Book Title: Problem Of Absolute In Madhyamaka School
Author(s): J W De Jong
Publisher: J W De Jong
Catalog link: https://jainqq.org/explore/269288/1

JAIN EDUCATION INTERNATIONAL FOR PRIVATE AND PERSONAL USE ONLY
Page #1 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ J. W. DE JONG THE PROBLEM OF THE ABSOLUTE IN THE MADHYAMAKA SCHOOL* The problem of the absolute in the Madhyamaka school has given rise to numerous interpretations, not only divergent, but sometimes diametrically opposed. This lack of unanimity bears witness once again to the inherent difficulties which beset any attempt to understand the essence of a philosophy. These difficulties are even greater when we are dealing with a philosophy which is not based on one of the two great sources of western civilization: Greco-Latin antiquity and Christianity. One must beware of drawing too hasty conclusions about analogies and proximities with western thought, because one runs the risk of distorting Indian thought and failing to recognise that each philosophy is an organic whole. Neither can one expect to find ready-made answers in a philosophy. Thus, too often, in order to define the nature of the absolute of the Madhyamikas, scholars are satisfied with searching for passages which could be quoted in support of a proposed interpretation. Isolated passages cannot be used to decide such questions. The only way of arriving at a satisfactory and non-preconceived answer is to follow step by step the development of Madhyamaka thought. Only in this manner can enough data be gathered for an attempt to be made of finding a solution to the fundamental problem of this philosophy: the nature of the absolute. With this aim in mind, we will first examine the principal themes and leading ideas in the thought of Nagarjuna. This philosophy is distinguished from all those which he attacks in that it excludes the possibility of establishing an ontology. He does not spare the Samkhya doctrine, nor the Vaisesika nor the Hinayana, but his criticism is aimed particularly at the Abhidharma of the Sarvastivadins and the Vaibhasikas. The Sarvastivadins had reduced the world to a limited number of ontological categories (dharma). Even though they considered the dharmas as real, they did not attribute any reality to the entities, made up of groups of dharmas. For them these entities were nothing but designations (prajnapti). Nagarjuna is not satisfied with this reduction to ontological categories and points out that each bhava (thing), Journal of Indian Philosophy 2 (1972) 1-6. All Rights Reserved Copyright 1972 by J. W. de Jong, Canberra Page #2 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ J. W. DE JONG each dharma is itself devoid of reality. The bhavas are not real, because they cannot come into being. Nagarjuna proves by reductio ad absurdum that 'a thing' does not originate from itself, nor from something else; it does not originate from itself and from something else, nor is it without cause. The idea of production" therefore is false. But a thing which does not come into being cannot be real. Therefore, the things which the layman considers as real are not real. According to Nagarjuna, a thing is real when it is endowed with svabhava, a concept which is of great importance for the understanding of his thought. It is very difficult to know exactly what he wishes to express by this word every time, as it contains several notions. Schayer has distinguished in it four meanings: (1) Svabhava means svo bhava, the essence. Heat, for instance, is not the essence of water, but the essence of fire, because fire is always hot. (2) Syabhava is also the svalaksana, the individual character. In this form it is found in the doctrine of the Vaibhasikas, according to whom the world consists of a multitude of elements each having its individua acter. The Vaibhasikas in fact make a distinction between individual nd general character. Impermanency, for instance, is a general characteristic of all the samsksta or conditioned elements. The svalaksana, on the other hand, only belongs to a single samskrta, and distinguishes it from others. (3) Svabhava is the asraya (basis) or praksti (nature), i.e. the unchanging substratum of each thing (bhava). (4) Finally, svabhava is the svato bhava, the absolute being, which is completely independent. However, this fourfold distinction cannot be accepted because, for Nagarjuna, the four concepts are directly linked one to the other and can be reduced to two. Let us take again the example of fire. Its origin depends on causes and conditions such as the sun, a lens, fuel etc. Heat, being the essence of fire, is dependent on the same causes and the same conditions. According to Nagarjuna the real svabhava is non-contingent and has no relation to anything whatsoever. Heat is thus not svabhava and fire, not possessing svabhava, has no 'own-being' or, as the Madhyamikas say, is empty of 'own-being' (sunyah svabhavena). All things, like fire, are born of causes (pratityasamutpanna) and are empty of 'own-being' Page #3 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE PROBLEM OF THE ABSOLUTE (sunya). The Madhyamikas in this way conclude that the concepts of sunya and pratityasamutpanna are equivalent. Candrakirti rejects the svalaksana, equating it with the svo bhava which has already been eliminated. As a matter of fact, in his opinion, the layman attributes to things an individual character (svalaksana), because they believe in a plurality of real elements. Consequently, the svo bhava and the svalaksana, the 'own-being' and the individual character have one and the same meaning. On the other hand, for Candrakirti, the unchanging basis (asraya) is identical to the absolute being (svato bhava). By no means does he distinguish, as Schayer leads us to believe, an asraya or a praksti peculiar to each thing, but he gives a more extensive meaning to this concept: asraya to him is the unchanging support of all things (bhava) taken together. This support can only be non-contingent, because there is nothing outside of it. It becomes thus the svato bhava. We may therefore conclude that for the Madhyamikas the concept of svabhava has only two meanings: (1) that of the 'own-being of each thing' (svalaksana or svo bhava), which, incidentally, they consider unreal, and (2) that of the 'own-being of all things taken together' (praksti or svato bhava). Do the Madhyamikas likewise reject the reality of this latter svabhava, arriving in this way at a total nihilism which has often been attributed to them? To answer such a question, one must proceed from the distinction made by the Madhyamikas between samvrti and paramartha. Samvrti is the 'apparent reality' of the world as seen by the layman. The laymen believe in the reality of things, they believe that everything is born and perishes. They believe in the reality of suffering, of transmigration and of deliverance obtained in Nirvana. In fact, they accept all the views and the whole soteriological doctrine of the Hinayana. The Madhyamikas, on the contrary, consider that the plurality of things and the categories of the Hinayana have no reality. They maintain that things are not real, that there is no real origination (samutpada), but only origination dependent on causes (pratityasamutpada). On the level of samvsti, things exist, but they do not exist on the level of paramartha, 'the supreme meaning', 'the absolute'. The layman remains on the level of samvsti, the Yogin is beyond it, on the level of paramartha. He does not see that what is seen by the layman. Candrakirti compares him to a healthy man whose eyes Page #4 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ J. W. DE JONG do not see the hairs which are perceived by the eyes of a man afflicted with ophthalmia (taimirika). Is paramartha then nothing but nothingness? Never has a direct and precise answer been given to the question "What is paramartha?" Paramartha, say the Madhyamikas, cannot be reached by words. The duality between words and the things that they designate, just as the duality which exists between knowledge and its object, belongs to samvrti, but does not exist in paramartha. Paramartha cannot be taught or known. However, the Madhyamikas have not refrained from talking about it. They resort to three methods which one finds again and again in the history of philosophy, when it is a question of expressing a concept which goes beyond the bounds of discursive knowledge. The first is the method of negation, which consists in denying a series of attributes to paramartha, yet without bestowing on it the contrary attributes. The second method bestows on it contradictory attributes. Paramartha becomes at the same time a void and a non-void, svabhava and asvabhava, sunyata (voidness) and svabhava. These two characteristics can also be simultaneously denied: paramartha is neither being nor nonbeing, neither a void nor a non-void. Therefore, the logical rule that "what contradicts itself cannot exist" (na vipratisiddham sambhavati) is no longer applicable to paramartha. The third and last method makes use of metaphor. Expressions by which the absolute is indicated, such as pratityasamutpada, sunyata, dharmata, praksti, naihsvabhavya, tathata etc. must be considered as metaphors in as much as the term "metaphor" is exact, because in each of these metaphors one of the terms is missing or rather escapes our knowledge. Thus, making use of all the resources of philosophical dialectics the Madhyamikas attempt to give an approximate idea of paramartha. But paramartha always remains beyond the comprehension of the layman. For it cannot be taught; it is only accessible, comprehensible to the saint (Yogin) who obtains deliverance. We have seen the layman being compared to the man afflicted with ophthalmia seeing hairs which do not exist in reality. The Yogin might be able to convince the layman of his illusion, but cannot prevent him from seeing those hairs; this vision disappears only when the ophthalmic has regained normal sight. It is the same with paramartha. Only that Page #5 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ THE PROBLEM OF THE ABSOLUTE layman who by himself attains true self-knowledge - he has access to paramartha. This knowledge, this "state", is dependent on mystical intuition, which dispels ignorance and so leads to deliverance. We are here beyond the realm of philosophical thought, where one proceeds with the aid of words and concepts, we are on the plane of individual experience, beyond all language and all thought. There is no doubt that paramartha, being the "supreme goal" of the believer, may be called 'the absolute'. But this absolute by its very nature is inaccessible to philosophical thought. One might try to approach it by indirect means, but all one could say or think about it would of necessity be false. It cannot be thought of as being or as nothingness. For the Madhyamikas it is "the silence of the saints". Schayer must rightly be credited with having emphasized the very important role of mystical intuition in the Madhyamika school. But it is impossible to follow him when he attempts to identify paramartha with the totality of being. According to Schayer the Madhyamikas only accept as real the totality of being and consider the plurality of ontological entities as resulting from discursive and analytical thinking and consequently as unreal. This interpretation is wrong on two points. In the first place it is contrary and entirely alien to the spirit of Buddhist thought, which never at any stage visualizes unreal constituents forming a whole, which is real. To illustrate this we need only look at the simile of the chariot and its parts, a simile taken up by Candrakirti. In opposition to the Hinayanists, but in conformity with the doctrine of the Madhyamikas, he not only considers the chariot as unreal, but moreover the parts which make up the chariot are for him just as unreal as the chariot itself. In the second place, by considering the absolute of the Madhyamikas as the totality of being, Schayer replies in philosophical terms to a question which, as we have seen, can only be solved on the mystical level. It seems that Schayer has floundered on the hazards which exist for Western thought with regard to an absolute which is neither totality nor nothingness. Stcherbatsky, for his part, has studied this same problem with a vast store of philological and philosophical knowledge, but the essential fault in his method consisted in looking for analogies with Western thinking. This often leads to a distortion of Buddhist thought, as is witnessed by his translation of sunya by "relative". Stcherbatsky reasons: - Each Page #6 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ J. W. DE JONG element is a void because it is pratityasamutpanna. Consequently, it can only be defined in relation to other elements. Each element thus becomes relative and "empty" therefore means "relative". The word "relative" has two meanings, "being in relation with" and "opposite of absolute". Stcherbatsky, in playing on those two meanings, introduces an interpretation which nowhere follows from the texts. Because of this initial error, all his subsequent interpretations of Nagarjunian thinking are false. In his article on The three directions of Buddhist philosophy published in 1934, Stcherbatsky departs even more from the spirit of Nagarjunian philosophy. Here, it is no longer a question of a "non-relative absolute", but of an "absolute truth", which he sets up as the sole principle of explanation of this world. The absolute, identified by him with dharmakaya (the body of the doctrine, the absolute) thus becomes an idea of dialectic reason. The attempt to elucidate the absolute of the Madhyamikas by means of the transcendental dialectics of the critique of pure reason, seems to indicate a lack of understanding of the mystical and soteriological character of the philosophy of the Madhyamikas. We hope that we have succeeded in establishing that it is impossible to consider the absolute of the Madhyamikas either as the totality of being or as nothingness. Such an alternative can only be put forward within the framework of western thought. The absolute has a completely different meaning for the Madhyamikas. On a philosophical level, they refrain from any opinion whatsoever, but mystical experience leads them to the absolute by way of deliverance. NOTE * The original French version of this paper was read at the 21st Congress of Orientalists in Paris on 27 July 1948. It was published in the Revue philosophique de la France et de l'etranger under the title 'Le probleme de l'absolu dans l'ecole Madhyamaka'. It contains several misprints due to the fact that no proofs were sent to the author. For instance Madhyamaka occurs twice as Madhyamaka! The author is much obliged to Miss E. J.J. C. Kat, Mrs L. A. Hercus and Professor O. Berkelbach van der Sprenkel for their help in preparing the English translation.