Book Title: Conceptualizations Of Being In Classical Vaisesika
Author(s): Wilhelm Halbfass
Publisher: Wilhelm Halbfass
Catalog link: https://jainqq.org/explore/269234/1

JAIN EDUCATION INTERNATIONAL FOR PRIVATE AND PERSONAL USE ONLY
Page #1 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ CONCEPTUALIZATIONS OF 'BEING' IN CLASSICAL VAISESIKA1 By Wilhelm Halbfass, Philadelphia While 'non-being' and 'negation' are among the favourite topics of recent Nyaya and Vaisesika studies, the corresponding theme of 1 Abbreviations: Kiranavali by Udayanacarya, in: Vaisesikadarsanam... with the comm. of Prasastapada and the gloss of Udayanacarya, ed. V. P. DVIVED! (Benares 1919; Benares Sanskrit Ser. 9). Nyayabhasya, see ND1, ND'. The Nyaya-Darshana. The Sutras of Gautama and Bhasya of Vatsyayana, with two comm. ed. GANGANATHA JHA and DHUNDHIRAJA SHASTRI. Benares 1925; Chowkhamba Sanskrit Ser.). Nyayadarsana of Gautama, with the Bhasya of Vatsyayana, the Varttika of Uddyotakara, the Tatparyatika of Vacaspati, and the Parisuddhi of Udayana (Volume I - Chapter I). Ed. ANANTALAL THAKUR (Darbhanga 1967; Mithila Inst. Ser. Ancient Text 20). NK/PB Nyayakandali by Sridhara, in: Bhashya of Prasastapada, together with the Nyayakandali..., ed. V. P. DVIVEDIN (Benares 1895; Vizianagram Sanskrit Ser. 6). Nyayamanjari of Jayanta Bhatta, ed. S. N. SUKLA, 2 vols. (Benares 1934/36; Kashi Sanskrit Ser. 106). Die Nyayasutras. Text, Ubersetzung... von W. RUBEN (Leipzig 1928; repr. Nendeln 1966; Abhandlungen fur die Kunde des Morgenlandes 18/2). Kir. NBh NDI NDS NM NS NVI NVI -PB2 PP VS1 VS Vy. The Nyayavarttikam by Udyotakara Miara, ed. V. P. DUBE (Cal. cutta 1887-1914; Biblioth. Indica). Nyayavarttika, see ND'. Prasastapadabhasyam... with comm. Sukti, by Jagadisa Tarka. lankara, Setu by Padmanabha Misra, and Vyomavati by Vyomasivacarya, ed. GOPINATH KAVIRAJ (Benares 1924-1930; Chowkhamba Sanskrit Ser.). Prakaranapancika of Salikanatha Misra, with Nyayasiddhi (by Jayapurinarayana Bhatta), ed. A. SUBRAHMANYA SASTRI (Banaras 1961; Banaras Hindu Univ. Darsana Ser. 4). The Vaisesika Sutras of Kanada..., transl. by N. SINHA (Allahabad 1911; Sacred Books of the Hindus 6; contains also the Sanskrit text of the Sutras). Vaisesikasutra of Kanada, with the comm. of Candrananda, crit. ed. JAMBUVIJAYAJI (Baroda 1961; Gaekwad's Oriental Ser. 136). Vyomavati by Vyomasiva, see PB. Page #2 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 184 WILHELM HALBTASS 'being', although both historically and systematically more-or at least equally-fundamental, has only met with a somewhat casual interest'. The conception of satta and bhava as highest universal' (param samanyam) is, no doubt, sufficiently familiar; yet, its exact implications in the context of classical Vaisesika, its interrelations with astitva, sattasambandha, svatmasattva etc., and its function and describability in terms of, or in contrast to, such Western concepts as 'existence' have never been thoroughly investigated. One of the consequences of this has been that discussions of abhava are often lacking in perspective and do not do justice to the full and proper historical and systematic dimensions of their theme. It usually remains unanswered or even completely unquestioned how and why abhava was "added" as a seventh padartha, and how, and to what extent, certain ways of conceiving of 'being' may have been conducive to certain corresponding ways of conceiving of 'non-being'. - At any rate: An exploration of the role and development of abhava especially in Nyaya and Vaisesika is necessarily incomplete as long as it does not go hand in hand with an exploration of the theme and terminology of 'being' which forms its counterpart and background; and this, of course, The following is a revised and considerably expanded version of a paper read at the 29th International Congress of Orientalists, Paris 1973. In the meantime, the stimulating discussions with the participants of my Seminar in Indian Philosophy (Oriental Studies 711) at the University of Pennsylva nia, with whom I read some of the related texts, gave me a welcome oppor. tunity to re-examine this complex of questions. Cf., e. g., J. B. BHATTACHARYA, Negation (Calcutta 1965). J. F. STAAL, Negation and the Law of Contradiction in Indian Thought. Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies 25/1 (1962) 52-71. - B. K. MATILAL, The Navya-Nyaya Doctrine of Negation (Cambridge, Mass. 1968). B. GUPTA, Story of the Evolution of the Concept of Negation. Beitrage zur Geistesgeschichte Indiens, Festschr. f. E. FRAUWALLNER (Wien 1968; WZKSO 12/13) 115-118. D. SHARMA, The Negative Dialectios of India (East Lansing, Mich. 1970). See below, notes 26-28; more specific references to this theme are to be found in D. N. SHASTRI, Critique of Indian Realism (Agra 1964), and especially in R. R. DRAVID, The Problem of Universals in Indian Philosophy (Delhi etc. 1972). A satisfactory treatment of this intricate historical question would require a more careful distinction of the Nyaya and Vaisesika traditions than it is usually met with especially in Indian contributions. Within Vaisesika itself, it is remarkable that Candramati's Dasapadarthasastra, in which the Vaisesika system is restricted to a 'doctrine of categories', presents 'non-being' as a separate padartha, while Prasastapada's Padarthadharmasamgraha, which re-emphasizes the more traditional 'physicalistic' aspects of the Vaisesika philosophy of nature, has no room for it. Page #3 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Conoeptualization of 'Being 185 also requires an awareness of the implications of our own terminological tools in the area of being' and 'non-being'. It is certainly not very helpful to use phrases like "negation as an entity" or "non-existence as reality", as long as it remains unclarified how the "reality" with which 'non-being' itself is credited has to be distinguished from, and related to, that meaning of 'to be' according to which non-being is not being. The following remarks are meant to be preliminary and do not claim to present anything like an exhaustive answer and solution. They are by and large confined to classical Vaisesika texts of the 1st millenium A. D., especially to Prasastapada's Padarthadharmasam. graha and its commentaries, and they are focussing on the genesis, meaning and function of that conceptual construction which is indicated by the terms satta, astitva, sattasambandha and svatmasattva. - Within the Indian panorama, the Vaisesika way of dealing with 'being' is cer. tainly not the most inspiring and convincing one; yet, it is illustrative in its stubborn and honest one-sidedness, and moreover, it is one of the most important catalysts for the development of Indian 'ontology', and highly effective in terms of the critical responses which it stimulates. As to the terminology of being in the Vaisesikasutras, the follow. ing short reminders may be sufficient for the purposes of our present discussion: In this text of notoriously unsatisfactory philological status, two terms, satta and bhava, represent the understanding of 'being' as the highest samanya?, i. e. the most universal, all-pervasive common feature-perceptible by all senses-, of 'substances', 'qualities and 'motions' (dravya, guna, karman). It appears likely that at an earlier stage Vaisesika did not go beyond these three 'categories' or constituents of reality. And if, in accordance with the testimony of Vyomaciva and others, Kanada actually announced his philosophy as a programme K. H. POTTER, Presuppositions of India's Philosophies (Englewood Cliffs, X. J. 1963) 200ff. * D. N. SHASTRI, Critique of Indian Realism (Agra 1964) 395ff. Cf. VS'. I, 2, 4ff.; on the perceptibility of bhavs cf. VS' IV, 1, 14 ( VS'IV, 1, 13). . VSI I, 1, 4--the only passage presenting an enumeration of all six 'categories' and using the term padartha -- is neither found in Vsnor in the Sutra version of the anonymous commentary published by ANANTALAL THAKUR (Vaisesikadarsana, Darbhanga 1957); the authenticity of VS I, 1, 4 was already questioned by M. R. BODAs in his introduction to Tarkasamgraha of Annambhatta, ed. Y. V. ATHALYE (Bombay 1897; ropr. of 2nd ed. Poona 1963) XXXIII ff. Cf. Vy. 47: yad sha bhavaru pam tat sarvam mayd-upacarthydavyam; Vy. 492: yad bhavarupar tat sarvam abhi doydmi. Lorike Page #4 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 186 WILHELN HALBTA88 of naming, enumerating whatever has the character of being (bhavarupa), we may assume that he was referring to this group of 'categories' which are obviously more suitable for being enumerated than the 'universals' (samanya) etc. It would, of course, be idle to speculate on whether 'being' was already an explicitly developed theme of thought in "original" Vaisesika, or whether the idea of 'being', which forms the horizon of this programme of exhaustive enumeration and classification, was simply and commonsensically taken for granted. - How the way of presenting asat and contrasting it with sat in VS IX fits in with the original bhara-orientation, and whether or to what extent this section of the text may at all be regarded as old and authentic, is a question which we cannot enlarge upon here". The most familiar rendering of satta and its terminological equivalent bhava is 'existence'13; this translation demands some caution insofar as it should not be taken as suggesting any contrast to 'essence'. Although the connotation of 'actuality' and 'manifestness' is undeniable in the actual usage of satis, satta, as used thematically and terminologically, leaves 'essence' and 'existence' undivided, just as it does not establish any confrontation between 'being' and 'nothing'. Rather, it puts what. ever there is, or 'exists', on a common ground with anything else that exists, thus providing a basis for comprehensive enumeration and classification. We may also note here that the traditional verbal and actional connotations of bhava, accentuated especially by grammarians and grammatically oriented philosophers", do not affect the Vaibesika * On the implication of completeness and exhaustiveness in Kanada's programme cf., e. g., NK 89: ... sarvajnena maharpind sarodrthopadeadya prarytiena ...; this formula is repeated on p. 149. u See above, n. 4. 1 This translation is taken for granted in most of the general histories of Indian philosophy; it is also used, e. g., in the majority of texts referred to in notes 2-3 and 26-27. B. K. MATILAL, however (cf. n. 2), has "beingness" in his more recent publication: Epistemology, Logic, and Grammar in Indian Philosophical Analysis (The Hague 1971) he paraphrases "existence or being-ness".-D. H. H. INGALLS, Materials for the Study of Navya. Nyaya Logic (Cambridge, Mass. 1951)-generally a work of considerable terminological impact upon English translations of philosophical Sanskrit terms-gives "reality". 1 This connotation in the understanding of sat is also evident in the rejection of the implicit, potential 'being' which is implied by the Sarpkhya dotrine of satkarya; cf., e. g., NK 143f. - M. BIARDEAU states: "... la pensee indienne ne distingue a aucun moment l'essence de l'existence" (La philosophie de Mandana Misra vue a partir de la Brahmasiddhi, Paris 1969, p. 71). 1 Cf. L. RENOU, Terminologio grammaticale du Sanskrit (Paris 1957) 243244; 470-71. has beinted Made in Mateo 1971) hos Logic, Page #5 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Conceptualization of 'Being' 187 usage. - Although awkward, an expression like beingness' might therefore be a more appropriate translation of satta. While satta and bhava, if and insofar as they are used terminologi. cally, are obviously treated as synonyms in the Vaisesikasutras15, there is, nevertheless, a functional difference which has to be taken into consideration: While satta has a strictly terminological role, to which it remains basically confined also in later texts, bhavale is much more flexible and open to various other, less terminological functions, which should not be taken as evidence for the Vaisesika doctrine of being' or 'beingness'17. Yet, this variety of other usages is by no means negli. gible. The very fact that it exists and that it accompanies, and inevitably intrudes into, the doctrinal and terminological statements about 'being' is itself a potential stimulus of raising questions and objections, 6. g. concerning such issues as the problem of self-reference, and it may thus have its direct or indirect bearing on the thematic and doctrinal level, too 18. Prasasta pada goes on using satta and bhava in accordance with the language of the Sutras, presenting 'beingness' as an attribute compar. able with, and only more extensive in its scope, than 'blueness'; insofar as they are factors of unity and similarity, objective bases of recurrent perception and linguistic repetition, they are on equal terms. In trying to accentuate his point, Prasasta pada even refers to the unity of the blue liquid which can give blueness to many different things in the process of dying: yatha parasparavisistesu carmavastrakambaladigv ekasman niladravyabhisambandhan nilam nilam iti pratyayanuvyttih, tathi paraspararitistesu draryagunakarmasv avisista sat sad iti pratyayanuvyttih, sa ca- arthantarad bhavitum arhati-iti, yat tad arthantaram sa satta-iti siddha. - In addition to satta, however, Prasasta pada has a term which is symptomatic of his way of restructuring and rounding off the Vaisesika system: the common abstract attribute' (sadharmya) astitoa, " The synonymity of both is explicitly stated by Candrananda on VS' I, 2, 4. - There is no evidence for equating Kanada's bhava with Prebastapada's Astitva, as D. N. SHASTRI, Critique of Indian Realism (Agra 1964) 148, would like to do. 16 To a lesser degree, this may be said about sattva (not in Vs), too, which appears sometimes in terminologically less committed functions than atti; cf. Vy. 126; NK 19. 17 In contrast with VS I, 2, 4, cf., e. h., the less terminological was of bhava and abhava in VS I, 2, 9ff. (= 'I, 2, 10 ff.). 1 Cf. the two levels of using abhava in locutions liko abhdaasya prihag anupadeso bhdvopdratantryan na to abhavde (NK 7). 10 PB 311-312. Page #6 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 188 WILHELM HALBTASS 'is-ners**, which, together with jneyatva ('knowableness') and abhi. dheyatva ('nameableness'), covers all six 'categories' and can accordingly be predicated of satta itself. 'Beingness', like all 'universals' (samanya), 'is' itself in that sense of 'to be' which is represented by astitva; its 'being' in the sense of satta would, of course, lead to an infinite regress (anarnstha). -- Although there is no such second-level term and concept of 'being in the Vaisesikasutras, there are nevertheless certain locutions -e. g. draryagunakarmabhyo 'rthantaram satta 11 - which may be taken as presupposing or implicitly requiring it; the word arthantara, often, but somewhat loosely used in the Sutras, is, as we have seen, explicitly referred to by Prasastapada, and it is obviously one of the signposts for his account of being'* Subsequent to his introduction of the term astitva-sannam api padarthanam astitvabhidheyatvajneyatvani --Prasastapada characterizes drarya, guna and karman as having satta sambandha, 'connection with beingness and samanya, visesa and samavaya as having svatmasattva, 'beingness of, or by virtue of, the own nature'. He does not explain these terms, which-if we may disregard here the occasional use of sattanusambandhaus -- occur only once in his text. There have been several usually rather incidental attempts to translate, paraphrase or account for this conceptual structure and its constituents. M. HIRIYANNA explains svatmasat as "intrinsically real" and contrasts it with the "bor. rowed being" of dravya etc.; he adds: "This distinction is remarkably like that between subsistence and existence" 24--but without really clarifying his understanding of these Western terms. G. PATTI interprets astitva as 'essentia' in the scholastic sense and satta as 'existentia', and he paraphrases svatmasattva as "Wesen, das sich selbst genugend ist". T. VETTER finds intimations of a transcendental approach (in the Kantian and Post-Kantian sense) in the Vaisesika formulations.By and large, the implications of the fact that there is a twofold concep * On the conception of a mahasamanya as coinciding with padarthatoa according to Jaina commentators cf. H. UI, The Vaiseshika Philosophy ("Varanasi 1962) 35ff.; it seems that Candramati himself does not have tho term and conocpt of astitva. 11 VSI': 1, 2, 8. * See above, n. 19.-In Candramati, sotto appears a separato padartha. # PB 16. # PB 17; 19. # PB 312. * Indian Philosophical Studies I (Mysore 1957) 111. >> Der Samavays im Nyaya-Vaisesika-System (Roma 1956) 143. * Erkenntnisprobleme bei Dharmakirti (Wien 1964) 94. Page #7 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Conceptualization of 'Being' 189 tuul purcetrom. st. satta-ustna on the one hand, sattasambandi svatmasattva on the other hand, have not really become thematic in these discussions. Returning now to Prasastapada's own text, we may first of all observe that the terms in the immediate neighbourhood of sattasambandha resp. satmasattva suggest some commonsensically obvious implications of such a distinction. The bringing about of 'merit' and 'demerit', the status of cause and effect, impermanence, etc. (dharma dharmakartstva, karanatva, karyatva, anityatva) - these features are restricted to the realm of particulars, which are, and have a concrete, 'manifest' being, insofar as satta is inherent in them". With regard to the second group of 'categories'--sc. 'universals', 'individualities' and 'inherence' - Prasastapada says: samanyadinam trayanam svatmasattvam buddhilaksanatvam so akaryatvan akaranatvam asamanyavisesavattvam nityatvam arthasabdanabhidheyatvam a ca-iti*. 'Universals' etc. can be said to be, insofar as they are genuine objects of knowledge; they are irreducible constituents, parts of the world; they are, however, not physically separable entities, nor metaphysically superior archetypal powers. As for astitva, which covers both groups of 'categories' and their respective ways of being, the conjunction with 'knowableness' and 'nameableness', together with the whole context in which it appears, gives us some hints: astitva means the applicability of the word 'is', i. e. the fact that there is an objective basis and condition for saying 'it is', in the sense of its being identifiable, recognizable, distinguishable from, not reducible to other entities, and thereby knowable, speakable, suitable as truth-condition for thought and speech. - We may recall here Prasastapada's familiar practice of justifying the assumption of entities by claiming them as indispensable causes or conditions (karana, hetu, nimitta") of undeniable occurrences in thought and speech (pratyaya, vyavahara). The word asti may be used to accentuate the veridical claim attached to such assumptions, as, e.g., in the following statement PB 17-18. * The term buddhilakpanatva obviously refers to the buddhya pekpam of VS". I, 2, 3; cf. NK 19. ArthasabdanabhidKeyatva reflects Vg1 VIII, 2, 3(= VS: VIII, 14): artha iti dravyagunakarmasu; as to the characteristic akaranatva, Sridhara specifies that it can only exclude samavdyycaamavdyikaranata, not, how. ever, nimittakaranatva as capability of 'causing' knowledge or apprehension (NK 20). # PB 19. >> Cf. Vy. 118. " On 'causality in the case of 'universals' eto. see abovo, n. 31. Page #8 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 190 WILHELM HALBFA88 with regard to samavaya:... iti pratyayadarsanad asty esam sambandha iti jnayates. Sridhara praphrases astitva as svarupavattva, and he determines that it is the characteristic nature of any entity which constitutes its 'is-ness' (yasya rastuno yat svarupam tad eva tasya-astitvam *). Obviously, this is in keeping with the connotation of identifiability and recognizability in Prasasta pada's use of Astitva and, moreover, with his use of the term svarupa, as in atmasvarupa, sarupabheda, svarupalocanamatra, etc. 7. At the same time, however, the concept of svarupa, in its functional openness and almost universal applicability, can hardly safeguard the ontological positivity which Prasastapada connects with his notion of astitva, which, according to the whole context and orientation of his thought, is not supposed to include 'non-being' (abhava). - Already Udayana romarks: abharas tu starupavan api ...*, and a critic like Sriharsa can justly emphasize that identifiability and distinguishability, * as constituted by svarupa, are no basis for contrasting 'being' and 'non being', reality and fiction". - In spite of its veridical functions, Prasastapada's astitva preserves a basically 'existential' connotation. It is insofar characteristically different from tattva, as it is at home in the more epistemologically oriented Nyaya, where it is explained as including both sat and asat: Both 'being' and 'non-being', 'presence' and 'absence' may be objective correlates of thought and speech, insofar as they may have a truth-conditioning function with regard to positive resp. negative propositions". Tattva is an essentially veridical term; and it indicates a framework and context of thought which was certainly more conducive to the later development of abhava than the original, 'positively' ontological world-orientation of Vaisesika. The second group of 'categories', sc. 'universals' etc., may easily be subsumed under this all-inclusive notion of astitva: Their whole # PB 325; cf. 311: yod anugatam asti ... (on samanya). * NK 16. Cf. the uses of nabhava, svarupa, wadharma in NBh on IV, 1, 38 (NDI 707 ff.; NS IVa 35 in Ruben's edition). " PB 311f.; 186f. * Kir. 6; Udayana discusses why abhava has not been mentioned a a special 'category' and adds: pratiyoginirupanddhinanirupanatvde, na tu tucchatuit cf. also Nyayakusumanjali on Karika I, 10. -Unlike later commentators, Udayana does not, as it is sometimes maintained, take astitva as including abhava, and insofar not as co-extensive with jneyatva and abhidheyatva; cf. Kir. 27. >> Cf. Khandanakhandakhadya, ed. with Hindi comm. by C. SUKLA (Benares '1961/62) 21 ff.; also 421ff. * Cf. NBh and NV on I, 1, 1 (ND: 1; 11f.); concerning V8 I, 1, 4, which may have been modelled on NS I, 1, 1, se above, n. 8. Page #9 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Conceptualization of 'Being' 191 'is-ness' is svatmasattva, often paraphrased as svarupasatta 4; as such, it consists exclusively in their being identifiable natures, forms of their oun and is consequently, although implying 'absence of beingness' (sattaviraha"), eternal, unchangeable and independent. The application of 'is-ness' to the particular 'manifest' 'substances' (drarya) etc. and their way of being is more intricate. In order to avoid confusion, we have to keep in mind that there are two kinds or levels of ontological dichotomy in Prasastapada (satta --astitva and sattasambandha - Svatmasattva), and we have to take into consideration that in the passage under discussion he uses the word sattasambandha, not simply satta". Within the context of his thought, this is by no means negligible: Dealing with the common and specific attributes of all six "categories', he can, according to his own principles, only speak in terms of sadharmya and vaidharmya, not in terms of samanya resp. samanyavisepa. Therefore, any use of satta in this context and on this level of discourse would be illegitimate. The 'categories' and their instances, such as satta itself, represent his way of naming and enumerating the components of the real world; they are immediately world-oriented ('intentio prima'). The dharmas (sadharmya -vaidharmya) as abstract attributes", on the other hand, do not present any further separable or juxtaposable world. components, but ways and viewpoints of comparing and conceptually relating the actual world.components. They constitute a kind of second level of the system, which still deals with the real objective world, but is less immediately world-oriented, more concerned with systematic and structural devices and without the crudely hypostasizing ontological commitment of the 'first level'. - Prasastapada does not have a theory of semantic levels, but he has a keen systematic mind and is keeping himself constantly aware of the danger of anavastha, 'infinite regress'. He carefully avoids confusing his two levels of discourse and never treats a samanya and & sadharmya as commensurable or comparable. Consequently, the question what satta and astitva have in common remains unasked; and the 'ontological dichotomy' which is involved here does not become explicitly thematic.-- The term sattasambandha, which is used in the sadharmya analysis, does not refer to satta, 'being. a Cf. NK 19: ... sparupam yot admdnyadinam tad eva tepdm sattvam. In Vyomaciva's 'ontological' sections, the notion of sarupa plays << less prominent role than in Sridhara and Udayana. Vyomasiva seems to be more interested in psychological explanation than in conceptual analysis. 4 Kir. 30. # Although this distinction is not really carried through by tho oom. mentators. u On the use of dharma, of. NK 16: yady api dharmdil pappadarthobhyo na vyatiricyante... Page #10 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 192 WILHELX HALBLASS ness' as such, but rather to the condition of being related to it, which, though being common to all the individual 'substances' etc., is not an actually pervasive and ontologically separable factor of community liko satta itself: Being found in all particular 'manifest' entities (vyakti), it nevertheless leaves them confined to their particularity. It is the universality of beingness' in the particularity of its being 'manifested' by individual entities. In a sense, sattasambandha comes closer to 'existence' than satta itself", insofar as there is a more notable connotation of actuality and temporality: 'Connection with beingness' is the, in itself temporal and in the more ordinary cases impermanent, condition of being qualified by the qualifying universal 'beingness', which is as such eternal or rather atemporal. - In Prasastapada commentaries and other later texts, the formula 'connection with beingness' often serves --especially in the compound svakaranasattasambandha, 'connection with the beingness of the own cause'--the purpose of explaining utpatti, 'genesis', and karyatva, the destructible contingent being of effects, i.e. composite entities. The question of its applicability to the ultimately simple and indestructible components or causes, such as the atoms, remains out of consideration or is, obviously not quite in agreement with Prasastapada's own position, explicitly dispensed with. - It may be noted that in later texts not only sattasambandha tends to coincide with 'destructibility' resp. 'producibility'; also satta itself, not being distin. guished from sattasambandha, appears in a more temporal perspective, and its role is often reduced to serving as a counterpart and presupposi. tion of pradhvamsabhava, i. e. non-being resulting from destruction.For a Vaibesika critic of the 1st millenium like salikanatha, on the other hand, satta still represents an understanding of 'being' which leaves no room for temporality and change". Accepting Prasastapada's own terms, the structure of his system and hiss way of not explicitly touching upon certain questions, one may concede that a conceptual settlement has been reached, and that 4 The basic unsuitability of 'existence' -- 'essence', 'contingent' and 'necessary' being, 'esse ab alio'--'esse & se' etc. for the translation of Pra. kastapada's 'ontological' terminology should, however, always be kept in mind. - On the temporality of ratudsambandha cf. Bhasarvajna, Nyiya. bhusana (Varanasi 1968) 468. E. g. Vy. 126; 129; 143; NK 18. . 67 E. g. NK 17; Vy. 126. Cf., e. g. Dinakari on Visvanatha's Karikavall, v. 9; od. SANKARA RAXA SASTRY (Mylapore, Madras 1923) 114. Cf. Rjuvimala on Prabhakara's Bphatl, od. A. CHWASWAN Serra (Banares 1929) 120f.; also PP 97 ff. Page #11 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Conoeptualization of 'Being' 193 his treatment of the problem of 'being' has its peculiar consistency. There are at least two ways and levels of talking about 'being': There is 'being' as satta, the most comprehensive instance of the 'category' samanya, hypostasized 'somethingness' which has itself become a something, a datum of sense-perception, one real and ontologically separable factor and component among others which constitute the world as it is given to us; and there is being' a8 astitva, which merely, and in a sense tautologically, states that whatever is, is (asti), i. e. has a certain character of positivity, identifiability.- Acceptance of this framework is, of course, not what we may expect from an opponent; and in the following centuries, this whole complex of being' was a highly welcome target of criticism and ridicule especially for Buddhists, Jainas, and Mimamsa kas, then also for Vedantins 50. The commentators- I am mainly referring to Vyomasiva, Sridhara, and Udayana -are forced into sometimes rather desperate conceptual efforts; occasionally, however, they cannot avoid to lay bare and make explicit the inherent tensions and ambiguities of Prasastapada's apparently well-closed system. It is beyond the scope of our present discussion to give a detailed account 51 of the origin and systematic implications of the objections to satta as they are stated in the purvapakpa sections of the Vaibesika commentators. Consequently, we cannot fully explicate how these com. mentators try to defend and justify both satta and astitva, nor can we analyze their attempts to rephrase the conceptual relationship between sattasambandha and svatmasattva; it may suffice here to recall their practice of utilizing the concept of 'metaphorical being' (upacarasatta, aupacariki satta 5) and of applying the principle of 'co-occurrence' (samanadhikaranya ss; cf. also sadharanadharmadhikaranata ), which accounts for the extrapolation of 'being' to whatever has a common substratum with beingness', i. e. also to 'universals' etc. - At any rate, 'beingness', satta itself is stubbornly defended against epistemological, pragmatistic and other decompositions (pramanasambandhayogyata, arthakriyakaritra, vartamanakalasambandhitva 56). The argumentation is . Such as Sriharsa (800 above, n. 39). " Exemplary materials from these discussions will be presented and analysed in a monograph now under preparation. " Cf. Vyomaciva's use of upacarasatia, Vy. 124ff.; on the function of this concept in the philosophy of grammar 100 K. A. SUBRAYANA IA Bhartshari (Poona 1969) 209ff. Cf. Kir. 24: sattaikarthasamavdya. - Vy. 142f. # E. g. Vy. 126f.; NK 12; vartamdnatva becomes again prominent in Raghuntha; cf. K. H. POTTER, The Padarthatattvanirupapam of Raghu. Datha Siromani (Cambridge, Mass. 1967) 61f. Page #12 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 194 WILHELM HALBFASS largely ad hominem; and all the opposing interpretations of 'being' are charged with leading to an infinite regress (anarastha, anavasthana 5). However, it is evident that the positive establishment of satta as common denominator of whatever exists and its defense in terms of 'supreme similarity' becomes increasingly difficult and awkward in this atmosphere of discussion. Sridhara incidentally concedes that this alleged similarity of all 'beings' ultimately consists in their being distinguishable from non-being 57. In this way, he obviously weakens the old claims concerning the independence (svatantrya) of the conception of being' 58 and consequently the defense-line against the Buddhist apohavada.-Astitva, being more of a functional concept, is in general more open to re-definition and re-interpretation, and accordingly subject to a process of semantic evaporation which is due to an increasingly epistemological and reflexive attitude. Its positivity is eventually relegated to the positivity, the affirmative character of the apprehension of which it is the object or content: Sridhara explains astitva occasionally as vidhi pratyayavisayatva 5o; Udayana's widely accepted formula is vidhimukhapratyayavisayatva. The difficulties and potential consequences of defining astitva as svaruparattve, as identifiability, distinguishability of what. ever may 'be' identifiable or distinguishable, have already been referred to - The problems inherent in Prasastapada's 'ontological construction and generally in the conception of satta as pervasive and qualifying sa manya of whatever is sat are further illustrated by a question which was not explicitly considered by Prasastapada himself, but, as one of stock arguments of the Vaisesika critics, had to be faced and discussed by his commentators: Does that which is connected with 'beingness' have any 'being' in itself or not? Pursuing the implications of this question we may add: 'Is there' anything like an individual entity in itself of which 'beingness' would just be a further 'real predicate'? u Vy. 124 ff.; NK 12f. 17 NK 12: ... tesam abhavavilaksanena rupena tulyata pratibha.sands; in his defense against Prabhakara objections (cf. PP 97ff.), Sridhara has to face the fundamental difficulties which Aristotle avoided by not accepting 'being' as 'highest genus' (nor any summum genus at all). 56 Cf. NV 11f.; this passage is referred to by Sridhara, NK 226. * NK 15; cf. NK 226: vidhirupats. * Kir. 27; Udayana adds pratiyogyanapekpanirupanatva. " See above, notes 38-39. * Vy. 126: kim sala saldm atha-asatam; NK 17: kim sattdsambandhan mato 'sato vd. - But see also below, n. 76. According to Kant's formulation, Kritik der reinen Vernunft B 626: "Sein ist offenbar kein reales Pradikat ...". Page #13 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 195 Conceptualization of 'Being' Is there an astitva of 'substances' etc. apart from their satta? And does satta actually add anything to what an individual thing 'is' as such? One method of reacting to this notorious dilemma (vikalpa) had been not to accept it as such and to deny any temporal, 'physical' implications of the idea of a 'connection with beingness': na satah sattasambandhah, na- asatah | yada-eva tad vastu tada-eva sattaya sam. baddham....The Vaisesika commentators are familiar with kind of reply and refer to it in their argumentation; yet this does not take care of all their problems: The basic Vaisesika attitude of dissection and juxtaposition precludes them from simply and firmly grounding the meaning and unity of 'being' in the concrete unity of the vastu; as their reactions demonstrate, the difficulties caricatured by this 'dilemma about being or non-being' (sadasadvikalpa) are, indeed, deeply rooted in the ontological orientation of the system. Especially Sridhara, blurring in a sense Prasastapada's distinction of two levels of discourse, goes rather far in suggesting an actual onto. logical cleavage. Arguing that both astitva and satta are necessary to adequately describe and explain the world as it is, he says that while satta is necessary to account for our apprehension of 'being' in its unity and universality, astitva or svarupavattva is indispensable insofar as satta would never inhere in what does not have a svarupa, a characteristic nature of its own". Arguing against the attempt of the Prabhakaras to understand 'being' in terms of the mere vastusvarupa, the 'characteristic nature' and self-identity of each single entity, and without the assumption of a real sattasamanya (satta being reduced to an 'extrinsic qualification'-upadhi, sc. pramanasambandhayogyata, 'suitability for being connected with a means of knowledge'"), Sridhara never says, nor does he presuppose, that there is no such thing as an independent vastu svarupa. Instead, his whole emphasis is on that it would not be sufficient to explain our apprehension of the unity of 'being' in the different entities. Vice versa, the Prabhakara's denial of an independent real 44 NV 322; cf. NM I 286. "Cf. Vy. 126: tad asat, nispadasambandhayor ekakalatvat; cf. also NK 15 (concerning samaraya in general): svakaranasamarthyad upajayamanam eva tatra sambadhyate, yatha chidikriya chedyena Vy. 690 has: nisthasambandhayor ekakalatvad iti; this may go back the Vakys and Bhasya commented upon in Prasastapada's lost Tika: see below, n. 76. 4 NK 16. 7 See the references given in n. 49; a long discussion concerning this point is found in Mandana, Brahmasiddhi, ed. 8. KUPPUSWAMI SASTRI (Madras 1937) 85 ff. Cf. also pp. 289 ff. (on svarupamatra as skaki bhavah). NK 11f.; cf. Kir. 23. Page #14 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 196 WILHELM HALBFASS satta, by reducing it to pramanasambandhayogyata, does not at all affect his acceptance of the independent extramental existence of things (vastu) as such. And, of course, no Vaisesika author ever says that without satta there would simply be nothing; the very idea of 'nothing' or 'nothingness' is, in fact, quite outside their horizon. On the other hand, to predicate satta of 'universals' etc. is regarded as mistaken only insofar as it superimposes a factor of unity and universality upon what has, or 'is', just its own form', svarupa". Satta, thus reduced to a factor of unity-in-diversity, appears as a kind of extra to the individual existence of each particular (dravya etc.); and according to its status as a real, epistemologically and ontologically separable 'universal', it cannot simply coincide with, and not even completely depend upon, the fact that things are or exist. Satta is not the being of the world, which is as such never really thematized; satta is and remains an occurrence in the world. What seems to be at the bottom of this understanding of 'being', and especially of the conceptual bifurcation of satta and astitva, is a deep-rooted ambivalence in classical Vaisesika which again is the result of an attempted integration of different historical levels, that is of an enumerative, physically oriented philosophy of nature and of a categorial analysis. In other words: It has to do with a tendency to present findings of categorial analysis in the old and traditional shape of an enumeration, juxtaposition of different entities. Initially, there may have been an enumerative philosophy of nature in terms of 'elements' or 'substances'. But then the substances themselves became subject to what is actually a categorial and conceptual analys and decomposition. They were distinguished from, and stripped of, their qualifications resp. qualifiers (visesana), which-satta being regarded as one of themappear as separate entities, side by side with their qualificands (visesya). The Vaisesika's drarya is insofar quite different from the Mimamsaka's vastu or, e. g., Aristotle's Tode T. Nevertheless-and this adds to the ambivalence-it continues being regarded as having its own, quasicomplete nature and being, and even some kind of separate percepti. bility"; it is never reduced to an unformed l and not even to what is NK 19: bhinnasvabhavesv ekanugamo mithya-eva, evarupagrahanam tu na mrsa, svarupasya yatharthatvat. 7 Vyomasiva (Vy. 143) says about 'universals', in a context dealing with satta: samastasrayavindee 'py avasthanam isyate. " Cf. L. SCHMITHAUSEN, Zur Lehre von der vorstellungsfreien Wahrnehmung bei Prasastapada. Wiener Zeitschrift fur die Kunde Sudasiens 14 (1970) 125-129. How the 'facticity' and 'positivity' implied in the perception of the actual thing (dravya) qua viscaya has to be related to the Page #15 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ Conceptualization of 'Being' called 'bare particular' by some recent and contemporary philosophers".-In spite of their conceptual courage, the Vaisesikas are too commonsensical to enlarge upon the more startling 'ontological' consequences of their system according to which, at the end of a process of enumerative dissection into factors and constituents, the unity of the world and each single thing has to be restored by postulating an additional enumerable and juxtaposable factor, i. e. 'inherence', samavaya. 197 In conclusion, we may say that astitva has not only the function of circumscribing the whole realm of 'categories', but also of regaining a meaning and type of 'being' which is not, like satta, a logically, epistemologically and ontologically separable attribute of what there is. Satta and astitva represent two different levels of philosophical reflection and thematization". In trying to integrate these in one system, Prasastapada shows a sound systematic instinct. Nevertheless, his construction remains easily accessible to misunderstandings and attacks, and, as the further development shows, it does not provide any firm and fertile ground for a tradition of ontology: While the old concept of satta appears more and more fossilized and obsolete", astitva represents a meaning of 'being' which tends to evaporate with the development of epistemological reflection, insofar as it tends to coincide with the mere objectivity or thematicity of whatever has been objectified and is positively taken into account at any given level of thought75. However, in stating that the Vaisesika conceptualizations of 'being' do not really lead to a tradition of ontology, we should not forget what apprehension of satta qua visegana is a question which does not really become thematic in Vaisesika; and there is nothing like the Vedanta attempt to equate what is given to 'indeterminate' (nirvikalpaka) perception with 'pure being' (sanmatra, sattamatra). 7 Cf. M. J. Loux (ed.), Universals and Particulars (New York 1970), esp. 235 ff. "Relating our discussion to the old theme of the one and the many, we may say that satta represents a meaning of 'being' according to which it is basically one, while astitva posits what there is in its irreducible mani. foldness. It is symptomatic that satta itself is understood in terms of astitva. 74 It is no longer acceptable to Raghunatha Siromani; cf. reference given in n. 55. " Insofar, it may be said to coincide with padarthatva (cf. n. 20) and to amount to a sense of 'being' as mere 'somethingness', as it is advocated by what is known in our days as 'allgemeine Gegenstandstheorie'.-On the difficulties of defining astitva, cf. Vardhamana and Rucidatta on Udayana in: Kiranavall by Udayanacaryya, ed. S. C. SARVVABHOUMA (Calcutta 1911) 137ff. Page #16 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 198 WILHELM HALBTASS has already been emphasized in our introductory remarks--sc. the historical role of this 'ontological theory as an important, stimulating and truly catalytical target of criticism?6. * According to Mallavadin's Dvadasaranayacakra, as presented by Simhasuri, it seems that Prasastapada's (= Prasastamati's) lost Tika on a Vaibesikabhasya (by Atreya !) contained more detailed discussions of 'ontological' questions, esp. of the concept of sattasambandha; see the extracts from Mallavadin's work in: VS' 147-152. Mallavidin explains Prasastapada's understanding of the formula nisthasambandhayor ekaka. latvdt (also quoted by Vyomasiva, cf. above, n. 65) as follows: siddhasya vastunah sakaranaih sattayd ca sambandha iti prdeastamato 'bhiprdyah (loc. cit. 162). - The question to what extent Prasastapada's 'ontology' may have been prepared during the somewhat obscure period between VS and PB, which was excluded from the present, more systematically oriented sketch, will be taken up in the projected monograph, referred to in n. 31.