛṭa sahitya ka itihāsa, p. 123. 2. Kapadia, H.R., A History of the Canonical Literature of the Jainas, p. 165. 3. Ibid., p. 165 Page #257 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 240 1. Niryukti : The Niryuktis are ascribed to Bhadrabahu, who seems to be a different person from the author of the Chedasutras and died in 297 B.C. Leumann holds that the present Niryuktis were composed in about 90 A D.1 At present we have Niryuktis on Acārānga, Sutrakṛtānga, Vyavahāra, Kalpa, Daśaśrutaskandha, Uttaradhyayana, Avaśyaka, and Datavaikālika. We have already referred to Pindaniryukti and Aughaniryukti, which are considered to be Mülas utras. Jaina Ethics 2. Bhāṣya: Like Niryuktis, these Bhasyas are also written in Prākṛta verses. Many times it has led to the intermingling of the two. Bhasya on Kalpa, Vyavahara and Niśitha are attributed to Sanghadāsa Gani and Viseṣāvasyakabhāṣya to Jinabhadra. There are Bhasyas on Pañcakalpa, Jitakalpa, Uttaradhyayana, and Dasavaikālika also. 3. Cūrņi: The Curnis, written partly in Samskṛta and partly in Prākṛta, are the forerunners of the Samskṛta Tikās. Kapadia informs us that the Curnis are available on Acārānga, Sutrakṛtānga, Vyakhyāprajñapti, Kalpa, Vyavahara, Nisitha, Pañcakalpa, Dasasruta, Jitakalpa, Jivābhigama, Jambudvipaprajñapti, Uttaradhyayana, Avasyaka, Daśavaikālika, Nandi and Anuyogadvāra.2 These Curnis also help us in interpreting the Jaina Agamas. These are mostly ascribed to Jinadasagani Mahattara. Leumann ascribes Avasyaka Curņi to 600-650 A.D.3 4. Tikā:4 Beginning from Haribhadra Suri (705-775 A.D.), who wrote Samskṛta Tikās on Avasyaka, Daśavaikālika, Nandi and Anuyoga, there was a chain of Samskṛta commentators. Šilänka Suri (862 or 872 A.D.) is said to have written commentaries on all the Angas, but only the first two are available to us. 1, Schubring, W., The Doctrine of the Jainas, p. 84. 2. Kapadia, H.R., A History of Indian Literature of the Jainas, p. 190. 3. Schubring, W., The Doctrine of the Jainas. p. 85. 4. Jaina, J.C., Life in Ancient India, Bombay, 1947, p. 42. Page #258 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Ethical Literature of the Jainas Säntisuri (11th cent. A.D.) wrote a commentary on Uttaradhyayana in Samskṛta. Nemicandra Suri (11th. A.D.) also wrote a commentary on Uttaradhyayana. Abhaya Deva Suri (11th cent. A.D.) wrote commentaries on the last nine Angas. Malayagiri wrote commentaries on six Upangas from second to seventh, and also on Vyavahara Bhasya, Pinda Niryukti, Avasyaka, Bṛhatkalpa Bhasya and Nandi. The last mentioned work was completed in 1235 A.D. 241 Besides, we may mention, Vijaya Vimala (1578 A.D.), Santi Candra (1594 A.D.) and Samaya Sundaragani (17th cent. A.D.) as some of the commentators on Agamas. Non-Canonical literature of the Svetambaras Besides the canonical literature, there is a vast literature of Svetambara sect covering every branch of knowledge. Herebelow we survey the most important works on Jaina morality in Prākṛta and Samskṛta. 1. Śrāvakaprajñapti and Tattvarthasūtra of Umāsvāti: The history of non-canonical literature of Svetambaras begins with Umāsvāti, to whom the authorship of Tattvarthasutra and Sravakaprjñapti is attributed. The former of these, as quite convincingly proved by R. Williams, seems to belong to the Digambara tradition from the point of view of its contents,1 and shall be dealt with under Digambara literature. Sravakaprajñapti, on the other hand, is certainly a Svetāmbara text. R. Williams thinks that it must be attributed to some author other than that of Tattvarthasutra.2 Though Abhayadeva, in his commentary on Pañcāsaka, refers to a Sravakaprajñapti of Umäsvāti,3 and Yasovijaya and Municandra Suri also refer to a Sravakaprajñapti of Umāsvāti, yet Abhayadeva himself refers to the second gāthā of the present Srävakaprajñapti as that of Haribhadra. Dr. Hiralala Jaina, 1. Williams, R., Jaina Yoga, London, 1963, p. 2. 2. Ibid., p. 3. 3. aranfaska &fugarealfaarada enaquaat | ant factoffga: 11 f: Quoted from Jaina, H.L., Bharatiya Sanskrti mem Jainadharma kā yogadāna, p. 110. Page #259 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 242 Jaina Ethics therefore, ascribes this work to Haribhadra (8th cent. A.D.). Velankar also informs that one of the manuscripts of the private library of Sri Hamsavijayaji Mahārāja ascribes it to Haribhadra. R. Williams, however, ascribes this work to Umāsvāti, who must be a different ācārya from the author of Tattvärthasūtra, and must have lived not later than the fifth century A.D.2 Consisting of 400 verses, it gives us the nature of samyaktva and vratas with their aticāras. Haribhadra Suri and his works: Haribhadra Suri is a versatile writer. He is said to have composed 1444 works. He tried to Brahmanise Jainism. He gave us a concept of Jaina society. To him are ascribed Pañcavastuka and Samyaktvasaptati, which deal with the conduct of a monk, and Śrāvakadharmavidhi and Pañcāŝikā prakaraṇa, dealing with the conduct of a householder. Pañcavastuka, consisting of 1714 gāthās is a comprehensive work dealing with the (1) Initiation into monkhood (2) Daily routine of a monk (3) Conduct of gaccha (4) Anujñā and sallekhana (i.e. voluntary death). The Samyaktvasaptati deals with samyaktva by giving examples of various saints. Śravakadharmavidhi, consisting of 120 gāthās, deals with the life and conduct of a householder. Some idea as to the contents of Pañcāsikās can be had from their titles given below : (1) Sravakadharma (2) Dikṣāvidhāna (3) Vandanavidhi (4) Pūjāvidhi (5) Pratyakhyānavidhi (6) Stavavidhi (7) Jinabhavanakaraṇavidhi (8) Pratiṣṭāvidhi (9) Yātrāvidhi (10) Upāsakaprati māvidhi, (11) Sadhudharma (12) Samācāri (13) Pindavidhi (14) Šīlāngavidhi (15) Alocanavidhi (16) Prayaścitta (17) Sthitästhitavidhi (18) Sadhupratimă and (19) Tapovidhi. R. Williams attributes the Pañcasikas to an earlier Haribhadra, whom he calls Haribhadra Virahānka, and places him in 529 A.D,3 whereas the rest of the works he ascribes to 1. Velankar, H.D. (ed), Jinaratnakośa, p. 393. 2. Williams, R., Jaina Yoga, p. 4. 3. Ibid., p. 5. Page #260 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Ethical Literature of the Jainas 243 Haribhadra Yākiniputra, whom he places, following Muni Jinavijaya, in 750 A.D.2 Siddhasena Gari and his commentary on Tattvārthas ātra After the Svopajñabhāşya of Umāsvāti, the most authoritative Svetāmbara commentary on Tattvārthas ātra is that of Siddhasena Gaņi, who gives us much information on the aticāras of vratas. R. Williams places him in the 8th century A.D.2 Devagupta He wrote Nava-pada-prakarana in which he tried to explain each vrata from nine points of views. He is also said to have written Nava-tattva-prakarana. He composed his first work in 1016 A.D.3 Sānti Sūri He is the author of Dharma-ratna-prakarana, consisting of 181 gāthās. It deals with the conduct of a householder and monk. Sānti Sūri died in about 1040 A.D.4 Deva Sūri He was the disciple of Viracandra Sūri and wrote his work Jivānušāsana in 1105 A.D.5 This work deals with the conduct of a Jaina monk. It consists of 323 Gāthās. Nemicandra and his Pravacanasāroddhāra Nemicandra wrote Pravacanasāroddhāra, which is an encyclopaedia of Jaina religion and philosophy. It deals almost with all topics of the code of conduct of a Jaina monk, in about 1600 gāthās. R. Williams says that Nemicandra is not later than the 1. Williams, R. Jaina Yoga, p. 6. For a summary of the views about the date of Haribhadra Cf. Winternitz, M., A History of Indian Lite rature. Vol. II, p. 479, f.n.l. 2. Williams, R., Jaina Yoga, p. 7. 3. Winternitz, M., A History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, p. 588. 4. Ibid., p. 486. 5. Jaina, H.L., Bharatiya Sanskyti mem Jainadharma kā yogadāna, p. 107, Page #261 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 244 Jaina Ethics 12th century A.D.1 Siddhasena Sūri wrote a SaṁskȚta commentary, Tattvajñānavikāsini, on it in Vik. Saṁvat 1242.2 Hemacandra and his Yogaśāstra The knowledge of Hemacandra is so comprehensive that he is styled as Kali-kāla sarvajña. He contributed to almost all : branches of knowledge of his time. Yogaśāstra or Adhyātmopanişad is the great monumental work ; of Hemacandra on the conduct of a householder and a monk. It consists of about 1000 verses with a Svopajña commentary, which is much more informative than the original. Hemacandra has vast knowledge of Brāhmaṇism also. The special interest of this work lies in the detailed description of meditation and its attributes, āsana, prāņāyāma, pratyāhāra and dhāraņā. These descriptions are very much influenced by the Jñānārnava of Subhacandra though some of the scholars seem to believe just the reverse. The personality of Hemacandra assumes a special interest in view of the part he played in the political set-up of Gujarāta through his patron, Kumārapāla. He lived between 1089 and 1172 A.D. He completed his Yogaśāstra in about 1160 A.D. Taśovijaya After Hemacandra, many minor works of authors like Devendra, Dharmaghoșa, and Ratnasekhara supply material regarding faina ethics. But the last and the most important of these authors is Yašovijaya, who lived from 1624 to 1688,8 and whose commentary on Dharmasaņgraha is the last authoratative work on Jaina ethics. Literature of Digambaras Canonical literature 1. Kasāyaprābhṛta of Gunadhara : In tenth century A.D., Indranandi in his Śrutāvatāra has 1. Williams, R., Jaina Yoga, p. 1o. 2. Velankar, H.D., (ed.). Jinaratnakośa, p. 271. 3. Winternitz, M., A History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, p. 593. Page #262 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Ethical liturature of the Jainas 243 said that there is no ascetic to give the lineage of Gunadhara. He also tells us that Arhadbali, whose time according to Prākrta Pattāvalis,a is 152 B.C. (565 Vira Nirvāna Samvat), gave the name of Guņadhara Samgha to one of the Samghas of Jaina ascetics.3 Parmānanda Sāstri has compared many passages of Kaşāyaprābhrta with those of Șațkhandāgama to prove that the former was composed before the latter and was the first of all scriptures of Digambara tradition. He has assigned this work to the 2nd century B.C. Dr. Nemi Candra ascribes it to 1st century A.D.5 Kaşāyaprābhịta contains 233 gāthā-sūtras which are very precise and are classified under fifteen adhikāras. This book is also known as 'Pejjadosapāhuda', after the name of the third sub-chapter of the tenth chapter of the fifth pūrva, jñānapravāda 'Pejjadosa' means attachment and aversion, which are dealt with in this book with reference to their importance in the Jaina doctrine of karman. Indranandi tells us that Aryamaṁkşu and Nāgahasti wrote commentaries on Kasāyapāhuda. Another commentary available on Kasāyapāhuda is that of Yativrşabha,? who is placed in the 6th century A.D. by J.C. Jaina. Ācārya Virasena wrote a big and comprehensive commentary, Jayadhavalā, on the original Kasāyapāhuda and Cūrņi Sūtra of Yativrsabha, which was completed by Jinasena, the teacher of Amoghavarşa, a king of Rāstrakūta in the year 759 of Saka era in Vațagrāmapura.' 2. Satkhandāgama and Mahābandha of Puspadanta and Bhūtabali Puspadanta and Bhūtabali were taught the scriptures by Dharasenācārya. Srutāvatāra of Indranandi mentions Arhad 1. Tattvānušásanādisangraha, Śrutāvatāra (Indranandi), 151. 2. Satkhandāgama, Vol. I, Prastāvanā, p. 26. 3. Tattvānušāsanādisangraha, Srutāvatāra (Indranandi), 94. 4. "Anekānta”, Vira Sevā Mandira, Delhi, year 14, Kirana 1,(August, 1956), pp. 8-10. 5. Šāstri, Nemicandra, Prākrtabhāşā aura sähitya kā älocanālmaka itihāsa, Varanasi, 1966, p. 213. 6. Tattvänušāsanādisangraha, Srutavatāra (Indranandi), 154. 7. Ibid., 155. 8. Jaina, J.C., Prāksta sähitya kā itihāsa, p. 291. 9. Kasāyaprabhsta, prastāvanā, p. 72. Page #263 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 246 Faina Ethics bali, Māghanandi and Dharasena, one after another, without showing their relation to each other. Prākyta Pațļāvali, however, mentions them as successors of each other. We have already referred to the time of Arhadbali as 152 B.C. If we subtract from it the time of Arhadbali, Mäghanandi and Dharasena, which is 28, 21 and 19 years respectively, the time of Puspadanta comes to 84 B.C.; and if we further subtract 30 years of Puspadanta, the time of Bhūtabali comes to 54 B.C.2 Dr. Nemicandra ascribes it to the first century of Saka era.3 The sixth khanda of ațkhan S'dāgama is composed by Bhūtabali alone and is termed as Mahābandha and is not commented upon. Satkhandāgama gives us details about fourteen guņas thānas, which are quite important from ethical point of view. Virasena wrote a commentary on the first four khandas of Satakhandāgama also, which is called Dhavalā. According to the Prasasti, this commentary was completed in 816 A.D.4 Virasena has quoted not only Digambara books but also svetāmbara Agamas like Acārānga. Brhatkalpas ütra, Daśavaikälikasūtra, Sthänāngațikā, Anuyogadvāra and Avaśyakaniryukti,5 This is a proof of his nonapproach. Virasena refers to the opinion sectarian of Nägahasti as following the tradition of the ancient ācāryas. Besides Dhavalā, commentaries by Kundakunda, Sāmakunda, Tumbulārācārya, Samantabhadra and Bappadevaguru are also referred to by Indranandis, and they have been assigned to 2nd 3rd, 4th, 5th and 6th century, respectively.? None of these commentaries is available today. Pro-canonical literature of Digambaras 1. Kundakundācārya One of the most important and earliest Digambara I. Tattvänušāsanādisangraha, Srutavatāra (Indranandi), 102-104. 2. Satkhandägama, prastāvanā, p. 26-27. 3. Sástri, Nemicandra, Präkstabhāṣā aura sähitya kā ālocanālmaka itihāsa, p. 212. 4. Satkhandāgama, Introduction, p. ii. 5. Ibid., Introduction, p. ji. 6. Tattvánuśāsanādisangraha, Srutāvatāra (Indranandi), 160-173. 7. Jaina, J.C., Prákyla sahitya kā itihāsa, p. 275. Page #264 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Ethical Literature of the Jainas 247 authors is Kundakundācārya. Pravacansāra, Samayasāra, Pañcāstikāya, Niyamasāra and Dvādaśānuprekşā are undisputedly his works. Besides, tradition ascribes to him 84 Pähudas and Prākrta Bhaktis. We have noted that Indranandi has ascribed a commentary on Satkhandāgama to Padmanandi of Kundakundapura, who is identified with Kundakundācārya. Vibudha Sridhara, however, ascribes this commentary to Kundakirti, a disciple of Kundakundācārya. This commentary is not available: and, therefore, nothing definite can be said about it. Another important book, the authorship of which is ascribed to Kundakunda, is Mülācāra with which we shall deal separately. As for the 84 Pāhudas, only eight of them are available to us and six of them have been commented upon by Srutasāgara. Tradition ascribes these Pāhudas to Kundakundācārya. Ratnasāra is another book of doubtful authorship, ascribed to Kundakunda. Ten Prākrta bhaktis are ascribed to Kundakunda by Prabhācandra in his commentary on Kriyākalāpa. Dr. A.N. Upadhye is of the view that part of these Bhaktis, containing traditional prayers, might have been written by Kundakunda. As for Dvādaśānupreksā, it is quoted by Pūjyapāda in his commentary Sarvārthasiddhi in the 6th century A.D. and according to Dr. A.N. Upadhye there is an appearance of antiquity about the text.? . As for the date of Kundakunda, the fact that Kundakundānvaya is referred to in a copper plate inscription of Merkara, dated 466 A.D., 3 helps us to fix the lower limit of his time. This inscription also gives the names of six disciples of Kundakunda lineage in succession. If we roughly allow hundred years for these six disciples, and keep in the mind that it takes some time to start the lineage of an ācārya after his death, we can fix the date of Kundakunda in the middle of 3rd century A.D. This is also corroborated by the tradition, which ascribes to him a commentary on Sațakhandāgama, which we have already placed in the 2nd century A.D. Winternitz tells us that 1. Siddhāntasarādisangraha, Śrutāvatāra (Vibudhasridhara), Bombay. Vik. Sam. 1979, p. 318. 2. Pravacanasara, Bombay, 1935, Introduction, p. XL. 3. Rice Lewis, (ed.), Coorg Inscriptions, Bangalore, 1886, p. 3. (line 15). Jais Education International Page #265 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 248 faina Ethics according to geneologies of the Digambaras, he lived in 1st century A.D.1 Amstacandrācārya and Jayasena are the two most important commentators on Prābhrtatraya i.e. Samayasāra, Pravacanasāra and Pañcāstikaya, Amrtacandr ācārya also wrote Samayasārakalaša, which is a part of his commentary on Samayasāra in the form of beautiful Saṁskṛta verses. His commentaries on Pañcāstikāya, Pravacanasāra and Samayasāra are called the Tattvapradipikāvrtti, the Tattavadipika and the Atmakhyāti, respectively. He is placed in the 10th century A.D.2 whereas Jayasena is placed in the 12th century A.D. by Dr. Upadhye:3 An early commentator on Niyamasāra, who quotes profusely from Amrtacandra, is Padmaprabhamaladhāri (1000 A.D.). Srutasāgara, who wrote commentaries on six out of eight available Pāhudas, is placed in the 15th century A.D. by Winternitz.5 2. Mūlācāra Consisting of 1248 gāthās, it is the earliest work on the conduct of a Faina monk from Digambara point of view. It gives 28 Mūlagunas of the Jaina monk. It is ascribed to Vațțakera or Vațțakeri? by its commentator Vasunandi (11th century A.D.).8 The Puspikā of Vasunandi's commentary mentions Kundakunda as the author of Mūlācāra. This has led to a great controversy about authorship of Mülācāra. Shri Premi thinks that Vattakeri should not be identified with Kundakunda because he is more influenced by Svetāmbara traditions.10 In the absence of any decisive evidence regarding the 1. Winternitz, M., A History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, p. 476. 2. Pravacanasāra, Introduction, p. CI. 3. Ibid., p. CVI. 4. Jaina, J.C., Prākrta sahitya kā itihāsa, p. 300. 5. Winternitz., M., A History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, p. 592. 6. Vasunandi on Mülācāra, Bombay, Vik. Sam. 1977, Part I, p. 2. 7. Ibid., Bombay, Vik. Sam. 1980, Part II, p. 324. 8. Vasunandiśravakācāra, Kāśi, 1952, prastāvanā, p. 18. 9. Vasunandi on Mülācāra, Part II, p. 324. 10. Premi, Nathurāma, Jaina sāhitya aura itihäsa, (Second ed.), Bombay, 1956, pp. 550-553. Page #266 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 249 Ethical Literature of the Jainas authorship of Mūlācāra, and following Dr A.N. Upadhye and Mukhtar, we assign it to Kundakunda whose date we have already discussed. Vasunandi, mentioned above, tells us that Mūlācāra is a summary of Acārānga.1 3. Bhagvati-Aradhanā This is an old book on the conduct of Jaina monk attributed to Sivakoti, who has been referred to by Jinsena in his Adipurāṇa. It is difficult to identify Sivakoti. One Sivabhuti is mentioned in the Kalpasūtra; and the Avasyakamulabhasya refers to a Sivabhuti who established Bodika (Digambara) Samgha in 609 Vira Samvat.3 Aradhana Katha Koşa and Rājā Vali Kathe speak of a Sivakoti who is disciple of Samantabhadra.^ Pujyapada in his commentary on Tattvarthas utra quotes 562nd gatha of Bhagavati Aradhana. The author of Bhagavati Ārādhanā should be distinguished from a Śivakoți who wrote a commentary on Tattvarthasutra and is mentioned in the 105th inscription of Sravanabelagola of 1455 Vikrama era. Similarly, he should be distinguished from the author of the same name of Ratnamālā. Premi has shown that he has some inclination towards Svetambara sect and belongs to Tapaniya Samgha.8 Consisting of 2166 gāthās,, the Bhagavati Aradhanā dwells on the scheme of darśana, jñāna, caritra and tapas. Sivakoti has included almost all subjects on Jaina ethics under these four heads. Many Acaryas have written commentaries on Bhagvati Aradhana. The most important and exhaustive of them is Śrīvijayodaya of Aparajitasūri who wrote a commentary on Daśvaikālikas utra also.10 Premi places him between 6th and 9th 1. Vasunandi on Mulācāra, p. 2. 2. Adipurāṇa, Käsi, 1963. Vol. I. 1.49. 3. Jaina, H.L., Bharatiya samskṛti mem Jainadharma kāyogadāna, p. 106. 4. Ibid., p. 106. 5. Pujyapada on Tattvärthas utra (Sarvärthasiddhi), Solapura, Saka era, 1839, 9.22. 6. Premi, Nathurama, Jaina sahitya aura itihasa, p. 78. 7. Ibid. p. 77. 8. Ibid., pp. 68-73. 9. Ibid., pp. 78-86. Also Mukhtara, J.K., Jaina sahitya ke itihasa para visada prakāśa, Calcutta, 1956, pp. 485-491. 10. Aparajitasuri on Bhagavatī Ārādhanā (Mūlārādhanā), Šolāpura, 1936, 6. 1197 Page #267 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 250 Jaina Ethics century of Vikrama era.1 Mukhtara places him in the 8th century of Vikrama era.2 Amitagati (11th century A.D.) wrote a Samskṛta version of the gathās of Bhagavati Aradhana. Many of the Samskṛta verses of this versions have been quoted in the commentary of Anāgāradharmāmṛta by Pt. Aśādhara. Pt. Asadhara (13th century A.D.) also wrote a commentary, Mūlārādhanādarpaṇa, on Bhagavati Ārādhanā. Premi has referred to two more commentaries, hitherto unpublished and preserved in Bhandarkar Research Institute of Poona.3 One of these tikās is Aradhana-pañjikā, whose author is not given in the commentary. Prabhācandra, author of Prameyakamalamartaṇḍa, also wrote an Aradhanapanjikā. If he is the author of Aradhanāpañjikā preserved at Bhandarkar Research Institute, then the commentary can be placed in 8th or 9th century A.D. The other commentary Bhāvārthadipikā, by Sivajilāla is ascribed to 1818 of Vikrama era. Mūlārādhanādarpana of Asadhara mentions a Prākṛta tikāR and a tippani by Sricandra and Jayanandis also on Bhagavati Aradhanā. All these commentaries have become extinct now. 4. Kartikeyanuprekṣā Dr. A. N. Upadhye is of the opinion that Kartikeya came later than Kundakunda, Vaṭṭakera, Šivārya, Umāsvālī, Pujyapada and Joindu i.e. later than 6th century A.D., and he is even doubtful whether Kartikeya could have lived even after Nemicandra (10th century A.D.). Mukhtara has rejected gāthā number 279 of Kartikeyanuprekṣā as an interpolation and has refuted any possible influence of Yoganusāsana of Yogindu I. Premi, Nathurama, Jaina sahitya aura itihasa, p. 79. 2. Mukhtara, Purātana Jaina vākya-sūcī, Sahārantura, (year of publication is not given), prastāvanā, p. 21. 3. Premi, Nathurāma, Jaina sāähitya aura itihāsa, p. 80-81. 4. Winternitz, A History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, p. 582, foot note 6. 5. Premi, Nathurāma, Jaina sahitya aura itihāsa, p. 82. 6. Asadhara on Bhagavati Aradhanā (Mūlārādhana), Solapura, 1335,4.526. 7. Ibid., 4.589. 8. Ibid., 7.1999. 9. Kartikeyanuprekṣā, (ed.), Upadhye, A.N., Agas, 1960, p. 69. ----- Page #268 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Ethical Literature of the Jainas on Kartikeya.1 He places Kartikeyanuprekṣā just after Tattvarthasūtra of Umāsvāti This book was commented upon by Subhacandra in Vikarma Samvat 1613.2 5. Tattvärthasutra of Umāsvāmi Tattvärthasutra is recognised as an authority by all sects of Jainism. J. L. Jaini has ascribed this sūtra to 135219 A.D. In his introduction to Vasunandiśrāvakācāra, Pt. Hīrā Lāla has said that Umāsvāmi followed Svāmi Kārtikeya. According to Digambara tradition, Umāsvāmi was the pupil of Kundakunda, whereas according to Svetāmbara tradition he was the pupil of Ghoşanandi Kṣamāśramana. His Tattvärtha sūtra is believed to have been taken from the sixth Anga, Jñatṛdharmakatha and the second Purva, Agrāyaṇī. Jaina ethics is dealt with in the last five chapters of Tattvärthasūtra. Another work ascribed to Umāsvāmi is Šrāvakaprajñapti, with which we have already dealt. R. Williams thinks that it was written by some Svetambara Acarya other than Umāsvāmi.3 Tattvärthasūtra is one of the most commented upon work of Jainism. There are 31 commentaries on this work. Sarvārthasiddhi of Pujyaṭāda (7th cent. of Vik.), Rājavārtika of Akalanka (7th-8th cent. of Vik.),5 Ślokavārtika of Vidyānandi (9th-10th cent. of Vik. ) and commentary of Śrutasāgara ( 16th cent. of Vik.) deserve special mention amongst Digambara commentaries. We have already referred to the Svopajñabhäşya and commentary of Siddhasena Gani amongst Svetambara tradition. 251 6. Samantabhadra The time of Samantabhadra is a controversial question. I. Mukhtara, Puratana Jaina vākya-sūcī, prastāvanā, p. 24-26. 2. Ibid., p. 22. 3. Williams, R., Jaina Yoga, p. 3. 4. Bhandarkar, R.G., Early History of Deccan, (Second edition), Bombay, 1895, p. 59. 5. Tattvärthasutra, (ed.), Samghvi, Sukhalala, (Second edition), Banaras, 1952, p. 48. 6. Ibid., p. 48. 7. Ibid., p. 48. Jairt Education International Page #269 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 252 Jaina Ethics Winternitz assigns him to 8th century A.D., whereas the traditional view places him in the 2nd century A.D. Here we may refer to a Sūtra of Jainendra Vyākarana of Pūjyapāda, where Samantabhadra is mentioned. One Pațțāvalīmentions Saka Samvat 60 (138 A.D.) in relation to Samantabhadra. Inscription of Sravanabelagolā places Samantabhadra after Simhanandi, who was the teacher of Korganivarman (103 A.D.).4 Samantabhadra is, therefore, to be placed in the 1st century A.D. That Samantabhadra preceded Simhanandi is borne out by three other inscriptions also.5 R. Williams says that Mukhtara places Samantabhadra between the first and fifth centuries A.D. He was perhaps not aware of the latest views of Mukhtara, where he has decidedly favoured 1st century A.D. as the probable date of Samantabhadra. It is as yet an open question as to which century Samantabhadra belonged. What we may do for the present is to place him after Kundakunda, Umāsvāmi, Svāmikārtikeya and Sivakoti on one hand, and before Pujyapāda on the other hand. This position is accepted by Pt. Hirālāla8 and R. Williamo also. Besides Devāgamastotra or Aptamimāṁsā, which is said to be the introduction to the lost commentary on Tattvārthas ātra, Yuktyanuśāsana and Ratnakarndafrāvakācāra are also attributed to Samantabhadra. Most important of all, Ratnakarndašrāvakācāra occupies an important place in the discussion of Jaina ethics as the earliest Digambara treatise on the rules of conduct for a laity. Aptamimāṁsā has been commented upon by Akalarika. His commentary is called Astašati, which has been again com I. Winternitz, M., History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, p. 580. Mukhtāra, J.K., Faina-sähitya ke itihasa para visada prakāśa, pp. 297-322. 2. Fainendravyākarana, Kāśi, 1956, 5.4.168. 3. Bhandarkar, R.G., Report of the Skt. Mss. in the Bombay Presidency during 1883-1884, Bombay, 1887, p. 320. One of the inscriptions on Konganivarman is dated Saka era 25. Epigraphia Carnatica, III, No. 110. 5. Epigraphia Carnatica, VII, Nos, 35, 36, 37 6. Williams, R. Jaina Yoga, p. 19. 7. Mukhtara, J.K., Jaina sāhitya ke itihasa para visada prakāśa, pp. 689.697. 8. Vasunandiśrävakācāra, prastāvanā, p. 45. g. Williams, R., Faina-Yoga, p. 19. 4. UIC Page #270 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Ethical Literature of the Jainas mented upon by Vidyananda under the name of Aşṭasahasri. Prabhācandra wrote a commentary on Ratnakaraṇḍa-śrāvakācāra. 7. Pujyapāda Pujyapada's another name is Devanandin. He wrote the most authoritative commentary on the Tattvarthasutra. This commentary is called the Sarvarthasiddhi. Bhandarkar places Pujyapada about 678 A.D.1 Winternitz places him between the 5th and 7th century. That he must follow Samantbhadra, we have already said. Besides Sarvarthasiddhi, Pujyapada wrote a small book Iştopadesa consisting of 51 verses. 8. Asadhara Asadhara, who is the author of Anāgāra Dharmāmṛta and Sāgāra Dharmāmṛta lays down the duties of an ascetic and a lay adherent, respectively. He belongs to the first half of the 13th century A.D., as his Jinavijayakalpa and Sāgāradharmāmṛta are dated 1228 A.D. and 1239 A.D., respectively. He also wrote a commentary on Dharmamṛta in 1243 A.D. Premi has given a brief sketch of his life. He also gives a list of his nineteen books, many of which are lost. Mention of his commentaries on Sivärya's Aradhana and Iṣṭopadesa may be made. Asādhara cites Samantabhadra, Jinasena, Cāmuṇḍarāya, Somadeva, Amitagati, Amṛtacandra and Vasunandi.5 Asadhara is said to have been influenced by Svetāmbara tradition in many respects, specially by Upasakādhyayana, Nitivākāmṛta and Srāvakadharmaprjnapti.® 9. Vasunandi 253 Pandita Asadhara in his commentary on Sāgāradharmāmrta of Vikrama Samvat 1296 has referred to Vasunandi." Vasunandi should, therefore, be placed before Asadhara. Winternitz I. Bhandarkar, R.G., Early History of Deccan, (Second edition), p. 59. 2. Winternitz, M., A History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, p. 478. 3. Premi, Nathurama, Jaina sahitya aura itihāsa, p. 342-358. 4. Ibid., pp. 345-346. 5. Williams, R., Jaina Yoga, p. 27. 6. Vasunandiśravakācāra, prastāvanā, p. 54. 7. Aśädhara on Sāgāradharmāmrta, Bombay, Vik. Sam. 1972, 3.16. Page #271 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 254 Jaina Ethics places him between the 10th and 13th centuries.1 A.N. Upad. hye has placed him in the 12th century of Vikrama era.? Vasunandi in his Ācāravrtti of Mūlācāra has quoted verses from Amitagati. He must, therefore, follow Amitagati.8 Pandita Hirālāla places Vasunandi in the second half of the 19th century as Nayanandi who was the teacher of his teacher, wrote a work of Apabhraíía, Sudarśanacarita in Vikrama Samvat 1100.4 Besides Srāvakācāra and Pratisthāsāra Sangraha which, according to Pandita Hirālāla, should be ascribed to the same person, three conmentaries on Aptamīmāṁsā, Jinaśataka and Mülācāra are also ascribed to him. He has also shown that Vasunandi used Bhāvasaṁgraha of Devasena and was familiar with Śrāvakācāra of Amitagati.? 10. Amrtacandra Amrtacandra is placed in about 900 A.D. by Winternitz.& Dr. Upadhye places him somewhere in the 10th century A.D.' Besides writing commentaries on Kundakunda's work, he wrote the Puruşārthasiddhyupāya, which holds a unique position for stressing the cardinal virtue of non-violence. Besides Tattavārthasāra, a versified form of Tattavārthas ātra, is also ascribed to him. 11. Amitagati Amitagati is placed at the end of 10th and the beginning of the 11th century by Winternitz.10 His Subhāṣitaratansandoha and commentaries on the Pañcasamgraha and Dharma 1. Winternitz, M., A History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, p. 577, foot note 2. 2. "Jaina Jagat” Bombay, (ed. Darbarilāla Satyabhakta), year 8, Vol. VII, (February, 1933), p. 20. Mukhtara, Puratana Jaina-vākya-sūci, prastāvanā, p. 100. 4. Vasunandi śrāvakācāra, prastāvanā, p. 18. 5. Ibid., p. 18. 6. Ibid., p. 18. 7. Ibid., p. 41. 8. Winternitz, M., History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, p. 576 and p. 584. 9. Pravacansära, Introduction, p. CI. Winternitz, M., A History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, p. 481. Page #272 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Ethical Literature of the Jainas 255 pariksă are dated Vikrama Samvat 1050, 1073 and 1070, respectively. Besides the three works mentioned above, Upāsakācāra, his Saṁskrta versification of Arādhanā of Sivārya, Sāmāyikapātha, and Bhāvanādvātrimśikā are also ascribed to Amitagati.1 12. Subhacandra Subhacandra has quoted a verse from Puruşārtha siddhyupāya of Amrtacandra, who has been quoted by Jayasena in his Dharma Ratnākara in Vikrama Samvat 1055. So we can fix this as the lower limit of subhacandra. The upper limit of his time can be fixed on the basis of a manuscript of Jānārņava, the praśasti of which mentions Vikrama Samvat 1248. According to Shri Premi, there is another manuscript of 7ñānārnava which must be at least 30 years older than the first one. Thus we can place Subhacandra somewhere between 1055 and 1248 of Vikrama era. Winternitz places Subhacandra at the close of the 8th or the beginning of the 9th century.3 We mention below some more works on Jaina morality, arranged chronologically, with their probable dates : Author Works Date Devasena Aläpapaddhati, Nayacakra, 10th cent. A.D.4 Brhadnayacakra, Bhāva Samgraha, Darśanasāra. Cāmundarāya Căritrasära 10th cent. A.D.5 Padmanandi Dharmarasāyana 12th cent. A.D.8 Māghānandi Srāvakācāra 1260 A.D.? Guna Bhūsana Srāvakācāra 13th cent. A.D.8 Padmanandi Srāvakācāra 15th cent. A.D.) 1. Premi, Nāthurāma, faina sāhitya aura itihāsa, p. 280-281. 2. Ibid., p. 334. . 3. Winternitz, M., A History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, p. 583. 4. Darśanasāra was completed in Vik. Sar. 990. Cf. Mukhtāra, Purātana Jain vākya sūci, p. 116. 5. Williams, R., Jaina Yoga, p. 17. 6. Ibid., p. 26. 7. Ibid., p. 28. 8. Ibid., p. 17. 9. Williams, R., Jaina Yoga, p. 17. Page #273 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Acārāngasūtra Acārasāra Adipuraṇa (II Parts) Aitareya Brāhmaṇa Amitagatisravakācāra Anāgāradharmamṛta Anguttara Nikaya Apta Mimāmsā Aradhanasāra Aşṭapāhuḍa Atharvaveda Avadānakalpalatā Avasyakasūtra Bhagavati-Arādhanā (Also known as Mülārādhanā) Bhagavatis utra Bhāvapāhuḍa Bhavasamgrahādi Bodhicaryavatāra Bṛhadaranyakopanisad Brhaddravyasamgraha Bṛhatkalpabhasya BIBLIOGRAPHY A. Primary books Ed. Puppha Bhikkhu, Gurgaon, 1950 Comm., Šilanka, Calcutta, V.S. 1936. Viranandi Siddhanta Cakravarti, Solapura, V.N.S. 2462. Acārya Jinasena, Kāśī, 1963. Ed. Haug, Martin, Bombay, 1863. Amitagati, Bombay, V.S, 1979. Aśādhara, Bombay, 1919. Ed. Bhikkhu J. Kasyapa, Bihar Govt. 1960. Samantabhadra, Solapura, S.S. 1826 Comm. Suri Vidyānandi, Rajnagar, V.S. 1993. Devasenācārya, Bombay, V.S. 1973. Kundakundācārya, Delhi, 1943. Ed. Satavalekar, S.D., Aundh, 1943. Kṣemendra, Calcutta, 1884. Cūrņi, Jinadāsagaṇī Mahattara, Ratlam, 1928. Śivakoṭyācārya Comm. Aparajitasūri, Solapura, 1935. Comm. Aśādhara, Solapura, 1935. Comm. Abhayadeva, BombayAhmedabad, Vik. Sam. 1974-1988. See Aṣṭapāhuḍa Ed. Pannālāla Soniti, Bombay, V.S. 1978. Santideva, Darbhanga, 1960. See Radhakrishnan, S., "The Principal Upanisads'. Nemicandra Siddhantideva Comm. Brahmadeva, Bombay, V.N.S. 2433. Ed. Guru Sri Caturvijaya and Punyavijaya, Bhavanagar, 1933. $ Page #274 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Bibliography 257 Cãritrapāhuda Cäritrasāra Chāndogyopanisad Cülikā Cullavagga Darśanapāhuda Daśavaikälikasūtra Dhammpada Dharmasangraha Pigha-Nikaya See Aştapāhuda. Cāmundarāya, Sri Mahāvirji, VNS. 2488. See Radhakrishnan, S, The Principal Upanişads. (Printed in Jaina Penance', by Jaina, C.R., Allahabad, 1930), Devanāgari Pāli Series, Nalanda, 1956. See Aştapāhuda Ed. Ācārya Tulasi, Calcutta, V.S. 2020. Niryukti, Bhadrabāhu, Ed. Abhyankara K.V., Ahmedabad, 1932. Ed. Narayana Avadhakishora, Benares, 1946. Gaņin Mānavijaya, Palitana, 1905. Ed. Bhagawata, N.K., Bombay, 1942 Trans. Sānkstyāyana Rāhul, Benares, 1963. Siddhāntacakravarti Nemicandra, Delhi, 1956. Ed. Annie Besant, Madras, 1930. Comm. Ācārya Samkara, Nirnayasagara Press, Bombay, 1936. Siddhāntacakravarti, Nemicandra. Jivakāņda--Pub. Śrī Paramaśruta Prabhāvaka, Srimadrājacandra, Jaina Šāstramālā, Agas, V.S. 2016. Karmakānda-Ed. Brahmacāri, S.P., Lucknow, 1937. Comm. Ācārya Samkara, Gitā Press, Gorakhapura, V.S. 1994. Pūjyapāda, Bombay, 1954. See 'Minor Upanişads' Pūjyapāda, Kashi, 1956 Āryaśūra, Darbhanga, 1959. Subhacandra, Bombay, 1907. Gaņin Yasovijaya, Bhavanagar, V.S. 1969. Dravyasaṁgraha Gita Gommațasāra Isopanisad Istopadeśa Jābālopanisad Jainendra-vyākarana Jātakamālā jñānārnava jñānäsāra Page #275 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 258 Jaina Ethics Jñānāştaka Kārtikeyānupreksā Kaşāyaprābhṛta Kathopanişad Kiraṇāvalibhāskara Labdhisāra Lalitavistara Lingapāhuda Mahābhārata Mahāvagga Majjhimanikāya See Jñānasāra. Swami Kārtikeya. Comm. Subhacandra Ed. Upadhye, A.N., Agas, 1960. Ācārya Gunadhara, Comm. Virasenācārya, Ed. Phulchandra, Mahendra Kumar, and Kailashcandra, Mathura, 1944. See Radhakrishnan, S., "The Princi. pal Upanişads'. Miśra Padmanābha, Benaras, 1920. Siddhāntacakravarti Nemicandra, Bombay, 1946, Comm. Keśavavarṇin Calcutta, 1946. Ed. Vaidya P.L., Darbhanga, 1958. See Aştapāhuda. Vyāsa, Poona, 1933. Ed. Bhikṣu, J., Kāśyapa, Bihar, 1956. Trans. Sünkrtyāyana, Rahula, Sarnath, 1933. Nārāyaṇa Bhatta, K. Ed. Kuhuna Raja and Šāstrī Sūryanārāyaṇa, S.S., Madras, 1933. Manu Pub. Khemarāja Śrīkysņadāsa, Bombay, 1894. Jaimini, Benares, 1929. Ed. Shrader, F., Otto, Madras, 1912. See Aştapāhuda. Vaţțakerācārya Comm. Vasunandin, Bombay, V.S. 1977-80. See Radhakrishnan, S., The Principal Upanişads. Ācārya Sureśvara, Poona, 1925. Ed. Anandasāgār, Ratlam, 1928. Ed. Muni Kanhaiyalal, Rajkota 1958. Mānameyodaya Manusmrti Mimāṁsādarśana Minor Upanişads Mokşapāhuda Mülācāra (II parts) Mundakopanisad Naişkarmyasiddhi Nandi Cūrni Nandi Sūtra Page #276 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Bibliography Nāṭakasamayasāra Niḥsprhāṣṭaka Nirbhayas taka Nirlepaṣṭaka Nisitha Niyamasära Nyayas ūtra Padma Purāṇa Pālijātakāvali Pañcādhyāyi Pancāstikāya Parisişṭaparva Paramatmaprakāśa Prakaraṇapañcaśikā Prasastapāda Bhāṣya Prasnopanisad Pravacanasara Pravacanasaroddhāra Prayaścittasamuccaya Puruşärthasiddhyupaya Rāmāyaṇa Banarasīdāsa, Bombay, V. S. 1986. See Jñanasara'. See 'Jñanasara'. See 'Jñanasära'. Visāhagaṇimahattara Cūrņi, Jinadāsagaṇimahattara, Agra, 1957. 259 Kundakundācārya, Lucknow, 1931. Gautama, Poona, 1939. Comm. Jayantabhatta, Benares, 1934. Comm. Vātsyāyana, Poona, 1939. Ravişena, Kashi, 1959. Ed. Sarma, B.N., Benares, V. S. 1997 Rajamalla, Indore, V.N.S. 2444. Kundakundācārya Bombay, V. S. Hemacandrācārya, Bhavanagar, V.S. 1972. 1968. Yogindudeva, Comm. Brahmadeva, Bombay, 1937. Sastri, A. S., B. H. U., Benares, 1961. Prasastapāda Benares, 1924. See Radhakrishnan, S., The Principal Upanisads'. Kundakundācārya Ed. Upadhye, A. N., Comm. Amṛtacandra, Comm. Jayasena, Bombay, 1955. Nemicandra, Bombay, 1922. Acarya Gurudasa, (printed in 'Jaina Penance', by Jaina, C. R., Allahabad, 1930). Amṛtacandrācārya, Agas V. S. 2022. Valmiki, Ed. Šarmā, Vasudeva, Bombay, S.S. 1830. Page #277 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 260 Ratnakarandafrāvakācāra , Rgveda Saddharmalankāvatāra Sāgāradharmāmta Samādhisataka Samayasāra Jaina Ethics Samantabhadrācārya, (printed under the title 'Samīcinadharmaśāstra', ed. Mukhtar, Jugal Kishore, Delhi, 1955). Ed. Satavalekara, S. D. Aundh, 1940. Ed. Vaidya, P. L., Darbhanga 1963. Āśādhara, Surat, V. N. S. 2466. Comm. Āsādhara, Bombay, V. S. 1972. Pūjyapāda, Delhi, V.S. 1878. Kundakundācārya, Comm. Amộtacandra, Delhi, 1959. Comm. Jayasena, Delhi, 1959. Comm. Jayacanda, Delhi, 1959. Comm. Kalaśa, Delhi, 1959. Amitagati, Delhi, 1966. Kapila, Comm. Vijñānabhikṣu, Calcutta, 1936. Isvarakļşņa, Poona, 1934, Miśra Vācaspati, Poona, 1934. Ed. Bhikṣu J. Kāśyapa, Nalanda, 1959. Trans. Bhikṣu J. Kāśyapa, Benares, 1954. Mādhavācārya Poona, 1951. Ed. Sarmā Candradhara, Kāśī, V.S. 1994 Puspadanta and Bhūtabali, Comm. Vīrasenācārya, Ed. Jaina, H.L., Amraoti 1939 Ed. Pannālāla Soni, Bombay V. S. 1979. Sāmāyikapāțha Sāṁkhyadarśana Sāṁkhyakārikā Samyuttanikāya Sarvadarśanaśamgraha Šatapathabrāhmaņa Satkhaņdāgama Siddhārtasārādi-saṁgraha (Śrutāvatāra of Vibudhaśrīdhara) Sloka vārtika Bhattombeka Madras, 1940, Trans. Jha, Ganga Natha, Calcutta, 1909. Umāsvāti, Bombay, V. S. 1961. Srāvakaprajñapti Page #278 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Bibliography 261 Sri Jainasiddhānta- Ed. Sethia Bhairodana, Bikaner, bolasamgraha (8 Vols.) 1945. Srimadbhagvadgitā Pub. Gitā Press, Gorkhpur, 10th Edition, V.S. 2009. Śrīmadbhāgavatapurāņa Vyāsa, Gita Press, Gorakhpur, V. S. 2010. Sthānāngas ūtra Comm. Abhayadeva, Ahmedabad, 1937. Sukla-rajurveda Ed. Śarmā, Vāsudeva, Nirnaya Sagar Press, Bombay, 1929. Sūtrakṛtānga Comm. Sīlānka, Bombay, 1917. Svayambhustotra Samantabhadra, Surat, V.N.S. 2458 Svetāśvataropanişad See Radhakrishnan, S., “The Princi pal Upanişads'. Syādvādamañjari Mallişeņa, Bombay, 1935. Tapostaka See Jñānasāra Tattvānuśāsanādisaṁgraha Pub. Māņikyacandra Digambara (containing Srutaskandha Jaina Granthamala Samiti, of Brahma Hemacandra V.S. 1975. and Srutāvatāra of Indranandi) Tattvārthasūtra Umāsvāti. Ed. Samghavi Sukhalāla, Second Edition, Benaras, 1952. Comm. Bhațța Akalanka, Calcutta, 1929. Comm. Ganin Siddhasena, Surat, 1930. Comm. (Sarvārthasiddhi) Pūjyapāda Solapura, S.S. 1839. Comm. Umāsvāti, Surat, 1930. Comm. Vidyānandi, Bombay, 1918. Taittiriyopanişad See Radhakrishnan, S., The Princi pal Upanişads'. Trilokaprajñapti Yati Vịşabhācārya, Solapura, 1943. Upāsakadaśārga Ed. Kanhaiyalal, Rajkota, 1961. Upāsakādhyayana Sūri Somadeva, Kāśi, 1964. Uttarādhyayana Ed. Puppha Bhikkhu, Gurgaon, 1954, Vaiseșikasutra Kaņāda, Allahabad, 1923. Comm. Candrakānta, Ed. Basu, B.D., Page #279 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 262 Vasunandi Srāvakācāra Vedāntas ātra Vidhyāşțaka Viseşāvasyakabhāşya Vişnupurāņa Faina Ethics Allahabad, 1923 (S.B.H. Vol. VI). Vasunandi, Ed. Jain Hiralal, Kāśī, 1952. Vyāsa Comm. Miśra, Vācaspati, Bombay 1917. Comm. Ācārya Sankara, Bombay, 1917. See Jñānasāra". Kșamāśramaņa Jinabhadraganin. Comm. Kotyācārya, Ratlam, 1936. Ed. Munilal Gupta, Gorakhapur, V.S. 2009, Benares, 1943. Buddhaghoșa, Benaras, 1943. Ed. Śarmä, Vasudeva, Bombay, 1929. Somadeva, Bombay, 1901. Yogindudeva, Bombay, V.S. 1993. Hemacandra, Comm. Hemacandra, Bhavanagar, 1926. Patañjali, Gita Press, Gorakhpur, V.S. 2013, Comm. Vyāsa, Poona, 1932. Samantabhadra, Saharanpur, 1951. Visuddhi Magga, Part II Yajurveda raśastilaka Yogasāra Yogaśāstra Yogasūtra Yuktyānušāsana B. Secondary Books Bahaduri, S. Studies in Nyāyavaiseșika Meta physics, Poona, 1947. Bertrand Russel. History of Western Philosophy, London, 1948. Bhandarkara, R.G. Early History of Deccan, (Second edition), Bombay, 1895. Report of the Sanskrit MSS, in the Bombay Presidency during 1883 1884, Bombay, 1887. Brahmachari, Sital Prasad A Comparative Study of Jainism and Buddhism, Madras, 1929. Dasgupta, Surendranath A History of Indian Philosophy, Page #280 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Bibliography Deo, S.B. Deussen, Paul. Eliot, Sir Charles. Gladstone, W.E. Green, T.H. Handiqui, K.K. Hume, David. Jaina, C.R. "" Jaina, H. L. Jaina, J.C. ور James, Hastings (Ed.) James, William. James, W. Kapadia, H.R. Karmarkar, A.P. Law, B.C. Mackenzie, John S. Max Müller (Ed.) 39 Mckenzie, John. Mukhtara, J.K. 263 Vol. I, Cambridge, 1932. History of Jaina Monachism, Poona, 1956. The Philosophy of the Upanisads, Edinburg, 1919. Hinduism and Buddhism, Vol. I, New York, 1954. Studies subsidiary to Butler's work, Oxford, 1896. Prolegomena to Ethics, Oxford, 1899. Yasastilaka and Indian Culture, Solapura, 1949. A Treatise of Human Nature, Vol. I, London, 1951. Jaina Penance, Allahabad, 1930. Samnyasa Dharma, London, 1926. Bharatiya samskrti mem Jaina dharma kā yogadāna, Bhopal, 1962. Prakṛta Sahitya ka itihāsa, Vārāṇasi, 1961. Life in Ancient India as depicted in the Jaina canons, Bombay, 1947. Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics New York, 1955. Psychology, New York, 1920. Pragmatism, New York, 1948. A History of the Canonical Literature, Surat, 1941. Purāņic Words of wisdom, Bhartiya Vidya Bhavana, Bombay, 1947. Mahavira, his life and teachings, London, 1937. A Manual of Ethics, London, 1929. Sacred Books of the East, Vol. XII, Oxford, 1884. Sacred Books of the East, Vol. XLV, Oxford, 1895. Hindu Ethics, London, 1922. Jaina sahitya ke itihasa para visada prakāśa, Calcutta, 1956. Page #281 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 264 Muirhead, John H. Muni Kalyāņa Vijaya. Muni Nathmala Pattison, Pringle. Premi, Nāthu Rāma. Radhakrishnan, S. Faina Ethics Purātana Jaina vākya sūci, Saharanpura (year of publication is not given). The elements of Ethics, London, 1910. Vira nirvāṇa samvat aura Jaina kāla gananā, Jalore, V.S. 1987. Ahimsa-tattva-darśana, Churu, 1960. Jaina darśana ke maulika tattva, Vol. II, Calcutta, 1960. The Philosophical Redicals, Edinburg, 1907. Jaina sāhitya aura itihāsa, (second ed.), Bombay, 1956. Eastern Religion and Western Thought, London, 1940. Indian Philosophy, Vol. I, London, 1941. Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, London, 1956. The Principal Upanişads, London, 1953. Dialogues of the Buddha, Part II, P.T.S., London, 1951. A Short History of Ethics, London, 1913. Prākṣta-bhāșa aura sāhitya kā ālocanātmaka itihāsa, Varanasi, 1966. The Doctrine of the Jainas, Delhi, 1962. Schools and Sects in Jaina Literature, Calcutta, 1931, Contribution to the History of Brahmanical Asceticism, Poona, 1939, Systems of Buddhist Thought, Calcutta, 1912. London (Year of publication is not given). Rhys Davids, T.W. and C.A.F. Rogers, A.P. Šāstri, Nemicandra Schubring, W. Sen, Amülyacandra. Sharma Har Dutt. Sögen, Yamakami. The Holy Bible Page #282 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Bibliography 265 Tilak, B.G. Srimad Bhagavadgitābhāșya, Poona, 1955. Todaramala. Mokşamārgaprakāśa, Mathurā, 1948. Upādhyāya, Baladeva. Bhārtīya Darśana, Benaras, 1948. Upādhyāya, Bharat Singh. Bauddhadarśana tathā anyabhāratiya darśana, Vol. II, Calcutta, Vik. Sam. 2011. Velankar, H.D. (Ed.) Jinaratnakośa, Poona, 1944. Williams, R. Jaina Yoga, London, 1963. Winternitz, Maurice. A History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, Calcutta, 1933. Zimmer, Heinrich. Philosophies of India, London, 1951. C. Epigraphical Records and Journals Anekānta Vira Sevā Mandira, Delhi. Ed. Mukhtar, J.K., and others. Coorg Inscriptions. Epigraphia Carnatica. Epigraphia Indica. Faina Jagat Bombay. Ed. Darabārīlāla Satyabhakta. Page #283 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Page #284 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INDEX I Source Books (The books have been quoted in the footnotes on the pages indicated by figures against each work.) Ācārāngasūtra, 1, 10, 29, 91, Bșhaddravyasamgraha, 98 96, 103, 157, 176 Bphatkalpabhāşya, 147, 150, Silānka's commentary, 10, 226. 153, 154, 155, 158, 174, Ācārasāra, 153, 172 190, 213 Adipurāņa (2 Parts), 206, Cāritrapāhuda, 142, 144 222, 249 Cāritrasāra, 85, 118, 121, 123, Amitagatiśrāvakācāra, 109, 130, 133, 134, 135, 138, 110, 111, 117, 120, 122, 142 130, 135, 137, 140, 141, Chandogyopanişad, 6, 39, 53, 144 91, 103, 181 Anāgāradharmāmpta 90, 152, Cūlikā, 185 153, 155, 166, 167, 168, Darśanapāhuda, 84, 94 169, 172, 182 183, 189, Daśavaikālikasūtra, 1, 39, 93, 190 107, 122, 155, 156, 174, 231 Anguttara Nikaya 6, 7 238 Āpta Mimāṁsā, 12, 22, 33 -Bhadrabāhu's Niryukti, 225, Arādhanāsära, 98 238 Atharvaveda, 15, 121, 181 Dhammpada, 193 Āvaśyaka sūtra, 227 Dharmasamgraha, 89, 149 Bhagavati Ārādhanā, 152, 153, Digha-Nikāya, 17, 18 155, 157, 160, 183, 184, Dravyasamgraha, 43, 44, 63, 64 186, 187, 188, 190, 191, Gītā, 22, 24, 91, 97, 105, 181 192 -Ācārya Sankara's Comarājitasūri's Commentary, mentary, 55 164, 191, 249 Gommațasāra, (Jiyakāņda), --Ašādhara's commentary, 250 165, 209, 211, 212, 213, Bhagayatīsūtra, 225 214, 215, 216, 217 Bhåvapāhuda, 93 Gommațasāra (Karmakāņda) Bhāvasaṁgrahādi, 77, 78 15, 16, 18 Bshadāraṇyakopanişad, 40, 70, Isopanişad, 81, 97 79 Istopadeśa, 5, 10, 77, 94 Page #285 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 268 Faina Ethics Jābālopanişad, 105 Nandi Sūtra, 225, 228 Jainendra-vyākaraṇa, 252 Nāțakasamayasāra 86, 90, 91 Jñānārņava, 98, 152, 155, 194, Niḥspịhāştaka, 95 195, 196, 197, 198, 201, Nirbhayāsţaka, 95 202, 203, 204, 206, 207 Nirlepășțaka, 95 Jñānasāra, 95 Niśitha, 153, 157, Jñānāştaka, 95 Niyamasāra, 84, 159, 161, 162, Kārtikeyānuprekṣā, 32, 75, 166, 167, 169, 208. 84, 87, 117, 119, 126, 128, Nyāyasūtra, 9, 40, 55, 71, 193 129, 131, 133, 135, 136, – Jayantabhațța's Commen 142, 143, 145, 208, 250 tary, 40 -Subhacandra's Commentary, - Vätsyāyana's Commentary, 128, 138, 144, 207 9, 40, 41, 55 Kaşāyaprābhịta, 225, 227, Pālijātakāvali, 33 228, 245 Pañcādhyāyi 3, 58, 98, 152 Kathopanişad, 4, 79, 193, Pañcāstikāya, 24, 26, 76, 94 Kiraṇāvalibhāskara, 66, Parisistaparva, 226 Labdhisāra 208, 209 Paramātmaprakāśa 76, 206 -Keśavavarņin's Commen- -Brahmadeva's Commentary, tary, 209 77 Lingapāhuda, 161 Prakaranapañcāśikā, 80 Mahābhārata, 5, 17, 116, 181 Prasastapāda Bhāșya, 65 Mahāvagga, 36 Praśnopanişad, 181 Majjhimanikāya, 11, Pravacanasāra, 33, 74, 77, 98, Manusmști, 1, 101, 105, 147, 106, 107, 162, 166, 182 163, 181 247, 248, 254 Mimāṁsādarśana, 1, 7, 55 -Amộtacandra's Commentary, Minor Upanişads, 149 76, 152 Mokşapāhuda, 84, 206, 207 -Jayasena's Commentary, Mūlācāra (2 parts), 84, 86, 107, 160 104, 151, 152, 153, 154, Pravacanasāroddhāra, 149, 155, 156, 159, 160, 161, 153, 175, 210 162 163 166. 167. 168. Prāvascittasamuccava. 185. 169, 170, 171, 183, 184, 186, 187, 188, 189, 190 185, 190, 191 Puruşārthasiddhyupāya, 86, -Vasunandin's Commentary, 87, 106, 108, 111, 112, 154, 191, 248, 249. 113, 114, 115, 116, 117, Mundakopanişad, 96, 119, 181 119, 120, 123, 128, 129, Naişkarmyasiddhi, 67 131, 133, 134, 135, 137, Nandi Cūrņi, 225, 228 138, 141, 159, Page #286 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Index I 269 228 Ratnakarandaśrāvakācāra, 85. 215, 216, 217, 218, 86, 87, 101, 102, 110, 111, 118, 120, 121, 124, 125, Siddhāntasārādi-samgraha 126, 128, 131, 132, 133, (Śrutāvatāra of Vibudhasri. 134, 135, 136, 139, 140, dhara), 247 141, 142, 143, 144 śloka Vārtika, 25, 48 Rgveda, 78, 91, 105, 119. Śrāvakaprajñapti, 209 Sāgāradharmāmộta, 105, 111, Śrī Jainasiddhāntabolasan 112, 113, 117, 118, 119, graha, 151, 176, 211, 212 120, 122, 126, 129, 130, Śrimadbhāgavatapurāņa, 105, 131, 132, 133, 134, 135, 148 136, 137, 139, 140, 141, Sthānāngasūtra, 1, 103, 150, 143, 144 153, 175, 182 -Āśādhara's Commentary, śuklayajurveda, 97 253 Sūtrakṛtānga, 18, 19, 155 Samādhisataka, 207 Svayambhūstotra, 32, 184 Samayasāra, 4, 76, 77, 83 84, Svetāśvataropanişad, 15, 193, 88, 107 202 -Amộtacandra's Commentary, Syādvādamañjarī, 12 29, 35, 43, 76, 98. Tapoștaka, 95 -Jayacandra's Commentary, Tattvānušāsanādisamgraha, 94 (containing Srutaskandha -Kalasa Commentary, 74, 76 of Brahma Hemacandra Sāmāyikapātha, 87, 90 and Śrutāvatāra of IndraSamkhyadarśana, 71, 80 nandi) 228, 245, 246 -Vijñānabhikṣu's Commen- Tattvārthasūtra, 13, 39, 44, 45, tary, 80 50, 51, 56, 83, 85, 88, 135, Sāṁkhyakārikā, 8, 41, 48 251 -Miśra Vācaspati's Commen- Bhațța Akalankā's Commen. tary, 8, 25 tary, 62, 63, 107, 163, Samkşipta Mahābhārata, 147 1 64, 186 Sarvadarśanasamgraha, 11,20 –Gaṇin Siddhasena's Com25, 40, 41 mentary, 108, 113, 114, Śatapathabrāhmaṇa, 119 118, 120, 121, 122, 130, Şațkhandāgama, 181, 183, 184 1 32, 134, 135, 136, 138, 214, 215, 225, 226, 227, 139 245, 246 -Pūjyapāda's Commentary, Virasenācārya's Commentary, 45, 56, 62, 68, 75, 83, 89, 75, 182, 183, 184, 187, 93, 98, 107, 118, 120, 122, 190, 205, 210, 211, 213, 123, 125, 126, 127, 128, Page #287 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 270 129, 130, 132, 134, 135, 136, 137, 139, 140, 141, 142, 152, 154, 155, 159, 160, 163, 164, 180, 181, 182, 183, 184, 185, 186, 187, 188, 189, 192, 193, 194, 195, 196, 199, 200, 203, 204, 205, 249 -Vidyānandis Commentary, 96 Taittiriyopaniṣad, 103, 115 Trilokaprajñapti, 228 209 Upāsakadaśānga, 85, 102, 113, -Kotyācārya's Commentary, 117, 120, 122, 123, 125, 126, 127, 129, 132, 134, 141, 142 Upasakādhyayana, 30, 118 Uttaradhyayana, 10, 83, 84, 89, 93, 104, 148, 155, 156, 159, 160, 161, 162, 163, 164, 166, 177, 182, 183, 184, 212 Jatna Ethics 111, 120, 127, 135, 137, 138, 139, 141, 142. 143, 144, 195, 248, 252, 253, 254 Vedāntasūtrās -Acarya Samkara's Commen tary, 442, 49 -Miśra Vacaspati's Commen tary, 67 Vidhyaştaka, 95 Viseṣāvasyakabhāṣya, 209 Visuddhi Magga, Part II, 54 Yasastilaka, 78 Vaiseṣikasūtra, 9, 40, 66 Vasunandi Śrāvakācāra, 85, Yūktyanuśāsana, 12 149, Yogasāra, 77 129, Yogaśāstra, 118, 123, 132, 140. Yogasūtra, 8, 9, 54, 65, 103, 193 -Vyasa's Commentary, 54, 64, 80 Page #288 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INDEX II Modern Works Bahaduri, s. Bertrand Russel. Bhandarkara, R.G. Studies in Nyāyavaiseșika Metaphysics, 48 History of Western Philosophy, 17 Early History of Deccan, 251, 253 Report of the Sanskrit MSS. in the Bombay Presidency during 1883-1884, 255 A History of Indian Philosophy, Vol. I, 42, 71 History of Jaina Monachism, 148, 157 The Philosophy of the Upanişads, Dasgupta, Surendranath Deo, S.B. Deussen, Paul. 79 Handiqui, K.K. Hume, David. Jaina, C.R. Jaina, H.L. Jaina, J.C. Yaśastilaka and Indian Culture, 116, 117, 119. 120, 121, 130, 140 90, 111 A Treatise of Human Nature, Vol. I, 46 Jaina penance, 50, 171 Samnyāsa Dharma, 178 Bhāratiya Samskặti Mem Jaina dharma kā yogadāna, 225, 241, 243, 249 Prāksta Sāhitya kā itihāsa, 235, 239, 245, 246, 248 Life in Ancient India as depicted in the Jaina Canons, 240 Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics, 19, 23, 24, 25, 31 Psychology, 46 A History of the Canonical Literature of the Jaina, 227, 228, 232, 239 James, Hastings (Ed.) James, William Kapadia, H.R. Page #289 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 272 Mackenzie, John S. Max Müller (Ed.) Mckenzie. John. Mukhtara, J.K. Jaina Ethics A Manual of Ethics, I Sacred Books of the East, Vol. XXII, 103, 150, 230, 231, 232 Sacred Books of the East Vol. XLV, 36 Hindu Ethics, 27, 81 Jaina Sāhitya ke itihāsa para Visada Prakāśa, 249, 252 Purātana Jaina Vākya Sūci, 250, 251, 254, 255 The elements of Ethics, 1, 2 Vīra Nirvāṇa Samvat aura Jaina Kāla gañanā, 227, 228, 229 Ahimsa-tattva-darśana, 110 Jaina darśana ke maulika tattva, Vol. II, 212, 213, 214 Jaina dharma aura darśana, 211 Jaina śāhitya aura itihāsa, 248 249, 250, 253, 255 Muirhead, John H. Muni Kalyāņa Vijaya Muni Nathmal Pandita Sukhalāla Premi, Nāthu Rāma. 70 Pali English Dictionary, Radhakrishnan, S. Rogers, A.P. Šāstri, Nemicandra Schubring, W. Eastern Religion and Western Thought. 81, 82 Indian Philosophy, Vol. I, 25, 49 79, 80 Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, 41, 72, 91 A Short History of Ethics, 2 Prākṣta-bhāṣā aura Sāhitya kā ālocanātmaka itihäsa, 245, 246 The doctrine of t 176, 231, 233, 240 Schools and Sects in Jaina Literature, 232 Contribution to the History, of Brahmanical Asceticism, 150, 171 Systems of Buddhist Thought, 52 23, 81 Mokşamārgaprakāśa, 34 Bhāratīya Darsana, 19, 63, 66 Jinaratnakośa, 232, 233, 234, 235, Sen, Amulyacandra. Sharma, Har Dutt.. Sögen, Yamakami. The Holy Bible, Todaramala. Upādhyāya, Baladeva. Velankar, H.D. (Ed.) Page #290 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Index II 273 Williams, R. Winternitz, Maurice. 241, 242, 243, 244 Jaina Yoga, 241, 244, 251, 252, 253, 255 A History of Indian Literature, Vol. II, 230, 231, 232, 237, 243, 244, 248, 252, 253, 254, 255 Philosophies of India, 7, 17, 18 47 Zimmer, Heinrich. Epigraphical Records and Journals Anekānta, 148, 245 Coorg Inscriptions, 247 Epigraphia Indica, 158 Epigraphia Carnatica, 153, 252 Jaina Jagat, 254 Page #291 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ INDEX III Words of classical languages (The figures indicate the pages and n refers to footnote) abhakşya, 113 adharma, 50, 51, 80 Abhayadeva, 233, 234, 235, ādhibhautika, 7 241 adhidaivika, 8 abhavyas, 209, 210 adhigama, 88 abhigama, 89 adhikāra, 245 abhikṣaṇajñānopayoga, 61 adhikaraniki kriyā, 57 abhiniveśa, 54 adhyātma śāstra, 69 abhişava, 133 Adhyātmopanişad, 244 abhyutthāna, 176 adhyātmika 7. ācāmla, 188 adhyayana, 231, 232, 234, Ācāradaśā, 237 235, 237, 238 ācārakalpa, 236 Adipurāņa, 249 Ācārānga, 100, 178, 231, 232, adşșța, 44, 49 236, 240, 246, 249 Āgamas, 226, 228, 230, 231, Ācārāngadhārī, 230 236, 238, 239, 240, 241 Ācārānga sūtra, 10, 29, 157 aghātikarmans, 59, 218 ācārya, 73, 111, 125, 127, 131, āgneyi dhāraṇā, 200 133, 139, 140, 142, 145, Āgrāyaṇī, 251 146, 155. 168. 174. 175. ahankāra. 48 178, 189, 191, 192, 225. Ahāraka, 63 227, 228, 229, 236, 242, Ahāraka miśra, 63 247, 249 āhāra śuddhi, 138, 138 Acārya Amitagati, 111 ahimsā, 65, 102, 106 ācārya bhakti, 61 ahiṁsā mahāvrata, 152 Ācārya Kundakunda, 106 ahimsā paramo dharmaḥ, 105 Acārya Somadeva, 111 ailaka, 145 Acārya Vajra, 227, 229 ajaīryașțavyam, 105 Ācārya Virasena, 245 ajīva, 13, 39, 47, 212, 223 acitta, 132, 154 ājñā, 88 ādānanikṣepaņa samiti, 162 ajñāna, 62, 94 ādhākarmadoșa, 174 ājñāvicaya dharma dhyāna, Page #292 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Index III 275 199 214, 216. ājñāvyāpādikī kriyā, 57 ananta sukha, 218. Akalankadeva, 107, 251, 252 ananta virya, 217, 218. akāma nirjarā, 60 anarthadaņdaviramaņa, 130. akampita doșa, 186 anarthadandaviramaņavrata, ākānkşā, 85 127. akāśa, 50 anarthadandavrata, 125, 128. akriyāvādin, 36 anāsaktiyoga, 62. äkrndana 159 anaśana, 182, 183, akartěvāda, 37 anasūyā, 138. akrodha, 65 anyalingasiddha, 212. alarkāras, 233. ānayanaprayoga, 127. Alāpapaddhati, 255. anekāntavāda, 37. alaulya, 137, Anga, 89, 202, 226, 227, 231 alīkavacana, 153 232, 233, 234, 235, 239, ālocanā, 166, 169, 185. 240, 241, 251 ālocanāvidhi, 242. Angabāhya, 225, 239. amarșa, 55. Angapravişța, 225. Amitagati, 119, 122, 144, 250, angula, 170. 254, 255. anidānatva, 138. ämnāya, 192. anihnavavinaya, 191. Amoghavarşa, 245. anişțasamyogaja, 194. Amstacandra, 85, 86, 106, 108, anivșttikaraṇa, 210, 212, 216. 111, 116, 128, 131, 133, anivșttisāmparāya guṇasthāna, 135, 142, 248, 254. 216. amūdhadşşți, 86, 88. antakṣtadaśānga, 234. anābhogakriyā, 57. antarmuhūrta, 191, 216, 217. anādara, 134, 135, 136, 238 antarāya, 58, 217. anāgāmin, 208. āntarikaparigraha, 46. anāgāra, 253. antarātman, 206, 207. Anāgāradharmāmộta, 167, 168, anubhayamana, 62. 250. anujñā, 242. anākānksa kriyā, 57. anukampā, 89, 90. ănanda, 72. anukampita, 186. anantacatuştaya, 52. anumānitadoșa, 186. anantadarśana, 218. anumata, 140. ananta jñāna, 217. anumatityāga, 145 ananta käyas, 132. anumatityāgapratimā, 145. ananta kāyajīva, 131. anumodanā, 109. anantānubandhi, 206, 210, anupadhā, 65. Page #293 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 138 276 Jaina Ethics anupasthāna, 189. apriya, 116 anupasthāpana, 189. Āptamīmāṁsā, 21, 252, 254 . anuprekṣā, 135, 192, 239 apūrvakaraṇa, 210, 216 anusmști, 132. āpya, 67, 81 anutseka, 60. ārādhanā, 250, 253, 255 Anuttara Upapātikadaśā, 234. Ārādhanā, Kathākoșa 249 aņuvrata, 100, 104, 111, 125, Ārādhanāpañjikā, 250 143 Arhadbali, 245, 246 Anuyogadvāra, 231, 239, 240, Ārambha, 109 246 ārambha himsā, 110, 112 Anuyogas, 225, 226, 228, 235 arambhakopadeśa, 128 anyadşștipraśaṁsā, 85 ārambhapravartana, 130 anyaļrştisamstava, 85 ārambhatyāga pratimā, 144 apadhyāna, 128 ärambhavāda, 48 apāna, 40, 50 arcanā, 138 Apabhramśa, 254 arcanāmada, 90 Aparājita, 229 Ardhamāgadhi, 226, 239 Aparājitasūri, 249 ardhaparyankāsana, 197 aparibhāvita, 138 ardhapudgalaparāvarta, 102, aparigraha, 81, 122, 123, 124, 217 156 Arhadbhakti, 61 aparigrhitā, 122 Arhantas, 61, 168, 198, 202, aparigrahītāgamana, 122 208, 239 apātra 137 ārīka, 158 apāyavicayadharmadhyāna, ārjava, 164 199 ārjavam, 102 apkāya, 132 ārta, 167, 169, 171 apkāyika, 45 ārtadhyāna, 128, 194, 195, apramāda, '65 198 apramattasamyata, 207, 215 artha, 5 apratyākhyānakriyā, 58 arthakāmau, 20 apratyākhyānāvarņi kaşāya, arthavinaya, 191 214, 215 Ārya, 233 apratyākhyāna kaṣāya, 214 Aryadeva, 152 apratyāvekṣitāpramārjitādāna. Aryadharmā, 229 niksepa, 136 Āryamangu, 229 apratyāvekşitāpramārjitasam- Āryamamkşu 245 stara, 136 Āryaśyāma, 230 apratyāvekṣitāpramārjitotsarga, Ārya Rakṣita, 230, 239 136 Arya Samāja, 23 Page #294 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Index III asadguṇodbhedana, 60 Aśadhara, 58, 105, 112, 113, 117, 118, 119, 122, 125, 128, 129, 130, 133, 135, 139, 140, 141, 143, 144, 250, 253 asamik syādhikaraṇa, 129 130 āsana, 65, 244 asātā, 59 aṣātāvedaniya, 75 asātāvedaniya karman, 59 asatyamana, 62 asmitā, 54 āśrama, 101, 147 āśrava, 11, 39, 56, 73, 235 aṣṭami, 135 aṣṭanga yoga, 65 aṣṭāngikayoga, 64 Aṣṭasahasrī, 33, 253 aşţ aśati, 252 asteya, 65 ästikya, 89, 90 asatyamṛṣā, 168 asatyāsatya, 116, 117 aśubhaśruti, 128 aśubhopayoga, 75, 76, 77, 78 asūyä, 55 Atharvaveda, 15, 181 atibhāra-vāhana, 124 aticāras, 113, 117, 118, 121, 124, 126, 132, 133, 134, 136, 138, 139, 141, 142, 145, 242, 243 atilobha, 124 atikleśa, 130 atilaulya, 132 atisamgraha, 124 atithisamvibhāga, 125 atithisamvibhāgavrata, 136, 138. 277 atitṛṣā, 132 ativahana, 124 ativismaya, 124 Atmakhyāti, 248 ātman, 36, 40, 43, 79, 98, 133, 159, 198, 206, 223 atmaprasamsā, 60 Atmapravāda, 238 ätura pratyākhyāna, 239 atyanubhava, 132 au dārika, 63 audarika miśra, 63 Aughaniryukti, 231, 238, 240 au pagrähika, 157 Au papātika 236 aupaśa mikasamyaktva, 213 avadhūta, 150 avalis, 213 avamaudarya, 182, 183 avaśa, 166. avasanna, 150 Avaśyaka, 166, 231, 238, 240, 241 Avasyakabhāṣya, 249 avaşyakaniryukti. 246 āvaśyakaparihāņi, 61 avidyā, 54, 93, 95 avikṣitā hāra, 132 avirata 214 avirata samyagdṛṣṭi, 100, 101 aviratasamy agḍṛṣṭi guņasthāṇa, 214 avirati, 13, 62 aviṣāda, 138 avyākṛta, 1, 187 avyakta dosa, 187 ayogakevali guṇasthāna, 218. Ayurveda, 233 ayuṣa, 218 ayuşkarman, 58, 60, 209 Page #295 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 278 Faina Ethics bhavyajiva, 209 Bhāvanädvātrimsikā, 255 bādaradoșa, 186 Bhāva Pāhuda, 93 bādarasāmparāya, 216 bhāvaprāņa, 106 badhikopadeśa, 128 bhāvatirthas, 167 bahirātman, 206 bhāva-Pratikramaņa. 169 Bahubali, 220 Bhāvasaṁgraha, 254, 255 bahūdaka, 150 Bhāvāśrava, 13 bahumānavinaya, 191 Bhāvatirthas, 167 bahuśrutabhakti, 61 Bhāvārthadīpikā, 850 bāhyaparigrha, 46 bhavyas, 209 bakuģa. 150 bhinnamāsa, 188 bāla, 177, 211 bhoga, 59, 131 bālabāla, 177 bhogavirati, 125 Baladeva, 75 bhogopabhogaparimāņavrata, bālapaņạita, 177 130 bālatapa, 60 bhogopabhoga, 125 Banārasīdāsa, 85 bhojanakathā, 62 bandha, 13, 39, 56, 61, 73 bhūtānukampā, 59 Bappadevaguru, 246 bhūta, 15, 19 başar ( Arabic word), 23 Bhūtabali, 245, 246 Baudhāyana, 103 bhūrisūri dosa, 186 Bhadrabāhu, 226, 227, 229, bija, 88 231, 232, 236, 237, 240 Boạikasamgha, 242 Bhadragupta, 229 Bșhadnayacakra, 255 Bhagavati-Ārādhanā, 178, 249, Brhadāranyakopanisad 39, 78 250 brahmacarya, 65, 121, 135, bhaktapāna, 176 144, 239 bhaktaparijña, 239 Brahmadeva, 42 bhaktapratyākhyāna, 178 Brahman, 21, 22, 51, 67, 115, bhakti, 91, 137, 247 129, 223 Bhakti sūtra, 91 Brāhmaṇa, 182 Bhāmatī, 66 Brahmasūtra, 42, 49 Bhāmatī prasthāna, 67 Brahmădvaita, 129 bhārādhikya, 130 Bphatkalpabhāșya, 150, 153, Bharat. 206, 222 174, 241 bhāṣāsamiti, 161 Bțhatkalpa sūtra, 157, 237, bhāşya, 240 246 bhāva, 63, 167 Buddha, 6, 7, 11, 17, 54, 63, bhāva himsā, 106, 107 70, 193. Page #296 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Index III Buddhibalavardhana, 175 Buddhilinga, 229 Buddhism, 207, 208 C caityakarma, 36 Camuṇḍaraya, 118, 120, 121, 130, 133, 134, 138, 253, 255. Candraprajñapti, 235 caraṇakarṇānuyoga, 226 caraṇānuyoga, 205, 226 caritra, 190, 249 căritramoha, 130 caritra mohaniya, Cūrņis, 152, 240 Cürni sutra, 245 cūla, 236 dāna, 59, 60, 102, 125, 137 dāna vidhi, 137 daṇḍa, 157 danapatiśraddhāvṛddhi, 175 dana sambhoga, 176 darśana, 249 darŝana kriya, 57 darśana mohaniya, 58, 93, 94 100, 206 darśanapahuḍa, 84 darśana pratimā, 142, 143 58, 100, darśanasara, 255 darśanavarṇī karmans, 217 darśanavaraṇīya, 58 darśana vinaya, 190 206 Căritra săra, 255 caritra vinaya, 191 Cārvāka, 40, 41, 42, 43, 45, darśana viśuddhi, 61 dāsa, 123 47, 53, 54, 70 Catuḥśaraṇa, 239 caturaṇuka, 48 caturvimśatistava, 166, 228 caturyāma, 103 caturyāmadharma, 102 cauryānandi raudra dhyāna, 195 Chandogyopanisad, 91, 102, 103, 104, 181 channa doșa, 186 cheda, 185, 189 Cheda sutras, 157, 225, 231, 236, 240 chedopasthāpanā, 165 cintămayi, 64 cit, 72 6, 39, cülikäs, 231, 235, 238, 239 D 279 daśākṣaramantra, 201 dasalakṣaṇadharma, 67, 163, Daśaśrutaskandha, 237, 240 Daśavaikālika, 174, 177, 230, 231, 238, 240 Daśavaikālika sūtra, 39, 107, 246, 249 dāsi, 123 dātavya, 137 dātṛ, 137 deśakathā, 62 deśana labdhi, 208 deśāvakāśika, 125 deśāvakāśikavrata, 125, 126, 127, 128 deva, 59, 229 Devāgamastotra, 252 Devagupta 243 Devarddhi gani kṣamāśramaņa, Page #297 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 280 Jaina Ethics 228, 230, 231 118, 130, 138, 142, 150, Devasena 254, 255 156, 171, 225, 226, 227, Devasūri, 243 228, 233, 241, 244, 245, Devavācaka, 239 246, 248, 249 devayāna, 181 Digambarācāryas, 143 Devendra 244 digvrata, 125, 126, 127, 128 Devendrastava, 239 dikṣā, 236 devopāsanā, 65 Dikṣāvidhāna, 242 Dhammapada, 193, 237 dipikī, 232 dhana, 123, diprā, 211 dhanadhānya-pramāṇātikra- dişțivāda, 89 maņa, 123 divābrahma, 142 dhāraṇā 65 divāmaithunavirati, 142, 144 Dharanindra, 222 doșas, 186 Dharasenācārya 245, 246 dravyas, 50, 51, 52, 63, 167, dharma, 1, In, 5, 9, 12, 50, 208 51, 59, 80, 84, 89, 98, 114 dravyahimsā, 106 119, 140, 147, 167, 162, dravya pratikramaņa, 169 168,178, 183 dravyānuyoga, 226 dharmadhyāna, 194, 196, 198, dravyārthika naya, 51 199, 202, 207 dravyatirthas, 167 dharmakāraka, 158 dravyāśrava, 13, dharmāmrta, 253 droha, 55 dharmamokṣau, 20 dụsta-phalānapekṣitā, 138 Dharmaparikṣā 254, 255 destivāda, 227, 233, 235 Dharmaratnaprakaraña 243, duḥśruti, 129 255 dukkha, 7, 59 Dharmasamgraha, 149 dukkha nirodha, 7, 63 Dharmaśāstra, 37 Dukkha nirodhagāmini pratiDharmasena, 227, 229 padā, 7 dharmāstikāya, 72 dukkha samudaya, 7 dharmopadeśa, 192 Duryodhana, 214 Dhavalā 246 duşpakvoşadhi, 133 dhīmada, 90 Dvādaśānuprekşā, 32, 67, 119, Dhștisena, 229 247 Dhruvasena, 229 dvāvimśati-parişahajaya, 67 dhyāna, 65, 184, 193, 194, dveșa, 9, 54, 55 198, 203, 235 dvipādacatuṣpādapramāṇātiDigambara, 100, 104, 117, kramaņa, 124 Page #298 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Index III 281 dvyaņu, 48 granthi, 209 granthibheda, 209, E 212 gphastha, 100, 147 ekabhakta, 151 gļhathāśrama, 101 ekādaśāngadhārī, 229 gļhasthavacana, 153 ekasthāna, 188 Gujarāta, 244 ekatvagamana, 133 Guņadhara, 244, 245 ekatvavitarkavicāra, 203 Gunadhara Saṁgha, 245 eșaņāsamiti, 161, 171. guņavratas, 102 gulikā, 158 guņas, 41, 47, 71 guṇasamkramaņa, 210 gaccha, 242 guņasreņi, 210 gacchācāra, 239 gunasthānas, 92, 165, 202, gaña, 189 205, 207, 208, 210, 212, Gañadhara, 75, 225, 230 213, 215, 216, 217, 246 Gandhiji, 115, 135 Guņasundra, 229 ganitānuyoga, 226 guņavratas, 115, 126, 130 gaộividyā, 239 garhā, 169 guptis, 159, 163, 167, 191 garhaņa, 111 guru, 136, 186 garhita, 116 gurumāsa, 188 gāthā, 29n, 165, 232, 239, 242, gurupūjā, 175 243, 248, 249, 250 gāthā sūtras, 245 Gautama, 229, 233 ghāti Karman, 59, 72 hamsa, 150 Ghātin, 72, 94 Haribhadra Sūri, 236, 238, ghee, 182, 183 241, 242 Ghośānandi kşamāśramaņa, 251 Haribhadra Virahānka, 242, Gītā, 22, 62, 66, 91, 92, 97, 243 102 Harikesin, 148 gitārtha, 153, 154 Hemacandra, 129, 140, 244 gocchaka, 157 Hemcandra Maladhārin, 238 Gommațasāra, 15, 165 hilitavacana, 153 Gosāla, 17 himsā, 106, 110, 123, 133 gotra, 218, 233 himsādāna, 128, 129 gotra Karman, 58, 60 himsanandi, 195 Govardhana, 229 himsāpravartana, 130 gup, 159 H Page #299 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 282 faina Ethics hinādhikamānonmāna, 120 237, 238, 240, 241, 242, 243, Hinayāna, 64 244, 245, 248, 252, 255 Hindu, 147, 171 Jaina ācārya, 13, 38, 78, 109 Hindu dharmaśāstra, 100 112, 152, 158 hiranya, 123 Jaina yoga, 204 hiraṇyasuvarṇapramāṇātikra- Jainedra vyākaraṇa, 252 mana, 123 Jainism, 182, 219, 223 Jambū, 229, Jambūdvipa, 200 Jambūdvipa Prajñapti, 236, ihālokāśaṁsā, 141 240 ilm (Arabic word), 23 Japa, 201 Indranandī, 244, 245, 246, Jarāmaraņa, 54 247 Jāti, 54 indriyajaya, 151 Jātibhavya, 212 ingitamaraṇa, 178 jātimada, 90 irādā (Arabic word,) 23 Jayadhavalā, 245 īrsyā, 55 Jayanandi, 250 īryāpatha, 56 Jayapāla, 229 iryāpathakriyā, 57 Jayasena, 229, 248, 255 iryāsamiti, 160, 161, 186 Jayasenācārya, 106 Islāma (Arabic word), 23 Jina, 32 Isopanişad, 97 Jinabhadra, 238, 240 iştāpūrta, 37 Jinabhadra Ganikşamāśraişțasādhanatājñāna, 66 maņa, 237 işțaviyogaja, 194 Jinabhavanakaraṇavidhi, 242 Istopadeśa, 253 Jinadāsagani Mahattara, 240 Isvara, 21 Jinahaṁsa, 232 Isvarapraņidhāna, 65 Jinapūjā, 136 Jitakalpa, 240 Jinaśataka, 254 Jinasena, 222, 245, 249 jaghanya bahirātman, 207 Jinavijaya kalpa, 253 Jaina, 25, 32, 39, 42, 43, 44, jīva, 13, 39, 44, 45, 64, 168, 56, 72, 118, 127, 135, 145, 213, 223, 236 147, 148, 149, 152, 153, Jivābhigama, 236, 240 154, 156, 158, 163, 165, Jivakalpa, 149, 150, 174. 171, 179, 180, 189, 193, Jivakāņda, 165 220, 222, 224, 225, 226, Jivanmukta, 208, 218 228, 231, 233, 234, 236, Jivānuśāsana, 243 Page #300 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Index III 283 jivātman, 40 182, 183, 191, 209, 210, jivitāśaṁsā, 141 212, 216, 218, 219, 223, Jñāna, 54, 190, 249 226, 235, 236, 245 jñānacetanā, 33, 34 karmānta, 69 Jñānadharmakathā, 251 Karmapravāda, 238 Jňānārņava, 194, 244, 255 karmasiddhānta, 14 Jñānakānda, 97, 147 karmavādins, 28, 29 Jñānapravāda, 245 karmendriya, 48 Jäānasāra, 95 kārmic, 56, 58, 59, 60, 61, 63, jñānāvarṇīya, 58, 93 67, 68, 69, 76, 99 Jñānāvarņiya karman, 94 karaņa labdhi, 209 Jñāna Vinaya, 190, 191 karņas, 209 Jñātādharmakathā, 234 karņānuyoga, 205, 226 jñānedriya, 48 Kartļvāda, 37 jñānī, 94 kartstvabhāvanā, 33, 34 jñānopādhi, 156 karuņā, 90 karuņāpātra, 137 kāryatājñāna, 66 kaṣāya, 13, 56, 57, 62, 123, Kaivalyaprāgbhāra, 207 159, 166, 167, 206 kalām( Arabic word), 23 kaşāvijaya, 38 kalikālasarvajña, 244 Kaşāyaprābhịta, 244, 245 kalpa, 240 kathāprabandha, 176 Kalpasūtra, 237, 249 Kathopanişad, 193 kalyāņaka, 188 Kaulas, 196 kāmabhogativrābhilāșa, 122 Kautkucya, 129, 130 kamalăsana, 197 Kāla, 15, 50, 51, 167 Kamatha, 222 kālaka, 229 Kamsācārya, 230 kālasūkta, 15 kandarpa, 129, 130 kālavinaya, 191 kārita, 109 kālātikrama, 139 karmacetanā, 33, 34 kālikasūtra, 228 Karmagranthas, 210, 212 kāmabhogāśaṁsā, 141 Karmkāņda, 147 kāmaśāstra, 129 karman, 7, 14, 22, 26, 27, 28, Kāmasūtra, 129 29, 30, 31, 33, 34, 35, 36, kāmya, 7 56, 58, 59, 60, 61, 63, kāntā, 211 66, 72, 76, 81, 83, 92, 93, Kāpālikas, 196 94, 95, 96, 102, 106, 114, kāpotika, 158 167, 168, 177, 180, 181, kārita, 140 Page #301 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 284 Faina Ethics kārmāņa, 53, 62, 63 ksetra vāstu pramāņātikrakämyakarma 66 maņa, 123 Kārmāņaśarīra, 44, 53 kşetra vỉddhi, 126 kārmic, 163, 165, 181 kṣīņakaṣāya, 207 Kārtikeya, 125, 129, 136, 142, kşīņakāṣāyachadmastha vita 143, 144, 250, 251, 252 rāga guṇasthāna, 217 Kārtikeyānuprekṣā, 75, 128, kşullaka, 145 207, 250, 251 kulamada, 90 kāyas 23, 107 kumbhaka, 198 kāyaduşpraņidhāna, 134 Kumārapāla, 244 kāyagupti, 159 Kumārilabhatta, 25, 26 kāyakleśa, 183, 184 Kundakirti, 247 kāyasuddhi, 138 Kundakunda, 4, 33, 35, 84, 85, kāyiki kriyā, 57 88, 104, 125, 130, 142, kāyotsarga, 166, 170, 171, 185, 143, 144, 156, 166, 169, 188, 197, 238 246, 247, 248, 249, 250, kevalajñāna, 167 252, 254 kevali, 59, 204, 229 Kundakundapura, 247 keśaluñcana 151 kupātra, 137 khanda, 246 kupya, 123 Kharapaţikās, 115 kupyadhātupramāṇātikrakhimsitavacana, 153 maņa, 124 khola, 154, 158 kuśā, 136 kleśavānijya, 128 kusalābhisandhitā, 138 Kośaka, 158 kuśīla, 150 kriyā, 89 kuțicaka, 150 kriyākalāpa, 247 kūtalekhakarņa, 117 kriyāvādin, 36 kūtalekhakriyā, 117, 118 krodha, 55, 62 kūțasthanityatā, 52 Krşņa, 234 kệta, 109, 140 krtikarma, 176 kṛtti, 158 labdhi, 209 kşamā, 60, 137 labdhis, 208 kşaņikatā, 52 lābha, 59 kşapaka, 217 laghumāsa, 188 kşapakaśreņi, 216, 217 lațaka 129 kşaya, 210, 216 leśyas, 195 kṣāyopaśama, 216,208 linga śarīra, 41 kşetra, 123, 167 lobha, 55, 62 Page #302 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Index III 285 M 83 Lohācārya, 230 mārgaprabhāvanā, 61 lokākāśa, 50, 72 mārutidhāraṇā, 201 luñcana, 145 Mathurā, 227, 228 matsara, 55 mātsarya, 58, 139 maukharya, 129, 130 mada, 54, 129 Māyā, 56, 62 madhyama bahirātman, 207 Māyā kriyā, 158 madhyastha, 90 Meru, 201 Māghanandi, 246, 255 Mimāṁsā, 42, 48, 66, 71, 80, Mahābandha, 245 Mahābhārata, 5, 17, 105, 125, Mimāṁsakas, 43 141, 147, 181, 246 Miśramohanīyakarmas, 214 Mahāgiri, 229 mithyādarśana, 13, 62, 95, Mahānisītha, 236 123 mahāprāņa, 227 mithyā darśana kriyā, 58 mahāpratyākhyāna, 239 mithyadesti gunasthăna, 211 Mahatma Gandhi, 222 mithyā jñāna, 9, 55, 95 mahattattva, 48 mithyopadeśadāna, 117, 118 Mahua, 113 mithyātva, 93, 129, 212, 213 mahāvākya, 67 mithyātva kriyā, 57 mahāvikști, 113 mitrā, 211 Mahāvīra, 17, 103, 104, 105, mitrānurāga, 141, 142 225, 226, 228, 230, 231, moha, 55, 123, 206 233, 237 mohanīya, 158 mahāvrata, 100 mokşa, 39 Maitreyi, 1, 69, 70, 79, 90 Mokşapāhuda, 84 Makkhaligosāla, 17, 18, 232 Mokşaśāstra, 37, 38 Malayagiri, 238, 241 mrga cāritra, 150 Manaḥśuddhi, 138. mặsānandi raudra dhyāna, 195 manana, 64, 67 mşşopadeśa, 117 manas, 44, 55, 62 mudhāsākṣipadokti, 118 Māņdalikas, 43 muhūrtas, 113, 210 manoduṣpraạidhāna, 134 mukhavastrikā, 157 manogupti, 159 mukta, 208 Mantra vidyā, 235 mūla, 185, 189 Manusmrti, 101, 108, 181 Mūlācāra, 84, 100, 150, 153, maraṇasamādhi, 239 156, 166, 167, 170, 171, maraņāśaṁsā, 141, 142 183, 184, 247, 248, 249, mārdava, 164 254 . Page #303 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 286 Jaina Ethics mūlaguņas, 111, 113, 143, 151, Neminathasiddhanta Cakra 189, 248 Mūlārādhanādarpaṇa, 250 Mūlasūtra, 157, 158, 225, 231, 237, 238, 240 mūlavrata, 143 Mundaka, 181 Muni Candra Sūri, 241 Muni Jinavijaya, 243 Muni Śriyaśovijaya, 211 mūrccha, 122, 156 N Naciketas, 79 Nāgahasti, 245 Nagarjuna Sūri, 228 Nāgārjuniya, 230 Nāgasena, 229 Naişkarmyasiddhi, 67 naiṣṭhika, 100 Naiyayikas, 40, 42, 80 nakharadana, 158 nakṣatra, 229 nāma, 167 nāmakarman, 58, 61 naman, 218 nāmarūpa, 54 namostu, 138 Nandi, 231, 239, 240, 241 Nandibhajana, 158 Nandimitra, 229 varti, 42, 85 Nepal, 227 nicaiḥ vṛtti, 60 nidāna, 111, 141, 142 nidanajanita, 194 nididhyāsana, 64, 67 nidrā, 217 nidrānidrā, 215 nigodas, 114 niḥkankṣita, 86, 88 nimantraṇa, 176 nimitta kāraṇa, 19, 32, 35 nindā, 169 ninhava, 58 nirjară, 13, 67, 69, 73, 99 nirupädhitva, 138 nirvāṇa, 26, 70 nirvicikitsā, 86, 88 nirvikṛti, 188 Niryuktis, 152, 157, 231, 232, 238, 240 nisarga, 88 nisarga kriya, 57 niścaya, 160 niscayahimsā, 106, 107 nicayamārga, 75, 248 niscayasamyagdarśana, 84, 93 niścayanaya, 29, 148 niścaya pratikramaņa, 169 nișiddha, 7, 66 Nārada, 6, 91 niṣiddhāhāra, 132 Niśitha, 236, 240 Nāradaparivrājakopaniṣad, 149 Niśithasutra, 153 Nataka samayasāra, 85 navapada-prakaraṇa, 243 naya, 85 nayacakra, 108, 255 Nayanandi, 254 Nemicandra, 243, 250 Nişkāma, 102 nişkāma karma, 81 nişkāmakarmayogi, 61, 92, 102 niśśankita, 86, 88 Nitiväkyāmṛta, 253 nityanaimittika, 7, 55, 66 Page #304 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Index III nivṛttibādara guṇasthāna, 216 niyama, 65, 131 Niyamasāra, 84, 85, 247 paralokāśaṁsā, 141 paramabhakti, 166 166, paramahamsa, 150 niyati, 15 paramasamādhi, 166 paramāņu, 48 nokaṣāyas, 123 nyāsāpahāra, 117, 118 paramāņuvāda, 48 paramātman, 206, 208 Nyaya, 6, 9, 25, 42, 55, 65, parañcika, 189, 190 71, 96 199 paranindā, 60 Nyaya Sutra, 40, 193 Nyaya-Vaiseṣika, 40, 44, 47, 48, 49, 50, 65, 71, 80 P padarthas, 26, 208 pādasthadhyāna, 178 Padmanandi, 247, 255 Padmapurāṇa, 32 pädopagamana, 178 Pähuḍs, 247, 248 paiśunya, 118 Pañcacaritra, 68, 165 pañcamahāvratas, 151 Pañcāśikā, 241 Pancaśikāprakaraṇa Pañcasaṁgraha, 254 pañcasamiti, 151, 167 pancasila, 103 Pañcastikāya, 247, 248 Pañcavastuka, 142 242 pandita, 177 Pandita Asadhara, 111 Pandita Hiralala, 252, 254 Pandita Todaramal, 34 pāṇḍu, 229 pāpa, 12 papopadeśa, 128 parā, 122, 211 parakartṛvāda, 35 paratirthakaraṇa, 158 Pārśva, 222 Pārsvanatha, 103, 104 pārsvastha, 150 parthividhāraṇā, 200 pātrakabandha, 157 pātrakasārika, 157 pātrakasthāpana, 157 paravivekakaraṇa, 122 paravyapadeśa, 139 paribhoga, 130, 131 paribhogavirati, 123 paridevana, 59 parigraha, 122, 123, 129, 156 parigrahatyāgapratimā, 144 parigrahiki kriyā, 58 parihāra, 185, 189, 190 parihāraviśuddhi, 165 parikarma, 235 pariṣaha, 192 pariṣahajaya, 164 paritāpikīkriyā, 57 parivada, 118 Paramātmahood, 198 paruṣavacana, 153 parvan, 145 paryankāsana, 197 paryaya, 35, 51, 52 paryāyārthikanaya, 51 patala, 157 patanjali, 95, 103 287 Page #305 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 288 Jaina Ethics Pātañjala yoga, 197 pramatta, 107 pātra, 137 Prameyakamalamārtaņda, 250 Pațţāvali, 252 pramoda, 90 pavitra dravyasevana 65 praņāma, 138 Pejjadoșa, 245 pranavanamokāramantra, 201 Pejjadosapāhuda, 245 prāņātipā tikikriyā, 57 picchi, 145, 162 prăņāyāma, 65, 197, 198, 204 Piņdaniryukti, 231, 238, 240, prāņihita sādhanā, 65 241 prārambha kriyā, 57 piņdasthadhyāna, 200 praśama, 89, 90 Pindavidhi, 242 praśasti, 246 pippalaka, 158 prathamāņuyoga, 226 pitryāna, 181 pratigraha, 138, 144 porisi, 150 pratikramaņa, 166, 169, 170, Prabhava, 229 185, 187, 238 prabhā, 211 pratimā, 110, 137, 142, 143, Prabhācandra, 247, 250 144, 145, 237 Prabhākara, 66 pratisthāpana samiti, 162 prabhāvanā, 87, 88 Pratişthāsāra samgraha, 254 prābhịtatraya, 248 pratișthāvidhi, 242 pracalā, 217 pratyākhyānāvaraṇa kaşāya, pracatãpracata, 215 215 pradhāna, 47 Pratyākhyānavidhi, 242 pradeśa, 51 pratyakșa, 19 pradoșa, 58 pratyāyikī kriyā, 57 pradoșikikriyā, 57 pratyāhāra, 65, 198, 224 prajñā, 64 pratyākhyāna, 166, 170, 238 Prakīrṇas, 231, 238, 239 Pratyākhyānapūrva, 238 Prākṣta, 241, 247 pravacanabhakti, 61 Prākṣtapatļāvali, 245, 246 pravacanamātņkā, 159 prakști, 13, 47, 48, 49, 51, 54, Pravacanasāra, 247, 248 64, 71 Pravacanasāroddhāra, 149, praksti-vikști, 48 175, 243 pramatta samyata guṇasthāna, pravịtti, 65 215 prāyaścitta, 155, 166, 174, pramattayoga, 119 185, 186, 187, 236, 237, pramāda, 13, 15, 62, 106, 207 242 pramādācarita, 128, 129 Prāyaśchittasamuccaya, 187 pramādacaryā, 128 prayoga kriyā, 57 pramāņa, 85, 199 prayoga labdhi, 209 Page #306 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Index III 289 prcchanā, 192 43, 44, 48, 55, 66, 71 preşya prayoga, 127 Puspadant, 245 preșyatyāga, 145 Puspamitra, 230 preyas, 4, 78, 79 puțaka, 158 prītiyoga, 138 proşadhopavāsa, 125, 136, 143 proșadhopavāsavrata, 135, 136 proșadhapratimā, 143 qudra, (Arabic word) 23 Prosthila, 229 Praína-vyākaraṇa, 235 R Praśnopanişad, 181 pệthagjana, 207 rāga, 54, 55, 129, 139 přthakatyayitarkasavicāra, 202, rahobhyākhyāna, 117, 118 203 rasa parityāga, 182, 183, prthvikāya, 132 rasaghāta, 210 pệthvīkāyika, 45 Ratnakarandaśrāvakācāra, pudgala, 50, 76 128, 131, 252, 253 pudgalaprakṣepa, 127 ratnatraya, 159 Pūjāvidhi, 242 raudra-dhyāna, 128, 167, 169, Pujyapāda, 5, 89, 107, 120, 171, 194, 195, 196 128, 129, 135, 136, 139, rājamāsa, 113 141, 183, 196, 247, 249, rajas, 8, 47 250, 251, 252 rājasika, 181 Pulāka, 150 Rājāvali kathe, 249 punya, 12 Rāja vārtika, 107, 163, 251 Purāņas, 147 rajoharaṇa, 162 purāņa Kāśyapa, 232 rajastrāņa, 157 pūraka, 198 Rājyakathā, 62 Pūrņa Kaśyapa, 17, 18 Rāșțrakūța, 245 pārņimā, 135 Ratnamālā, 249 purumaņdala, 188 Ratnasekhara, 244 purușa, 13, 15, 21, 48, 49, 51, rātribhuktivirati, 142 54, 64, 71 recaka, 198 puruṣārtha, 32, 34, 35, 63 Reyatimitra, 229 puruşārthasiddhyupāya , 115, Rgveda, 78, 119 254, 255 Rgvedic, 119 pūrva, 202, 225, 227, 233, 235, Rşabhadeva, 148 245 Pūryamīmāṁsā, 1, 5, 7, 9, 41, sta 119 Pūrvāgata, 235 stu, 144 rșis, 181 Page #307 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 290 Jaina Ethics rüpa, 70 sam, 160 rūpānupāta, 127 samācāri, 242 rūpātīta, 200, 202 samādāna kriyā, 57 samadhi, 64, 65 samādhija nyaniscaya, 64 samādhimaraņa, 168, 178 Sabdākulita dosa, 186 samājaśāstra, 69 śabdānupāta, 127 Šāmakunda, 246 saccitta, 132, 133 samārambha, 109 saccittāhāra, 139 Samantabhadra. 12, 21, 32. sacittaniksepa, 139 88, 118, 119, 121, 125, 126, sacittāpidhāna, 139 128, 130, 132, 133, 136, sacittasambandhāhāra, 133 138, 139, 140, 141, 142, sacittasamiśrāhāra, 133 143, 144, 184, 246, 249, sacittatyāga, 143 251, 252, 253 Sadāśiva, 42 samantāpatana kriyā, 57 şadāvaśyaka, 151 samavasarana, 176 şadāyatana, 54 samaśakta, 150 sadguṇācchādana, 60 Samavāyānga, 232, 233 sādhanā, 205, 224 samaya 51, 98, 216, 217, 218 şadītis, 8 Samayasāra, 88, 147, 149, 247, sādhu, 135, 139, 149, 150, 227, 248 239 Samayasāra kalaśa, 248 sādhudharma, 242 Samaya Sundara gaņi, 241 sādhupratimā, 242 Sāmāyika, 125, 133, 134, 135, sādhusamādhi, 61 136, 143, 166, 167, 188, 238 Sāgaradharmāmộta, 253 sămāyika cāritra, 165 sagaropamakoţākați, 233 Sāmāyikapātha, 255 sahasābhyākhyāna, 117 sāmāyikavrata, 133, 134 saikşyabahumāna, 175 sambhoga, 176 śaileśīkaraṇa, 218 sambandākṣepa, 25 sakāramantrabheda, 117, 118 Sambhūtivijaya, 229 sakti, 137 saṁgha, 59, 150, 174, 175, śaktimada, 90 189, 190, 192, 226, 227, śaktitastapas, 61 245 saktitasatyāga, 61 samitis, 152, 160, 163, 191 sallekhanā, 125, 139, 140, 141, sañjñā, 70 142, 177, 178, 242 samjvalana, 215 sallekhanāvrata, 139, 141, 151 samkalpa, 64 sam, (Arabic word), 23, samkalpahiṁsā, 110 Page #308 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Index III Samkhya, 6, 7, 8, 9, 13, 36, 41, 42, 43, 44, 47, 48, 49, 51, 54, 64, 71, 80, 83, 94, 95, 96, 97 Samkhyatattvakaumudi, 24 Sāmkhyakārikā, 24 Samkhya-yoga, 44, 64, 80 samkṣepa, 89 sāmparāyika, 56 saṁsāra, 10 samsaraprāgbhāra, 207 Sanat kumāra, 6 Saṇḍilya, 91 sandhyā, 66 Sanghadāsa Gaṇī, 240 śankā, 85 Sankara, 52, 66, 81, 91 Sankarabhāṣya, 66 Sankarācārya, 42 Santicandra, 241 Säntisuri, 241, 243 Santoșa, 65 samskāra, 63, 70 sarāga samyama, 60 Sarvadarśanasaṁgraha, 11, 20 samskarya, 67 Samskṛta, 27, 241, 248, 250, Sarvārthasiddhi, 107, 247, 251, 255 samsaya, 62 samstaraka, 239 samsthāna vicaya dharma dhyāna, 199, 200 samucchinnakriyā, 204 samucchinna kriyātipāti, 218 samudghāta, 203, 204, 218 samvara, 13, 39, 64, 67, 73, 79, 163, 180, 235 Samavāyānga, 232, 233 samvega, 61, 89, 90 samyaktva, 84, 86, 206, 242 253 śastrakośa, 158 213 samyogaḥ eṣām, 15 246, 247 sätvika, 80 satva, 47 samyaktva kriyā, 57 Samyaktvasaptati, 242 samyagdarśana, 84, 85, 86, 213, satya, 65, 158. satyam, 115 satyamana, 62 satyapravāda, 238 satyāsatya, 116 satya vacana, 103 91, 92, 93, 137, 142 samyagdṛṣṭi, 64, 92, 97, 212, sauca, 60, 68, 164 224 samyama, 39 śaucopadhi, 157 sāvadya, 116 savipāka-nirjarā, 180 291. sāsvādanasamyagdṛṣṭi gun sthāna, 213 sat, 49, 51, 72 sātā, 59 Satapatha, 119 sātāvedaniya, 59, 60, 75 satkāryavāda, 48 ṣatkhaṇḍāgama, 181, 242, 245, samyamāsaṁyama, 60 samyagamithyādṛṣṭiguṇasthāna, asayogakevaliguṇasthāna, 217 Sayyambhava, 229, 231, 238 Sayyāsana, 123 Page #309 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Jaina Ethics Shri Premi, 255 śrama, 180 Siddhārtha, 229 śramaņa, 1 04, 105, 106, 107, Siddhas, 26, 88, 168, 198, 201, 108, 180 202, 208, 239 śramaņa bhūtapratimā, 100 siddhasena, 121, 139 śrāvaka, 100, 102, 130, 142, Siddhasena Ganin, 118, 120, 143, 144, 145, 147, 168, 121, 122, 132 215, 224 Sidhasena Sūri, 244 śravakācāra 25, 100, 254, 255 siddhasilā, 200 śrāvaka dharma, 140, 242 sikkaka, 158 Srāvakadharmavidhi, 242 śikṣāvratas, 102, 125, 130, 131, Śrāvakaprajñpti, 241, 251, 253 133, 143, 243, 251 śravaņa, 64, 67 sila, 64 Śravaņa belgolā, 249 Silāngavidhi, 242 śreņīs, 216 Śīlānka, 10, 36, 232 śreyas, 4, 78, 79 Silānkasūri, 240 Sri Candra, 250 Simhanandi 252 Śrīgupta, 229 Sisyahitā, 238 Śri Hansa Vijaya ji Mahārāja, silavratas, 125 242 silavrateșvanaticāra, 61 Sri Vijayodayā, 249 Śiva bhūti, 93, 249 śrotriya, 229 Śivājīlāla, 250 śrotāpanna, 207 Śivakoți, 191, 249, 252 śruta, 59 Sivārya, 250, 253, 255 śrutakhanda, 235 Skandila Sūri, 227, 228, 229, Śrutamayi, 64 230 Śrutasāgara, 247, 248, 251 Ślokavārtika, 25, 251 Śrutaskandha, 231, 232 Smști, 1, 65 Śrutāvatāra, 244, 245 smộtyantardhāna, 126 Stavavidhi, 242 smrtyanupasthāna, 135, 136 stenaprayoga, 120 snāna, 65 sthāna, 232 śoka, 59 Sthanānga, 150, 182, 232, 233 Somadeva, 89, 116, 117, 118, sthānāngasūtra, 148 120, 121, 129, 132, 142, 143, Sthānāngațīkā, 246 144 sthāpana, 167 sparsa, 54 sthavira, 152, 239 sparśana kriyā, 57 Sthūlabhadra, 227, 229 sprhā, 55 sthavirakalpa, 149, 150 śraddhā, 91 sthira, 211 śraddhāna, 185, 190 sthirikaraņa, 87, 88 Page #310 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Index III Sthitasthitavidhi, 242 sthitighāta, 210 strikathā, 62 styānagṛddhi, 215 Subhacandra, 197, 198, 201, 202, 203, 244, 251, 255 Subhadra, 230 Subhāṣitaratnasandoha, 254 subhopayoga, 45, 75, 76, 77, 78 sūcī, 158 Sudarsana carita, 254, 255 Suhastin, 229 sukhānubandha, 141, 142 Sukhasana, 197 Sukladhyāna, 167, 171, 194, 196, 197, 202, 207, 218 sūkṣmadoṣa, 186 sūkṣmakriyānivṛtti, 218 sūkṣma samparāya 216, 217 sūkṣmasāmparāya caritra, 165 Šūnyavādins, 36 sūkṣma kriyā pratipatti, 203 Sureśvarācārya, 66, 67 Suryaprajñapti, 235 sūtra, 88, 163, 170, 171, 182, 228, 232, 233, 235, 237, 239, 251, 252 Sūtrakṛtānga, 15, 18, 19, 23, 36, 232, 240 sūtrārthasthirikaraṇa, 174 sūtrasambhoga, 176 Suttanipata, 237 svädhyāya 65, 184, 192 svahasta kriya, 57 svakartṛvāda, 35 Svāmikārtikeya, 84, 126, 129, 131, 133, 142 Śvetambara, 100, 128, 130, 132, 138, 139, 142, 145, 149, 151, 156, 157, 225, 226, 227, 228, 230, 241, 243, 249, 251 Svetambara ācārya, 251 Śvetāmbara agama, 246 Śvetāśvataropaniṣad, 193 svopajña, 244 syādvāda, 15 293 T suvarņa, 123 svabhāva, 15 svabhāvavādin, 16 svadāra, 121 svadāramantrabheda, 117, 118 Tattvajñānavikāsinī, 244 svadārasantoșa, 122 tattvamasi, 67 tadāhṛtādāna, 120 tadubhaya, 185, 187 tadubhaya vinaya, 191 tamas, 47 Tandulamatsya, 30 Tandulavaicărika, 239 tanmātrās, 48 tantras, 95 tapas, 59, 65, 95, 102, 180, 181, 182, 183, 184, 185, 249 14, tapaścaryă, 164 tapomada, 90 tapovidhi, 242 tapovinaya, 191 tatsevita doșa, 187 Tattvadīpikā, 248 Tattva dipikā vṛtti, 248 tattvajñāna, 65, 66, 80, 83, 96 Page #311 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 294 tattvarūpavatīdhāraṇā, 201 tattvas, 199, 235, Tattvārthabhāṣya, 138 Tattvärthasutra, 72, 85, 96, 107, 125, 129, 130, 132, 135, 136, 141, 154, 155, 163, 185, 193, 194, 199, 241, 242, 243, 249, 251, 252, 253, 254 tālikā, 158 tāmasika, 187 tāpanāt, 95 tārā, 211 tejaskāyika, 45 tiryagdikpramāṇātikramaṇa, 126 tiryagvāņijya, 128 ṭīkā, 232, 235, 238, 240, 250 țippaņi, 250 Tirthankaras, 26, 61, 75, 92, 103, 165, 167, 168, 169, 170, 194, 234, 239 trividhatapa, 64 triratna, 63 tṛṣṇā, 54, 55 tṛṣā, 152 trasareņuka, 48 trigupti, 67 154 tubaravṛkṣagutikā, Tumbulūrācārya, 246 turiyātīta, 150 tuști, 137 U Ubhayamana, 62 uccāsana, 138 uddeśas, 236 uddiṣṭatyāga, 145 Udumbara, 111, 112, 113, 142 Udyamihimsā, 110 Udyapana, 140 Umāsvāmi, 251, 252 Umāsväti, 85, 106, 142, 181, 241, 242, 243, 250, 251 upabhoga, 59, 130, 131 upabhogadhikya, 129, 130 upabṛmhana, 87, 88 upacāra, 190 upacāra vinaya, 191, 192 upadeśa, 88 upaguhana, 87 upaghata, 58 upakaraṇa, 188 upalakṣaṇa, 163 Jaina Ethics Upangas, 241 Upanisad, 6, 28, 39, 53, 54, 70, 78, 79, 81, 119 Upāsakācāra, 255 Upāsakādhyayana, 253 Upāsakapratimāvidhi, 242 upaśama, 210 upaśamaka, 217 upaśāntamohaniya guņasthāna, 217 upasthapana, 185 upavāsa, 188 upaviṣṭopaviṣṭa, 171 Upādāna, 54 upādānakāraṇa, 19, 32, 35 upādhāna vinaya, 191 upādhisambhoga, 176 upādhyāya, 111, 192, 236 upangas, 225, 231, 235, 236 Upāsakadaśānga, 102, 117, 118, 128, 141, 142 Upasakādhyayana, 234 upāsanā, 56 upaviṣṭotthita, 171 ūrdhvadikpramäṇātikramaṇa, 126 Page #312 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Index III 295 utkęsta bahirātman, 207 Vārtānīti, 129 utpādanadoşa, 173 vāruņi dhāraṇā, 201 utpādya, 67, 81 Vātsyāyana, 41 utsarga samiti, 162 vasikaranatantra, 129 utsāha, 181 Vāstu, 123 Uttarādhyayana, 10, 93, 104, Vastusvabhāva, 12 156, 166, 181, 231, 237, Vāsudeva, 75 240 Vasunandi, 85, 125, 126, 133, uttaraguņa, 177 135, 137, 139, 141, 142, utthitanivista, 171 143, 144, 253, 254 utthitotthita, 171 Vațagrāmapura, 245 Uvaggahiya, 157 vātsalya, 87, 88 Vațţakera, 248, 250 Vațţikeri 248 vedaniya, 58, 59, 218 vācanā, 192 vedaniya karman, 59 vacanaśuddhi, 138 vaijukāyika, 45 Vācaspati Miśra, 66, 67 Vedānta, 6, 9, 38, 41, 42, 44, vadha, 59 47, 49, 52, 55, 56, 64, 66, vāgdușpraņidhāna, 134 72, 81, 83, 91, 95, 96, 97, vāggupti, 159 147, 218, 223, 224 Vaikālika, 240 Vedanā, 54, 70 vaikriyaka 63 Vedanājanita 194 väikriyakamiśra, 63 Vedāntin, 51 Vaiseșika, 6, 9, 48, 49, 65, 80, Vedas, 1, 5, 6, 7, 66, 96, 97 147 Vaiseșika Sūtra, 40 vibhūtimada, 90 vaiyyāvștyakaraņa, 61 Vibhūtiśrīdhara, 247 vaiyyāvștya 92, 136, 176, 184, vicikitsā 55, 85 187 vidāraṇa kriyā, 57 Vajrāsana, 197 vidhi, 27 vāk, 64 Vidyādhara, 75 Valabhi, 228 Vidyānanda, 253 vanaspatikāyika, 45 Vidyānandi, 96, 249, 251 vañcanăpravartana, 130 Vijaya, 229 vandanā, 166, 168, 238 Vijaya Vimala, 241 Vandanāvidhi, 242 vijñāna, 54, 70, 137 • vānaprastha, 100 vikārya, 81 vardhna, 158 Vikrama Samvat 251, 253, 254, vargas, 234, 235 255 on Page #313 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 296 vikṛti, 47 vinaya, 62, 175, 184, 190, 191, 192 vinaya sampannatā, 61 Vipākasūtra, 235 Vira Nirvāṇa Samvat 227, 228, 235 vipaka vicaya dharma dhyana vyavahārapratikramaņa, 169 199 vyavahārasamyagdarśana, 84 viparīta, 62 viparyaya, 54 Virabhadra, 239 vyasanas, 143 vyavaśamita vacana, 153 vyuparatakriyānivṛtti, 203 vyutsarga, 184, 188, 193 Viracandra Sūri, 243 Virakathā, 129 vīrāsana, 197, 246 virasena, 246 virodhi himsā, 110 viruddharājyätikrama, 120 virya, 59 viryam, 18, 64 Viśākhācārya, 229 visaṁvāda, 61 viṣayānandi raudra dhyāna, 195 Vişayavisatonupekṣā, 132 Viseṣāvaśyakabhāṣya, 238, 240 Viṣṇu, 229 vistāra, 89 viśuddhi labdhi, 208 vivaraṇaprasthāna, 67 vivartavāda, 49 viveka, 185, 187 vivekakhyāti, 64 viviktaśayyāsana, 183, 184 vrata, 64, 125, 126, 127, 132, 136, 140, 143, 163 vratapratima, 143 vratas, 242, 243 vṛtti, 127, 233, 234, 235 vṛtti parisankhyāna, 182, 183 vratyānukampā, 60 Vyakhyāprajñapti, 233, 240 vyañjana vinaya, 19, 191 Vyasabhāṣya, 64 vyavahāra, 160, 236, 240 Vyavahārabhāṣya, 241 vyavahāramarga, 74 vyavahāranaya, 29, 148 Y yaddṛṣṭa, 186 yadṛccha, 15, 19 yajña, 28 Jaina Ethics Yajnavalkya, 70, 78 yama, 64, 65, 79, 103, 104, 131 yantra, 95 Yapaniya samgha, 249 Yaśobahu, 230 Yasobhadra, 229, 250 Yaśovijaya, 241, 244 yathākhyātacāritra, 165 yathāpravṛttikaraṇa, 209, 210 yati dharma, 147 Yativṛṣabha, 245 Yātrāvidhi, 242 Yoga, 6, 8, 9, 13, 60, 62, 63, 64, 80, 95, 202, 203, 204, 207, 218 Yogacara, 47 Yogānuśāsana, 250 Yogaśāstra, 244 Yogasūtra, 8, 54, 55, 64, 103, 104, 193 yogavakratā, 61 Yogavatāradvātrimŝikā, 211 Yogindu, 250 Yuktyanusāsana, 252 Page #314 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 17 : ::: : ਤਰਨ ਤt u9 n