Book Title: Kundakunda on Samkhyapurusa
Author(s): Shivkumar
Publisher: Z_Deshbhushanji_Maharaj_Abhinandan_Granth_012045.pdf
Catalog link: https://jainqq.org/explore/250198/1

JAIN EDUCATION INTERNATIONAL FOR PRIVATE AND PERSONAL USE ONLY
Page #1 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Kundakunda on Samkhya-Purusa Dr. Shiv Kumar Kundakunda occupies a unique position in Jaina tradition. His early date, the authoritative character of his works, the utility of his writings equally for all spiritual minded persons monks or laymen, Jaina or Nonjaina, are some of the important features which raise him to the place of honour in the arena of Indian philosophy. His writings carry still more importance for history of Indian philosophy specially the Samkhya system. At his age the philosophical doctrines of the Sāṁkhya were crystalised. However, the early works of Samkhya are in oblivion and we know very little of the Sāmkhya theories before Iśvarakļşpa. Kundakunda's exposition of Samkhya presents a picture of pre-Isvarakrsna Samkhya, His exposition is significant for the reconstruction of pre-Isvarakļyna Samkhya. The points of criticism raised by the early authors like Kundakunda surely help in the further clarification of the Samkhya thought. The present paper purposes to study Kundakunda's comments on the Samkhya concept of Puruşa with the above view point. Kundakunda finds following faults in the Samkhya-explanation of the nature of Puruşa. The Samkhyas do not hold that the molecules of karmans change into various modes of karmans. Therefore, Sâmkhya theory implies the non-existence of worldly state and transmigration of soul. The same defect will further result if it is again supposed that the soul does not undergo emotional modifications like anger, etc.? Kundakunda further finds fault with the theory that agency of all kinds belongs to Prakrti and the Purusa is ever free, eternal, non-agent, not liable to any change and contamination. According to this theory Purusa is bound by karmans and the karmans are done and belong to Praksti, though the experiencing entity is the Purusa. It implies that the acting entity and the entity experiencing the fruits of the karmans are different and, hence, the acting agent will not enjoy or suffer for the acts. Consequently, it will leave no utility for the prescription of ethical discipline. No one will suffer for the sin of co-habitting with other's wife because the soul, the experiercing entity, is not involved in such an act. The karmic material in man creating or longing for woman belongs to Prakrti and the karmic material in woman longing for man also belongs to Prakrti Praksti is not an experiencing entity. Similarly, no one will experience the fruit of killing 1.414 419 HATTE F AI HERE : wwwfer niet a,' Samayasära, Kashi, 1950, 117 'अपरिणममाने हि स्वयं जीवे क्रोधादिभिः भावः। BREYTT: warfa 44441 arl,' Samayasara, 122 ‘एवं सांख्योपदेशे ये तु प्ररूपयन्तीदृशं श्रमणाः । agt wefa: TITATTU741741: = 11,'Samayasära, 340 4. Samayasāra, 335-37 जनवर्शन मीमांसा Page #2 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ others. The act of killing someone is the karmic material belonging to Prakrti and the act of being killed also is the karmic material belonging to Prakrti. Therefore, the experiencing entity, viz., the Puruşa is tot affected at all. Kundakunda's record of Sāṁkhya presents the pre-Isvarakļşna stage of Samkhya. On account of the non-availability of some work of that period we have no evidence to test the verasity of the account. The fundamental position of Sārkhya recorded by Kundakunda that Puruşa is not an agent; the agency belongs to Prakrti is in accordance with the Samkhya position. The Samkhyas emphatically maintain that Puruşa is inactive, though an experiencing entity. The Sámkhyas further emphasize as expressed by Kundakunda, that agency belongs to Prakrti. Kundakunda, in accordance with the Jaina doctrine, assigns independent status of a category to karman and thinks that the karma-molecules should be regarded as causing some mode of karmans while the self undergoes emotional modifications. When Kundakunda states that the Sāṁkhyas do not believe in it; it implies that it is the presupposition of the Jainas while the Samkhyas do not accept it. According to the Samkhyas, karmans are not an independent category. It can be reduced by them to the substratum of activity through the maxim of non-difference between act and the agent. In case of an embodied being, according to the Sankhyasútra, agency belongs to Ahankāra wbich, according to Vijñānabhiksu, represents the internal organs It is again right to say from Sarkhya point of view that the soul does not undergo any psychic change. No post-Kundakunda Samkhya author has tried to alleviate these objections. It will worthwhile, therefore, to evaluate them from Samkhya point of view. The Samkhyas do not consider acts as molecules or having substial existence. The acts cast their impressions on Buddhi and these impressions determine Purusa's future state of birth. In worldly existence karmans are erroneously ascribed to Puruşa. Even though Puruşa may appear active, yet he is not really so. Activity is falsely attributed to him due to his association with Buddhi just as a brahmin being taken up along with the thieves is falsely considered to be a thief. He can only be metaphorically considered to be active just as the lord of warriors is metaphorically called a warrior.8 The Yuktidipikā remarks that activity may be of seven kinds and Puruşa does not have any of them. (i) It does not ascertain the objects through its contact with the external and the internal organs. (ii) It does not attain the state of subordination or principal through the qualities in the form of consciousness, etc., to the three Gunas. Thus, Puruşa does not act with the Gunas as woman and a boy. (iii) It does not employ anyone to activity wbile situated at one place just as the one who sets a charriot, a cart or a machine in motion. (iv) It does not produce anything from itself like a lump of clay. (v) It does not act upon something like a potter. (vi) It does not get something done through mere order just as juggler. (vii) It does not produce something jointly like mother and father.' The Yuktidipika further observes that Puruşa cannot be active because it is conscious 1. Fra sfo fra Jasa gourmet * * f # refa worry 16.' Samayasära, 339 2. Sänkhyakārikā (with Tattvakaumudi), Delhi, 1967, 19. 3. Sāṁkhyakārikā, 11 4. En: Raf 7 yer:', Sārkhyasūtra (with Pravacanabhāsya), Delhi, 1977, 6154 5. ETC, ......... :*TUTET aftar I, Saṁkhyapravacanabhāsya, 6154 6. Sārkhyasūtra, 11164 7. Mājharavịtti (with Jayamangalā), Varanasi, 1920, 20 8. 441 Fara 544941&if qacere uafer cyfared, ae gerardo Fafer 1, Jayamangalā, 20 9. Yuktidīpika, Delhi, 1971, 19 प्राचार्यरत्न श्री वेशभूषण जी महाराज श्रमिनन्दन अन्य Page #3 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ in nature while activity is observed in unconscious objects only. Moreover, Puruşa is pure and unmixed in nature and, hence, the activity is not possible in him. Activity is observed only in the objects which are mixable in nature as is the case with milk. It suggests that the Samkhyas admit contrast or opposition between conscious and unconscious and when the unconscious element is supposed to be active on account of its very constituents, the conscious principle is supposed to be inactive. The Samkhyas hold that Puruşa is above all kinds of agency to retain its immutability and eternality. Agency involves some change and the change ultimately amounts to non-eternity. Though the Prakrti is accepted by the Sāmkhyas as eternal even though liable to change also, but such a case is not possible with Puruşa. Change is possible in case of an object having form and shape but Puruşa is not so. Moreover, agency may be understood as producing something from itself or inducing others to activity. The former is not possible because Puruşa is formless and unproductive, and the acceptance of second will lead to the further absurdities of admitting in Puruşa the desire, aversion, effort, volition, etc., as also the power of inducing others to activity, Since no activity is possible in case of Puruşa, the doership is also negated in him. In this way logically speaking from Samkhya point of view the acts cannot bring any change in Puruşa. Therefore, all types of reactions to karmans are negated in case of Puruşa. The crux of the problem lies in the supposition of the Samkhyas that inspite of its non-agency Puruşa is the experiencer of results of the acts done by Prakrti. This, according to Kundakunda involves various absurdities. The major defect is that there remains no cause to bring Puruşa to worldly state. Further, it leaves no scope for the prohibition of transgression of ethical conduct. If Puruşa is not an agent, there remains nothing to make him bhoktä. It is unreasonable to suppose that one experiences the result of the acts done by the other. The absolute uncompromising dualism of Samkhya allowing no scope for any change in soul in empirical stage exposes Samkhya for such a criticism. The Sāmkhyas justify their theory on the basis of common experience. Puruşa experiences the result of the acts though not doing the acts thinking itself identical with or owner of Buddhi which is the real agent just as the result of victory or defeat of the soldiers is experienced by the king when the king considers himself identical with or owner of the soldiers. The case is further exemplified as Puruşa though inactive experiences the result done by other entity just as the king enjoyes the grains grown by others. The Jayamangalā states that Puruşa, though inactive, is the enjoyer as a child, fire or a tree are enjoyer though doing nothing for themselves. As a matter of fact, bhoga in real sense is not possible in Purusa. Puruşa is devoid of all physical and mental faculties required for it Hence, he is considered to be an experiencer only as inactive spectator. Therefore, earlier authors of Sankhya-Yoga like Iśvara. krsnas and Vyása explain experience through Puruşa's proximity or contact with Buddhi, through which the Purusa developes in himself a sense of pleasure or pain arising of the real experience by Buddhi. Due to its contact with Buddhi which is real enjoyer Purusa considers itself an owner of Buddhi's activities and experiences pleasure or pain really situated in Buddhi. Here, process of Purusa's experience remains unexplained. ** 1. HET fafoueafafara? T r a ta!,' Yuktidipikā, 19 2. Hafra: gah 579fara f& aest wafai 471 4:arata tara: Fifa faca, Yogabhāsya, Varanasi, 1970, 1214 also : Sāṁkhyatattvakaumudi, 62 3. starfa HS119', Sāṁkhi asutra, 11105 4. aragarerea: 6499 arti fa : 1 goeisfa faqatat part of war 1,' Jayamangalā, 19 5. Sāṁkhyakārika, 20 6. 'fare per far fafarwraaf couchat Fati wafar 96963 Faifa: '' Yogabhāsya, 114 न बना PER Page #4 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Vacaspatimisral introduces his theory of single reflection and Vijnanabhiksu? of double reflection to explain it. According to the former Purusa is reflected into Buddhi and according to the latter the Buddhi having Purusa's reflection is again reflected back into Purusa. It implies that the bhoga of Purusa is different from that of Buddhi. The bhoga understood in common parlance can be divided into two stages in Sarkhya In the case of experience of taste, for example, the physiological organ of taste coveys its impression to Buddhi which assumes a state abounding in Sattva, Rafas and Tamas in accordance with the nature of the object. This is real bhoga. Purusa situated in contact with Buddhi as a witness feels himself the owner of the feeling. This is the bhoga of Purusa. Purusa develops this feeling as long as his sense of ownership is not dispelled by true knowledge of his unrelated nature. Here also a question naturally arises if experience of Purusa is not real why Purusa is considered to be an enjoyer and not an apparent enjoyer as is the case with its being active. The real position of Samkhya remains that the characteristics not demanding some change are supposed to really belong to Purusa while the others requiring some deviation from the real nature are negated in him. It clarifies why Purusa is not an agent, but is an experincer. The sufferings due to committing sin are actually experienced by Buddhi which accompanies Purusa as long as he is bound. The impressions of past acts-good or bad are stored in Buddhi while Purusa enjoys or suffers only through its association with Buddhi. The Samkhyas can thus alleviate the objection raised by Kundakunda that the experience of suffering through transgressing the moral conduct cannot be satisfactorily explained in Samkhya. As a matter of fact all experiences are unreal from Purusa's side but seem to be real due to ignorance. This is precisedly bondage. When this notion is dispelled, Purusa gets liberation. The above discussion is concluded with the following remarks. Samkhya is very close to Jainism in metaphysical position but some presuppositions of the two syslem introduce such differences. The Jainas consider karmans as molecules affecting the soul while the Sarkhyas consider karmans to be the functioning of Buddhi. According to Jaina metaphysics soul reacts to the karmans and becomes the object of vyavaharanaya, while according to the Samkhyas there is no fundamental difference in Purusa in its vyavaharska state from the parmarthika state. Even in body Purusa remains uncontaminated and without change. The above defects may apply to Samkhya if the whole situation is viewed in light of Jaina metaphysics, but the Samkhyas may alleviate them in their own way, which may not be acceptable to the Jaina position. At the present state of our knowledge we cannot rise abovecertain presuppositions to explain the metaphysical problems, and hence the objections. Kundakunda has suggested the drawbacks in uncompromising absolute dualism of Samkhya, which serves as a guideline for later authors. No Samkhya text tries to alleviate these objection from Samkhya point of view. It adds to the credit of Kundakunda that his discussion of the nature of Purusa presents picture more vivid than that presented by Samkhya authors themselves. 1. Samkhyatattvakaumudi, 5 Samkhyapravac प्रचार्यरत्न श्री वेशभूषण जी महाराज अभिनन्दन ग्रन्थ