Book Title: Book Review Encyclopedia Of Indian Philosophies
Author(s): Johannes Bronkhorst
Publisher: Johannes Bronkhorst
Catalog link: https://jainqq.org/explore/269427/1

JAIN EDUCATION INTERNATIONAL FOR PRIVATE AND PERSONAL USE ONLY
Page #1 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ ENCYCLOPEDIA OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHIES, V: THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE GRAMMARIANS. Edited by Harold G. Coward and K. Kunjunni Raja. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1990. Traditional Sanskrit grammar is primarily a technical enterprise, which does not constitute, in and by itself, a system of philosophy. Grammatical discussions may, and do, from time to time touch upon philosophical questions, but the idea Page #2 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BUCHBESPRECHUNGEN / COMPTES RENDUS 719 of a grammarians' philosophy might not have arisen were it not for Bharthari. This thinker of the fifth century (as secms now as much as certain) worked out a philosophical system which he claimed to be grammatical', and which (or parts of which) came to be accepted by later grammarians as belonging to their own tradition. Moreover, this philosophy came to be included in such works as Sayana-Madhava's Sarvadarsanasangraha (14th century). In spite of Bharthari, most grammarians went on to write technical grammar, with at best the odd reference to what came to be looked upon as their philosophy. Works wholly or mainly dedicated to this philosophy are few, and include primarily Bhartrhari's Vakyapadiya and the commentaries thereon, and some relatively late authors (from the 17th century onward), chief among them Konda Bhatta and Nagesa Bhatta. One of the main aims of the present volume of the Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies (as it was of preceding volumes), is to provide summaries of primary sources. No need to say, by far the longest summaries are those that concern Bhartrhari and Konda Bhatta. And the summary of Bhartrhari's ideas (by Ashok Aklujkar) has, inevitably, to be looked upon as something like the pivot of the book. "The summaries of primary sources" - the Preface elucidates - "aim at making available the substance of the main philosophical ideas contained in these works, so that philosophers who are unable to read the original Sanskrit and who find difficulty in understanding and finding their way about in the translations (where such exist) can get an idea of the positions taken and arguments offered." This is a laudable aim, which can, however, only be realized where the philosophical ideas concerned are clear to those who are able to read the original Sanskrit and find no difficulty in understanding and finding their way about in the translations. As far as Bhartshari is concerned, we are still very far from such an understanding. Radhika Herzberger has rightly drawn attention to "the absence of an integrated portrait of Bhartrhari's thought, a portrait that would convey the essential links between his grammatical ideas and his metaphysical oncs" (Bhartrhari and the Buddhists, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1986, p. 10). And there are numerous other obscure aspects and points of dispute in Bharthari's thought. Presenting Bhartrhari to outsiders, therefore, implies making them aware of the difficulties and disagreements that exist, and providing them with the means to turn to the existing translations, secondary literature and even primary sources. Unfortunately the summary of Bhartrhari's thought does nothing of the kind. It begins with a "Brief analysis" of almost four pages, which contains virtually no justifications and no references. Its very beginning (p. 122) exemplifies its apodictic approach: "Language (vac) has four levels or phases: speech (vaikhan), mental/intellectual or potential speech (madhyama), latent totality of units (pafyana), and pure, basic language principle (para pafyanarupa)." As it happens, there is disagreement among scholars regarding the Page #3 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 720 BUCHBESPRECHUNGEN / COMPTES RENDUS precise number of levels accepted by Bhartrhari (he may have accepted only three of them), but nothing in the "Brief analysis" hints at this. Nor is there any indication where in his work Bharthari presents these levels of speech. It will be instructive to pursue the inspection of this first section of the "Brief analysis" somewhat further, for it illustrates the difficulties users of this book will encounter. Imagine an innocent philosopher who reads this section and believes - understandably - that this first section describes an important aspect of Bharthari's philosophy. He wishes to know where Bharthari discusses this point. Since the "Brief analysis" does not tell him, our philosopher turns to the index at the end of the book. He finds here the terms vaikhari, madhyama, and pasyanti, but notices with surprise that there is no reference to page 122 which is the page from which he started. If he takes the trouble to investigate this enigma, he finds out that the page numbering in the index is too high by 2 for part of the book: page 122 corresponds to p. 124 in the index. Our philosopher now looks for a page number in the index that corresponds to the summary of contents of the Vakyapadiya, pp. 126-172, i.c., presumably, pp. 128-174 in the index. But none of these three terms occur hcre, at least if the index is to be believed. Suppose now that our philosopher does not give up, and reads through the summary. He will find on p. 137: "Grammar is the highest station of the threefold speech (vac) of vaikhari, madhyama, and pasyansi, and it appears in a different form in each of its loci." It is only in the description of the contents of the Vrtti that the philosopher will find a mention of the fourth level. If he now recalls from the very beginning of the section on Bhartrhari (p. 121) that it only "seems likely that Bhartrhari also composed the commentary called vrtti on at least the first two chapters of the (Vakyapadiyal", he may wonder just how central the four levels of speech are to the philosophy of Bhartshari. If he further knew that it is not at all certain, even unlikely, that the Vrtti was written by Bhartphari, he might prefer to leave the whole section on the four levels of specch aside as not established, and in any case of peripheral importance. But this far he will not get, for the book he is reading does not tell him about these uncertainties. But what will our philosopher think of the statement that "grammar is the highest station of the threefold speech ..., and it appears in a different form in cach of its loci", which he has just read? Docs hc from these lines "get an idea of the positions taken and arguments offered"? One doubts it. Yet much of the Vakyapadiya is difficult and requires further study by specialists before it will be understood. In the situation one can only hope that the philosopher will not feel called upon to write about Bharthari and thus add to the confusion surrounding the ideas of this author, and that he will leave it to philologists to make further headway first. Confusion about Bharthari's intentions is not confined to minor points of doctrine and isolated verses of the Vakyapadiya. Consider the central question of what there is. The "Brief analysis" (p. 125) has this to say about the subject: Page #4 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BUCHBESPRECHUNGEN / COMPTES RENDUS 721 "one who is out to find out what really exists will realize that ultimately only the physical things and the language principle exist; the rest of the multiplicity of objects is simply a result of the interaction of these two existents. Qualities ..., capacities ..., relations ..., universals ..., numbers, phases ..., grouping ..., and absence ... do not have any existence of their own apart from the physical objects." (emphasis mine). But in the section on "Buddhist logicians" of the same book, written by Shoryu Katsura, we read (p. 27): "Bhartrhari too seems to have held an idealistic view of reality". And on p. 91 we find what must be the opinion of the editors of the volume: "Bharthari identifics ... the ultimate being with the essence of the speech principle ... The entire world is an appearance ... of this speech principle. ... . It is the same speech essence that appears in the form of various ideas and meanings on the one hand and their symbols - words and sentences - on the other, and thus constitutes the phenomenal world. This speech essence is of the nature of consciousness." (emphasis mine). Different interpretations of an essential aspect of Bharthari's philosophy occur therefore in different parts of the same book. Which of these interpretations is to be accepted by the non-specialized reader to whom the book addresses itself, and who is not even warned, much less informed, about the differences of interpretation that exist regarding many aspects of the Vakyapadiya? Bharthari's philosophy, as will be clear from the preceding paragraph, is not only discussed in the summary of his works referred to above, but also in various passages of the "Introduction to the philosophy of the grammarians", which covers pp. 3-97. It is not possible to deal with these passages in further detail here. Suffice it to say that throughout the book, wherever Bhartrhari's philosophy is discussed, more often than not it is the particular interpretation of the author of that section that is presented. Such interpretations are not necessarily without interest within the context of the ongoing exploration of Bharthari's thought (provided that justifications and references are provided, which is not always the case), but they are hardly the kind of more or less definite knowledge that one would like to present to complete outsiders. As far as Bharthari is concerned, the statement in the Preface according to which "[t]he summarics... are intended primarily for philosophers and only secondarily for indologists" secms therefore particularly inappropriate. Before leaving Bharthari, one further observation must be made. The Vakyapadiya has been edited a number of times, and several of these editions call themselves critical, yet only one of them is critical in the truc sense of the term: this is the edition by Wilhelm Rau. It is true that Rau based his edition only on mss of the karikas, not on mss containing also one or more commentaries. Yet only in the case of Rau's edition is it possible to choose a reading, not on the basis of personal inclination or ad hoc reasoning, but with an awareness of the relative importance of various mss-readings. It is true that further studies could, and should be carried out in order to ascertain the position of the archetype and hyparchetypes of Rau's mss with regard to the texts used by the commentators. Page #5 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 722 BUCHBESPRECHUNGEN / COMPTES RENDUS But as long as no such studies have been carried out, Rau's edition is the best we have and it should be used as a matter of course. Most regrettably, most recent studies of Bharthari ignore Rau's edition completely. Sometimes this leads to misinterpretations that could have been avoided (see, e.g., Etudes Asiatiques/Asiatische Studien 45, 1991, p. 9-11). In all cases it shows a lack of appreciation of what textual scholarship is all about. Unfortunately the book under review is no exception. References are made to Iyer's non-critical editions (which, for no clcar reason, call themselves critical), without any explanation as to why Rau's edition is not used. Later grammatical philosophers lend themselves more easily than Bharthari to a presentation in the Encyclopedia, the main reason being that their works, though perhaps sometimes difficult, present no insurmountable problems of interpretation. One notices with appreciation the elaborate summary of Konda Bhatta's Vaiyakaranabhusana by S.D. Joshi (pp. 255-308). Nagesa Bhatta has been given a less generous treatment: his Manjusa and Laghumanjusa have not been summarized; only summaries of the Paramalaghumanjusa and the Sphotavada, as well as of some relevant portions of the Mahabhasyapradipoddyota, have been included. Bhartrhari's predecessors are dealt with, sketchily, in the 'Historical Resume' (pp. 3-32), and in the summaries dedicated to Vedic literature, Yaska's Nirukta, Panini's Astadhyayi, and Patanjali's Mahabhasya. No mention is anywhere made of the Sarvastivadins. Yet these Buddhists accepted the three dharmas called namakaya, padakaya and vyanjanakaya, entities which are very similar to, if not identical with, the different kinds of sphota that are so important in the grammarians' philosophy. These dharmas might very well be the historical precursors and sources of inspiration of the sphora. Some words about them would have been appropriate. The body of the book is divided into two parts. Part One is called "Introduction to the philosophy of the grammarians" (pp. 3-97) and deals not only with grammarians; it pays also some attention to other thinkers about language, such as the Mimamsakas, the Naiyayikas, the Buddhist Logicians, and the authors of Literary Criticism. Part Two, which calls itself Survey of the literature of grammarian philosophy" (pp. 101-431), confines itself primarily to grammarian writers on philosophy. A checklist of authors and works on Vyakarana philosophy is provided on p. 22 f. of the Historical Resume in Part One. Here we find, of course, Patanjali and Bhartshari, and all those who defended the grammarians' position on the sphoca in original works or commentaries. We find here besides the authors of commentaries on Bhartrhari's Vakyapadiya, also authors of commentaries on Patanjali's Mahabhasya. This last circumstance explains the length of the list, which contains no less than 63 authors. Most of these have been given a section in Part Two, of which there are altogether 85. The number of original and significant authors in the field of grammarian Page #6 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BUCHBESPRECHUNGEN / COMPTES RENDUS 723 philosophy is however far smaller than 63 or 85. This fact must be held partly responsable for a feature that will strike anyone who leafs through the book: the large number of empty or nearly empty pages. The explanation is as follows: Each author gets a section, each section starts on the right hand page, and sections about authors who have written nothing of interest about philosophy (or whose works have not yet been studied, or even edited) range between short and very short. The result is more than seventy (!) completely empty pages in Part Two, and about as many that are more than half empty. This is not only regrettable for ecological reasons. The empty pages, as well as the pages that begin a new section, carry no page aumbering. Long stretches of the book under review are therefore without a single page number. Yet the index at the end refers to these. The practical use of the book is in this way seriously impeded. Pp. 433-548 contain a "Bibliography on grammar (vyakarana)", compiled by Karl H. Potter. Unlike the main parts of the book, this bibliography deals with grammarians in general, not only with philosophers among them. Surprisingly, this bibliography contains no entry more recent than 1983. Even more surprisingly, the information it contains has not been systematically used by the authors of Part Two. This is strikingly illustrated in section 11 of Part Two (p. 199). The whole of this section reads: "PRAMEYASAMGRAHA. The unknown author of a lost commentary on the Vakyapadiya called Prameyasangraha must have lived about A.D. 1000." No notes, no references. The bibliography (G900, p. 475) is better informed: "Prameyasarngraha on book 2 of Bhartshari's Vakyapadiya ... Edited by Wilhelm Rau. Munich, 1981." But not even the bibliography is aware of the review of Rau's edition in Kratylos 27, 1982 (1983), pp. 78-81, which shows that the Prameyasarngraha is not a commentary but an independent work, and that it is almost certainly younger than the commentator Punyaraja. Unfortunately this is not the only lacuna in the bibliography, even where publications from before 1983 are concerned. Major works such as Pierre Filliozat's translations into French of the Mahabhasya (first volume published in 1975) and Kielhorn's English translation of the Paribhasendusekhara are missing. The only critical edition of Bhartrhari's Vakyapadiya, by W. Rau, which is arguably the single most important work to be mentioned in this bibliography, is described incorrectly as "with word index" (p. 469); the book contains a pada-index. (A word-index has been published separately by W. Rau in 1989.) The bibliography, in spite of these and other shortcomings, will be gratefully used by all those who are interested in the Indian grammatical tradition. Yet its lack of connection with the other parts of the book in which it is published will be experienced as disturbing. Part Two, to give another example, dedicates one of its sections to Yaska's Ninukta, the bibliography, as against this, announces that "... sciences, such as ninukta, are not covered" (p. 433). Panini's date is "350 B.C.?" according to the bibliography (p. 441), about the fifth century B.C. Page #7 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ 724 BUCHBESPRECHUNGEN / COMPTES RENDUS according to pages 4 and 111. (The former of these two dates appears to be correct; sec O. v. Hinuber, Der Beginn der Schrift und fruhe Schriftlichkeit in Indien, Stuttgart 1989, p. 34.) Durgasimha (sic), who wrote a commentary on the Katantra grammar, lived "around or before A.D. 800" according to p. 17, around "950?" according to the bibliography (p. 475). (This time it is the compiler of the bibliography who appears to have made a slip; he refers to Belvalkar (Systems of Sanskrit Grammar) p. 73, which however states: "As Durgasimha is quoted by Hemachandra, and as he knew the Chandra Dhatupatha, on the basis of which he put together another Dhatupatha for the Katantra, Durgasimha probably is to be assigned to the cighth century.") The bibliography assigns the date 1540 to Scsa Krsna, author of the Sphotatattvaninupana; p. 22 repeats this date. But section 19, which is dedicated to this author, presents an argument to push back the time in which he must have flourished to 1510 (p. 215). The date assigned to sesa Narayana Bhatta in the bibliography is 1546, with a reference to Yuddhisthira Mimamsaka's Sanskrta Vyakarana-Sastra ka Itihasa vol. 1 p. 405 f., which contains no such date. The section dedicated to the same author observes, on the other hand, that "this writer must have flourished about 1540 (though Yudhisthira Mimamsaka gives a date half a century carlier)", without offering any justification. P. 22 mentions as main philosophical work of Bhattoji Diksita the Vaiyakaranasiddhantakarika. This work, also known by the names Vaiyakaranamatonmajjana and Vaiyakaranabhusanakarika, is the basic text on which Konda Bhatta's famous Vaiyakaranabhusana is a commentary. Yet the section dedicated to Bhattoji Diksita (ao. 30, p. 241-42) makes no mention of this work, and provides only a summary of the philosophical ideas in the Sabdakaustubha. The bibliography mentions both works. A 'Cumulative index' covers the last pages (563-609). While using this index it is to be kept in mind that the page numbering used here does not always correspond with the actual page numbering of Part One (see above). A serious shortcoming of the main portions of the book is the frequent lack of references. This was pointed out above in connection with the sections on Bhartshari, on the Prameyasangraha and on Sesa Narayana Bhatta, but these are not the only examples in Part Two. The same shortcoming is present in Part One. The section on Literary Criticism (pp. 28-32), for example, contains one reference to John Ruskin, Sesame and Lilies unto This Last (London, 1952), and one to Rg Veda 10,71.2c; that's all. The discussion it contains of the ideas of Anandavardhana, Abhinavagupta, Bhattanayaka and Jagannatha Panditaraja, never refers to passages in their works, nor to any secondary literature. P. 52 states that "Bharthari in his Mahabhasyafika accepts three pramanas: perception --, inference ... and scripture" but refers to no precise passage. P. 58 refers to some paradoxes discussed in the Vakyapadiya, but does not tell us where to find them. These and many other instances seriously reduce the value of the volume. Sometimes the information provided is misleading at best. P. 44, for example, states: "Before Bharthari, Patanjali in his Mahabhasya included in the aims of Page #8 -------------------------------------------------------------------------- ________________ BUCHBESPRECHUNGEN / COMPTES RENDUS 725 grammatical study (vyakarana) the attainment of heaven (svarga) through the correct use of words and liberation from bondage (moksa)." This is misleading, for Patanjali's Mahabhasya does not even contain the word moksa. A note refers to K.A. Subramania Iyer's article "Bhartrhari on vyakarana as a means of attaining moksa" (ALB 28, 1964, 112-131) pp. 112-113. But these pages do not contain the words liberation and moksa either (except of course in the title). In fact, Iyer concludes his first section with the words: "Thus, according to Bhartrhari, the author of the Mahabhasya looked upon both abhyudaya and nihsreyasa as two of the aims of the study of grammar" (my emphasis). Be it noted that not even nihsreyasa is offered by Patanjali as an aim of grammar. One regrets once again that a work meant for non-Indologists (i.e., for those who cannot, or are not likely to check what is presented to them) is so sloppy in the information it provides. To conclude, the volume on The Philosophy of the Grammarians is as a whole rather disappointing. Let us hope, however, that it will inspire others to improve upon it, and especially that it will induce them to participate in the exploration of Bhartshari's philosophy, and of the role of language in Indian thought in general. Johannes Bronkhorst