Book Title: Truthfullness and Truth in Jaina Philosophy
Author(s): Peter Flugel
Publisher: ZZ_Anusandhan
Catalog link: https://jainqq.org/explore/269136/1

JAIN EDUCATION INTERNATIONAL FOR PRIVATE AND PERSONAL USE ONLY
Page #1 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Truthfulness and Truth in Jaina Philosophy Peter Flugel* Truthfulness and truth are not clearly distinguished in Jaina scriptures. A maxim of speaking the truth is stated in the so-called "satya-mahavrata", which Jain ascetics recite twice a day during their obligatory pratikramana ritual. In accordance with the preferred Jain method of negative determination, the general principle of truthful speech is treated in terms of its characteristic violations, aticara, that is, as the opposite of speaking non-truth, a-satya.' Normative principles such as this are constitutive for Jain discourse to the extent that they are used by speech communities, both to generate and to interpret speech. The precise implications of the maxim of truthfulness for language usage are specified in form of a distinction of four types or 'species of speech, bhasa-jaya , which are at the centre of the Jain theory of discourse, supplemented by context-sensitive rules for proper ways of speaking, and examples. These analytical categories should be known and utilised by mendicants (ideally by all Jains) to prevent both the preparation and performance of violence, arambha. The rules and clauses for language usage expressed by the bhasa-jata tetrad consider speech primarily from a normative point of view, rather than from the perspective of the intention of the speaker. In this respect, the analysis of the uses of language in the Jaina scriptures shares many characteristics with the approach of universal pragmatics in contemporary * This article is a slightly amended extract of a chapter of my essay 'Power and Insight in Jaina Discourse', published in Logic and Belief in Indian Philosophy, ed. Piotr BALCEROWICZ, 85-217. Warsaw: Oriental Institute (Warsaw Indological Studies, Vol. 3) / Delhi: Motilal Banarsidas, 2010. It is republished here, with permission of the editor, as an offering in memory of Muni Jambuvijayaji. Page #2 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 philosophy:2 'A mendicant should know that there are four kinds of speech: The first is truth; the second is untruth; the third is truth mixed with untruth; what is neither truth, nor untruth, nor truth mixed with untruth, that is the fourth kind of speech: neither truth nor untruth' (Ayara 2.4.1.4).3 167 Notably, the same scheme of four modes is applied to speech and to cognition (mana ) or knowledge (nana ) (Viy 622b/8.7.1b, 874b/15.1.4). Hence, the four bhasa-guttis , or controls of speech, and the four mana-guttis , or controls of the inner sense, are both characterised by the same terms in Utt 24.19-23. The four modes, thus, represent general attitudes towards truth, both in mind and in speech: 1. sacca Page #3 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 168 anusandhAna 50 (2) According to Pann 860 (255b), the first two modes are distinct (pajjattiya ) ways of speaking, whose validity or non-validity is indeterminable. The sub-categories of distinct speech are true speech (satya bhasa) and wrong or false speech (mrsa bhasa), and the sub-categories of indistinct speech are true-as-well-as-false speech (satya-mrsa bhasa) and neither-true-nor-false speech (asatya-mssa bhasa). A muni should use only the first and the last mode of speech, and avoid the remaining two by all means' (DVS, 7.1) in order to minimise harm: A monk or a nun, considering well, should use true and accurate speech, or speech which is neither truth nor untruth (i.e. injunctions); for such speech is not sinful, blameable, rough, stinging, &c.' (Ayara 2.4.1.7). (a) Speaking truthfully can either be interpreted ethically, as straightforward and accurate talk (on-record), or ontologically, as an assertion of the way things are. Both perspectives can be found in the Jain and non-Jain commentary literature alike, 10 often mixed together, as the identical characterisation of the four guptis of mind and speech illustrates. Satya bhasa refers both to the psychological and the normative conditions of truthfulness, that is, sincere, grammatically accurate and contextually acceptable speech, and to propositional truth." It is explicitly recognised in the Jain scriptures (though not in these terms) that, as a speech act, propositional language has also an expressive and normative content. The normative, the expressive, and the propositional components of spoken language are altogether necessary to communicate something. Pann 862 states that 'the truth or validity of the speech depends on various situations and conditions' (MALVANIYA 1971: 325). Ten different dimensions or 'validity conditions of truthful Page #4 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 169 speech are distinguished12 (the compound "sacca Form 6. paducca-sacca ) of canonical hermeneutics (AnD 75), especially by the method of contextual interpretation (anugama ) through progressive specification via fixed standpoints (naya) (AnD 601-606).15 The occurrence of the terms nama, sthapana and bhava indicates the deliberate incorporation of a variant of the 'canonical' nikkheva , as BHATT (1978: xv, 20) suggested, although the davva standpoint is missing. 16 A niksepa is a scholastic scheme which delineates fixed perspectives for the analysis of the principal dimensions of the possible contextual meanings of a word (contemporary linguistics is still struggling to establish comparable categories). The original purpose of the list of ten, as a whole, may have been similar. That is, assessing the meaning of an utterance from several commonly relevant perspectives. 17 25 D: SHEELANUSANDHAN ANU-50 Page #5 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 170 anusandhAna 50 (2) 19 Most categories are self-explanatory. Truthful utterances based on the linguistic conventions of a country are explained by the commentaries through the example that 'in Konkan piccam is said for payas and that by the gopala the lotus is called aravinda only' (SCHUBRING 2000: 157 n. 4, SS 74). Because terms such as these are synonyms, they are all equally true.18 Similarly, what is accepted by many people, i.e. linguistic expressions, is conventionally true (sammata-satya).19 Pragmatic theories of truth would fall under this perspective. A figurative representation, such as a statue which is not god itself, may itself not be accurate, but that what it symbolises can be recognized as true (sthapana-satya).20 The same applies to a name such as Devadatta or 'given by god' (nama-satya) (MAC 113).21 Allusions to external appearance in form of prototypes such as 'white cranes' (not all cranes are white) are examples of rupa-satya.22 According to the commentators Haribhadra (PannV) and Malayagiri (PannT), the term pratitya-satya designates an utterance which is true only under certain conditions, and thus predicated on empirical confirmation.23 Examples are relative size ('this is long') or the relative state of transformation of objects at a given time (cf. MAc 114).24 Like other conventional expressions which, under certain conditions, could equally be classified as 'truth-mixed-withuntruth', common or idiomatic utterances such as 'the kura (i.e. the cooked rice) is cooking' (MAc 114) are acceptable as customarily true (vyavahara-satya). 25 The Svetambara commentators explain the inner truth (bhava-satya) expressed by certain utterances with the example of a 'white crane' (sukla balaka), which MAC 113 uses to illustrate rupa-satya, whereas Vattakera interprets the term as designating the 'higher truth', i.e. saying something untrue in order to avoid injury to someone (MAc 116). This perspective is also applied to other contexts in the Svetambara texts Ayara 2.4.1.6 and DVS 7.11. An example of truth based on association with practice (yogasatya) is to describe someone according to his / her activity, Page #6 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 171 for instance the designation chattri (a ksatriya who should protect his realm performs chattra-yoga), or dandi (who performs danda-yoga or punishment).27 Instead of yoga-satya, the Mulacara 115 has sambhavana-satya, which means that assuming the possibility of something is a valid condition of truthful language: 'If he wanted, he could do it. If Indra wanted, he could overturn the Jambudvipa' (OKUDA 1975: 128). As an example of speaking the truth, using comparison or analogy (aupamya-satya),28 MAC 116 mentions the word palidovama < palyopama>, literally like a sack of corn', which designates a high number.29 Anuogaddaraim (AGD) 368-382 demonstrates the practical 'usefulness' of this simile through the naya method of progressive disambiguation.30 (b) Untruthful language or speaking untruthfully (mrsa bhasa) is the proscribed opposite of truth or truthfulness.31 In contrast to the ten conditions of truth, featuring the semantics of propositional utterances, the ten conditions out of which untruth 'arises' (compound: "nissiya ), listed in Pann 863, are primarily psycho-physical conditions.32 According to SCHUBRING (2000: 157, SS 69), 'speech springing from emotion is by itself understood as mosa.deg33 Eight of the ten categories overlap with the standard Jain list of the eighteen sources of sin (pava-thana ),34 starting with the four passions (kasaya ), and attachment and aversion, which in the Pann are the sole cause of karmic bondage, disregarding yoga, or activity (MALVANIYA 1971: 384). Most types of untrue speech, conditioned by these factors, can be categorised as expressive utterances. The last two categories, akhyayika-nihssita's and upaghata-nihsrita,36 do not refer merely to an underlying negative psycho-physical state in general, but to the unspecified psycho-physical conditions of two specific types of self-referentially defined commonly untrue speech actshearsay and false accusation--with predominately constantive and regulative attributes. 26 D:\SHEELANUSANDHANVANU-50 Page #7 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 172 31LHEITA 40 (?) Fear 1. koha-nissiya Anger 2. mana-nissiya Pride 3. maya-nissiya Deceit 4. lobha-nissiya Greed 5. pejja-nissiya Attachment 6. dosa-nissiya Aversion 7. hasa-nissiya Ridicule 8. bhaya-nissiya 9. akkhaiya-nissiya Hearsay 10.uvaghaya-nissiya False Accusation CAILLAT (1991: 11) observed that the Pann presents the kasayas as the cause of untruth, not of injury, as in Ayara 2.4.1.1 and DVS 7.11. This change of perspective, from ahinsa to "satya as the main criterion, may reflect the shift of emphasis in classical Jain karman theory from act to intention. The ten categories seem to have in common that they refer to acts which, intentionally or unintentionally, produce unwholesome perlocutionary effects in the addressee (and the speaker as well). They are either factually false, ethically wrong or both.37 (g) The category 'partially true speech?38 or "truthmixed-with-untruth' (sacca-mosa bhasa ) should not be mixed up with the conditionally true standpoints of syad-vada, which apply only to valid statements, not to false knowledge (apramana). "Truth-mixed-with-untruth' designates intentionally or unintentionally ambiguous or unclear speech, which is strictly prohibited.39 The meaning of the term is explained by DVS 7.4-10: 4. But this and that topic which confines the Eternal within limits--this half-true speech the wise [monk] should avoid. 5. By a speech which is untrue, though its appearance is that of a true one, a man is touched by sin, how much more a man who speaks plain untruth!' (DVS, Page #8 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 173 7.4). 40 Satya-mrsa bhasa is sinful language, based on the whole on non-universalisable ethical principles. For instance, the language of heretical forest-monks, who do not abstain from killing, whose thought, speech and behaviour is not well controlled: 'They employ speech that is true and untrue at the same time: "do not beat me, beat others; do not abuse me, abuse others; do not capture me, capture others; do not torment me, torment others; do not deprive me of life, deprive others of life" (Suy 2.2.21). The ten types of truth-mixed-with-untruth listed in Pann 86541 do not explicitly address expressive or regulative aspects of speech acts, but only propositional content; despite the fact that performatives can also be both true and untrue. According to the commentaries, all types deal with indiscriminate speech, and with semantic and logical fallacies, such as category mistakes regarding the quality or quantity of objects or temporal modalities which can be easily 'mixed up' (compound: "missiya ), for instance in utterances designating part-whole relationships. 1. uppanna-missiya Born 2. vigaya-missiya Destroyed 3. uppanna-vigaya-missiya Born-Destroyed 4. jiva-missiya Life 5. ajiva-missiya Matter 6. jivajiva-missiya Life-Matter 7. ananta-missiya Infinite 8. paritta-missiya Separate 9. addha-missiya Time 10. addhaddha-missiya Halftime The list of ten modalities evidently reflects general issues of 27 D:SHEELANUSANDHAN ANU-50 Page #9 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 174 anusandhAna 50 (2) particular concern for Jain doctrine. It can be thematically subdivided in two triplets and two pairs. The first tripletutpanna, vigata, utpanna-vigata_addresses unclear distinctions concerning life and death. The commentators explain the meaning of utpanna-misrita as speaking in non-specific ways about the born, mixed with references to the yet unborn; for instance birth occurring in this or that village or town, that ten or more or less boys were born ('ten boys were born in this village today') etc.42 In the same way, vigata-misrita refers to cases of 'stating mortality in an indefinite way, e.g. saying that ten people have died in this village, etc.' (RATNACANDRA 1988 IV: 400).43 Utpanna-vigata-misrita refers to both true and false, or contradictory assertions (visamvada) regarding manifestations of both birth and death.44 The second triplet - jiva, ajiva, jivajiva--similarly addresses the problem of pointing in a general way to 'great numbers? of either living or dead beings, or quantities of mixed living and dead beings.45 Life (jiva) in abstract and concrete form can be confused through vague language, such as the language of sets (rasi), or other numerical expressions. The same applies to matter (ajiva), and both life and matter (jivajiva). The consequence of imprecise language may be unintentional violence against individual living beings (in a 'heap of dead beings'). According to Avassaya-nijjutti (AvNi 8.56-100), one of the principal heretics of the canonical period, Rohagutta, committed the mistake of mixing up categories by positing a third principle, no-jiva or the half-living, which mediates between jiva and ajiva. Hence, his heresy was called terasiya.46 The pair ananta and parita addresses indiscriminate language regarding aspects of finite-infinite, part-whole, or singular termexistence relationships. The commentaries explain ananta-misrita with reference to the case of certain plants, for instance root vegetables such as radish (mulaka), which have only one body, yet are composed of an infinite number of souls (anantajiva).47 The category parita-misrita focuses, conversely, for Page #10 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 175 instance on the independence and separateness of each individual element within a composite form of vegetation.48 The two ontological levels of the relationship between one and many can easily be mixed up in these cases; which has potential ethical (karmic) consequences. One of the principle concerns of the Pannavana, highlighted in Malayagiri's commentary, is the difference between the categories infinite (ananta) and uncountable (asamkhyata).49 With regard to adhva, time, speech is both true and untrue if one says, for some reason, that "it is night during the daytime, or 'get up, it is day' when it is night. 50 The same applies to the part of a measure of time, or ardhadhva, such as a prahara, a quarter of the bright or dark period of the day. 51 The statements may be true in as much as time in general is concerned, but false with regard to time in particular (i.e. it may be bright, although technically it is still night). 52 Examples for a potential mix up of the modalities of time, which may have negative moral consequences in cases of promises for instance, are given in Ayara 2.4.2, and in DVS 7.6-10 as paradigmatic cases for satya-mrsa speech. The illocutionary form of these sentences is not essential, since they can be transformed into propositions of the form: 'x promises (commands etc.), that p':53 6. Such speech therefore, as e.g. "we [shall] go", "we shall say", "we shall have to do that", or: "I shall do that", or "he shall do that", 7. uncertain in the future or with regard to a matter of the present [or] of the past, a wise [monk] should avoid. 8.9. If [a monk] does not know, [or] has some doubt about, a matter which concerns past, present and future, he should not say: "it is thus"; 10. (this he should do only) when there is no room for doubt' (DVS. 7.6-10).54 Somadeva, in his Yasastilaka of 959 CE (YT, p. 349- 350), mentions a similar example of a statement which is on the whole true but to some extent false, that is, when someone 28 D:\SHEELANUSANDHANIANU-50 Page #11 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 176 31LHEITA 40 (?) 'after promising to give something at the end of a fortnight, gives it after a month or a year' (HANDIQUI 1968: 265). He also mentions the statement 'he cooks food or weaves clothes as one which is to some extent true but on the whole false because 'properly speaking, one cooks rice etc. and weaves yarn'. A different example of mixed speech, mentioned in Viy 18.7.1 (749a), are utterances of someone who is possessed. The fact that this case, referring to an existentially mixed psycho-physical state rather than to semantic ambiguity, cannot be easily fitted into any of the ten categories illustrates that the list is not exhaustive. From other viewpoints, the examples may also fit the categories of the other lists. All of the ten enumerated modalities seem to refer to utterances in which the universal and the particular, or modalities of time, quantifiers, or other categories,55 are mixed up in an indiscriminate and hence ambiguous way.56 Though the mistakes discussed in the texts seem to be primarily based on indiscriminate cognition, producing objectionable uncertainty (cf. Ayara 2.4.1-2), the ten categories are very broad and can cover a great variety of motives, logical and semantic conundrums, such as vagueness or paradoxes, and linguistic forms and discursive strategies, such as off-record uses of metaphor, similes, veiled speech and politeness, which GRICE (1975) and BROWN-LEVINSON (1978) have analysed as popular forms for saying one thing and meaning another. 57 These phenomena deserve more detailed analysis in future studies. For the purpose of this essay, a few comparative notes on the implications of the findings for the question of the stance of Jain philosophy on the law of non-contradiction must suffice. For PRIEST-ROUTLEY (1989: 3), 'admission or insistence, that some statement is both true and false, in a context where not everything is accepted or some things are rejected, is a sure sign of a paraconsistent approach--in fact Page #12 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 177 a dialethic approach', i.e. the assumption that 'the world is inconsistent'. The Greek word dialetheia (two-way truth) refers to a true contradiction facing both truth and falsity.58 PRIESTROUTLEY (1983: 17) were the first to point out parallels between Jaina logic and modern discussive logic, but argue, like most logicians before them, that Jain perspectivism is predicated on the rejection of the law of contradiction.59 However, GANERI (2002: 274) demonstrated in his reconstruction of the assumptions underlying the method of seven-fold predication (sapta-bhangi), based on an extension of discussive logic via modalised many-valued truth-tables, that Jain logic 'does not involve any radical departure from classical logic ... The underlying logic within each standpoint is classical, and it is further assumed that each standpoint or participant is internally consistent.' The findings of BALCEROWICZ (2003: 64) on the contextual logic of the seven nayas concur with this general conclusion. Both authors show that Jain logic is context-sensitive and a quasi-functional system. To syad-vada and anekanta-vada the Jain catus-koti of the modes of speech can be added, as another example of Jain logic' which clearly operates within the confines of the law of non-contradiction, and does not need to be interpreted as a form of scepticism, nor of syncretism predicated on the notion of a total truth integration of all viewpoints, as MATILAL (1981) argues. Our brief glance at the Jain interpretation of the third mode of the so-called 'four-valued logic of the catus-koti, applied to language usage, that is, the explicit exclusion of the values 'false' and both true and false', showed that Jain logic' does not 'flatly deny'60 the law of non-contradiction. The examples in Jain scriptures for modes of speech which are both-true-and-false, and their explicit rejection, demonstrate, on the contrary, that Jain philosophy is unequivocally opposed to violations of the law of non 29 D: SHEELANUSANDHAN ANU-50 Page #13 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 178 anusandhAna 50 (2) contradiction. This conclusion is also borne out by the Jain analysis of the temporal aspects of action (Viy 1.1.1=13a, 9.33.2d = 484a), which explicitly denies the possibility that an action that is being performed is not equal to the completed action, as the heretic Jamali held ('has the bed been made or is it being made'). The question of the identity of an action in time has important consequence for the evaluation of karmic consequences, also of speech-acts. Contrary to PRIESTROUTLEY's (1989) intuitions, it seems, the main technique of argumentation used by Jain philosophers in all these cases resembles Aristotle's refutation of Heraclitus and other 'paraconsistent' thinkers in ancient Greece: *Key parts of his analysis involved the use of time to avoid contradiction instead of saying that a changing thing was both in a given state and also not in that state, it was said that the thing was in that state at time tl, but not in that state at a different time t2-- and the theory of potentiality-required to reunify these now temporarily isolated states as parts of the one (and same) change. The appeal to different temporal quantifiers illustrated the method of (alleged) equivocation used since ancient times to avoid contradiction and reinforce consistency hypothesis; namely, where both A and - A appear to hold, find a respect or factor or difference r such that it can be said that A holds in respect rl and - A in respect r2. It can then be said that a contradiction resulted only by equivocation on respect or factor r. Often however the method of alleged equivocation does not work in a convincing way, and it breaks down in an irreparable way with the semantic paradoxes, as the Megarians were the first to realize' (PRIEST-ROUTLEY 1989: 8). Speech that is both-true-and-untrue is rejected in the Jain scriptures, because it mixes aspects which can be Page #14 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 discriminated, if necessary with the help of the method of perspective variation in time. To what extent ancient Jain philosophers would have agreed with Aristotle on this point is a question which can only be clearly answered in a separate study. It seems to me that the Jain theory of time is fundamental, also for Jain perspectivism. (d) The most interesting of the four modes of speech (and cognition) is 'speaking neither truth nor untruth' (asaccamosa). That is, speech to which the true false distinction is not applicable. Twelve types of the asatya-mrsa bhasa are distinguished in Pann 866 Viy 10.3.3 (499b):61 1. amantani 2. anavani 6. paccakkhani 7. icchanuloma 9. abhiggahiya 10. samsaya-karani 179 Address Order Request Question Communication Renunciation Consent Unintelligible Intelligible Doubt-Creating Explicit Implicit Nine of the twelve categories are also listed in Mac 5.118-119. The categories 1-7 are identical in both texts. Of the last five, only samsaya (No. 10) is mentioned by Vattakera, and a category labelled anakkhara , 'incomprehensible', which can be read as an equivalent of anabhiggahiya Page #15 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 180 anusandhAna 50 (2) great variety of listed speech acts (only the first three are injunctions), it seems better to use AUSTIN's (1962) term 'performatives', which are by definition neither true nor false, to characterise the first seven terms.64 The last five terms cover aspects which GRICE (1975) discussed under the conversational maxims of relation (relevance') and manner ('avoid obscurity'). In Austin's terminology, addressing, ordering, requesting, and questioning etc. are all illocutionary acts. Questions,65 commands, and exclamations are not propositions, since they can not be asserted or denied; that is, they are neither true nor false. Imperatives (directives), such as orders and requests, and regulatives (commissives), such as consenting and renouncing (promising, vowing etc.), through which the speaker commits him / herself to perform certain actions in future, imply normative conditions which ought to be fulfilled, but which are not fulfilled yet. In this sense, the propositional content is also neither true nor false. Truth, and its opposite, falsity, are properties that belong only to propositions. Propositions are statements that either assert or deny that something is the case. Not all sentences are true or false, because not all sentences make such claims. Commands, questions, and expressions of volition neither assert nor deny that something is the case, and are, consequently, neither true nor false. ARISTOTLE (PH 4) already noted that 'every sentence is not a proposition; only such are propositions as have in them either truth or falsity. Thus a prayer is a sentence, but is neither true nor false.' Problems related to the ontological and truth-functional status of future events and the grammatical future were also discussed in Greek philosophy, which may or may not have influenced Indian philosophy in this point.6274 In De Interpretatione (PH), ARISTOTLE offers the following solution to a paradox posed by Diodoros Cronus as to the truth-value of the sentence 'Will there be a sea battle Page #16 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 181 tomorrow?' Any definite answer ('yes' or 'no') to this indecidable question is presently neither true nor false, but if in future one becomes true, then the other becomes false: 'One of the two propositions in such instances must be true and the other false, but we cannot say determinately that this or that is false, but must leave the alternative undecided. One may indeed be more likely to be true than the other, but it cannot be either actually true or actually false. It is therefore plain that it is not necessary that of an affirmation and a denial one should be true and the other false. For in the case of that which exists potentially, but not actually, the rule which applies to that which exists actually does not hold good' (PH 9). For Aristotle, as for the Jains, it is both unethical and factually wrong to assume the future is determined, since actions evidently influence events. Although it is not entirely clear what exactly Aristotle and the Jain author(s) had in mind, in both cases the commitment to free will and to the logic of events overrules the logic of propositions. Generally, empirical facts can neither be proven true nor false by logical necessity: 'Even if I say "It's raining now" when the sun is shining, I have not said something that is necessarily false, just something that happens to be false' (HARNAD 1999: 1).67 From a purely logical point of view, Bertrand RUSSELL (1905) showed that all predicates with variables are not propositions to which a truth value can be attached in an unambiguous way. Hence they are neither true nor false. However, they can be transformed into propositions by replacing the variable with a value or a quantifier.68 It is, of course, difficult to say to what extent ancient Jain philosophers already shared certain intuitions with modern logicians. The first seven categories, sometimes combined, cover most speech acts a Jain ascetic would conventionally use in 31 D:\SHEELANUSANDHAN ANU-50 Page #17 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 182 31LHITE 40 (2) contexts of monastic life;69 for instance taking vows (paccakkhana), requesting permission (apucchana), ordering (ajna), confessing (alocana), begging forgiveness (ksamapana) etc. Amantani speech or language, for instance, is 'used for attracting somebody's attention, a vocative word or expression (GHATAGE 2003 III.2: 1001), for instance 'O Devadatta!'70 MALVANIYA (1971: 325) gives the following examples of an address and an order: 'when a person wanting John to come near him says "O! John", or 'when a person says to another person, "Go ahead". However, not in all contexts are such expressions neither-true-nor-false. Under certain circumstances, the first example may represent or can be read as an 'indirect' or 'implicit performative speech act clad in form of an address, and it could be argued that, in certain contexts, the second example does not correspond to the prescription in Ayara 2.4 for mendicants to avoid pragmatic interventions. The last five terms of the list are of a different nature. The term anabhiggahiya refers to 'unintelligible or incomprehensible speech' (RATNACANDRA 1988 1: 156), which is either 'irrelevant' (DELEU (1970: 169) or/ and 'unacceptable' (GHATAGE 1996 I: 237), but neither-true-norfalse. Its antonym, abhiggahammi boddhavva, intelligible instruction, refers to 'clear and intelligible language (RATNACANDRA 1988 IV: 351), which is relevant and 'acceptable', and neither-true-nor-false.71 Malayagiri's commentary72 explains the difference between irrelevant and relevant speech through the following example: 'to the question "What shall I do now?" the answer "Do as you like" is anabhiggahiya, the answer "Do this, do not that!" is abhiggahiya (DELEU 1970: 169). It is not entirely clear why samsaya-karani bhasa , ambiguous language which causes doubt' (RATNACANDRA 1988 IV: 570), is regarded as Page #18 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 183 neither-true-nor-false, and therefore permissible. It must be assumed that only the use of strategically ambiguous messages for the purpose of creating vairagya-shocks is seen as legitimate, but not language which creates doubt about Jainism in the minds of believers. He seems to follow Malayagiri (PannT), who argued that from the niscaya-naya not only satya-mrsa but also asatya-mrsa statements are false if they are spoken with the intention of deceiving others' (MALVANIYA 1971: 346). However, Viy 18.7.1 (749a) states that, by definition, the speech of a Kevalin, because it is harmless, can only be true or neither-true-nor false.73 The statement associates higher moral truth with this type of speech, which can thus be compared with the 'twilight-language' (sandha-bhasa) of Tantric Buddhism, which is also characterised as neither-true-nor-false.74 Jambuvijaya's edition of the Thana 4.23 (238) contains the following commentary of According to OKUDA (1975: 129), MAC 119 explains samsaya-vayani as 'speech which expresses doubt'. But its commentator Vasunandin (11th-12th century) interprets this as 'speech of children and old people' as well as the sounds of (five-sensed) 'roaring buffalos' etc., which cause doubt as to their meaning, while the Digambara authors Aparajita and Asadhara and the Svetambara Haribhadra commenting on DVS 7, read samsayakarani simply as 'ambiguous speech' (anekartha-sadharana). Haribhadra classifies speech of children as anakkhara , incomprehensible, which also figures as the ninth and last category listed in MAC 119, which Vasunandin reserves for expressions of animals of two-four senses, and for sounds created by snipping fingers etc. (OKUDA 1975: 129).75 Vyakrta bhasa refers to clear distinct speech with explicit unambiguous meaning (RATNACANDRA 1988 IV: 511).76 There is no example given by the commentaries for distinct speech which is neither-true-nor-untrue. Avyakrta-bhasa, refers to indistinct involuted or poetic speech consisting of obscure 32 D:\SHEELVANUSANDHAN\ANU-50 Page #19 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 184 anusandhAna 50 (2) or unintelligible words 'with deep and profound meaning' (RATNACANDRA 1988 IV: 445; cf. GHATAGE 2001 II: 800)." Mantras or sutras may be fitting examples. The fact that the Mulacara does not mention these two categories reinforces the suspicion that they are redundant, and overlapping with the category of incomprehensible language. The most interesting case is pannavani-bhasa as 'we will lie down' and 'we shall lie down' respectively, that is, as the description of a future action or state.79 MALVANIYA (1971: 211), who points to kindred views in the Pali text Puggala-pannatti, prefers the word 'describing' as a translation of pannavani which he renders as 'speech that intends to describe a thing'. In this, he follows the 13th century commentary of Acarya Malayagiri who stated that pannavani 'means the speech that intends to describe the thing (or event) [as it is]'.80 It is a form of asaccamosa speech, 'a speech which has nothing to do with norm (validity or invalidity) but which only describes the thing (or event)': 'To be more explicit, the speech which has nothing to do with religious dos and do-nots but which simply describes Page #20 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 185 the thing is called Prajnapani.deg81 MALVANIYA (1971: 212) cites the example quoted by the commentator Malayagiri's Prajnapana-tika, "Those who refrain from killing living beings live long and enjoy good health (in the next birth)',82 and notes: "The gatha in point contains no command "do not kill" but simply describes the fact that those who do not kill live long and remain healthy. Such speech 'has nothing to do with religious dos and do-nots' (MALVANIYA 1971: 211). Hence, it should be distinguished from implicit performative speech. But, of course, it may be interpreted as such by a listener who infers an 'ought from the 'is'. MONIERWILLIAMS' (1986: 659) Sanskrit - English Dictionary translates the causative prajnapana as 'statement, assertion'. LALWANI (1985 IV: 133) apparently follows the Illustrated Ardhamagadhi Dictionary of RATNACANDRA (1988 III: 443), based on Malayagiri, in using the word "advice' (upadesa).83 What is probably meant by the term pannavani is that from the conventional point if view, which underlies the Jain "catuskoti of language usage, the testimony of an authoritative person is neither true nor untrue, because its meaning may be incomprehensible for a hearer, similarly to unintelligible utterances of non-enlightened creatures. With imperatives and addresses expressing universal truths or ideals has in common that no referent exists in re at a given place and point of time (as for instance in Malayagiri's example which should not be read as a prediction relating to a specific individual). The multidimensional implications of a general statement or rule such as this cannot be understood entirely in an instant, as WITTGENSTEIN (1953: 53-55, $ 138 40) noted in his remarks on the relation between meaning and use of a word (ib., pp. 190 ff., SS 138 f.). Moreover, the example given by the commentaries concerning the necessary link between nonviolence and health cannot be proved or disproved from a conventional perspective. It must be accepted on the basis of the authority of the speaker. Interestingly enough, the two 33 D:SHEELANUSANDHAN ANU-50 Page #21 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 186 31LHETA 40 () truth theory is not invoked by the commentaries in defence of the concept of transcendental speech, being neither-true-norfalse, in spite of its capability to immunise any statement against criticism. 84 Pann 832-857 gives another example for speech which is neither-true-nor-false by discussing the question of the 'congruity of grammatical and natural gender and number' (SCHUBRING 2000 SS 74: 158). It argues that words such as go, cow, which express (genderless) universals but are employed in masculine singular, are not false or both-trueand-false, say, with regard to female cows, but neither-truenor-false. The same applies to imperatives (ajnapani), since 'we may order a person of any gender and this person may or may not carry out our orders' (MALVANIYA 1971: 326).85 The last of the four variants of oharani-bhasa ), in which case they are true by definition, harm religion (virahiya Page #22 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 187 will count for nothing (Pannav. 268a)' (SCHUBRING 2000 SS 74: 158). Conversely, as mentioned before, 'a mode of speech springing from emotion is by itself understood as mosa' (SCHUBRING (2000 SS 74: 157). In other words, the speaker's state of mind, his/her beliefs, attitudes or intentions (if not his/her Being), and the specific pragmatic context is decisive, not the words themselves, or their propositional meaning. Arguments relating to the 'higher truth' of morality based on similar considerations. HANDIQUI (1968: 266) notes that the 10th century Digambara acarya Somadeva is more concerned with ethics than with propositional truth: 'Somadeva appears in certain circumstances to attach greater importance to self-preservation and philanthropic considerations than to speaking the truth. He opines that the truth must not be spoken if it is likely to endanger others and bring inevitable ruin to oneself.' Another example of this attitude is given by the Svetambara Acarya Hemacandra who, in his 12th century Yogasastra (Ys 2.61) and self-commentary, narrates that the sage Kausika, who was famous for speaking the truth, 'went to hell because accurate information given by him led to the capture and killing of a band of robbers' (cited by HANDIQUI 1968: 266 n. 4): 'On the other hand (api), even though a statement may be true, it should not be spoken if it causes affliction to others [This is] because, even if it is accepted [by all the people] in the world, Kausika was sent to hell [on account of making such a statement]' (YS 2.61).88 The explanations of the four modes of speech in canonical Jain literature and its medieval Sanskrit commentaries 34 D:\SHEELVANUSANDHANIANU-50 Page #23 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 188 311HETTA 40 () show that they are conceived as meta-rules, on a level of abstraction comparable to the discourse ethics of universal pragmatics, while the sub-categories and examples correspond to the level of empirical semantics and pragmatics. The levels of abstraction of the lists of examples in the commentaries vary, since the Jain lists are relatively unsystematic, although some may have been intended as scholastic devices for cumulative indexication qua fixed analytical perspectives. From the point of view of comparative analytical philosophy, some examples could serve as illustrations for one or other of the conversational postulates a la Grice (be relevant etc.), Searle, or Habermas, while others can be related to the modern logical investigations of vagueness, category mistakes, quantifiers, or modalities of time in particular. In contrast to modern intentionalist semantics, Jain philosophers of language analyse examples of their four fundamental types of speech rarely with reference to the intention of the speaker, but prefer an objective or listener's standpoint. That is, they investigate the structure of the utterance as a whole, from the de-contextualised point of view of the four combinations of the basic true / false distinction, seen from the perspective of discourse ethics. The same perspective is preferred by universal pragmatics. We can conclude from this brief discussion of the explanations of the four modes of speech in the Svetambara canon and the commentaries that the rules of Jain discourse are less concerned with referential truth than with the pragmatics of speech;89 in particular with the expression of the higher truth' of religious insight gained through direct self experience, and speaking in accordance with the ethics of non-violence. Yet, it would be a mistake to assume that truth in Jain discourse is always defined as an aspect of objective illocutionary force, depending on the form of the utterance and the intentional state of a speaker alone, without the need to be backed up by argument in processes of critical inquiry. The primacy of Page #24 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 189 pragmatic ethical and moral considerations, though considered from a monological perspective, makes the Jain theory of speech in many ways akin to universal pragmatics. It is apparent that, albeit unsystematically presented, for almost all universal pragmatic principles and conversational postulates there are functional equivalences amongst the Jain principles and rules of speech, which are by no means "primitive and 'ill-assorted', as for instance the philologist SCHUBRING (2000 SS 74: 157) believed. Jain principles and rules of discourse are not mere examples of a culture-specific 'particularistic ethics', as LAIDLAW (1995: 14) argues, but form a comparatively systematic code which is well-grounded in objective considerations' (CAILLAT 1991: 14). The analysis of the implications of the Jain maxim of truth and the general rules for proper language usage shows that the 'universal validity claims': propositional truth, normative rightness, and truthfulness are important considerations of Jain discourse ethics. Despite the primacy of non-violence and sincerity of expression, there are numerous examples for rules concerning referential truth, the ideal of univocal or straight (rju) speech, and the avoidance of deception, especially Ayara 2.4.1.1, Ayara 2.4.2.19, and DVS 8.46.90 Such rules of avoidance of false representations (including false reference to past, present and future) and non-deceptive speech etc., can be understood as expressions of a pragmatic anti-illusionist (anti-Brahmanic) realism, that is, as anti-deception strategies. Although, the Jaina texts deliberately avoid defining certain words as 'sacred', for Jainism, too, 'correct speech is of religious value' (CAILLAT 1984: 71) in so far as the foremost requirement for the realisation of Jain norms is restraint (negative politeness) in mind, speech and action. The norms of unequivocal and grammatically correct signification and transmission of information are fundamental for the Jain understanding of proper language use. The religious ideal of 35 D:SHEELANUSANDHAN ANU-50 Page #25 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 190 31LHEITA 40 (?) correct, truthful and non-violent manner of speech is summarised in the following passage, already quoted above: A monk or nun, putting aside wrath, pride, deceit, and greed, considering well, speaking with precision, what one has heard, not too quick, with discrimination, should employ language in moderation and restraint (Ayar 2.4.2.19).91 What is manifest in this statement is that the Jain maxims themselves address the necessity of avoiding the violence and the consequential karmic results of 'flouting' the rules of proper speech by means of off-record strategies. At the same time, negative politeness (especially conventional indirectness) is regarded as mandatory for maintaining the vows of nonviolence and truth in language usage. Recommended speechstrategies are usually forms of negative politeness, such as conventional indirectness, impersonalisation or nominalisation.92 Impersonalisation by way of transforming directives and commissives into assertives, that is, a second-person performative perspective into a third-person observer's perspective, is the preferred method; evidently, because in this way 'illocutionary force switches over into the propositional content and thereby loses, if not its meaning, at least its force' (HABERMAS 1993: 27).93 For instance, one should not say "this should be done', but this is'. And one should not speak about forbidden subjects, such as business-choices etc., at all. One should not ask householders to do something, or 'forecast, or make promises to them (DVS, 7.46 f.; 51). Thus, although the Jain analysis of language usuage is essentially pragmatist, its rules of proper speech are predicated on the denial of pragmatic intent in favour of propositional statements whose pragmatic implications are, if at all, to be worked out by the listener, in a Gricean fashion: 'Guessing the teachers thought and the purport of his words, one should express one's assent, and execute Page #26 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 191 (what he desires to be done). An excellent pupil needs no express directions, or he is (at least) quickly directed; he always carries out his duties as he is told' (Utt 1.43 f.) The running comparison between the theory of communicative action and Jain discourse ethics revealed significant similarities. Both approaches are rule-oriented, not goal oriented. That is, they are concerned with the general interest of many, not with the eudaemonic perspective of a single actor, despite the fact that the methods of universalisation are different. The respective ideals of consensus and nonviolence leading to liberation mutually implicate each other. Basic non-violence is presupposed by communicative action, and the general interest of all is presupposed by universal non-violence. Though the criterion of generalisability, equal interest, is not theorized in Jain philosophy, and only touched upon with reference to specific negative rights such as the privileged case of the universal interest in avoiding pain,94 the scope of the moral universe is extended from humanity to all living beings, whose essential spiritual equality is a fundamental principle of Jaina philosophy. The vanishing points of both theories, the ideal consensus of an infinite community of interpretation and the ideal omniscient observer, presuppose absolute knowledge and absolute consensus. Yet, there are also significant differences. The main difference between the transcendental pragmatics of mutual recognition and the monadological Jain ethics of non-violence concerns the nature of the fundamental principles. The former is predicated on positive norms and the latter on norms of prohibition. The implicit method of universalisation of Jain ethics is the double negation, that is, the negation of nongeneralisable statements. The resulting priority of physical nonaction as a theoretical limiting case (not as a practical maxim) unburdens the doctrine of discussions of specific dilemmas of 36 D:\SHEELVANUSANDHANIANU-50 Page #27 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ anusandhAna 50 (2) norm application, thus safeguarding both generalisability and contextual determinateness, while maintaining a perspective of disengagement with the world and non-specific positive duties. The second main difference between the two types of discourse ethics concerns the moral division of labour presupposed by Jain norms of discourse, which privileges institutionally verified competent speakers or apta. In contrast to universal pragmatics, Jain discourse ethics is not concerned with questions of human justice, but with the negative freedom of the individual. Footnotes 1 The earliest formulations of this maxim in the Agamas use the expression musa-vaya veramanam (S. mrsa-vada viramana), cessation of telling lies. Like SCHUBRING (2000 SS 171: 301), BRUHN (2003: 8) notes: 'The concept of "truth" is not uniform. But there are several references to the kasaya.s as the root of undesirable speech". 192 2 This approach, which informs the following analysys, goes back to Peirce, Royce and Mead, and was further developed by APEL (1973) and HABERMAS (1980). The principal analytical question is not: What does it mean to understand an intention? But: What does it mean to understand a speech act? Universal pragmatics focuses not only on speech acts but on the normative presuppositions of linguistically mediated interaction' and on the social function of speech for the coordination of action. Building upon the work of analytical philosophers such as WITTGENSTEIN (1953), AUSTIN (1962), GRICE (1975), SEARLE (1969) and sociolinguists such as GUMPERZ (1964) and HYMES (1972), HABERMAS (1980) distinguishes three universal validity claims presupposed by every communicative action: 'truth', 'rightness' and 'truthfulness'. 3 Ayara 2.4.1.4: aha bhikkhu janejja cattari bhasa-jayaim, tam jaha saccam egam padhamam bhasa-jayam, biyam mosam, taiyam saccamosam, jam n'eva saccam n'eva mosam n'eva sacca-mosam-asaccamosam nama tam cauttham bhasa-jayam. CAILLAT (1991: 8 n.4) located the following parallels to the above sutra in the Svetambara canon: Utt 24.20-23, Thana 4.23 (238), Viy 13.7.1a (621a-b), Pannavana 11 (860866). See also Viy 16.2.2b (701a), 18.7.1 (749a), 19.8 (770b), Samavaya 13.1, and DVS 7.1-3. OHIRA (1994: 14, 155) is of the opinion that the Page #28 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 four modes were first taught at the time of DVS 7, which she dates between 5th-4th century BCE. 193 4 In contrast to the debate on the use of the catus-koti in 'Buddhist logic', focusing largely on the 'negative dialectic' of Nagarjuna, the cited Jain cases indicate that the catus-koti was used (at least by Jains) from early on as a scholastic frame for the discussion of logical alternatives, without specific doctrinal implications being connected with the frame itself. MURTI (1955: 129) noted early on: 'Four alternative views are possible on any subject'. Notably, the four alternatives in Ayara 2.4.1.4 etc., are disjunctive, not additive, as stereotypical representations of 'Jaina Logic' generally assume. Because Jain usage of catus-kotis was ignored, and because of the almost exclusive focus on Nagarjuna, Buddhist scholars compared the 'four-cornered negation' only with the 'Jain relativism' in general. They derived the catus-koti either speculatively from Jain syad-vada (GUNARATNE 1980: 232) or vice versa (BAHM 1957: 128), or (and) contrasted it with 'the relativistic logic proposed by the Jains, to which Buddhism was opposed' (JAYATILLEKE 1967: 82). According to RAJU (1954), the mythical Sanjaya framed the four alternatives already in the 7th century BCE, negating all of them, whereas 'Jaina logicians saw a relative truth in each pole and thus adopted a more positive and determinate attitude toward our cognitions of the world." For recent, less logocentric, views on Nagarjuna, focusing on 'skillful means', see for instance JONES (1978), SCHROEDER (2000). A similar four-valued theory of truth was defended by the Megarians (PRIESTROUTLEY 1989: 13), which demonstrates that no specific philosophical position is associated with the form itself, only with its uses. 5 See DUNDAS (2007: 50 f.) on the analogy between four types of armies and four types of ascetics in Thana 292 (4.280-1). ALSDORF (1966: 186 f., cf. 190 f.) discussed a different type of catur-bhangas in Jaina literature, made up of combinations of two positive and two negative possibilities. He pointed out that the use of the 'fourfold combination' is 'very typical of the scholastic who never misses an opportunity to make a "caturbhanga", i.e. the four possible combinations of two positive and two negative possibilities...' (p. 186). Thana 3.239 offers also a trilemma: (1) to state the truth (tavvayana ), (2) to state the untruth (tadannavayana ), (3) to state something meaningless or negative (no-avayana ); Thana 7.129 a heptalemma: (1) speech (alava ), (2) 37 D:\SHEELVANUSANDHANIANU-50 Page #29 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 194 anusandhAna 50 (2) taciturnity (analava ), (3) flattery (ullava ), (4) insult (an-ullava ), (5) dialogue (samlava ), (6) prattle (palava ), (7) contradiction (vi-ppalava ). 7 The differentiation between the True (sacca) and the Wrong (mosa)' was characterised as 'primitive' by SCHUBRING (2000 SS 74: 157). I do not give the original wording in all cases. In different words, the same teaching is expressed in DVS, 7.1-3, which may be the oldest text concerning this subject: caunham khalu bhasanam parisamkhaya pannavam / donham tu vinayam sikkhe, do na bhasejja savvaso || 1 || ja ya sacca avattavva saccamosa ya ja musa / ja ya buddhehi 'nainna, na tam bhasejja pannavam // 2 // a-sacca-mosam saccam ca anavajjam akakkasam/ samuppeham asamdiddham giram bhasejja pannavam // 3 // [1] Of the four kinds of speech, the thoughtful [monk] should, after consideration, learn the training in two, [but] should not use the other two ones at any occasion. [2] That [form of speech] which is true, [but] not to be uttered, that which is halftrue, that which is [quite] untrue and which is not practised by the Jinas, the thoughtful monk should not use. [3] [But] he should, after deliberation, use a speech not exposed to doubt, [a speech] which is neither true nor untrue and [a speech] which is true, provided that it is not to be blamed [and] rough' (SCHUBRING 1932: 101). See Ayara 2.4.8-11 and cf. DVS 7.11, 7.2 for examples. "Cf. HABERMAS' (1980: 419 ff.)/(1984-1987 I: 312 ff.) defence of his clear-cut distinction between claims to truth and claims to truthfulness. 10 Mookerjee, in TULSI (1985: 107): 'Truthfulness is the revelation of truth. (Gloss) Truth means the straight-forwardness [rjuta] in deed (physical movement), intention and word, and non-discrepant behaviour. The revelation (disclosure) of that truth is called truthfulness.' '(Note) Here "truth", as an ethical principle, is defined and explained. Umasvati Page #30 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 195 [Tattvartha-bhasya 7.9], however has included revelation of ontological reality also as an aspect of truthfulness.' 11 Thana 308 (4.349) gives the niksepa of satya: name, object, knowledge, knowledge and action according to truth. Thana 254 (4.102) distinguishes four types (aspects) of truth defined in terms of unequivocality or sincerity (ujjuyaya Page #31 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 196 anusandhAna 50 (2) aravimdam eva pamkajam iti. 20 PannU 81: sthapana-satyam nama aksara-mudra-vinyasadisu yatha masako'yam karsapano'yam satam idam sahasram idam iti. 21 PannU 81: nama-satyam nama kulama-varddhayann api kulavarddhana ity ucyate dhanam avarddhamano 'pi dhana-varddhana ity ucyate, apaksas tu paksa iti. 22 PannU 81: rupa-satyam nama tad-gunasya tatha rupa-dharanam rupa-satyam, yatha prapancayateh pravrajita-rupa-dharanam iti. Pann?, 257a: yatha dambhato grhita-pravrajitarupan pravrajito 'yam iti. 23 OKUDA (1975: 127) translates pratitya-satya as 'relative truth'. 24 PannU 81: pratitya-satyam nama yatha anamikaya dirghatvam hrasvatvam ceti, tatha hi tasyanamta-parinamasya dravyasya tat tatsahakari-karana-sannidhanena tat tad-rupam abhivyajyata iti satyata. PannT, 257a uses the expression pratitya-asritya, recourse to confirmation. PanV 11.17 gives the synonym apeksa, consideration or regard. 25 PannU 81: vyavahara-satyam nama dahyate girih galati bhajanam anudara kanya aloma ediketi, giri-gata-trnadi-dahe loke vyavaharah pravarttate, tathodake ca galati sati, tatha sambhoga-jivaprabhavodarabhave ca sati, lavana-yogya-lomabhave ceti. 26 PannU 81: bhava-satyam nama sukla balaka, saty api pamcavarna-sambhave. 27 PannU 81: yoga-satyam nama chattra-yogac chattri danda-yogad dandity evam adi. 28 Cf. UPADHYAYA (1987: 105-7) on Hemacandra's examples of upacara, secondary meaning of a word based on similarity. 29 PannU 81: upamaya satyam nama samudravat talagam. 30 The problem of the vagueness of the concept of 'heaps' is also addressed in the so-called sorites paradoxes attributed to Eubilides. 31 Thana 254 (4.102) distinguishes four types (aspects) of untruth defined in terms of equivocality or insincerity (anujjuyata Page #32 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 197 are linked. See also HYMES (1972: 283) notion of communicative competence: "The specification of ability for use as part of competence allows for the role of non-cognitive factors, such as motivation, as partly determining competence. In speaking of competence, it is especially important not to separate cognitive from affective and volitive factors, so far as the impact of the theory on educational practice is concerned; but also with regard to speech design and explanation.' 33 Arguably, conditions such as anger and pride can also evoke (painfully) true statements. 34 Viy 1.9.1 (95a). 35 Following Haribhadra (PannU 82: akhyayika asambhavyabhidhanam) and Malayagiri (Pann?, 258b.9: akhyayika-nihsrta yat-kathasvasambhavyabhidhanam), akkhaiya is usually understood as a narrative (katha) of something non-existing or impossible, based on mere 'legend' or hearsay. See RATNACANDRA (1988 I: 59), and GHATAGE (1996 I: 64). This betrays the spirit of realism of Jain philosophy. Though, katha may also refer to 'talk', discussion or 'disputation'. Potentially negative consequences of knowledge based on mere hearsay are explained in Viy 9.31(430a-438a). Thana 7.80 lists seven types of gossip (vi-kaha >). 36 Uvaghaya / uvagghaya is explained by Malayagiri (PannT 258b.10) through the example cauras tvam ("you are a thief"), understood here as abhyakhyana--false and groundless accusation. The term upaghata generally designates an act of violence, but here more specifically an insult. See also Ayara 2.4.8 for this and similar examples of 'sinful speech'. Thana 6.100 lists six types of unwholesome speech. Thana 6.101 lists six types of false accusations, related to the context of enumeration (pathara ) in confession. 38 See for instance NYAYAVIJAYA (1998: 343-5). 39 On combinations of truth and untruth in behaviour (vyavahara), intent (parinata), belief (drsti) etc., for instance in succession, theorised in terms of character types, see Thana 241 (4.35-44). See CAILLAT (1965/1975: 80) on types of duplicity to be avoided. 40 DSV 7.4-5: 39 D: SHEELANUSANDHAN ANU-50 Page #33 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 198 31LHITE 40 (2) eyam ca atthamannam va jam tu namei sasayam / sa bhasam sacca-mosam pi tam pi dhiro vivajjae // 4 // vitaham pi tahamottim jam giram bhasae naro/ tamha so puttho pavenam, kim puna jo musam vae // 5 // 41 See also Thana 10.91. 42 PannU 82: sacca-mosa dasa-viha uppanna-misaga-vigata-misagadi, uddissa gamam va nagaram va dasanham dara-ganam jammam pagasamtassa unesu ahiesu va evam adi uppanna-missiya. Pann?, 258a: "uppanna-missiya' ity-adi, utpanna misrita anutpannaih saha samkhyapuranartham yatra sa utpanna-misrita, evam anyatrapi yatha yogam bhavaniyam, tatrotpanna-misrita yatha kasmimscit grame nagare va unesy adhikesu va darakesu jatesu dasa daraka asminn adya jata ity-adi. 43 PannU 82: em eva marana-kahane vigaya-missiya. PannT, 258b: evam eva marana-kathane vigata-misrita. 44 PannU 82: jammanassa maranassa ya kaya-parinamassa ubhayakahane visamvadane uppanna-vigata-missita. Pann, 258b: tatha janmato maranasya ca krta-parinamasyabhidhane visamvadena cotpanna-vigatamisrita. 45 PannU 82: jivamta-mayaga-samkhanagadi-rasi-darisane aho maham jiva-rasi tti bhanamtassa jivamtesu sacca maesu mosa tti jivamissita, ettha ceva bahusu matesu aho mahamto'jiva-rasi tti bhanamtassa maesu sacca jivamtesu musa iti ajiva-missiya, saccam mayam amayam va ubhayam niyamena avadharayamtassa visamvade jivajiva-missiya. Pann?, 258b: [4] tatha prabhutanam jivatam stokanam ca mrtanam sarkhasankhanakadinam ekatra rasau drste yada kascid evam vadati-aho mahan jiva-rasir ayam iti tada sa jiva-misrita, satya-mrsatvam casya jivatsu satyatvat motesu mrsatvat, [5] tatha yada prabhutenu mrtesu stokesu jivatsu ekatra rasi-kstenu sarkhadisv evam vadati--aho mahanayam meto jiva-rasir iti tada sa ajiva-misrita, asya api satya-mrsatvam mrtesu satyatvat jivatsu mrsatvat, [6] tatha tasminn eva rasau etavanto 'tra jivanta etavanto 'tra mrta iti niyamenavadharayato visamvade jivajiva-misrita. See LEUMANN's (1885) article on the seven early schisms (ninhava). 47 PannU 82: mulakadi anamta-kayam tasseva padirikkaya-pamdumpattehim annena va vanassaikaena missam datthuna esa anamta-kayotti bhanamtassa anamta-missiya. Pann?, 259a: tatha mulakadikam ananta Page #34 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 199 kayam tasyaiva satkaih paripandu-patrair anyena va kenacitpratyekavanaspatina misram avalokya sarvo 'py eso 'nanta-kayika iti vadato 'nanta-misrita. Cf. GHATAGE (1996 I: 227). On the ananta-kayas see WILLIAMS (1983: 113-6). 48 PannU 82: tam eva samudayam karamette sarittanam amilanam rasi-kayam parittam iti bhanamtassa paritta-missiya. Panni, 259a: tatha pratyeka-vanaspati-sanghatam ananta-kayikena saha rasi-krtam avalokya pratyeka-vanaspatir ayam sarvo 'piti vadatah pratyeka-misrita. 49 See MALVANIYA (1971: 271, 430). Thana 10.66 lists ten meanings of the word ananta. 50 This characterisation cannot be related to the difference between experienced or conventional time (samaya) and imperceptible abstract time (addha) explained in Viy 11.11.1 (532b) (DELEU 1970: 178), because in this case the speech act would be neither-true-nor-false. As the authoritative work of Jain scholastic hermeneutics, the Anuogaddaraim shows, Jains are careful to distinguish semantic ambiguity from philosophical perspectivism (anekanta-vada, syad-vada, niksepa, naya etc.), which is seen as an analytic instrument for disambiguation: 'Whereas in the fallacy of chhal (fraud), one word has two meanings, no word in this argument [of syad-vada) is of such nature. ... To declare the existence of an object from one point of view and to declare its non-existence from another point of view, is not to indulge in a pun, and thus to be guilty of this fallacy' (KANNOOMAL 1917: 16). Cf. C. R. JAIN (1929: 8, 16- 18), GANERI (2001: 133). It should be noted that similes and analogies are considered to be media of disambiguation and not conveyors of mixed truth and untruth. Obviously, they can play both roles. On chala, features of 'god', 'bad debates' etc., especially in the Nyaya-sutra, see MATILAL (1999, Chapters 2-3). SI RATNACANDRA (1988 I: 270 f., 268), GHATAGE (2001 II: 454, 461). 52 PannU 82: addha kalo so divaso ratti va, jo tam-missiyam kareti, param turiyavemto divasato bhanati-utthehi ratti jayatti, esa addha-missiya, tasseva divasassa ratie va ega-padeso addhaddha, tam padhama-porisikale taheva turiyamto majjhanhi-bhutam bhanatassa addhaddha-missiya. PannT, 259a: [9] tatha addha--kalah, sa ceha prastavat divaso ratrir va parigrhyate, sa misrito yaya saddha-misrita, yatha kascit kancana tvarayan divase varttamana eva vadati-uttistha ratrir yateti, ratrau va varttamanayam uttisthodgatah surya iti, [10] tatha divasasya ratrer va 40 D:ISHEELANUSANDHANIANU-50 Page #35 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ poo 31THEIRA 40 (?) ekadeso 'ddhaddha sa misrita yaya sa addhaddha-misrita, yatha prathamapaurusyam eva varttamanayam kascit kancana tvarayan evam vadaticala madhyahni-bhutam iti. 53 HABERMAS (1981: 97-117) / (1984-1987 II: 62-76), and others, showed that semantic content of normative sentences can be transformed into propositional sentences while the reverse is not always possible. 54 DVS 7.6-10: tamha gacchamo, vakkhamo, amugam va ne bhavissai/ aham va nam karissami, eso va nam karissai // 6 // evamai u ja bhasa esa-kalammi sankiya / sampayaiyam atthe va tam pi dhiro vivajjae // 7 // aiyammi ya kalammi paccuppannam anagae/ jamattham tu na janejja "evameyam" ti no vae // 8 // aiyammi ya kalammi paccuppannam anagae/ jattha sanka bhave tam tu "evameyam" ti no vae // 9 // aiyammi ya kalammi paccuppannam anagae/ nissarkiyam bhave jam tu "evameyam" ti niddise // 10 // 55 See the mixed true-false utterance 'The god of the sky' (Ayara 2.4.1.12-13) and similar examples of mislabelling discussed in footnote 90. 56 In symbolic logic such problems are discussed under the labels such as 'no-item thesis', 'misleading form thesis', 'truth value gap thesis', and 'new truth-value thesis' (HAACK 1974: 47 ff.). According to PRIEST (1987 / 2006) the single rationale underlying the theory of different types of truth value gaps, derived from the correspondence theory of truth, is that 'for certain sentences, a there is no Fact which makes a true, neither is there a Fact which makes a true', which are to be distinguished from dialetheia, or true contradictions such that both statement A and its negation, -A, are true. In his view, the argument fails, because 'if there is no Fact which makes a true, there is a Fact which makes a true, viz. the fact that there is no Fact which makes a true' (ib., p. 54). 57 See for instance BALBIR (1987: 9) and DUNDAS (1996: 62). 58 PRIEST-ROUTLEY (1983: 14) cite Stoic and other authors from Greek antiquity defending this view. 59 'In this respect the Jains anticipate contemporary discussive logic, initiated by Jaskowski, and they may similarly be interpreted in Page #36 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 201 terms of integration of different worlds, or positions, reflecting partial truth ... Naturally such a theory risks trivialisation unless some (cogent) restrictions are imposed on the parties admitted as having obtained partial truth restrictions of a type that might well be applied to block amalgamation leading to violations of Non-Contradiction. Unlike the Jains, the Madhyamikas apparently affirmed the law of Contradiction. But this does not prevent a certain unity of opposites, e.g. in the negative dialectic of Nagarjuna, a concept, such as Being, can become indistinguishable from its opposite, Non-Being' (PRIESTROUTLEY 1983: 17). 60 STCHERBATSKY (1958: 415), cited in PRIEST-ROUTLEY (1989: 16). 61 LALWANI's (1985 IV: 133 f.) rendition of Viy 10.3.34 reads as follows: '[Gautama speaks] Bhante! There are twelve forms of language address, order, prayer, question, advice, refusal, consent, enquiry, conviction, confusion, distinct and indistinct. Now, when one says, I shall take lodge, I shall lie, I shall stand, I shall sit, I shall stretch, do these forms conform to the fifth type viz. advice, and it is correct to say that they are never false?-[Mahavira answers) Yes Gautama! They conform to the fifth type and they are never false.' 62 On articulated (akkhara-suya) evidence, composed of written and oral sources see SCHUBRING (2000: $ 74). 63 Ayara 2.4.1.4 n., 2.4.1.7. 64 AUSTIN (1962) distinguishes between implicit and explicit, selfverifying, performatives. An 'explicit performative sentence', such as taking a vow, 'indicates that the issuing of the utterance is the performing of an action--it is not normally thought of as just saying something' (ib., pp. 6 f.)--this would be a 'descriptive fallacy' (ib., p. 3). 'None of the utterances cited is either true or false' (ib.). 'It is essential to realize that "true" and "false", like "free" and "unfree", do not stand for anything simple at all; but only for a general dimension of being a right or proper thing to say as opposed to a wrong thing, in these circumstances, to this audience, for these purposes and with these intentions. ... This doctrine is quite different from much that the pragmatists have said, to the effect that the true is what works, &c. The truth or falsity of a statement depends not merely on the meanings of words but on what act you were performing in what circumstances' (ib., p. 144). The problem of 41 D:SHEELANUSANDHAN ANU-50 Page #37 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 202 31LHETA 40 () determining truth-values of performative utterances has been discussed, for example, by FAUCONNIER (1981: 182). 65 Thana 6.111 lists six types of question-contexts, not all of which can be categorised as neither-true-nor-false; e.g. vuggaha-pattha , questioning an opponent. 66 On ambiguities created by the use of the future tense see also FAUCONNIER (1981: 180 f.), and others. 67 HAACK (1974: 58 f., 73-90) criticises the 'modal fallacy'in Aristotle's argument on future contingents, but accepts it as valid if interpreted as a truth value gap theory. 68 See further STRAWSON (1950) and the ensuing debate, on which see also HORN (1985), (2001: 362 ff.), and others. 69 Muni Nathmal (Acarya Mahaprajna) characterized asatya-mrsa language as vyavahara-bhasa, or conventional or common speech (Thana 4.23, Hindi commentary). 70 PannU 82 f.: "amantani" ity-adi, he deva iti amantani, esa kilapravarttaka-nivarttakatvat satyadi bhasa-traya-laksana-viyogatas casatyamrseti, evam sva-buddhaya anyatrapi bhavana karyeti, kajje parassa pavattanam jaha imam karehitti anavani, katthai vatthu-visesassa dehitti magganam jayani, avinnayassa samdiddhassa va atthassa jananattham tad-abhijutta-codanam pucchani, viniyassa uvaeso jaha--panavahau niyatta havati dihauya aroga ya emadi pannavani pannatta viyaragehim. Pann?, 258b: "amantani" iti tatra amantrani he devadatta ity-adi, esa hi prag-ukta-satyadi-bhasa-traya-lakcana-vikalatvan na satya napi mrsa napi satya-mrsa kevalam vyavahara-matra-pravrtti-hetur ity asatya-mrsa. 71 Pannt, 259a: abhigrhita prati-niyatarthavadharanam, yatha idam idanim karttavyam idam neti. 72 Pannt, 259a: anabhigraha yatra na prati-niyatarthavadharanam, yatha bahukaryesv avasthitesu kascit kancana prcchati--kim idanim karomi?, sa praha-yat pratibhasate tat kurv iti. 73 DELEU (1970: 241). 74 Jambuvijaya's edition of the Thana 4.23 (238) contains the following commentary of Jinabhadra's Visesavasyaka-bhasa (VaBh) 376- 7: anahigaya ja tisu vi saddo cciya kevalo asacca-musa. Page #38 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 203 75 Pannt, 259a: samsaya-karani ya vak anekarthabhidhayitaya parasya sansayam utpadayati, yatha saindhavamaniyatam ity atra saindhava-sabdo lavana-vastra-purusa-vajisu. SCHUBRING (2000 $ 74: 157 f.): 'All animals with two to four senses and beings with five senses express themselves in the neither true nor wrong way, but the latter will employ the first three modes just as well (Pannav. 260a) provided they have learnt to do so or carry along with them a higher ability.' 76 PannT, 259a: vyaksta ya prakatartha. 77 Pannt, 259a: avyaksta atigambhira-sabdartha avyaktaksaraprayukta va avibhavitarthatvat. 78 The Pali equivalents of pannavana and pannatta are pannapana, pannatta (MALVANIYA 1971: 212). The word pannatti are used in to describe Mahavira's preaching activity. Hence, his teachings are called pannavana , exposition, or paruvana , explanation (AGD 51, MALVANIYA 1971: 210). The 'proclamations' (Kundmachung) or preachings of the unattached ones are also called niggantha pavayana/ pavayana in Viy 2.5.5 (134b), 20.8.5 (792b) and Thana 176a. See SCHUBRING 2000 SS 37: 73). 79 DELEU (1970: 169) writes: 'asaissamo is asayisyamah, not, as Abhay. says, asrayisyamah.' According to the rules of speech in Ayara 2.4.1.5 and DVS 7.8-10 one should avoid such a statement if one cannot be entirely sure. 80 PannT 249b: yathavasthitarthabhidhanad iyam prajnapani, in MALVANIYA (1971: 211, cf. 346). 81 Contrary to MALVANIYA's (1971: 211) view that asatya-mrsa speech 'has nothing to do with norm' it is obvious that by referring to situations that ought to be both imperatives, commissives (vows), and declaratives imply normative conditions, even if used by an enlightened being. Only assertives attempt to represent situations as they are. Searle showed that from the hearer's perspective even literal speech implies a contextual horizon to be intelligible (HABERMAS 1980: 452) / (19841987 I: 337). According to Pann 246b, asatya-mrsa speech signifies not only oharani or determinative expressions such as 'I believe' or 'I think', but all attempts to communicate transcendental truth through 42 D:ISHEELANUSANDHANIANU-50 Page #39 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 204 anusandhAna 50 (2) descriptive (prajnapani) speech, which is assumed to be context-free and thus by definition neither-true-nor-false (satya-mrsa). The Pann accounts for the use of certain classificatory terms and words which express universals (e.g. masculine, feminine, neuter) without clearly specifying their contextual range of meaning. Imperatives such as 'go ahead' belong to this category too. For instance, we may 'order a person of any gender and this person may or may not carry out orders.... This ajnapani (imperative) speech too could not be held as false. It should be regarded as a case of prajnapani speech' (MALVANIYA 1971: 326). PannT, 249b: 82 panivahau niyatta havamti dihauya aroga ya / ema pannatta pannavani viyaragehim // 3 Utt 28.16 ff. lists amongst the ten sources of right insight (samyagdarsana) communications such as upadesa, instruction, ajna, command, bija, seed (suggestion), as well as abhigama, comprehension of the sacred scriptures, and vistara, complete course of study (including proofs, pramana, and perspectives, naya): nisagguvaesa-rui, ana-rui sutta-biya-rui-meva / abhigama-vitthara-rui, kiriya-samkheva-dhamma-rul // . 4 Cf. MURTI (1955: 129) on transcendental language which expresses truth which is beyond language; and GANERI (2002: 271) on the non-assertible (inexpressible) in classical Jain seven-valued logic (sapta-bhangi), which may be conceptually related to incomprehensible speech. 5 This example could be interpreted as an early version of the 'misleading form thesis' addressed by RUSSELL (1905) and others. See HAACK (1974: 53-55). By contrast, the example 'Devadatta, give me the cow', mentioned by GLASENAPP (1915: 46), is neither-true-noruntrue as a simple performative. 86 Cf. SCHUBRING (2000 SS 74: 158), MALVANIYA (1971: 325 f.). 87 Cf. CAILLAT (1965/1975: 80), QVARNSTROM (2002: 41 n. 4). For discussion of the ethical implications of this dilemma, for instance in terms of appropriateness, see for instance GERT (1973), HARE (1981), WELLMER (1986: 26 ff.), and HABERMAS (1991: 170). GANERI (2002: 277) shows that the sapta-bhangi is also 'not strictly truth-functional', but suggests a solution to this problem. Page #40 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 205 90 Interestingly, some slokas are similar to the last of GRICE's quality maxims: 'Do not say that for which you lack adequate evidence', which invokes questions of referential truth and of the relationship between representational and expressive functions of language. The definition of the concepts of truth and falsehood, or of aspects thereof, is a notoriously difficult problem for modern science and philosophy, whose discourse is constituted by this fundamental distinction according to FOUCAULT (1981) and LUHMANN (1990). It is therefore interesting to see how the Jains tackle this issue, which is one of their foremost concerns. There is a note by LALWANI added to DVS 24.12 which identifies three types of falsehood: (i) to deny what is, (ii) to establish what is not, and (iii) to alter the meaning'. They can be illustrated by the following examples: Jainism propagates epistemic realism. Hence, it is not surprising that there are explicit statements defending the ideal of objective truth in the scriptures, as opposed to mere appearance, opinion, or consensus. The following passage stresses the necessity for ascetics to use their faculty of judgement to discover the truth of a given phenomenon, and not to be deceived by false appearances: 'Employing their judgment, they should know something for certain and something for uncertain: (1) Having received food or not having received food, having eaten it or not having eaten it, has come or has not come, comes or does not come, will come or will nor come' (Ayara 2.4.1.1-2). This orientation toward the world, predicated on a realistic analysis of the modalities of time, is diametrically opposed to Brahmanism and Vedantic concepts such as maya etc. This is evident in the following passage, which implicitly criticises the confusion of natural phenomena with illusory imagery of divine agency: 'A monk should not say: "The god of the sky! the god of the thunderstorm! the god of lightning! the god who begins to rain! the god who ceases to rain! may rain fall or may it not fall! may the crops grow or may they not grow! may the night wane or may it not wane! may the sun rise or may it not rise! may the king conquer or may he not conquer!" They should not use such speech. ... But knowing the nature of things, he should say: "the air; the follower of Guhya; a cloud has gathered or come down; the 43 D:\SHEELANUSANDHANVANU-50 Page #41 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 206 (ii) anusandhAna 50 (2) cloud has rained" (Ayara 2.4.1.12-13). False appearance and deception should be avoided by all means: 'A muni speaks of appearance, ignoring the truth, encounters a sin. Then what to speak of one who indulges in whole untruth [Note by LALWANI: When a woman is dressed as a man and if she be called a man, it is a falsehood, though in her dress she appears like a man...].' (DVS, 7.5, cf. Ayara 2.4.1.3). Ways of 'establishing what is not', such as vague promises and speculation, are also seen. indiscriminate or deceptive utterances, because of the confusion of past, present, and future. Language which may create doubt (maybe or not') has to be avoided by all means: 'When one knows not true implication, in the context of the present, past, and future, says not one, "surely it's like this". When one is in doubt about implication, in the context of the present, past and future, says not one, "surely it's like this". "Surely it's so", says one when one has not an iota of doubt of implication about the present, the past and future' (DVS, 7.8-10, cf. DVS, 7.6-7, Ayara 2.4.1.5). It is remarkable, that early Jainism already insists on the correct use of temporal modalities, which must be related to the philosophy of transmigration, but also with the critique of the Brahmanic sacred-word theory: 'speech exists only the moment when being spoken' (SCHUBRING SS 68 2000: 149). The practical value of all the cited examples is the same: reducing illusory appearances to their 'real' content. (iii) There are no further maxims concerning 'changing the meaning' in the texts on the ways of speaking. Effectively, however, Jain narrative literature is based on a method of 'changing the meaning' of Indian folklore (HERTEL 1922). The combined systematicity and context-sensitivity of Jain rules and regulations is particularly obvious in the following statement of the Digambara author Vasunandin's (1100 CE) Sravakacara 209, which propagates not only the 'abstention from untruth spoken out of passion or hate' but 'from truth too, if it provokes the destruction of a living being' (cited in WILLIAMS 1983: 78). This and similar examples illustrate how the hierarchically superior principle of ahimsa supersedes the maxim of truthfulness in cases of rule Page #42 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 207 contradiction. Cf. MALVANIYA (1971: 325) on the role of the (situational) conditions of truthfulness in the Pannavana. 91 Conversely: '[1.] The monks and nuns may not use the following six forbidden forms of speech: lying, sneering, insult, coarse speaking, worldly speech, or speech renewing atoned matters. 2. There are six cases of idle talk about right conduct: of speaking rashly in relation to others, of damaging living creatures, of untruthfulness, of forbidden appropriation, of a jade, a eunuch, or a slave. Whoever uses those six kinds of idle talk, without being able to prove them fully, ranks as one who has committed the transgression himself' (KS 6.1). 92 Cf. BROWN-LEVINSON (1978: 134 ff.). In PannT folio 259 B cited by MALVANIYA (1971: 212) the positive karmic consequences of not killing are expressed in this way; avoiding commandments of the form 'do not kill' for example by saying: "Those who refrain from killing living beings live long and enjoy good health in the next birth).' 93 See also AUSTIN (1962: 4) on disguising a performative utterance as a descriptive or constative statement. 94 Cf. GERT's (1973) "minimal ethic'. 44 D:SHEELANUSANDHAN ANU-50 Page #43 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 208 37THENTA 40 (?) BIBLIOGRAPHY Primary Sources AnD = Anuogaddaraim [Anuyoga-dvara]. T. Hanaki (English tr.): Anuogaddaraim (English Translation). Prakrit Jain Institute Research Publications Series Vol. 5, Vaishali 1970. AvNi = Avassaya-nijjutti [Avasyaka-niryukti]. Edited with Haribhadra's Tika. Agamodaya Samiti, Bombay 1918. Ayara = Ayaramga-sutta [Acaranga-sutra]. (1) [English translation:] JACOBI (1884: 1-216). (2) [Original Ardhamagadhi-Text:) Tulsi, Acarya, Muni Nathmal (eds.): Angasuttani. Vol. 1. Second Edition. Jain Visva Bharati, Laanun 1992: 1-248 [first edition: 1974). DVS = Arya Sayyambhava: Dasa-veyaliya-sutta [Dasavaikalika-sutra]. (1) Ernst Leumann (ed.), Walther Schubring (tr.): The Dasaveyaliya Sutta. Introduction and Notes, by Walther Schubring. The Managers of the Sheth Anandji Kalianji, Ahmedabad 1932. (2) Kustur Chand Lalwani (tr.): Arya Sayyambhava's Dasavaikalika Sutra. With Translation and Notes. Motilal Banarsidas, Delhi 1973. (3) Acarya Tulsi [Vacaka Pramukha), Muni Nathmal [Sampadaka aur Vivecaka] (eds.): Dasavealiyam (Mulapatha, Samskrt Chaya, Hindi Anuvada tatha Tippana). Jain Visva Bharati, Ladnum 1974 [first edition: 1964]. KS = Bhadrabahu: Kappa-sutta [Kalpa-sutra]. Walther Schubring (tr.): Das Kalpa-sutra. Die alte Sammlung jinistischer Monchsvorschriften. Einleitung, Text, Analysen, Ubersetzung, Glossar. Indica 2. Hg. E. Leumann. Otto Harrassowitz, Leipzig 1905 [English Translation of the revised German translation: J.A.S. Burgess: 'The Kalpa-Sutra. An Old Collection of Disciplinary Rules for Jaina monks.' The Indian Antiquary 39 (1910) 257-267]. MAC = Vattakera: Mulacara. See: OKUDA (1975). Page #44 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 209 Pann = Pannavana-sutta [Prajnapana-sutra]. Muni Punyavijaya, Pt. Dalsukh Malvaniya, Pt. Amritlal Mohanlal Bhojak. (eds.): Pannavana (Prajnapana). Jaina-agama-Series No. 9, Part 1-2. Mahavira Jaina Vidyalaya, Bombay 1969-1971. See also: PaanT, PannV. Pann] = Malayagiri: Prajnapana-tika. (1) Srimacchyamacarya-dTbdham sriman-Malayagiryacarya-vihitavivarana-yutam sri-prajnapanopangam (Purvarddham). Agamodaya-samiti, Mehasana 1918, 1919 [printed: NirnayaSagara Press, Bombay]. (2) Pandit Bhagavanadasa Harsacandra [Anuvadaka ane Samsodhaka] (ed.): Vacakavara-Bhagavadarya-syamacarya-viracita Mula tatha srimad-acarya-Malayagiriviracita tikana Anuvada-sahita. Bhag I-III. Jaina Sosayati, Amadavada (Ahmedabad) 1935. PannV = Haribhadra-suri: Prajnapana-vyakhya (Purvabhagah). Rsabhadeva-kesarimalaji [Mudrayitri] (ed.): Suvihita-dhurandhara-sahityasaudhananya-stambhopama-sriHaribhadra-Suri-sutrita-pradesavyakhya-samkalitam. Phakircanda Maganalala Badami, Jainavijayananda Printing Press, Surat 1947. PH = Aristotle: Peri Hermeneias. E.M. Edghill (tr.); On Interpretation. In: W.D. Ross (ed.): The Works of Aristotle, Volume 1: Logic. Clarendon Press, Oxford 1928 [http:// classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/-interpretation.html]. Suy = Suyagadamga [Sutrakrtanga]. English translation: JACOBI (1895: 235-435). Thana = Thananga-sutta [Sthananga-sutra]. (1) Acarya Tulsi [Vacaka Pramukha), Muni Nathmal [Sampadaka Vivecaka], Acarya Mahaprajna (eds.): Thanam (Mul Path, Sanskrt Chaya, Hindi Anuvada tatha tippana). Jaina Visva Bharati, Ladnun 1976. (2) Muni Jambuvijaya [Sampadak] (ed.): Sthananga-sutram. Navangi-tikakara-sri-Abhayadeva-suriviracita-vivarana-sametam. Bhag I-III. Jaina-agama-Granthamala 45 D:\SHEELANUSANDHANVANU-50 Page #45 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 210 31LHETA 40 () 19 (1-3). Mahavira Jaina Vidyalaya, Mumbai 2002-2003. (3) Uttara Bharatiya Pravartaka Amar Muni Pradhana Sampadakal, Sricand Surana "Saras' [Saha-Sampadaka] (eds.): Sacitra Sthananga Sutra. Bhag I-II. Mula Path-Hindi-Angrezi Anuvada, Vivecana evam Rangina Citrom Sahita. Padma Prakasa, Dilli 2004. Utt = Uttarajjhayana-sutta [Uttaradhyayana-sutra]. (1) UpaPravartaka Amar Muni [Sampadaka], sricand Surana "Saras' [Saha-Sampadaka] (eds.); Brj Mohan Jain [Angrezi Anuvada] (tr.): Sacitra Uttaradhyayana Sutra Mula Patha, Hindi-Angrezi Anuvada, Visesa tippana tatha Bhavapurna Citrom Sahit. Atma Jnan Pith, Manasa Mandi 1992. (2) English Translation: JACOBI (1895: 1-232). VABh = Jinabhadra: Visecavasyaka-bhasa. Dalasukha Malavaniya (ed.): Sri-jinabhadra-gani-ksama-sramana-viracitam Visecavasyakabhasyam. Svopajna-vrtti-sahitam. Lalabhai Dalapatabhai Bharatiya Samskrti Vidyamandira, Amadavada 1966-1968. Viy = Viyaha-pannatti [Bhagavati-sutra]. (1) DELEU (1970). (2) Kustur Chand Lalwani (tr.): Sudharma Svami's Bhagavati Sutra. Prakrit Text with English Translation of satakas 1-11. Vol. 1-4. Jain Bhawan, Calcutta 1973-1985. YS = Hemacandra-suri: Yoga-sastra. Olle Qvarnstrom (tr.): The Yogasastra of Hemacandra. A Twelfth Century Handbook on Svetambara Jainism. Harvard Oriental Series Vol. 61, Cambridge (Massachusetts) 2002. YT = Somadeva-suri: Yasas-tilaka. See HANDIQUI (1968). Secondary Sources APEL, Karl-Otto: Transformation der Philosophie. 2 Bande. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1973 [English translation Page #46 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 211 (selection): Towards a Transformation of Philosophy. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980). ARISTOTLE = See PH. AUSTIN 1962 = Austin, John Langshaw: How to Do Things with Words. The William James Lectures delivered at Harvard University in 1955. Clarendon Press, Oxford 1962. BAHM 1957 = Bahm Archie J.: Does Seven-Fold Predication Equal Four-Cornered Negation Reversed?' Philosophy East and West 7,3-4 (1957) 127-130. BALBIR 1987 = Balbir, Nalini: 'The Perfect Sutra as Defined by the Jainas.' Bulletin D'Etudes Indiennes 3 (1987) 3-21. BALCEROWICZ 2003 = Balcerowicz, Piotr: 'Some Remarks on the Naya Method', in: Piotr Balcerowicz: Essays in Jaina Philosophy and Religion. Motilal Banarsidas, Delhi 2003: 37-70. BHATT 1978 = Bhatt, Bansidhar: The Canonical Niksepa. Studies in Jaina Dialectics. E. J. Brill (Indologica Berolinensa 5), Leiden 1978. BROWN-LEVINSON 1978 = Brown, Penelope & Levinson, Stephen: "Universals in Language Usage: Politeness Phenomena', in: E. Goody (ed.): Questions and Politeness. Strategies in Social Interaction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1978: 56-310. BRUHN 2003 = Bruhn, Klaus: 'The Mahavratas in Early Jainism.' Berliner Indologische Studien 15/16/17 (2003) 3-98. BRUHN-HARTEL 1978 = Bruhn, Klaus; Herbert Hartel: 'Editors' Foreword', in: Bansidhar Bhatt: The Canonical Niksepa: Studies in Jaina Dialectics. Indologica Berolinensa 5, E. J. Brill, Leiden 1978: v-vi. CAILLAT 1975 = Caillat, Colette: Atonements in the Ancient Ritual of the Jaina Monks. Translated by Mr Jones, 46 D:ISHEELANUSANDHANIANU-50 Page #47 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 212 anusandhAna 50 (2) Mr & Mrs McKenna, & Mr Whitehouse. Ahmedabad: L. D. Institute of Indology, L. D. Series No. 49, 1965 / 1975. CAILLAT 1984 = Caillat, Colette: "Prohibited Speech and Subhasita in the Theravada Tradition', Indologica Taurinensia 12 (1984) 61-73. CAILLAT 1991 = Caillat, Colette: "The Rules Concerning Speech (Bhasa) in the Ayaranga- and Dasaveyaliya-Suttas', in: M. A. Dhaky, S. Jain (eds.): Aspects of Jainology. Pt. Dalsukhbhai Malvania Felicitation Volume. Vol. 3. P. V. Research Institute, Varanasi 1991: 1-15. DELEU 1970 = Deleu, Jozef: Viyahapannatti (Bhagavai). The Fifth Anga of the Jaina Canon. Introduction, Critical Analysis, Commentary & Indexes. Rijksuniversiteit de Gent, Brugge 1970. DUNDAS 1996 = Dundas, Paul: "Somnolent Sutras: Scriptural Commentary in svetambara Jainism.' Journal of Indian Philosophy 24 (1996) 73-101. DUNDAS 2007 = Dundas, Paul: "The Non-Violence of Violence: Jain Perspectives on Warfare, Asceticism and Worship', in: J.R. Hinnells, R. King (eds.): Religion and Violence in South Asia: Theory and Practice. Routledge, London 2007: 41-61. FAUCONNIER 1981 = Fauconnier, Gilles: "Social Ritual and Relative Truth in Natural Language', in: K. Knorr-Cetina, A.V. Cicourel (eds.): Advances in Social Theory and Methodology. Routledge & Kegan Paul, Boston 1981: 175- 202. FOUCAULT 1981 = Foucault, Michel: L'ordre du discours. Gallimard, Paris 1971 [English translation: 'The Order of Discourse.' Translated by Ian McLeod. In: R. Young (ed.): Untying the Text: A Poststructuralist Reader. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London 1981: 48-78]. Page #48 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 213 GANERI 2001 = Ganeri, Jonardon: Philosophy in Classical India. Routledge, London 2001. GANERI 2002 = Ganeri, Jonardon: "Jaina Logic and the Philosophical Basis of Pluralism. History and Philosophy of Logic 23 (2002) 267-81. GERT 1973 = Gert, Bernard: The Moral Rules: A New Rational Foundation for Morality. Harper & Row, New York 1973. GHATAGE 1996-2003 = Ghatage, A.M. (ed.): A Comprehensive and Critical Dictionary of the Prakrit Languages with Special Reference to Jain Literature. Vol. I-III.1-2. Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute, Pune 1996-2003. GLASENAPP 1915 = Glasenapp, Helmuth von: Die Lehre vom Karma in der Philosophie der Jainas. Otto Harrassowitz, Leipzig 1915 [English translation: The Doctrine of Karman in Jain Philosophy. Translated from the original German by B. Gifford and revised by the author. Ed. H. R. Kapadia. Bombay: Bai Vijibai Jivanlal Panalal Charity Fund, 1942]. GONDA 1959 = Gonda, Jan: "Why are Ahimsa and Similar Concepts often Expressed in a Negative Form?' Jan Gonda: Four Studies in the Language of the Veda. Disputationes Theno-Trajectinaeis. Mouton, 'S-Gravenage 1959: 95-117. GRICE 1975 = Grice, H. Paul: 'Logic and Conversation.' P. Cohen, J. L. Morgan (eds.): Syntax and Semantics. Vol. 3. Academic Press, London 1975: 41-58. GUMPERZ 1964 = Gumperz, John J.: 'Linguistic and Social Interaction in Two Communities.' American Anthropologist (N.S.) 66,6,2 (1964) 137-53. GUNARATNE 1980 = Gunaratne, R. D.: 'Understanding Nagarjuna's catus-koti.' Philosophy East & West 30,2 (1980) 211-239. 47 D:SHEELANUSANDHAN ANU-50 Page #49 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 214 31LHEITA 40 (?) HAACK 1974 = Haack, Susan: Deviant Logic: Some Philosophical Ideas. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1974. HABERMAS 1979 = Habermas, Jurgen: "What is Universal Pragmatics?" Communication and the Evolution of Society. Translated by Thomas McCarthy. London: Heinemann Educational, 1976 / 1979: 1-68. HABERMAS 1980-1981 = Habermas, Jurgen: Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns. 2 Bande. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main 1980-1981 [English translation: HABERMAS (1984- 1987)]. HABERMAS 1983 = Habermas, Jurgen: Moralbewusstsein und kommunikatives Handeln. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main 1983 [English translation: HABERMAS (1990)]. HABERMAS 1984-1987 = Habermas, Jurgen: The Theory of Communicative Action. Vol. 1-2. Translated by Thomas McCarthy. Polity Press, Cambridge 1984-1987 [English translation of HABERMAS (1980-1981)]. HABERMAS 1991 = Habermas, Jurgen: Erlauterungen zur Diskursethik. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main 1991 [English translation: Justification & Application: Remarks on Discourse Ethics. Translated by Ciaran P. Cronin. The M.I.T. Press, Cambridge (Massachusetts) 1993]. HABERMAS 1993 = Habermas, Jurgen: "Comments on John Searle: "Meaning, Communication, and Representation".' LEPORE-VAN GULICK (1993: 17-30). HANDIQUI 1968 = Handiqui, Krishna Kanta: Yasastilaka and Indian Culture. Or Soma Terapanth deva's Yasastilaka and Aspects of Jainism and Indian Thought and Culture in the Tenth Century. Jivaraja Jaina Granthamala No. 2, Jaina Samskrti Samraksaka Sangha, Sholapur 1968 [first edition: 1949]. HARE 1981 = Hare, Richard Mervyn: Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Method, and Point. Clarendon Press, Oxford 1981. Page #50 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 HARNAD 1999 = Harnad, Stevan: 'Re: Are Axioms Empirical?' 19 February (1999) 1 [http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/ ~harnad/Hypermail/Advanced.AI99/0009.html]. HERTEL 1922 = Hertel, Johannes: On the Literature of the Shvetambaras of Gujarat. Sachsische Forschungsinstitute in Leipzig. Forschungsinstitut fur Indogermanistik Indische Abteilung Nr. 1, Merkert & Petters, Leipzig 1922. 215 HORN 1985 = Horn, Laurence R.: 'Metalinguistic Negation and Pragmatic Ambiguity.' Language 61,1 (1985) 121-74. HORN 2001 = Horn, Laurence R.: A Natural History of Negation. CSLI Publications, Stanford: 2001 [first edition: Chicago University Press, Chicago 1989]. HYMES 1972 Hymes, Dell: 'On Communicative Competence', in: J. Pride, J. Holmes (eds.): Sociolinguistics. Penguin, Harmondsworth 1972 [first edition: 1971]. = JACOBI 1884 = Jacobi, Hermann: Jaina Sutras I. Sacred Books of the East Vol. 22 Oxford University Press, Oxford 1884. JACOBI 1895 = Jacobi, Hermann: Jaina Sutras II. Sacred Books of the East Vol. 45 Oxford University Press, Oxford 1895. JAIN 1929 = Jain, Campat Ray: Faith, Knowledge and Conduct. The Indian Press, Allahabad 1929. JAYATILLEKE 1967 = Jayatilleke, K.N.: 'The Logic of Four Alternatives.' Philosophy East & West 17,1/4 (1967) 69- 83. = JONES 1978 Jones, Richard Hubert: "The Nature and Function of Nagarjuna's Arguments.' Philosophy East and West 28,4 (1978) 485-502. KANNOOMAL 1917 = Kannoomal, Lala: The Saptabhangi Naya or the Pluralist Aspects of the Jaina 48 D:\SHEELVANUSANDHANIANU-50 Page #51 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 216 31LHETA 40 () Dialectics. Atmanand Jain Pustak Pracharak Mandal, Agra 1917. LAIDLAW 1995 = Laidlaw, James: Riches and Renunciation: Religion, Economy and Society among the Jains. Clarendon Press, Oxford 1995. LALWANI 1973 = Lalwani, Kustur Chand: Arya Sayyambhava's Dasavaikalika Sutra. Translation and Notes. Motilal Banarsidas, Delhi 1973. LALWANI 1973-85 = Lalwani, Kustur Chand: Sudharma Svami's Bhagavati Sutra. Prakrit Text with English Translation of satakas 1-11. Vol. 1-4. Jain Bhawan, Calcutta 1973-1985. LUHMANN 1990 = Luhmann, Niklas: Die Wissenschaft der Gesellschaft. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main 1990. MAHIAS 1985 = Mahias, Marie-Claude: Delivrance et convivialite: Le systeme culinaire des Jaina. Editions de la Maison des Sciences de l'Homme, Paris 1985. MALAMOUND 1982 = Malamoud, Charles: "On the Rhetorics and Semantics of Purusartha', Contributions to Indian Sociology (N.S.) 15 (1982) 33-54. MALVANIYA 1971 = Malvaniya, Dalsukh. D.: 'Introduction', in: Muni Punyavijaya, Pt. Dalsukh Malvaniya, Pt. Amritlal Mohanlal Bhojak (ed.): Pannavanasuttam. JainaAgama-Series No. 9, Part 2. Mahavira Jaina Vidyalaya, Bombay 1971: 201-487. MATILAL 1981 = Matilal, Bimal Krishna: The Central Philosophy of Jainism (Anekanta-Vada). L.D. Institute of Indology, Ahmedabad 1981. MATILAL 1999 = Matilal, Bimal Krishna: The Character of Logic in India. Eds. J. Ganeri & H. Tiwari. Oxford University Press, New Delhi 1999 [1st ed.: 1998]. MONIER-WILLIAMS 1986 = Monier-Williams, Monier: Sanskrit-English Dictionary. New Edition, Greatly Enlarged and Page #52 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ mArca 2010 217 Improved. Oxford University Press, Oxford 1899 [reprinted: Marwah Publications, New Delhi 1986). MURTI 1955 = Murti, Tirupattur Ramaseshayyar Venkatachala: The Central Philosophy of Buddhism: A Study of the Madhyamika System. Allen and Unwin, London 1955. PRIEST 2006 = Priest, Graham: In Contradiction: A Study of the Transconsistent. Second Edition. Oxford University Press, Oxford 2006 [first edition: Martinus Nijhoff, Leiden 1987]. PRIEST-ROUTLEY 1983 = Priest, Graham; Routley, Richard. "An Impressionistic Survey of Paraconsistent Positions and Theories." Collected Papers of the 1982 Foundations of Logic Conference, University of Waterloo, 1983. PRIEST-ROUTLEY 1989 = Priest, Graham; Routley, Richard. "First Historical Introduction: A Preliminary History of Paraconsistent and Dialethic Approaches.' G. Priest, R. Routley, J. Norman (eds.): Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent. Philosophia Verlag, Munchen 1989: 3-75. RAJU 1954 = Raju, P. T.: "The Principle of Four-Cornered Negation in Indian Philosophy.' Review of Metaphysics 7 (1954) 694-713. RUSSELL 1905 = Russell, Bertrand: 'On Denoting.' Mind 14 (1905) 479-93. SCHROEDER 2000 = Schroeder, John: "Nagarjuna and the Doctrine of "Skillful Means". Philosophy East and West 50,4 (2000) 559-583. SCHUBRING 1932 = Schubring, Walther, see: DVS1. SCHUBRING 2000 = Schubring, Walther: The Doctrine of the Jainas: Described after the Old Sources. Translated from the Revised German Edition by Wolfgang Beurlen. With the Three Indices Enlarged and Added by Willem Bollee and Jayandra Soni. Motilal Banarsidas, Delhi 2000 [first German edition: 1935). 49 D:\SHEELANUSANDHANVANU-50 Page #53 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 218 3TYRET 40 (2) SEARLE 1969 = Searle, John E.: Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language. London: Cambridge University Oress, 1969. SEYFORT RUEGG 1985 = Seyfort Ruegg, David: 'Purport, Implicature and Presupposition: Sanskrit Abhipraya and Tibetan Dgons Pa/Dgons Gzi as Hermeneutical Concepts.' Journal of Indian Philosophy 13,4 (1985) 309-25. STAAL 1962 = Staal, J. Frits: 'Negation and the Law of Contradiction in Indian Thought: A Study.' Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies 25,1/3 (1962) 52-71. STCHERBATSKY 1958 = Stcherbatsky, Fedor Ippolitovich: Buddhist Logic. 2 vols, Mouton, Gravenhage 19301932 / 1958. STRAWSON 1950 = Strawson, Peter F.: 'On Referring.' Mind 59 (1950) 320-344. TULSI 1985 = Tulsi, Acarya: Illumination of Jaina Tenets (Jaina-Siddhanta-Dipika). Translated by Satakari Mookerjee. Jain Vishva Bharati, Ladnun 1985 [first edition: 1945]. WELLMER 1986 = Wellmer, Albrecht: Ethik und Dialog: Elemente des moralischen Urteils bei Kant und in der Diskursethik. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main 1986. WILLIAMS 1983 = Williams, Robert: Jaina Yoga. Motilal Banarsidas, Delhi 1983 [first edition: 1963]. WITTGENSTEIN 1953 = Wittgenstein, Ludwig: Philosophische Untersuchungen-Philosophical Investigations. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. Blackwell, Oxford 1953 [first edition: 1945]. Dept. of the Study of Religions SOAS, University of LONDON Thornhough Street, Russell Square LONDON WCIHOXG' 50 D:ISHEEL ANUSANDHAN ANU-50